Jackendoff-Bloom-Wynn - Language Logic and Concepts
Jackendoff-Bloom-Wynn - Language Logic and Concepts
Jackendoff-Bloom-Wynn - Language Logic and Concepts
It is with a deep sense of gratitude and humility that we offer this collec -
tion of essaysin memory of John Macnamara by his students, colleagues,
and friends . The essays speak eloquently to the intellectual influence he
had on all of us, but it is seemly that we begin with John himself .
John grew up in County Limerick , Ireland , and spent the early part of
his adult life as a member of the Vincenti an community . He taught at
Castleknock and at St. Patrick 's College , Drumcondra . In 1963 he gained
a doctorate from the University of Edinburgh . His controversial research
findings cast doubt on the value of some of the educational priorities of
postindependenceIreland; they were published in a book entitled Bilin-
gualism and Primary Education . In 1966 John moved to Canada , where he
became Professor of Psychology at McGill University , a post he held till
the end of his life in 1996 .
John ' s intellectual impact in the period after he came to McGill was as
a scholar in the study of the mind and how it develops. Before reviewing
some of the contributions he made in different areas of psychology , it is
important to understand his broader intellectual commitments . These
pervade his work and are themselves interesting and important .
There is a tendency for psychologists to conclude that the human mind
is really quite simple . Psychologists influenced by the ideas of Watson and
Skinner have long argued that thinking and learning can be explained
through a few basic laws. Some reductionists believe that psychological
phenomena can be entirely accounted for in terms of principles of biology
We are grateful to John 's wife Joyce for her assistance in writing this introduction .
Some paragraphs are adapted from a previously published essay by Paul Bloom .
We also wish to thank Albert Bregman for his assistance and encouragement in
the initial stages of developing this volume .
x
Jackendoff, Bloom, and Wynn
and chemistry . Many contemporary scholars are entranced with the idea
that the mind works like a computer (according to some, a rather un-
complicated computer ) . And surely , it is often said, we only need a simple
theory to account for the inner workings of a child - who is, after all , a
quite simple creature !
In John 's writings , one finds the sometimes unfashionable conviction
that the mind of the child is extraordinarily rich and complex . He begins
his 1982 book Names for Things by noting that psychologists typically
ignore the complexity of language learning - at the cost of not being able
to explain it . His favorite example , as will be seen throughout this vol -
ume, was that something as apparently simple as learning the name of a
dog requires considerable mental resources. For instance , children must
be able to appreciate the intentions of others . The 2-year -old must realize
that when an adult uses the name " Freddie " in certain contexts , he or she
intends it to refer to the dog and nothing else. Children must also possess
certain logical resources. The child has to understand how this new word
" Freddie " relates to other parts of speech, such as the common noun
" dog " and the adjective " brown ," and how it contributes to the meanings
of the sentencesthat it appearsin . Perhapsmost importantly , children can
use words to refer : to a real animal for a proper name like " Freddie , " to
an abstract kind for a common noun like " dog ," and to different kinds of
entities altogether when it comes to words like " two " and " Santa Claus ."
John argued that explaining the child 's learning and understanding of
language requires a psychology that includes notions such as inten -
tionality , reference, and truth . This means that psychology and philoso -
phy are more related than many would have thought . It also means that a
complete theory of the mind cannot be found in the fields of biology and
computer science , as such sciences cannot capture these essential proper -
ties of our mental life .
In 1972 John published a classic article with the title " The Cognitive
Basis of Language Learning in Infants ." This article presented a proposal
that has grown to be highly influential . John suggested that although
there are important regards in which language learning is special, distinct
from other sorts of learning that children succeed at, it also relies crucially
on the child 's general understanding of the situations in which sentences
are used. He proposed that the child 's learning of basic grammar (what is
a noun and what is a verb , how words are ordered within a sentence , and
so on) requires knowing what words and sentences mean , and how they
correspond to the external world . In support of this perspective , John and
two colleagues, Nancy Katz and Erika Baker , wrote their 1974 article ,
" What 's in a Name ? A Study of How Children Learn Common and
Proper Names ," which reported an amazing finding . Their experiments
found that even 18-month -olds can use subtle linguistic cues, such as the
grammatical difference between " This is wug " and " This is a wug ," to
learn proper names and common nouns . These two articles have had a
substantial influence on the study of language , motivating considerable
research seeking to better clarify the relationship between children 's
understanding of meaning and their learning of basic grammar .
After the publication of these articles , most of John 's research into
language focused on the learning of words . This work was first discussed
at length in Names for Things and was subsequently elaborated in many
articles and in two further books , A Border Dispute .' The Place of Logic in
Psychology ( 1986) and The Logical Foundations of Cognition ( 1994, edited
in collaboration with Gonzalo Reyes) . This research, some in collabora -
tion with Gonza10 Reyes and Marie La Palme Reyes, focused on the
logical foundation of the learning of proper names and common nouns .
Consider again what a child must know in order to understand a proper
name . One aspect of this knowledge is that this word follows a single
object over time . Even if Freddie were to change color or lose a leg, he
would still be Freddie . On the other hand , if he were to have a twin
brother that looked just like him , this brother would not be Freddie . The
name " Freddie " does not pick out all objects with a certain appearance; it
picks out a unique dog , regardless of his appearance . The child must also
have some understanding of what changes dogs can go through and still
..
XII Jackendoff, Bloom, and Wynn
meanings of pronouns like " I " and " me," since learning these pronouns
requires taking the perspectivesof others? If they have no conception
of fairness or morality , how is it that they understand a fairy tale like
" Cinderella ," which is impossible to appreciate without understanding
that the stepmother is acting unfairly ? All the evidence, John argued ,
leads to the conclusion that children possess a rich set of cognitive , logi -
cal, and moral capacities from the very start .
John also presented more general arguments against the view that
children lack an appreciation of logic and morality . He noted that psy-
chologists fond of this view have never explained how children come
to acquire such capacities . Followers of Jean Piaget have appealed to
" assimilation " and " accommodation ," processes through which the
child 's primitive knowledge becomes more abstract through interaction
with the environment . But in a 1976 article entitled " Stomachs Assimilate
and Accommodate , Don 't They ?" , John argued that these notions are
empty metaphors that explain nothing . Along with the work of Jerry
F odor and N oam Chomsky , John 's empirical and theoretical defense of
the notion of innate ideas and capacities caused a major shift in the way
psychologiststhink about the mind and its development.
The final aspect of John 's work that we wish to mention is his proposal ,
first outlined in a 1990 article entitled " Ideals and Psychology ," that an
adequate psychology must explain the human capacity to understand
ideals . A good example of this , discussed first by Descartes, lies in the
domain of geometry . We all possess the notion of perfect geometric
forms , such as a perfect triangle or a perfect point , but no such forms exist
in nature and none ever will . Scientific progress is also based on ideals ;
physics would be nowhere without its frictionless plane and its perfect
vacuum . Similarly , we have personal ideals that we aspire to , notions such
as humility , friendship , and courage . As John put it , " Idealization is as
natural to the mind as breathing to the body ." But how is it that we come
to appreciate such ideals, given that , by their very nature , they are not to
be found in our experience?
In a 1991 article called " The Development of Moral Reasoning and the
Foundations of Geometry ," John provided a hint of what a psychology of
ideals would look like . The article begins with a critical discussion of a
well -known stage theory of moral development proposed by Jean Piaget
and extended by Lawrence Kohlberg . John argued that this theory seri-
ously underestimates children ' s knowledge , fails to describe adult moral
competence, and does not explain how notions of morality actually de-
.
XIV Jackendoff, Bloom, and Wynn
velop and how supposedlyamoral children grow into moral adults. John
then proposed an alternative theory of moral development, based on an
intriguing analogy betweensystemsof morality and systemsof geometry.
In both domains, there exist ideal elements(in geometry, elementssuch as
point and line; in morality , elements such as fair and good) that are
related to one another through a system of axioms. John suggested
that there are extensive unlearned elements within both geometry and
morality . Children start off with an understanding of certain ideals in
both domains, and these are the notions that all people share. But psy-
chologists must also explain how new geometric and moral knowledge
emergesin adults and children. New geometries have been developed
by mathematicians, such as the non-Euclidean geometry proposed by
Riemann in the nineteenth century, and new moral ideals have been in-
troduced in the course of history, such as the ideal of chastity introduced
by the Christians. How are these learned and understood? The parallel
betweengeometry and morality placesthe study of moral developmentin
a striking new light . It might be that the child who is coming to grasp a
novel moral system is actually acquiring a coherent formal structure,
complete with ideals and axioms, in much the sameway he or shewould
learn a new systemof geometry, or mathematics, or physics.
This article is not as well known as many of John's other works dis-
cussedabove. (Perhaps the title scarespeople away!) But it is hard to
think of a better work in developmental psychology. Although it is
entirely accessiblein style and content, it doesnot shy away from the hard
questions. It is a significant intellectual accomplishment, but also some-
thing more, as it displays severalproperties typical of John's work . There
is creativity, intellectual courage, and a strong curiosity about the work-
ings of the world . Most of all, there is respectfor its subject matter: the
minds of young children and how they develop. It is more than an article
about morality ; it is itself a highly moral work .
For a closer look into John as a person, we quote from the eulogy by
John's friend and collaborator Gonzalo Reyes. The essencethat Gonzalo
so beautifully evokeshere strikes a familiar chord for anyone who knew
John.
I first met John ten yearsago whenhe gavea talk in the Mathematics
Departmentat McGill in October1985.He raisedthequestionof givinga
logicalaccountof thephrase" Freddieis a dog" that childrenlearnby the
Introduction xv
logic , since he had missed so much of what was going on during his long
illness .
an alternative theory with the words " This simply cannot be done. . ." But
at the same time, this man who was a Fellow of the Royal Society of
Canada would sit down with undergraduatesin my course of elementary
logic, and would bring his homework to my teaching assistantto fight
with him for a better grade. Nothing is so touching for me as the sight of
this distinguishedman of over sixty going back to school to study logic
and category theory becausehe believedthat thesewere tools that a cog-
nitive psychologist should know. " My " John is also John the student. In
this context, I cannot forget his son Kieran's role as John's teacher: John
told me how he could appreciate films that were at first foreign to his
sensibility thanks to his son's efforts.
But I feel that I cannot enumerate, let alone do justice to, all the Johns
that so many peopleloved and found so fascinating. . . . John: we will miss
you . . .
The essaysin this volume are grouped roughly along thematic lines. We
begin with Richard Kearney's remarks expanding on John's early work
on languageand ethnicity. This is followed by a seriesof chapterson the
foundations of logic and conceptsby Anil Gupta, Michael Makkai , Ray
Jackendoff, Storrs McCall , David Olson, and SandeepPrasada. Then
comes an interlude of chapters on more philosophical topics by Steven
Davis and Leslie McPherson, after which we turn more directly to the
relation between language and conceptualization in chapters by Steven
Pinker and Alan Prince, Myrna Gopnik, Paul Bloom, SusanCarey and
Fei Xu , Geoffrey Hall , and Yuriko Oshima-Takane. We end with two
chapterson mathematical approachesto cognition, one by William Law-
vere and the other by John himself and his three dear colleaguesMarie La
Palme Reyes, Gonzalo Reyes, and Houman Zolfaghari.
This grouping, however, does not bring out the rich interconnections
among the chapters and their relation to John's work . We leave the
appreciation of thesedetails to the reader.
Paul Bloom Ray J ackendotI
Department of Psychology Program in Linguistics and
University of Arizona Cognitive Science
[email protected] Brandeis University
[email protected]
SusanCarey
Department of Psychology Richard Kearney
New York University Department of Philosophy
[email protected] University College Dublin
rkearney @ollamh .ucd .ie
StevenDavis
F . William Lawvere
Department of Philosophy
Simon Fraser University Department of Mathematics
[email protected] State University of New York at
Buffalo
Myrna Gopnik
wlawvere @acsu.buffalo .edu
Department of Linguistics
McGill University Michael Makkai
David Olson F ei Xu
Ontario Institute for Studiesin Department of Psychology
Education Northeastern University
University of Toronto fxu @neu.edu
[email protected]
Houman Zolfaghari
Yuriko Oshima-Takane Montreal , Quebec
Department of Psychology hzo If aghari @micro -intel .com
McGill University
yuriko @hebb.psych.mcgill.ca
StevenPinker
Department of Brain and
Cognitive Sciences
MassachusettsInstitute of
Technology
[email protected] .edu
SandeepPrasada
Department of Psychology
Dartmouth College
[email protected]
Alan Prince
Department of Linguistics
Rutgers University
[email protected]
Gonzalo E. Reyes
Department of Mathematics and
Statistics
University of Montreal
[email protected]
Marie La Palme Reyes
Montreal, Quebec
[email protected]
Karen Wynn
Department of Psychology
University of Arizona
[email protected]
Introduction Ray Jackendoff , Paul Bloom ,
and Karen Wynn
It is with a deep sense of gratitude and humility that we offer this collec -
tion of essaysin memory of John Macnamara by his students, colleagues,
and friends . The essays speak eloquently to the intellectual influence he
had on all of us, but it is seemly that we begin with John himself .
John grew up in County Limerick , Ireland , and spent the early part of
his adult life as a member of the Vincenti an community . He taught at
Castleknock and at St. Patrick 's College , Drumcondra . In 1963 he gained
a doctorate from the University of Edinburgh . His controversial research
findings cast doubt on the value of some of the educational priorities of
postindependenceIreland; they were published in a book entitled Bilin-
gualism and Primary Education . In 1966 John moved to Canada , where he
became Professor of Psychology at McGill University , a post he held till
the end of his life in 1996 .
John ' s intellectual impact in the period after he came to McGill was as
a scholar in the study of the mind and how it develops. Before reviewing
some of the contributions he made in different areas of psychology , it is
important to understand his broader intellectual commitments . These
pervade his work and are themselves interesting and important .
There is a tendency for psychologists to conclude that the human mind
is really quite simple . Psychologists influenced by the ideas of Watson and
Skinner have long argued that thinking and learning can be explained
through a few basic laws. Some reductionists believe that psychological
phenomena can be entirely accounted for in terms of principles of biology
We are grateful to John 's wife Joyce for her assistance in writing this introduction .
Some paragraphs are adapted from a previously published essay by Paul Bloom .
We also wish to thank Albert Bregman for his assistance and encouragement in
the initial stages of developing this volume .
x
Jackendoff, Bloom, and Wynn
and chemistry . Many contemporary scholars are entranced with the idea
that the mind works like a computer (according to some, a rather un-
complicated computer ) . And surely , it is often said, we only need a simple
theory to account for the inner workings of a child - who is, after all , a
quite simple creature !
In John 's writings , one finds the sometimes unfashionable conviction
that the mind of the child is extraordinarily rich and complex . He begins
his 1982 book Names for Things by noting that psychologists typically
ignore the complexity of language learning - at the cost of not being able
to explain it . His favorite example , as will be seen throughout this vol -
ume, was that something as apparently simple as learning the name of a
dog requires considerable mental resources. For instance , children must
be able to appreciate the intentions of others . The 2-year -old must realize
that when an adult uses the name " Freddie " in certain contexts , he or she
intends it to refer to the dog and nothing else. Children must also possess
certain logical resources. The child has to understand how this new word
" Freddie " relates to other parts of speech, such as the common noun
" dog " and the adjective " brown ," and how it contributes to the meanings
of the sentencesthat it appearsin . Perhapsmost importantly , children can
use words to refer : to a real animal for a proper name like " Freddie , " to
an abstract kind for a common noun like " dog ," and to different kinds of
entities altogether when it comes to words like " two " and " Santa Claus ."
John argued that explaining the child 's learning and understanding of
language requires a psychology that includes notions such as inten -
tionality , reference, and truth . This means that psychology and philoso -
phy are more related than many would have thought . It also means that a
complete theory of the mind cannot be found in the fields of biology and
computer science , as such sciences cannot capture these essential proper -
ties of our mental life .
In 1972 John published a classic article with the title " The Cognitive
Basis of Language Learning in Infants ." This article presented a proposal
that has grown to be highly influential . John suggested that although
there are important regards in which language learning is special, distinct
from other sorts of learning that children succeed at, it also relies crucially
on the child 's general understanding of the situations in which sentences
are used. He proposed that the child 's learning of basic grammar (what is
a noun and what is a verb , how words are ordered within a sentence , and
so on) requires knowing what words and sentences mean , and how they
correspond to the external world . In support of this perspective , John and
two colleagues, Nancy Katz and Erika Baker , wrote their 1974 article ,
" What 's in a Name ? A Study of How Children Learn Common and
Proper Names ," which reported an amazing finding . Their experiments
found that even 18-month -olds can use subtle linguistic cues, such as the
grammatical difference between " This is wug " and " This is a wug ," to
learn proper names and common nouns . These two articles have had a
substantial influence on the study of language , motivating considerable
research seeking to better clarify the relationship between children 's
understanding of meaning and their learning of basic grammar .
After the publication of these articles , most of John 's research into
language focused on the learning of words . This work was first discussed
at length in Names for Things and was subsequently elaborated in many
articles and in two further books , A Border Dispute .' The Place of Logic in
Psychology ( 1986) and The Logical Foundations of Cognition ( 1994, edited
in collaboration with Gonzalo Reyes) . This research, some in collabora -
tion with Gonza10 Reyes and Marie La Palme Reyes, focused on the
logical foundation of the learning of proper names and common nouns .
Consider again what a child must know in order to understand a proper
name . One aspect of this knowledge is that this word follows a single
object over time . Even if Freddie were to change color or lose a leg, he
would still be Freddie . On the other hand , if he were to have a twin
brother that looked just like him , this brother would not be Freddie . The
name " Freddie " does not pick out all objects with a certain appearance; it
picks out a unique dog , regardless of his appearance . The child must also
have some understanding of what changes dogs can go through and still
..
XII Jackendoff, Bloom, and Wynn
meanings of pronouns like " I " and " me," since learning these pronouns
requires taking the perspectivesof others? If they have no conception
of fairness or morality , how is it that they understand a fairy tale like
" Cinderella ," which is impossible to appreciate without understanding
that the stepmother is acting unfairly ? All the evidence, John argued ,
leads to the conclusion that children possess a rich set of cognitive , logi -
cal, and moral capacities from the very start .
John also presented more general arguments against the view that
children lack an appreciation of logic and morality . He noted that psy-
chologists fond of this view have never explained how children come
to acquire such capacities . Followers of Jean Piaget have appealed to
" assimilation " and " accommodation ," processes through which the
child 's primitive knowledge becomes more abstract through interaction
with the environment . But in a 1976 article entitled " Stomachs Assimilate
and Accommodate , Don 't They ?" , John argued that these notions are
empty metaphors that explain nothing . Along with the work of Jerry
F odor and N oam Chomsky , John 's empirical and theoretical defense of
the notion of innate ideas and capacities caused a major shift in the way
psychologiststhink about the mind and its development.
The final aspect of John 's work that we wish to mention is his proposal ,
first outlined in a 1990 article entitled " Ideals and Psychology ," that an
adequate psychology must explain the human capacity to understand
ideals . A good example of this , discussed first by Descartes, lies in the
domain of geometry . We all possess the notion of perfect geometric
forms , such as a perfect triangle or a perfect point , but no such forms exist
in nature and none ever will . Scientific progress is also based on ideals ;
physics would be nowhere without its frictionless plane and its perfect
vacuum . Similarly , we have personal ideals that we aspire to , notions such
as humility , friendship , and courage . As John put it , " Idealization is as
natural to the mind as breathing to the body ." But how is it that we come
to appreciate such ideals, given that , by their very nature , they are not to
be found in our experience?
In a 1991 article called " The Development of Moral Reasoning and the
Foundations of Geometry ," John provided a hint of what a psychology of
ideals would look like . The article begins with a critical discussion of a
well -known stage theory of moral development proposed by Jean Piaget
and extended by Lawrence Kohlberg . John argued that this theory seri-
ously underestimates children ' s knowledge , fails to describe adult moral
competence, and does not explain how notions of morality actually de-
.
XIV Jackendoff, Bloom, and Wynn
velop and how supposedlyamoral children grow into moral adults. John
then proposed an alternative theory of moral development, based on an
intriguing analogy betweensystemsof morality and systemsof geometry.
In both domains, there exist ideal elements(in geometry, elementssuch as
point and line; in morality , elements such as fair and good) that are
related to one another through a system of axioms. John suggested
that there are extensive unlearned elements within both geometry and
morality . Children start off with an understanding of certain ideals in
both domains, and these are the notions that all people share. But psy-
chologists must also explain how new geometric and moral knowledge
emergesin adults and children. New geometries have been developed
by mathematicians, such as the non-Euclidean geometry proposed by
Riemann in the nineteenth century, and new moral ideals have been in-
troduced in the course of history, such as the ideal of chastity introduced
by the Christians. How are these learned and understood? The parallel
betweengeometry and morality placesthe study of moral developmentin
a striking new light . It might be that the child who is coming to grasp a
novel moral system is actually acquiring a coherent formal structure,
complete with ideals and axioms, in much the sameway he or shewould
learn a new systemof geometry, or mathematics, or physics.
This article is not as well known as many of John's other works dis-
cussedabove. (Perhaps the title scarespeople away!) But it is hard to
think of a better work in developmental psychology. Although it is
entirely accessiblein style and content, it doesnot shy away from the hard
questions. It is a significant intellectual accomplishment, but also some-
thing more, as it displays severalproperties typical of John's work . There
is creativity, intellectual courage, and a strong curiosity about the work-
ings of the world . Most of all, there is respectfor its subject matter: the
minds of young children and how they develop. It is more than an article
about morality ; it is itself a highly moral work .
For a closer look into John as a person, we quote from the eulogy by
John's friend and collaborator Gonzalo Reyes. The essencethat Gonzalo
so beautifully evokeshere strikes a familiar chord for anyone who knew
John.
I first met John ten yearsago whenhe gavea talk in the Mathematics
Departmentat McGill in October1985.He raisedthequestionof givinga
logicalaccountof thephrase" Freddieis a dog" that childrenlearnby the
Introduction xv
logic , since he had missed so much of what was going on during his long
illness .
an alternative theory with the words " This simply cannot be done. . ." But
at the same time, this man who was a Fellow of the Royal Society of
Canada would sit down with undergraduatesin my course of elementary
logic, and would bring his homework to my teaching assistantto fight
with him for a better grade. Nothing is so touching for me as the sight of
this distinguishedman of over sixty going back to school to study logic
and category theory becausehe believedthat thesewere tools that a cog-
nitive psychologist should know. " My " John is also John the student. In
this context, I cannot forget his son Kieran's role as John's teacher: John
told me how he could appreciate films that were at first foreign to his
sensibility thanks to his son's efforts.
But I feel that I cannot enumerate, let alone do justice to, all the Johns
that so many peopleloved and found so fascinating. . . . John: we will miss
you . . .
The essaysin this volume are grouped roughly along thematic lines. We
begin with Richard Kearney's remarks expanding on John's early work
on languageand ethnicity. This is followed by a seriesof chapterson the
foundations of logic and conceptsby Anil Gupta, Michael Makkai , Ray
Jackendoff, Storrs McCall , David Olson, and SandeepPrasada. Then
comes an interlude of chapters on more philosophical topics by Steven
Davis and Leslie McPherson, after which we turn more directly to the
relation between language and conceptualization in chapters by Steven
Pinker and Alan Prince, Myrna Gopnik, Paul Bloom, SusanCarey and
Fei Xu , Geoffrey Hall , and Yuriko Oshima-Takane. We end with two
chapterson mathematical approachesto cognition, one by William Law-
vere and the other by John himself and his three dear colleaguesMarie La
Palme Reyes, Gonzalo Reyes, and Houman Zolfaghari.
This grouping, however, does not bring out the rich interconnections
among the chapters and their relation to John's work . We leave the
appreciation of thesedetails to the reader.
Publications of
John Macnamara
Books
Articles
Press , 1994 .
Occasional Pieces
1977 , 1 , 40 - 44 .
mai , 5 .
Macnamara , J . Cinderella and the soul . New Oxford Review , 1990 , Nov .,
7 - 11 .
15 - 16 .
Reviews
Maratsos , M . P.: The use of definite and indefinite reference in young chil -
dren: An experimental study in semantic acquisition . In Child Development
Abstracts and Bibliography, 1977, 51, 156.
Moerk , E . L .: Pragmatic and semantic aspects of early language develop-
ment. In Child DevelopmentAbstracts and Bibliography, 1978, 52, 85- 86.
Gelman , R ., and Gallistel , C . R .: The child 's understanding of number. In
Canadian Journal of Psychology , 1978, 32, 270- 271.
McLaughlin , B .: Second language acquisition in childhood . In Child
Development Abstracts and Bibliography , 1979, 53, 76- 77.
aleron , P.: L 'enfant et I 'acquisition du langage (Review title : Cognition in
language learning ) . In Contemporary Psychology , 1980, 25, 497- 498.
Lock , A .: The guided reinvention of language (Review title : Anthropology
in the nursery ). In Contemporary Psychology , 1981, 26, 542- 543.
Ginsburgh , H . P. (Ed .) : The development of mathematical thinking
(Review title : All about sums) . In Contemporary Psychology , 1984, 29,
136 - 137 .
..
Publications XXVII
Pinker , S.: The language instinct ,. and Jackendoff , R .: Patterns in the mind .
In Boston Globe , 13 March 1994 .
Cha pter 1
What gave unity to the nation , what made it a home , a place of passionate at-
tachment , was not the cold contrivance of shared rights but the people 's preexist -
ing ethnic characteristics : their language , religion , customs and traditions . The
nation as Volk had begun its long and troubling career in European thought . All
the peoples of nineteenth -century Europe under imperial subjection - the Poles
and Baltic peoples under the Russian yoke , the Serbs under Turkish rule , the
Croats under the Hapsburgs - looked to the German ideal of ethnic nationalism
when articulating their right to self-determination . ( 1993, 7)
Irish Britons , for example , can affirm a strong senseof national allegiance
to their " land of origin " even though they may be three or four gen-
erations away from that land and frequently of mixed ethnicity . With the
formulation of a " new nationalism " in the Forum for a New Ireland
( 1984- 85), the then Foreign Minister , Peter Barry , included the Irish em-
igrant population in his definition of the nation (appealing , for example ,
to " Irish nationalists North and South and everywhere else in the world " ),
as did President Mary Robinson when she came to office in 1990 . Similar
appeals are heard whenever the international community is solicited to
support peace in Northern Ireland (the international Ireland Funds , etc.),
or when it is a question of debating emigrant voting rights in national
elections and selecting national football teams.
In short , although the " migrant nation " is still largely ethnically based,
it is far more inclusive than the ethnic nation model in that it embraces
the exiled along with the indigenous .7 By implication , this means accept-
ing that the Irish diaspora comprises not only different Irish peoples
(" Ulster Scots" as well as " native Gaels" ) but , through intermarriage in
the melting pots of overseas continents , different racial confections as
well . One wonders how many of the Irish Irelanders - who sought to
confine the nation to those of Gaelic extraction - would have believed
that by the 1994 World Cup the Irish team would be over half British -
born with a center forward named Cascarino .8
A fifth , and final , variable that merits attention here is what might
broadly be called the " nation as culture ." This is not unrelated to the two
preceding definitions but differs in this crucial respect: the cultural para -
digm of national identity is not reducible to any specific race. National
culture can include many things besides ethnicity : for example , religion ,
language , art , sport , dance, music , cuisine , clothes, literature , philosophy ,
even (some believe) economics . As such, it is by nature far more pluralist
than any strictly racial understanding of nationhood . For its part , the
Irish nation includes several different religions (as Wolfe Tone 's reference
to " Catholic , Protestant , and Dissenter " recognized), two different lan -
guages (Gaelic and English ) , and a rich variety of philosophical tradi -
tions . Indeed , even when cultural nationalism does refer to ethnicity , it is
obliged - if it is to be consistent - to invoke several different ethnic lega-
cies. In the case of the Irish cultural nation this requires acknowledgment
of the Viking , Norman , Scots, and Anglo -Saxon contributions alongside
those of the " ancient Celtic race." Thus , we might say that the exclusivist
equation of " Irish Irish " with Gaelic and Catholic , by D . P. Moran and
6 Kearney
Although Gaelic is the official " first language " of the Republic , and an
invaluable resource to the nation , it is not the first tongue spoken by the
one of the world ' s great modern literatures . Joyce , Yeats , Wilde , Kava -
nagh , Heaney may well be haunted by Gaelic as their souls " fret in the
shadow of the ( English ) language " - but it is English that they speak and
write , albeit in a singularly Irish way . The language question is even more
did , for a time , pursue the quasi - Herderian thesis that the collective genius
of the race found its true expression in the Irish tongue . Hence the view
course , that because Ireland had a unique and ancient language , it had a
Garvin notes the irony that the more the Irish embraced English , the more
English has always been the language of Irish political separatism , in an extra -
ordinary succession from Jonathan Swift and Clement Molyneux in the early
eighteenth century , through Theobald Wolfe Tone and William Drennan in the
1790s , to John Mitchel , Arthur Griffith , James Connolly and Patrick Pearse in the
nineteenth and twentieth centuries . Political sentiment in the Irish Gaelic language
tended to be rather pre - political , rarely getting further than a sentimental and
It certainly seems the case that it was through English that the republican
Thus , it has been remarked that the acquisition of English , " far from
making the Irish assimilate to English attitudes and loyalties , rather gave
The same could be said about religion and Irish nationalism . Although
one , and besides carries a strong " internationalist " component that COll -
7
Language and Nationalism
trasts with the notion of a closed insular Volk (e.g., the missionary tradi-
tion of diaspora throughout Europe, Africa , Asia, and the Americas).
That said, one should not underestimatethe powerful role religion has
played in Irish nationalism, and nationalism worldwide. The fact that
nationalism, particularly in its modern republican guises, is an offspring
of Enlightenment secularismhas not prevented its more popular mani-
festations from being fueled by the collectivist, and often atavistic, en-
ergies of traditional religions. Though this connection has been greatly
underrated in much academic literature, recent research by Marianne
Elliott (1996) shows the pivotal symbiosisbetweenIrish nationalism and
Catholicism in our own century and argues that the Ulster Protestants'
rejection of Catholicism dominates their rejection of nationalism.10 Tom
Garvin makes a similar point : although he concedesthat the founders of
the separatistIrish tradition were Protestant rather than Catholic (largely
due to the Protestants' near-monopoly of higher education in Ireland up
to the twentieth century), he observesthat the nationalist rank and file
have been overwhelmingly Catholic since the 1790sand the nationalist
leadership so since the 1900s. " Irish nationalism," he concludes, " has
always been rhetorically anti-sectarian, but is tempted into sectarianism
becauseof its anthropological rooting in the Catholic majority and in the
ideology of dispossessionand repossession " (1994, 89).11 The fact that
Protestantismwas the religion of the dominant Ascendancyclass, which
disenfranchisedthe Catholic majority , was an additional factor in the
equation.
Here once again, history is vexed. One of the main reasonsthe Catholic
hierarchy was not officially allied to Irish nationalism during the eigh-
teenth and nineteenth centuries was that it feared that the nationalist-
republican ideasbeing imported into Ireland from the French Revolution
were anti-Catholic. The fact that theseideaswere also anti-British meant,
logically, that a tacit alliance of interests bound the Catholic hierarchy
and Westminster together: the Catholic hierarchy actually approved the
abolition of the Irish parliament and union with Britain in 1800, and the
English government financed the establishmentof the Catholic seminary
Maynooth in 1795. After the fall of Parnell and 1916, however, it became
clear to the Church that the soul of the Irish nation was up for grabs and
that the need for a unifying collective identity for the newly emerging
state could best be provided by a form of Catholic nationalism that
allowed (in Joyce's words) " Christ and Caesargo hand in hand." Indeed,
8 Kearney
Notes
1. On this tension between civic universalism and state nationalism , see Ingram
1995 , Garvin 1993 , and Ricoeur 1995b . As Ricoeur observes , one of the main
dangers of equating nation with state is the eclipse of society behind the state.
Thus we see, for example , how the French Revolution apportioned political
sovereignty to all levels of the community , from the government at the top to the
individuals at the bottom , but allowed the state to become omnipresent in the
process, reducing the citizen to a mere fragment of the state.
2. Fennell develops his analysis of territorial nationalism as follows :
The definition of the nation as a community determined by a territory - the so-called
national territory - was typical of much European nationalism . . . . As a matter of history ,
most European nation -states were constructed by using force , administrative pressures, and
schooling to convert this theory into fact . . . . The primary aim of Irish nationalism , a united ,
self-governing Ireland , was also typically nationalist : the nation inhabiting the national ter -
ritory , so the theory ran , had the right to political autonomy under a single government .
(1989, 20- 21)
3. For example :
The image of the Emerald Isle alone and inviolate in the ocean has itself become a cultural
symbol , a mute argument for the unity of Ireland and its necessary separation from Britain .
This argument from geography has commonly impressed not only Irish separatists them -
selves, but also many British observers and perhaps most third -country observers of the tor -
tured and tortuous relationship , one of mutual love and mutual hatred , between the two
islands . Anti -partitionists in particular commonly justify the Republic 's constitutional claim
to Northern Ireland by claiming that what God and History have united , no man , and cer-
tainly no Englishman , can sunder . (Garvin 1994, 84)
This debate has direct relevance to current discussions of a revised Irish constitu -
tion . De Valera ' s constitution of 1937 described the " Nation " in terms of three
articles . The Irish nation is asserted (axiomatically ) rather than defined in Article
1. It is described in terms of national territory encompassing the entire island in
Article 2 ; and the divided condition of the island is referred to as a temporary
matter , " pending the re-integration of the national territory ," in Article 3. The
subsequent descriptions of the " State" that follow - Articles 4 to 9- are equally
nebulous and ambiguous . Hence the need for a revised constitution setting out a
clear definition of citizenship and nationality , and taking into consideration the
new status of Northern Ireland as a region relating concentrically to the island of
Ireland , the British archipelago , the European Union , and the United Nations . I
am indebted to Philip McGuinness for several of the above comments .
4. See Sluga 1993, 60, 91, 103- 108, on the Romantic philosophy of Germany as
an ethnic nation . In his Addresses to the German Nation ( 1807), Fichte called on
the spirit of the German people to remember " its own true nature " and to realize
that the battle against other nations cannot be " fought without one's household
gods, one' s mythic roots , without a true 'recovery ' of all things German " (sec. 23) .
It was not a huge leap from these musings of the German Romantics to the
argument of a Nazi idealogue like Rosenberg , who , in his speech " The Crisis and
Construction of Europe " ( 1934), called for a rejection of the Enlightenment uni -
versalism that had dominated European thought and politics , concluding , " The
10 Kearney
point , the idea , the fact from which we must start today is the fact of the nation "
larly in the contemporary context where the traditional equation of " people , "
" nation , " and " state " is becoming increasingly confused and questioned , see
internationalism that typified National Socialism were not , it is fair to say , qual -
ities shared by Irish , British , or French nationalists in any general sense . Although
British and French nationalisms are in principle civic rather than ethnic , recent
responses to the " immigration problem " have revived some concept of the latter ,
albeit frequently at a cultural level - for example , the British Heritage Industry or
On this vexed distinction between civic and ethnic nationalism , see Ricoeur ' s
pertinent remarks :
The notion of ' people ' according to the French Constitution is not ethnic . Its citizenship is
defined by the fact that somebody is born on . the territory of France . For example , the son or
daughter of an immigrant is French because he or she was born on this territory . So the rule
of membership has nothing to do with ethnic origin . This is why it was impossible to define
the Corsican people , because we had to rely on criteria other than citizenship , on ethnic cri -
teria . . . . The Corsican people are also members of the French people . Here we have two
meanings of the term ' people ' . On the one hand , people means to be a citizen in a state , so
it ' s not an ethnic concept . But on the other hand , Corsica is a people in an ethnic sense -
within the French people which is not an ethnic concept . I think it ' s an example of what is
phenomenon of " late nationalism ," or what we might call retro -nationalism , is a
phenomenon that Anderson links with the dislocationary processes of late capi -
talism . The more people feel surrounded by a disenchanted universe - an alien -
ated, simulated , mass-produced world - the greater their need for a return to
a reenchanted universe . Neonationalism seems a response to such a need (as
witnessed in the doubling of newly formed nation -states since World War I ,
accelerated by the breakup of the " Communist bloc " ) . Yet another feature of
" long -distance nationalism " is the internationalization of national politics as evi -
denced in the growing number of expatriate or foreign citizens - usually American
or Canadian - entering the presidential campaigns of post -Communist nation -
states (e.g., Croatia , Poland , Estonia ) . Nor should we underestimate the influential
role played by American -Irish politicians , especially the Kennedys and President
Clinton , in the Northern Ireland peace process ( 1994- 1996) .
9. It was through the use of the English language , as Garvin points out , that " the
idea of an Irish Republic , free of aristocratic privilege , monarchical trappings and
religious distinctions , was transmitted to a popular culture " ( 1994, 86). In this re-
spect language proved to be a far more malleable badge of national identity than ,
say, race or religion . " Language has the great advantage from the point of view of
nation -builders , of being learnable ; unlike one's religion , there is no spiritual price
to pay for 'changing sides' " (Garvin 1993, 72) . See also Macnamara 's ( 1977) more
psychological -philosophical -linguistic approach to this subject .
The complex relationship between language and nation extends beyond the
Irish case and has many repercussions in the emerging European context . As Paul
Ricoeur puts it :
10. See also O 'Brien 's ( 1994) trenchant critique of what he calls " sacral national -
ism " ; and see Kearney 1984, Murphy 1988, and Keogh 1988. The relationship
between nationalism and Catholicism resurfaced during the heated debates on
abortion information and divorce in the 1990s, particularly as they affected the
Irish constitution . The narrow passing of the controversial Divorce Referendum in
November 1995 was a particularly significant moment in this ongoing process of
Irish " self-identification ." The reverse side of the Catholic -nationalist equation is
the Protestant -unionist ; on this relationship between Protestantism and Orangeism
see, for example , Moloney 1980.
Language and Nationalism 13
11. Seealso Garvin 1990, Kiberd 1995. An additional reasonfor the reversion of
Irish nationalism to confessionalallegiancemay have something to do with the
more general issue of new nation-states' experiencing a foundational crisis of
legitimation. As Paul Ricoeur points out (1995a, 201): " A la racine du politique, a
son fondement, il y a l'enigmede l'origine de l'autorite. D 'ou vient-elle? C'est une
chosequi est toujours non reglee, et qui fait que I' ombre ou Ie fantome du theo-
logique continue de roder autour du politique" ('The enigma of the sourceof au-
thority lies at the very root and foundation of politics. From what does it derive?
This is something never fully resolved, which means that the political is always
haunted by a theological ghost or shadow').
12. Seealso Neary 1984and Daly 1988.
13. Among these contradictions and complexities, Garvin (1993) points to the
tension betweenthe Anglo-Irish and Gaelic traditions that Yeats sought to com-
bine in a single narrative.
Yeats, himselfa Protestant
, wishedto devisean Irish nationalmyth that providedroomfor
peopleof his own'Anglo-Irish' tradition. Thetroublewasthat thematerialshewishedto use
weremutuallyincompatible , beingderivedfrom Anglo-Irish andIrish traditions, whichhad
historicallyalwaysbeenat loggerheads and, worse,werestill knownto havebeenso. (p. 64)
Another, more general contradiction involves the conflict between modern-
secularistand tribal -traditionalist aspectsof Irish nationalism.
The modernself-contradictory , attemptedderivationsof Irish nationality from Gaelic,
Catholic, or evenAnglo-Irish aristocraticidentitieswould havehorrified and bewildered
Wolfe Toneand the otherFrance-inspiredIrish Jacobinsof the 1790s . The Enlightenment
conceptof 'citizenship
' independentof one's traditionalidentificationhassurvivedin Ireland,
but it hasfacedveryseverecompetitionfrom, in particular, religion-basedidentities. (p. 65)
While conceding that modern political nationalism is a child of Enlightenment
universalism, in principle, Garvin arguesthat nationalism as a cultural phenome-
non (with political consequences ) is far more ancient, and more atavistic, than the
modern universalizedversion.
In Ireland, land hunger, a quasi-racistsenseof common'stock', memoriesof confiscation
anda strongCatholicism , all disguised
ineffectively
in theragsof thedeadGaelicidentity, lie
behindthe theoreticallysecularmodernnationalidentityof English-speakingIreland. The
inheritanceis ambivalent , andhasseveralideologicalrepertoires that may be drawnupon.
(p. 66)
References
Ascherson, N . (1995). Nations and regions. In R . Kearney (Ed.), Statesof mind:
Dialogues with contemporarythinkers on the Europeanmind. Manchester: Man-
chesterUniversity Press, and New York : New York University Press.
Daly , M . (1988). The impact of economic development on national identity. In
lrishness in a changing society (Princess Grace Irish Library 2). Totowa, NJ:
Barnesand Noble.
Elliott , M . (1996). Religion and identity in Northern Ireland. In W . A . Van Horn
(Ed.), Global convulsions : Race, ethnicity and nationalism at the end of the twen-
tieth century'. Albany , NY : SUNY Press.
14
Kearney
2.1 An Example
Figure2.1
(3) The directionof the ray dc is the sameasthat of the ray b71
.
(Seefigure2.1.) Furthermore, they recognizethe denialof (1) to be war-
rantedwhenbasedon (2) and the denialof (3). Thesetwo criteria, let us
assume , are of equalimportancein the usesof 'up'. Both criteria come
Meaning and Misconceptions 17
Standard Up
= the direction of
Satellite
s theraypi
Mountain
peak p
Figure2.2
into play to an equal degree, and neither can be given priority over the
other.
(ii) Let us also assumethat the community usescertain objects to de-
fine the " Standard Up " direction. The community, let us assume, defines
the Standard Up to be the direction of the ray jiSdetermined by a moun-
tain peakp and a natural satellite s located in a geostationaryorbit above
p . (Seefigure 2.2.) So, the community's conceptual criterion can also be
reformulated as follows:
-+
a is up above b iff the direction of the ray ba is the Standard Up .
This criterion, let us imagine, is so strongly embeddedin the community
that the two sidesof the biconditional are regardedas equivalent ways of
saying the samething.
(iii ) Let us assumethat the community engagesonly in Plain Speech.
There is in its discourseno subtle exploitation of conversationalmaxims
to communicate one thing while saying another.1 The content of, for ex-
ample, an assertionmade by using 'a is up above b' is preciselywhat the
conventional meaning of the sentencewould dictate it to be. The as-
sumption of Plain Speechwill enableus to focus on the main issuesbefore
us, freeing us from irrelevant distractions.
18 Gupta
(iv) Finally , let us assumethat the main conventions and facts about
" up" and other related subjectsare common knowledge. All membersof
the community are (and are recognizedto be) authorities of equal stand-
ing on these subjects.2 This assumption, like the previous one, removes
merely extraneousfactors from our deliberations. We lose nothing essen-
tial by making it .
The question before us is how to think about the meaningof sentences
such as 'a is up above b' in the community's language. It will be necessary
to address also the parallel question about the contents of speechacts
(e.g., assertions) and of attitudes (e.g., beliefs) that the speechactsexpress.
The meaning of a sentencewill be assumedto be fixed; it will not vary
from context to context. But the content that a sentenceis used to express
cannot be assumedto be fixed, and I shall explore both possibilities with
respectto it . In one group of theories I shall consider- namely, the abso-
lute theories- content will remain fixed through all contexts. Thesetheo-
ries will identify meaning with content. In the other group of theories I
shall consider- namely, the relativistic theories- content will vary with
context. These theories will draw a categorial distinction betweenmean-
ing and content.
The concept of meaning is called upon in current philosophy of lan-
guage and mind to servemany functions. Thesefunctions are so diverse
that one may be excusedfor thinking that no concept can servethem all,
that different notions of meaning are neededfor different kinds of ends.
The notion- or aspect- of meaning of interest here, I should stress, is
one that yields a true/false distinction (or something similar such as the
warranted/unwarranted distinction). The account of meaning (and con-
tent) should yield a satisfactory assessment of speechacts and of practices
found in the community. The account should provide a way of separating
those assertionsthat are true (or warranted) from those that are false (or
unwarranted). And it should provide a way of separatingthose inferential
practices that are sound (or adequate) from those that are unsound (or
inadequate).
2.2 Conceptual
-RoleSemantics
a linguistic element is- or is constructed out of- what the item repre-
sentsor would representin various contextsand possiblesituations. Thus,
on this approach, the meaning of a proper name (e.g., 'Socrates') might be
identified with the referent of the name (the man Socrates)3 and the
meaning of a predicate F might be identified with the property F repre-
sents. The vocabulary this approach favors for the assessmentof speech
acts is that of the true and the false. An assertion of 'Socratesis F ', for
example, is evaluated as true if Socrateshas the property representedby
F; otherwise, the assertionis evaluatedas false.
The second, conceptual-role, approach attempts to explain meaning via
the rules governing the proper use of language. On this approach, the
meaning of a linguistic element is given by the rules that specify the ele-
ment's conceptual role in the linguistic system. Thus, on this approach,
the meaning of a predicate F might be given by rules that state the con-
ditions under which predications of F are warranted (" F-introduction "
rules) and by rules that state the conclusions, both discursiveand practi-
cal, that may be basedon thesepredications (" F-elimination" rules).4 The
vocabulary this approach favors for the assessmentof speechacts is that
of the warranted and the unwarranted. An assertion of 'Socratesis F ',
for example, is evaluatedas warranted, if the conditions under which the
assertion is made are of the kind laid out in the F-introduction rules;
otherwise, the assertionis evaluatedas unwarranted.s
The two approachesto meaning rest on vastly different pictures of lan-
guage. Still, the assessmentof speechacts they yield are similar: the true/
false distinction coincides with the warranted/unwarranted distinction
over a large domain. This is not surprising, for both the language-
world relations of the representational approach and the introduction-
elimination rules of the conceptual-role approach have their foundations
in the actual use of language. Over " decidable" assertions(i.e., assertions
whosetruth or falsity can be settledby the usersof the language), the two
approachesaim to yield the same verdicts. The debate betweenthe two
approachescenters on the " undecidable" assertions. Here the language-
world relations of the representationalapproach may yield an assessment
whereasthe introduction-elimination rules of the conceptual-role approach
may fail to do 80.6
Although they illuminate much about language, the two approachesdo
not yield a solution to the problem of meaning before us. This is easiestto
show for the conceptual-role approach. This approach takes the meaning
of 'up' to be given by the rules governing its use- rules such as the per-
20 Gupta
b are objects such that the direction of the ray ba is epistemically accessi
-
ble to the community . The near spherical shape of the earth ensures that
~
objects c and d can be found (or placed) so that the direction of the ray dc
~
is the same as that of the ray ba and , furthermore , the perceptual criterion
for 'c is up above d ' is satisfied. The conceptual criterion now yields that
the assertion of 'a is up above b' is warranted . Similarly , the conceptual
criterion can be made to yield that the denial of 'a is up above b' is war - ~
not the same as that of the ray ba and , furthennore , the assertion of ' e is
Figure2.3
Meaning and Misconceptions 21
clined individuals to locate Vishnu in the night sky . Now , if the direction
of the ray from Chandra to Vishnu is in fact the same as that of the local
warranted ( or true ).
Incoherence in conceptual rules , then , does not erase the true / false
2 .3 Representational Semantics
Let us now turn to the representational approach . The key question here
- one to which it is difficult to find a good answer - is what relation ' up '
This suggestion respects the conceptual criterion , but it neglects the per -
tions ; for instance , it yields that A ' s assertion in the lamp example is false
and B ' s assertion true . 9
x bears S to y iff the straight line joining x and y passes through the
center of the earth 0 and the ray Y; points away from 0 ( equivalently ,
One response to these difficulties is to insist that ' up ' represents Sand
that the troublesome phenomena can be explained away . But the explan -
various other relations - that constitutes the proper semantics for ' up ' .
Meaning and Misconceptions
23
There must be something about the use of 'up ' that makes S the proper
interpretation , but our example provides nothing to distinguish it as
proper . (2) An explanation has to be provided how certain sentences
evaluated as false by the proposed semantics (e.g., the astronomers ' pre-
diction ) are nonetheless good guides for action - whereas their true neg-
ations are poor guides. (3) This explanation will have to be quite different
from the explanation given for those more straightforward cases in which
sentences deemed true by the semantics are good guides for action . An
account has to be given of this difference in the two explanations . Why
are certain instancesof successfullinguistic behavior explainedin one way
and others in a completely cliffe' ent way ?
(iii ) Suppose it is said that '1I.p ' represents the conjunctive relation R &
S , where
This suggestion lands us in an " error theory " for 'up' : nearly all assertions
of the form " x is up above y " are evaluated as false; only if a and bare
collinear with the mountain peak p and the geostationary satellite s (see
figure 2.2) can the assertion " a is up above b" be true . Thus , the theory
fails in the same way that the conceptual -role approach failed : it does not
yield a significant true / false distinction . (This kind of difficulty attaches, it
seems to me , to all error theories . Hartry Field and J . L . Mackie are well
known for their advocacy of error theories for , respectively , mathematics
and ethics (see Field 1980; Mackie 1977) . Field regards mathematical
statements to be untrue and Mackie takes the same view of ethical claims .
However , even if all the premises on which Field and Mackie base their
views are granted - principally , that mathematical statements are bur -
dened with an unacceptable Platonism and ethical statements with an
unacceptable claim to objectivity - their error theories will remain un -
acceptable until these theories are shown to yield a significant true / false
distinction .)
(iv ) Suppose it is said that 'up ' is ambiguous between Rand S. This is
also unsatisfactory . First , the postulated ambiguity is not discoverable by
the community members through reflection on their language . Second, R
and S are plausible candidates for the semantics of 'up ' in only a few of its
uses; other uses demand other relations . Hence, a manyfold ambiguity in
'up ' will have to be postulated - something that is plainly unattractive .
(v) Suppose the idea of indeterminacy is tried in place of ambiguity .
The suggestion now is that the semantics of 'up ' is indeterminate , that 'up '
24 Gupta
this is not an improvement over earlier ideas . It implies that virtually all
assertions of the form " x is up above y " are neither true nor false . We are
Let us note , finally , that this and the previous difficulties are not over -
come by the idea that we assign truth - conditions to ' a is up above b '
all uses of ' a is up above b ' to have the same content irrespective of the
Perhaps the most natural way of relativizing content here is to view ' up '
course , much as it supplies such elements as speaker and time for the
interpretations of ' I ' and ' now ' . We can use the location to define " the
the ray ol determined by the center of the earth 0 and the location l supplied
by the context c . And we can say that , in a context c , ' up ' represents the
relation T c , where
to c .
On this view , the relation represented by ' up ' is determined by both the
perceptual and the conceptual criteria governing ' up ' , but the application
location yields its own standard up direction and its own distinctive
b ' and the meaning of ' a is up above b ' . The content expressed by ' a is up
above b ' varies from context to context , but the meaning of ' a is up above
b ' does not vary . Further , the content can - but the meaning cannot - be
evaluated as true or false . One can think of the content expressed by ' a is
of ' a ' and ' b ' and the relation represented by ' up ' in the context c . And ,
following David Kaplan , one can think of the meaning of ' a is up above
such as 'A believes that the broken lamp is up above the stove ' are simi -
larly incomplete . But this plainly does not fit the facts . It is a plausible
principle governing belief that the content of a belief is the content of any
expression in his assertions of ' The broken lamp is up above the stove '.
So the indexical view implies that the content of A 's belief changes as
A moves from location to location . This yields the undesirable result that
persistence of A ' s belief " Here is Mooresville " when he has long left the
town behind on Route 67 . 11
The essential problem with the indexical view , then , is the same as that
with the absolute views considered earlier . The indexical view finds only
error where there is in fact much truth , and only fallacy where there is in
2 .4 Conceptual Disengagement
Let us gather together what we should accept from the theories consid -
ered above . First , we should accept the absolutist idea that 'a is up above
tional attitudes such as 'X believes that a is up above b ' and 'X desires that
follows that we should accept also that ' up above ' expresses a binary
should concede to the absolutist that , in one sense , the proposition " a is
up above b " is not true or even perhaps truth - apt . 13 That is , in one sense ,
all assertions of the form " x is up above y " are infected with error . Third ,
relativistic ideas .
The difficulties we have had in making sense of the " up / down " dis -
course have their source , it seems to me , in the idea that the elements of
Meaning and Misconceptions
27
impossible to see how an assertion such as " The broken lamp is up above
the stove" could be true . For the assertion conceptually implies numerous
claims that are plainly false- for example , " The direction of the ray that
begins at the stove and goes through the broken lamp is the Standard
Up .,,14 The same holds of assertions of the form " x is up above y " gen-
erally . So the absolute approach lands us in an error theory for the dis-
course. We can avoid the error theory by shifting to the relativistic
approach . But matters do not improve if we stick with the idea of rigid
conceptual connections . For we are now forced to deny that sentences
containing 'up ' have problematic conceptual connections and , thus , that
there is conceptual incoherence in " up ." The indexical theory considered
above goes so far in this direction as to say that the sense of ' up ' , like that
of 'he' , is not rich enough to yield assertible contents ; some contextual
information must be supplied before sentences containing 'up ' express
complete propositions . But to say this is to recoil from the phenomenon
confronting us to the opposite extreme . The fact is that the sense of 'up ' is
not at all poor like that of the indexicals . The sense is actually far too
rich - so rich that it constitutes a problem . If we stick with the idea of
rigid conceptual connections , we are confined to unpalatable choices:
error theory and the denial of the phenomena at hand .
Not all conceptual connections are relevant - not all are invoked , not
all come into play - in every use of language . This is the lesson we should
draw from the lamp example . Given the way the assertion " The broken
lamp is up above the stove" is used, and is expected to be used, the rele-
vant conceptual component is that provided by the perceptual criterion
for 'up ' . The noffi1al use of the sentence might be something like this : the
sentence is passed from person to person till it reaches a repairman , who
then uses it to perceptually locate the lamp he will repair . Given that this
is how the sentence is used, assertions of 'The broken lamp is up above
the stove' are good and fruitful guides to action - they are true . Asser-
tions of the negation are poor and misleading guides to action - they are
false. This assessment of truth -value is one at which the community
members themselves will arrive once they know the relevant facts . And
the assessment would survive any unmasking of their misconception .
28 Gupta
Even a god with a sweeping and eternal view of the world would concur
with their assessment. In short , the assessment is neither parochial , nor
fleeting , nor unstable . It is one that an account of meaning needs to
respect and accommodate .
Every assertion of the form " x is up above y " contains error . The as-
sertion of the sentence 'The broken lamp is up above the stove' can be
used, it has to be conceded, in ways that conform to conceptual rules but
lead to error . One , less serious , kind of error occurs in idle uses - when ,
for example , one derives from the lamp sentence the false claim that
the direction of the ray that goes from the stove to the broken lamp is the
Standard Up . If this derivation does not materially affect the use of the
lamp sentence, then it is idle .15 A more serious kind of error is also pos-
sible, however . Suppose, for example , that the repairman were to use the
assertion in the following way : The repairman goes on an expedition to
find the direction called 'the Standard Up ' . Then through elaborate
engineering he somehow constructs a pointer at the stove that points in this
direction . Finally , he uses the pointer to locate the lamp he will repair . If
he were to do all this , he might uncover a deep misconception in his
community but he would not find his way to the right lamp . He would
have been misled by the sign. This hypothetical way of using the sign is
utterly eccentric , however .16 And its existence should not call into ques-
tion the idea that the assertion " The broken lamp is up above the stove"
is , in one sense , true .
An analogy will help make this point clear . Suppose we have a flawed
map of a city . The map , let us say, accurately depicts the streets in the
center of the city , but is inaccurate regarding some streets that lie on the
periphery . Plainly , despite the errors , the map remains a good and true
instrument for navigating through the city center . This is so even though
the map could mislead one if it is used to plan an eccentric roundabout
route from one city -center street to another . Similarly , many conceptual
paths issue from 'The broken lamp is up above the stove'; one can use this
sign in many ways to guide one's actions . But some ways of using it are
(in certain situations ) salient and ordinary , whereas some other ways
- of
using it are extraordinary and eccentric . The eccentric uses are valid and ,
indeed, important : they can expose fundamental flaws in our conceptions .
Nonetheless , their possibility leaves intact the need for a distinction be-
tween truth and falsehood that respects actual practice .! 7
As noted above , not all conceptual connections come into play in all
uses of language . This conceptual disengagement or isolation may occur
Meaning and Misconceptions
29
even when we are not explicit- or even clear- about its extent or exis-
tence. Sometimes, however, conceptual disengagementresults becauseof
an explicit stipulation on our part. Consider, for example, our use of the
notion of the celestial sphere- a notion that is a product of an ingenious
synthesisof agesof ancient astronomical observations. We find this notion
useful- even indispensablein some contexts- though we recognizeit to
rest on a deeperror. Our use of the notion is in someways very similar to
that of the ancients: we follow them in speaking of certain parts of the
sphereas constituting the constellationsof the zodiac; we speakof the sun
as being in Capricorn one month and Aquarius another; we infer the on-
set of spring when we seethat the sun has a certain position in the zodiac;
and so on. But we disengageall this talk from various other parts of our
discourse: we no longer infer motion from variation of position; we no
longer derive the true distance betweenstars from their (apparent) loca-
tion on the sphere; we no longer think of the sphereas having a definite
volume; and so on. A farmer in ancient times might have looked at the
starsin the westernnight sky somechilly night and have said, " The sun is
in Pisces; spring will be here soon." A modern child might do the same.
The farmer's assertionis in one senseerroneous- the sensein which it is
seenas fully engagedwith the ancients' conception of the zodiac. But in
another sense - one in which we are concernedwith how the assertionis
used in the farming community- the assertion might be as true as the
child's. The child is explicit about the disengagement ; the farmer is not.
Nonetheless, the farmer's assertion, like the child's, can be assessedas
true and can report a hard fact about the world .
Our language is not a rigid system. Its terms do not stand in fixed
interlocking conceptual connectionswith each other. Engagementof our
conceptsis important for both theoretical and practical purposes. But so
also, I want to stress, is disengagement. Only if we keep thesedual possi-
bilities- the possibility of engagementand of disengagement - firmly in
mind can we make senseof how our languagecan function evenwhen it is
infected with deepmisconceptions.
2.5 Frames
features of context. The content, in turn, fixes, in light of the facts, the
truth-value of the assertion. Thus, for example, the sentence'She is in
Indianapolis' has a certain meaning. SupposeI use the sentenceto make
an assertion and that the context of use suppliesa person- say, MJ- as
the denotation of 'she' and 24 January 1997as the time referencefor the
present tense. This contextual information together with the meaning of
'She is in Indianapolis' fixes the content of my assertionto be that MJ is
in Indianapolis on 24 January 1997. In view of the fact that MJ is actually
in Bloomington on 24 January 1997, the content fixes the truth -value of
my assertion to be the False. We can schematizethis familiar way of
thinking about meaning thus:
(Meaning + Context) Fixes =;.. Content;
(Content+ The World) Fixes =}- Assessmentof truth-value.
Theories of meaning often use these schematain reverseto " solve" for
meaning. Thus, the secondschemais used to derive the idea that content
is a function that maps worlds to truth-values. And the first schemais
used to derive the idea that meaning is a function that maps (relevant)
contextual information to content.
This familiar way of thinking about meaning needsa little fine-tuning if
it is to fit the phenomenahighlighted above. We need to distinguish first
of all two types of assessment , which we shall call 'assessmentof absolute
truth-value' and 'assessmentof effective truth -value' . We encountered
instancesof these types in the previous section. The assessmentof A 's
assertion, " The broken lamp is up above the stove," as erroneous is an
assessmentof its absolutetruth-value. The other assessment , namely, that
A 's assertionis true, is an assessmentof its effectivetruth -value. We need
to distinguish also two types of content that are correlated with these
assessments : absolute content and effective content. Absolute content is
simply the old and familiar content under a new name. This content takes
into account all the conceptual connectionsof an assertionand provides
the basis for the assessmentof absolute truth -value. Effective content, on
the other hand, takes into account the conceptual engagementsand dis-
engagementsthat are in effect and provides the basisfor an assessmentof
effectivetruth -value. 18Absolute content captureswhat an act of assertion
is committed to; effectivecontent capturesthe content that is in play .
The two types of assessmenthave their own distinctive meaning-truth
schemata. The version for absolute assessmentparallels the original ver-
sion closely:
Meaning and Misconceptions 31
value .
The version of the schemata for effective assessment has to be a little more
and this something else I shall call ' frame ' . Under this terminology , the
value .
frames differ .
First , let us note that contexts are local but frames are not . Contexts
that is provided by the local speech situation . 19 But this local sort of
information will not suffice to fix effective content . For this we need ,
spread across uses of language . Frames , then , are not local in that they
for the denotations , say , of the personal pronouns are liable to shift
Context is highly local , language is global , and frame lies in between the
two .
example of the repairman and how he locates the broken lamp. Room-
mate A determines the position of the broken lamp perceptually and
arrives at the judgment that the broken lamp is up above the stove. He
utters the words 'The broken lamp is up above the stove' to inform others
of the location of the lamp. These words (or their variants) are passed
from mouth to mouth till they reach the repairman, who uses them to
perceptually locate the lamp to be repaired. The sentence'The broken
lamp is up abovethe stove', we have seen, cannot be assigneddeterminate
truth-conditions. However, relative to the pattern of useexemplified, rela-
tive to the frame of use, we may be able to assign 'up above' a definite
relation- perhapsthe relation S defined in section2.3- and the sentence
determinatetruth -conditions. Once we keep the frame fixed, we can rea-
sonably view A 's perceptual interaction with the world as providing A
with information about the relative positions of the lamp and the stove,
information that he passes to the repairman via the various inter-
mediaries. Absolutely speaking, 'up' doesnot representany relation, but
relative to a frame, when the use of 'up' is disengagedfrom some of the
conceptual elements, it may well representa definite relation. Disengage-
ment within the conceptual systemcan help bring about engagementwith
the world .
The successof our linguistic and conceptual practices proves at most
that our assertionshave true effectivecontents. That is, it proves at most
that within their respectiveframes our assertionshook on to the world .
But from this we cannot conclude that our assertionshave true absolute
contents and that our discourse pictures the world . Such a conclusion
would follow only if our linguistic and conceptual practicesconstituted a
monolithic whole, unfragmented into multiple frames. Mere successof
our practicesdoesnot establishthe requisite unity in our thought.
The proposal, then, is to combine nonrepresentationalismand engage-
ment in the following way. We allow a discourse to be nonrepre-
sentational in that the absolute contents expressedby its statementsare
problematic- perhapsthey all contain error; perhapsthey are ill defined.
But we allow the discourseto engagewith the world in that much (per-
haps most) of the discourseis viewed as separableunder severalframes.
Relative to theseframes, the statementsof the discoursehave (effective)
contentsthat can be assessed for truth and falsehood.
This combination of nonrepresentationalismand engagementavoids
some of the weaknessesof both realism and antirealism. Antirealism is
prone to view our theory construction as being so much storytelling;
36 Gupta
realism , on the other hand , is prone to view it as so much revealed truth .
Neither tendency is acceptable- except insofar as it provides a counter to
the other . Realists are correct to insist that there is a vast difference
between fictional discourse and theoretical discourse . Fictional discourse
does not - but theoretical discourse does - engage with the world .25
Unlike fictional discourse, a discarded scientific theory - even one that
proves to be deeply erroneous , and one for which we are unable to pro -
vide a representational semantics- generates useful frames and true effec-
tive contents . ( Example : " Don 't touch that . It has high caloric content ." )26
Indeed , sometimes a discarded theory proves such a convenience within
certain frames that we allow its continued use, with the proviso that
the use shall not extend beyond those frames (as in the celestial sphere
example given above). I suspect that this kind of fragmented use is more
prevalent in our language than we realize .
Antirealists , on the other hand , are correct to insist that our present
theoretical terms do not have a special status over those of the earlier
scientists, prophets , and myth -makers : there is little reason to count as
representational our present-day theoretical terms while denying this
status to the terms of the earlier , discarded theories . Our evidence and our
situation in the world are not essentially different from those of our an-
cestors. Our evidence is not so comprehensive , nor our understanding so
deep and clear , that we can rule out the possibility that we ourselves suffer
from deep misconceptions . The perennial problems of philosophy and the
irresistible force of the skeptical arguments stand witness to the fragmen -
tation in our understanding and the narrowness of our evidence. 27
Conceptual disengagement and fragmentation of thought are essential
for creatures such as we are. Had God (or evolution ) equipped us with the
right set of concepts once and for all , had the overall structure of the
world been somehow revealed to us (as Plato and Descartes thought ), had
our inquiries only the simple goal of filling in the mere details in a given , a
priori , picture of the world - had our epistemic position been so fortu -
nate, disengagement and fragmentation might have had no place in the
workings of our language and thought . But , unfortunately , our epistemic
position is a precarious one. We do not approach the task of under -
standing the world with perfect ready -made tools in our hands . We
approach the task bare-handed; we need to make the tools, including the
tools needed to make the tools themselves. We need to make (or discover )
the system of concepts needed to conceptualize the detailed facts about
the world , facts that are essential to our well -being . However , we cannot
Meaning and Misconceptions 37
Notes
1. The importance of conversationalmaxims for the study of languagewas first
observedby Paul Grice (seeGrice 1989).
2. So I wish to set aside what Hilary Putnam calls 'the division of linguistic labor '
(see Putnam 1975 ) .
3. And it is so identified by a currently popular theory .
4. The version of conceptual -role semantics I shall be working with is due to
Wilfrid Sellars and Robert Brandom (see Sellars 1953, 1974; Brandom 1994) . Two
distinctive features of the Sellars-Brandom semantics are worth noting . First , it
explains meaning and content in terms of inferential role , as opposed to , say,
functional role in the user's psychology (cf . Harman 1982) . Second, it understands
inferential role to include role in substantive , material inferences, not merely for -
mal inferences .
5. Note that the conceptual -role approach uses an absolute notion of " warrant ."
This notion is connected to , but it is not identical with , the notion " warranted
given that the language user is in such-and-such epistemic situation ." The con -
nection between the two notions is roughly as follows : P is warranted in the
absolute sense if and only if P would be warranted by the rules of language under
idealized epistemic conditions .
6. I follow Michael Dummett jn seeing the primary disagreement between the
representational approach and its rivals to be over undecidable sentences (see
Dummett 1978, 1993) .
7 . Let me stress that the sense in which ' ~ Tarrant ' is used here is not that of per -
sonal warrant . It does not mean " being warranted given one' s epistemic situa -
tion . " In this latter sense , it could well be that both the assertions of A and Bare
warranted - or that neither of them is .
8. Here and below , I make several simplifying assumptions - for example , that
objects can be treated as if they were points and that 'up ' is not vague . Further , I
38 Gupta
suppress the relativity of 'up ' to time . (Some of the complexities of our actual uses
of 'up ' are detailed in Jackendoff 1996.)
9. Assuming , as I shall , that A 's and B 's kitchen is not on the mountain peak p
(figure 2.2) .
10. I am assuming , of course, that there are no other reasons to call into question
A ' s authority on this matter .
11. Another way of putting the difficulty is this : the wish of a person , X , that a be
up above b can be fulfilled only by adjusting the positions of a and b, not by
moving X to a place where the standard up is the direction of ~ !
12. The idea that 'a is up above b' expresses a proposition and 'up above ' a binary
concept will meet resistance from the Platonist and from the Nominalist . These
new entities will seem to the Platonist to be unworthy of a place in the realm of
Platonic Heaven ; to the Nominalist they will seem unworthy of a place even in the
realm of ordinary existence. In response, it may be observed to the Platonist that
the new entities exemplify an important virtue : they do real work in our concep-
tual scheme . Furthermore , whatever flaws may be found in these entities , the same
flaws (and many more ) are found reflected in Truth , whose place in Platonic
Heaven is unquestioned . To the Nominalist it may be observed that the new enti -
ties are not going to make their programs any more difficult to execute. Any
scheme they devise that succeeds in eliminating the familiar abstract entities will
succeed in eliminating the new , unfamiliar ones as well .
13. Propositions are defined in the literature in two nonequivalent ways . Some-
times they are defined as the objects of attitudes such as belief and desire;
sometimes they are defined as objects that are truth -apt . The first definition puts
propositions closer to the representings ; the second puts them closer to the repre-
senteds. I have chosen above to follow the first definition , but the choice is purely
terminological . The important point is that the two definitions define distinct
notions . Which notion ends up winning the label 'proposition ' is not at all
important .
14. Recall we are assuming that the kitchen is not located on the mountain peak p
(see figure 2.2).
15. Another sort of idle use is worth noting . Suppose roommate A informs the
repairman of the location of the lamp by saying ,
(i) The direction of the ray that goes from the stove to the broken lamp is the
Standard Up .
The repairman naturally uses (i) to infer that
(ii ) The broken lamp is up above the stove,
and proceeds in his usual way to locate the lamp to be repaired . The use of (i) is
not now idle , for it informs the repairman of the lamp 's location . But the detour
via directions contained in (i) is idle . For A arrives at (i) through (ii ), and he relies
on the repairman to return to (ii ) from the assertion of (i) . ( This sort of idle detour
via the theoretical is also witnessed in a college cafeteria when a student employee
marks the water container 'H2O '.)
Meaning and Misconceptions
39
16. More eccentric than if at a dinner party a guest should pullout a microscope
to examine the contents of her plate before declaring that the host had served peas.
Deep errors in our botanical theories might be revealed by this chance examina -
tion, but a dinner party is not the time and place to explore the possibility.
17. This conclusion is bolstered by the fact that we, who are aware of the mis -
conception , are willing to ascribe knowledge that the broken lamp is up above the
stove. We would explain some of the successes of the community members in
terms of their possession, and some of their failures in terms of their lack , of this
knowledge . Since knowledge implies truth , it follows that we recognize that there
is a sense in which the assertion that the broken lamp is up above the stove is true .
18 . I use the word ' effective ' here to indicate that the notions of truth - value and
content under discussion serve to explain the practical effectiveness of language .
This is not the place to develop a precise account of effective contents . For the
purposes of this chapter , effective contents can be thought of as being of the same
generaltype as absolute contents. Whether one favors the idea that absolute con-
tents are conceptualroles, or the idea that they are setsof possibleworlds, or that
they are Russellian structured entities , one can take a parallel view of effective
contents . Note that absolute and effective contents , though they can formally be
similar , are, in general , materially different . For example , if content is understood
as conceptual role , effective content will be restricted conceptual role . For another
example , if content is understood as a set of possible worlds , the effective and
absolute contents of an assertion will often be given by different sets of possible
worlds .
19. For a good account of information that might be supplied by context , and
how it might evolve in the course of conversation , see Lewis 1979.
20. Hence , the meaning -truth schemata for effective truth should not be used to
" solve" for meaning , if we wish to preserve a connection between meaning and
understanding .
21. The importance of separating factors that help explain understanding from
those that help explain the workings of language has been stressed by Mark Wilson
( see Wilson 1994, forthcoming a,b) .
22. The literature generated by these debates is vast (see Field 1980; Mackie
1977; Leplin 1984; Sayre-McCord 1988; Devitt 1991 and the works cited there) .
Jackendoff 1991 is a valuable contribution to the realism debate for intentional
discourse . Maddy 1990 and Wright 1992 contain illuminating discussions of sev-
eral aspects of the debates .
23. This claim needs qualification . First , it should be understood to be restricted
to names and predicates that are essential to the discourse . A realism with respect
to physics may be willing to allow that some of the names and predicates found in
physical discourse (e.g., arithmetical ones) fail to refer . Second, the names and
predicates that are essential may not be discernible simply from the surface
grammar of the discourse ; it may be necessary to reveal the deeper logical form of
the discourse . Third , on some varieties of realism , language -world relations count
as representationalif statementsare correlated with states of affairs, bypassing
40 Gupta
References
Grice, P. (1989
). Studiesin thewayof words.Cambridge
, MA : HarvardUniversity
Press
.
Harman, G. (1982 ). Conceptualrole semantics . Notre DameJournalof Formal
Logic, 23, 242- 256.
Jackendoff , R. (1991). Theproblemof reality. Noils, 25, 411- 433.
Jackendoff , R. (1996 ). The architectureof the linguistic-spatial interface
. In
P. Bloom, M. Peterson , L. Nadel, and M. Garrett (Eds.), Languageand space
(pp. 1- 30). Cambridge , MA : MIT Press .
Leplin, J. (Ed.). (1984). Scientificrealism
. BerkeleyandLosAngeles : Universityof
CaliforniaPress .
Lewis, D. (1979 ). Scorekeeping in a languagegame. Journal of Philosophical
Logic, 8, 339- 359.
Mackie, J. L. (1977 ). Ethics: Inventingright andwrong. London: Penguin .
Maddy, P. (1990 ). Realismin mathematics . Oxford: ClarendonPress.
Putnam, H. (1975 ). Mind, language , and reality: Philosophicalpapers, vol. 2.
Cambridge : CambridgeUniversityPress .
Putnam, H. (1978 ). Meaningandthemoralsciences . London: Routledge& Kegan
Paul.
Sayre-McCord, G. (Ed.). (1988 ). Essayson moral realism. Ithaca, NY: Cornell
UniversityPress .
Sellars, W. (1953 ). Inferenceandmeaning . Mind, 62, 313- 338.
Sellars, W. (1974 ). Meaningandfunctionalclassification . Synthese
, 27, 417- 437.
Wilson, M . (1994 ). Canwetrust logicalform? Journalof Philosophy , 91, 519- 544.
Wilson, M. (Forthcominga). Inferenceandcorrelationaltruth.
Wilson, M. (Forthcomingb). Physicastint, non leguntur.
Wright, C. (1992 ). Truth and objectivity
. Cambridge , MA : Harvard University
Press.
Chapter .L 3
Mathematics
For some years , I have been pursuing a program I call the structuralist
Samuel Eilenberg and Saunders Mac Lane about fifty years ago ( Eilen -
berg and Mac Lane 1945 ) . William Lawvere ' s work ( e . g . , Lawvere 1969 )
and Lawvere ' s and Myles Tierney ' s top os theory ( Lawvere 1971 ) , subjects
the distinguishing features of SFM are , first , that its aims are global , en -
The author ' s research is supported by Canada ' s Natural Sciences and Engineering
Research Council and Quebec ' s Fonds pour la formation de chercheurs et l ' aide a
la recherche .
Reyes , and Marek Zawadowski for the conversations they had with me about the
subject of this chapter . The chapter is based on a talk that I gave in the Depart -
ment of Philosophy at McGill University in the fall of 1994 . I also thank Ray
John Macnamara was , for many years , a constant source of inspiration and
discourse behind the foffi1al theory . It turns out that the latter articulation
involves a fairly novel mathematical metatheory .
There is a structuralist philosophy of mathematics behind the program
of SFM . In this chapter , my aim is to make an initial contribution to the
statement of this philosophy . This structuralism , it seems to me, is quite
different from the structuralism found in the literature of the philosophy
of mathematics . The basis of this difference is , of course . the almost total
In his famous 1965 paper , " What Numbers Could Not Be ," Paul
Benaceraff describes two children , Ernie and Johnny , " sons of militant
logicists ," who , before learning about numbers , how to count , and so
on, had been instructed in set theory in the standard Zermelo - F raenkel
formulation . After that instruction , the parents " needed only to point out
what aspect or part of what the children already knew , under other
names, was what ordinary people called numbers " (p . 48). Benaceraff
goes on to describe how this pointing out took place in the case of Ernie ;
but he temporarily and cleverly conceals what actually took place in the
process. The story looks like the familiar one, the one of defining the
natural numbers as the finite von Neumann ordinals , and defining zero
and the successor operation in the familiar ways- the one we teach now -
adays in set theory courses. As Benaceraff puts it :
To recapitulate : It was necessary [for a proper education in arithmetic ] ( 1) to give
definitions of " 1 " , " number " , and " successor " , and " + " , " x " , and so forth , on
the basis of which the laws of arithmetic could be derived ; (2) explain the " extra -
mathematical " uses of numbers , the principal one being counting - thereby in -
troducing the concept of cardinality and cardinal number . I trust that both were
done satisfactorily , that the preceding [description of Ernie ' s education ] contains
all the elements of a correct account , albeit somewhat incompletely . (p . 54)
Delighted with what they had learned , they started proving theorems about num -
bers . Comparing notes , they soon became aware that something was wrong , for a
dispute immediately ensued about whether or not 3 belonged to 17 . Ernie said that
it did , Johnny that it did not . Attempts to settle this by asking ordinary folk ( who
had been dealing with numbers as numbers for a long time ) understandably
brought only blank stares . ( p . 54 )
At this point in the story , we learn what exactly happened in the respective
numbers are ( Johnny ) von Neumann ordinals . Johnny , on the other hand ,
was told that they are the ( Ernie ) Zermelo numerals ; that is , zero is the
empty set , and the successor of n is { n } , the singleton whose unique ele -
ment is n .
But if , as I think we agreed , the account of the previous section [ in which the set -
theoretic reconstruction of the concept of number was related , albeit with what the
numbers and their operations actually were left unspecified ] was correct - not only
as far as it went but correct in that it contained conditions which were both nec -
essary and sufficient for any correct account of the phenomena under discussion ,
then the fact that they disagree which particular sets the numbers are is fatal to the
Later :
is obviously such a predicate , but that is something else than to say that
seventeen is such a predicate ) . He then summarizes :
If numbers are sets, then they must be particular sets, for each set is somepartic-
ular set. But if the number 3 is really one set rather than another , it must be pos-
sible to give some cogent reason for thinking so; for the position that this is an
unknowable truth is hardly tenable . . . . There is no way connected with the refer -
ence of number words which will allow us to choose among them , for the accounts
differ at places where there is no connection whatever between features of the
accounts and our uses of the words in question. . . . [ AJnyfeature of an account that
identifies 3 with a set is a superfluous one, and therefore , 3 and its fellow numbers
could not be sets at all . ( p . 62)
Benaceraff emphasizes that for the purposes of explication , one may very
well wish to temporarily identify numbers with particular sets and show
that we can do with the sets what we now do with numbers . However , as
he says :
It should be clear by now that I want to turn the issue at hand into one
concerning language , from the ostensible one that is about ontology . True ;
I think the issue is not what numbers are , but what the nature of numbers
is , nature that can only be revealed in the language of the practice dealing
with numbers . The question " What are numbers ? " is inherently defective .
provide ; it presumes that we can point out a domain of things that are
already familiar and can proceed to narrow down that domain to arrive at
the precise domain of the numbers . The question " What are numbers ? "
has a reductionist bias . We will not likely get to know the numbers by
coming to see that they are just like some other things that we already
know ; it is quite possible that they are unique in their essential nature .
What that nature is , is the good question . And , we then must realize , that
nature is to be found in the only tangible reality that contains the num -
3 .2 Structures
Let us get closer to the way mathematicians talk about , and use , numbers ;
in this instance , by " number " I mean " natural number " ( any of 0 , 1 , 2 , 3 ,
etc .) . I will invoke the " Ideal Mathematician " ( I . M .) , a creation of Philip
construct the " ideal belief " ( not necessarily the best belief ; see Davis and
( \ in E N . P ( n ) ) .
Structuralism in Mathematics 51
set, (say, t == { Q5} , but it does not have to be that); note that a mapping
from t to any set A is really the same as an element of that set, the element
which is the value at the unique element of t. The condition for (N , 0, S)
to be a Peano system is this : given any (A , a : t ~ A , 1 : A ~ A ) (thus , so
far , we have something that is " like " our system (N , 0, S)),
there is a unique function g : N - + A such that the diagram
0 s
t 1 N 1 N
i 0 190 19
t , A , A
a f
commutes .
For example , when we first apply S, and then g (on the right ), the effect is
the same as when we first apply g, and then f (this is the commutativity of
52 Makkai
the right - hand square ) ; also , the left vertical i denotes the one possible
function from t to t , the identity function . When we rewrite this in " alge -
braic notation , " we get this :
f (f (f ( . . . f ( a ) . . .) ) == In ( a ) ,
i i
nil
n - l
I . M . should now sit down and prove to his satisfaction that indeed , we
have an equivalent definition . Of course , he is allowed to use set theory ; it
is unlikely that he is unfamiliar with the needed tools .
This definition is nice for instance because it is more compact than the
traditional one . There is no talk about S being one - to - one and missing 0
in its range ; also , it is unifoffi1 in the sense of being " diagrammatic ,"
using sets and functions , but not properties ( subsets ) . But really , the nicest
thing about it is that it has a pattern . It looks like we can talk about a
0
19 19
A
0
~ A
a
f
Q. You said that you fixed any Peano system for the purposes of
" number ." Does it not matter which one you have chosen ? To put it dif -
ferently, suppose you are probing some property P(n) of the natural
numbers , and you are not sure whether the property is universally true or
not of numbers . You discover that it is indeed true in your chosen system .
How do you know that it would have turned out to be true if you had
picked another Peano system as your numbers ?
L M . Aha ! Good question . Well , the answer is simple . If I have dis-
covered that the natural numbers have that property you have in mind ,
then I must have inferred this on the basis of the general principles of
mathematics (set theory if you wish ), and on the basis of the definition of
" Peano system" ; as I say, I make a point when I reason about numbers of
not using anything else than the defining properties of " Peano system."
Q. But wait ; does everybody make such a commitment ? Maybe I ex-
plicitly refuse to make such a commitment ; I simply take my system of
natural numbers , a Peano system , and by direct examination , mixed with
ingenuity , I see that in my system P (n) in fact holds for all n. I tell you
about this ; I describe to you how I directly examined my Peano system.
You said that you can do anything that I can do with numbers . Are you
sure that you can now also show that all n satisfy P (n) , given that in effect
you have committed yourself to using only methods of proof that apply to
all Peano systems ?
L M. How clever- that is a good question indeed . But there is an
important fact here: actually , any property that is verified in one Peano
system is going to be true in any other . More than that : any property
of any Peano system as a whole will also be' shared by any other Peano
system. Take the example that the underlying set of a Peano system
(the set of natural numbers , in anyone interpretation ) can be mapped in
one - to - one fashion into any infinite set . This is a fact ; but even if I did not
know that , but knew that it was true for one Peano system , I would know
that it was true for any other . The reason is that any two Peano systems
are isomorphic ; there is a one-to -one and onto mapping from one to the
other taking the zero of one to the zero of the other , and taking a pair that
is in the relation of one term 's being a successor of the other term into a
pair in the same relation in the other . Isomorphic structures share all
conceivable properties .
Q. That is indeed interesting . I can actually see why any two Peano
systems are isomorphic ; this is quite easy using Lawvere 's definition . We
54 Makkai
have a morphism from one to the other , and from the other to the one;
moreover , their composites are self-morphisms of the systems, and thus
they must be identities ; I really have an isomorphism , because I have an
invertible morphism ; great ! But how do you know that isomorphic struc-
tures share all properties ? I can see this holds for the one you just quoted ;
this is quite obvious . But why so in case of any conceivable property ?
Anyway , you cannot be quite right . Look : suppose you take the property
that the empty set Q5is an element of the Peano system. This is clearly not
going to be shared by all Peano systems; I can willfully make this both
true and false by simply exchanging elements, clearly not disturbing the
fact that I have a Peano system! Something is wrong .
1 M . No , no ! Of course, when I said " all conceivable properties ," I
meant " all meaningful properties ," " all properties of Peano systems as
Peano systems." Q5, being an element of the Peano system, is not a
meaningful property of Peano systems at all ; no sane person would con-
template such a property .
tures, and you can rigorously show that these properties are invariant
under isomorphism. The most basic of theselanguagesis first-order logic.
As Tarski has shown, we have a precisenotion of truth for sentencesof
first-order logic in structuresof the right kind (interpreting all the symbols
in the sentencein question), defined globally for the whole language of
first-order logic at once. When for instancewe were asking whether P(n)
held for all n, we A were askingAwhether the Peanosystem(N , 0, S) satisfied
.
a sentenceVnP(n), where P(n) is a first-order formula expressmgthe
property P(- ), of courseprovided that such a formula is available. As a
matter of fact, in most casesof interesting Ps it is not available; in most
cases, it would become available if we added new operations such as
addition and multiplication to the primitives of the structure (N , 0, S).
Now , the important point is that, with the help of the Tarski truth-
definition, there is a rigorous proof of the fact that properties given by
first-order sentencesare invariant under isomorphism; it is a proof by
induction on the complexity of the sentencein question. Thus, there is a
partial answerto the question " What are I . Mis meaningful properties?" ;
they include the first-order properties. It is true, however, that most
mathematically interesting properties of structures- and now I am talk-
ing about not just Peano systemsbut all the various structuresmathema-
ticians use: groups, rings, topological spaces, and so on- are in fact not
expressiblein first-order logic. The way out is that there are other, more
expressivelanguagesfor which the Tarskian way of defining truth is also
available; now the truth-definition may be more conspicuouslydependent
on set theory, but in fact, it was so dependentalready in the caseof first-
order logic. These languages include second-order logic, higher-order
logic, infinitary logics, logics with generalizedquantifiers. It turns out that
the proof that a property expressiblein any of these languagesis iso-
morphism invariant is a very straightforward structural induction on the
complexity of the expressioninvolved.
Q. May we then say that the idea of a " meaningful property of a struc-
ture" is ultimately an open-ended one; there is no uniform syntactical
criterion that describesall the meaningful properties that mathematicians
contemplate?
1 L . Yes, this is correct; there are large classesof explicitly described
properties that are meaningful, for which we indeed have a proof in
advancethat they are isomorphism invariant, but it seemsrather impos-
sible to give such a classthat would be all-encompassing .
56 Makkai
I . M . was urging the view that one does not have to assumethat terms
like 3, 17, 1010have absolutely fixed denotations; the latter can be made
dependent on a free choice of a structure of natural numbers, a Peano
system, in which the denotations then becomedetermined. It also seems
that this attitude toward denotation is the prevailing one in mathematics,
dealing as it does with definite descriptions of various entities- " the
monster-group," " the field of the real numbers," and so on- in a sys-
tematically ambiguousmanner. This may be so in mathematical practice,
but it is entirely possiblethat this way of behaving is necessarilya meta-
phorical one, and when it comesto the crunch of articulating a founda-
tion for mathematics, this ambiguity has to be given up. This would not
Structuralism in Mathematics 57
necessarily mean that one would have to adopt the precise foundations of
Zermelo -Fraenkel set theory , but it would show that something like that
system, with a single domain of well -individuated objects at its base, is
necessary, after all ; and in particular , it seems to me, it would answer our
question " Is it possible to articulate a language of mathematics in which
we talk about numbers as numbers ?" in the negative .
And indeed, there are many signs in mathematical practice suggesting
that ultimately it may be necessary to fix reference of terms unambiguously .
In " Complete Functors in Homology I " Max Kelly writes :
(The objects of a category have but a tenuous individuality ; 'the group 7L of
integers ' is not the same set of elements to different writers , or even to the same
writer in different contexts . In a sense it is only the isomorphism class that counts ;
and yet we must at any instant be considering a definite set of elements, in order
that we may sensibly talk of homomorphisms : a group is not the same thing as a
group type , because there are non -identical automorphisms . . . .) ( 1964, 722)
Well, what about an electronically stored copy of Blake's poem? You say,
" Of course, I meant that also in an extended senseof 'ordered set of
inscriptions.' " Can you be more explicit? You may resort to the formula
on the inside coversof books (" No part of this book shall be reproduced,
stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted by any means, electronic,
mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise. . ." ), in order to exhaust
all the possiblerepresentationsof the poem. But note the indefinitenessin
the italicized phrase " or otherwise" ; the practical people know that it is
impossible to foreseeall possibleways one may representthe poem, and
they want to forestall all (lucrative) representations.Trying to say that the
poem's essenceis somehow synonymous with the totality of its repre-
sentationsis wrong-headed, for two reasons, at least. One is that we know
perfectly now what the poem is, but we cannot know now all its repre-
sentations, not even the possibletypes of its representations. The other is
that one representationis perfectly enough for knowing what the poem is!
Then again, you will now say that referring to Blake's poem is just a
fat;on de parler; you can eliminate it from any context, in exchangefor
referencesto first-class objects. I doubt that; how do you do that when
I say, " I like Blake's poem 'The Chimney Sweeper'" ? Here we enter an
infinite, and familiar , controversy, involving behaviorism and the like.
Sufficeit to say that the correspondingquestion that we really care about,
the one concerning objects in mathematics, is answereddefinitively: we
know that, for instance, the presenceor absenceof the notion of natural
number doesmake a differencein our ability to prove theorems(a form of
G6del's incompleteness ). In other words, we cannot eliminate the notion
of natural number from contexts.
In the last two paragraphsI tried to show a bit what it would be like to
deny the existenceof " The Chimney Sweeper" as a poem. I think , how-
ever, the best reaction to the " philosophical question" of the existenceof
" The Chimney Sweeper" as a poem is that it is meaningless . There is no
mystery, we have everything in front of us; the question cannot seriously
imply a searchfor something temporarily unknown answeringa descrip-
tion, and it seemsthat how we answerthe question is largely arbitrary .
Before we probe matters along theselines a bit more, I want to suggest
that the question of the existenceof the system of the natural numbers
may be to a large extent similar and, as a consequence , meaningless .
Here you will quickly object, " No ; whereasin the caseof 'The Chimney
Sweeper' the question of the existenceof a representationis not in ques-
tion, now, with the system of the natural numbers, this is precisely the
62 Makkai
sentational objects most clearly. The talk about the software becomes
sharply separatedfrom the representation, which is a particular imple-
mentation of the software. The existenceof the software as such becomes
more pronounced; we are now more ready to accept the existenceof
the software as something separate and independent from any imple-
mentation, more ready than in the caseof the poem (perhaps). Another
element in favor of the existenceof the software as such is its potency.
One may doubt whether poems do anything; but we do not doubt that
pieces of software do things. They have very specific and occasionally
large effects- of course, never in themselves, always in an implementa-
tion . Discussing, describing, planning around the effect of the software
takes place mostly in talk that is independent of any particular imple-
mentation. I am inclined to the view that mathematical objects are like
software, more specifically, like the datatypesof software.
But let us return to poetry once again. Maybe our brave talk about
poems as genuine representational objects can be shown up as hot air,
after all. It is very well to talk about the many representationsof " The
Chimney Sweeper" in books, in people's minds, and so on; but there is a
distinguished, an authentic, an original representation: the one that Blake
himself put to paper. When we talk about the poem " The Chimney
Sweeper," we talk about this original copy; we talk about a first-class
object pure and simple. When we use ostensionand point to the copy on
page 11 of my book, what we do is deferred ostension, to use Quine's
expression. We mean referring to the Original; we refer to the Original.
This is what Benaceraffmeant by the " homogeneoussemanticaltheory of
the rest of the language," that is, the language that refers to reality as
opposedto mathematics.
Before we try to answer this devastating argument, we have to ac-
knowledge its force. In this we can see why we want the Platonistic,
uniquely referring, standard semantical theory: we want authenticity, an
objective point of reference, to which we can return when in doubt. There
may always be a question whether a particular printing of the poem is
correct; ultimately, the only way to answer this question is to go to the
original and verify whether the copy in question and the original can be
mapped to each other perfectly.
The attempt to answerthe argumentis this. Assumeyou discoverthat in
fact, there is no original " The Chimney Sweeper." In fact, worsethan that,
you discover that there is somethingentitled " The Chimney Sweeper" in
a manuscript of Blake's, but it differs substantially from the " standard
64 Makkai
version," the version that has been most frequently reprinted; moreover,
no trace of a version of the poem as we know it can be found in Blake's
manuscripts. You counter: This does not matter; the poem as we know it
was composedby someoneat some definite time and place, and when we
talk about the " The Chimney Sweeper" as we know it, we talk about that
original, even though it may differ from anything attributable to Blake
himself. To which I say that now the original of " The Chimney Sweeper"
as we know it is a purely fictive entity; it has lost its role as the grounding
of authenticity. However, in fact still there is no problem about what
" The Chimney Sweeper" as we know it is; it simply is what it is, and no
one will try to authenticate it , especially now (we are still within the
assumption that we have lost the good connection to Blake) that we
know that it cannot be authenticated. To which you say: There is no way
of stopping people from fixing the first, or most visible, or whatever, but
in some definite way unique source where the ' 'The Chimney Sweeper"
can be found, a source which becomesthe standard referenceto " The
Chimney Sweeper" as we know it. And then I reply: Oh, but now you
cannot say that " The Chimney Sweeper" as we know it is, by definition,
that given by the standard reference, since in fact there was something
entirely clearly defined before we had located that standard reference;
the location of the standard referencewas an a posteriori act of mock
authentication, an act entirely dependenton the clear and prior idea of
" The Chimney Sweeper" as we know it .!
Maintaining " the fiction of the homogeneoussemanticaltheory for the
language of the nonmathernatical world " (Benaceraff' s words, essen-
tially ) is hard work. I am suggestingthat it is too hard, what with all those
gadgetsthat comeflooding into our lives, eachhaving little or large pieces
of structure, defined in terms of someabstract functionality or what have
you. To make senseof all this, we resort to representational objects,
rather than trying to find unique authentic originals to which we would
have to run in caseof doubt. Certainly, theserepresentationalobjects are
abstractions (I do not mean to imply that the teffi1 I just used explains
them; rather, its use puts them in their place as inferior in some sense
to concrete things) and thus decidedly second-class objects that cannot
live without being rooted in medium-sized physical objects. But still, we
cannot do without them.
Is this a pragmatic argument? Yes, it is; but remember, the argument is
not about the existenceor nonexistenceof representational objects, but
about the fact or nonfact of the homogeneity of the semanticsfor the
Structuralism in Mathematics 65
Note
1. Ray Jackendoffhas suggestedto me a real exampleparalleling the hypothetical
case describedabove of being unable to find an authentic original. I describeit
essentiallyin his words.
There is a piece of music that has been in the repertoire at least since the early
nineteenthcentury, which is called " Sinfonia Concertantefor oboe, clarinet, horn,
bassoon, and orchestra by Mozart ." Only there is no known manuscript for this
piece. In a letter, Mozart himself referred to having written a sinfonia concertante
for flute, oboe, horn, and bassoon- which is totally unknown- and people gen-
erally assumethat the piecewe know is a later reorchestrationof that. The trouble
is that all attempts to " reconstruct" the original have been awkward at best;
basically, the clarinet part in the piece we know cannot easily be transferred to
idiomatic writing for any of the instruments mentioned in Mozart 's letter. More-
over, the last movement of the piece we know has someparts that Mozart never
would have written . So no one knows where this piececame from, prior to its first
publication someyears after Mozart 's death.
Jackendoff also pointed out to me that he has had to deal with representational
objects in his work on music, which involves an additional layer of performance,
making the semanticsof, say, " Beethoven's Fifth Symphony" even stranger.
References
Benaceraff, P. (1965). What numbers could not be. Philosophical Review, 74,
47- 73.
Benaceraff, P. (1973). Mathematical truth . The Journal of Philosophy, 70,
661- 675.
Davis, P. J., and Hersh, R . (1980). The mathematical experience. Birkhauser
Verlag.
Eilenberg, S., and Mac Lane, S. (1945). General theory of natural equivalences
.
Transactionsof the American Mathematical Society, 58, 231- 294.
66 Makkai
Makowski and E . V . Ravve ( Eds .) , Logic colloquium '95 ( Lecture Notes in Logic
11 , pp . 153 - 190 ) . New York : Springer -Verlag .
Makkai , M . (to appear ) . First - order logic with dependent sorts ( Lecture Notes in
Logic ) . New York : Springer - Verlag .
Parsons
303,.C.(1990
-346 ).The
structuralist
view
ofmathematical
objects
.SyntheseJ
84
,
Chapter~ 4
and Obligations
4 .1 Introduction
The focus of John Macnamara ' s work over three decades was an in - depth
Chomsky , John was asking what it is possible for a child to learn on the
basis of the input in the environment - and what parts of the child 's
knowledge cannot be learned , but must serve as the basis for learning .
Some of his results were absolutely startling , at least in the context of the
Anyone acquainted with John sensed that he was a man of deep moral
a topic of study as well , for instance in his paper " The Development of
the honor of presenting this work as the first John Macnamara Memorial Lecture
at McGill in April 1997 , and I benefited a great deal from the discussion there as
well . This research was supported in part by National Science Foundation grant
92 - 13849 to Brandeis University .
68 Jackendoff
b. *8uehas{ a 0bl.19atlon
anright . } lor B.II to Ieave
1 sky
c { the to beblue} .
72 Jackendoff
say the Actor " has" the right or obligation (the use of HA VE will be
further justified shortly ).6
( 10) a. HAVE (Xa , R T (ACT (a))) == 'X has a right to do Action '
b. HAVE (Xa , OB (ACT (a))) == 'X has an obligation to do
Action '
Actor (it may have further variables , irrelevant in the present context ) . In
( 10), this Actor position is bound to the holder of the right or obligation
by the bound variable Ct, where the superscript (X on X indicates that X
binds the variable in the argument position of ACT .
The fact that righ "ts and obligations have an Action rather than a prop -
osition as their argument places them in the general domain of deontic
logic , which deals with such notions as permissions and prohibitions and
with the logic of may , must, should, and ought, and which contains moral
reasoning as a particular subcase (von Wright 1963).
However , passive rights do not fall altogether comfortably into the
standard deontic domain , since their arguments are not volitional actions .
It is interesting therefore that the modal may cannot be used comfortably
to express passive rights : Sue may be paid for her work does not para -
phrase (7e). (Deserve to VP, which has a related meaning , has constraints
on its VP argument similar to those of right .)
A further constraint on the Action argument is deeply rooted in the
notions of right and obligation . Essentially , a right normally concerns
something one wants to do , whereas an obligation normally concerns
something one does not want to do .
( 11) a. Sue has a right / ??an obligation to eat her ice-cream sundae.
b. Sue has an obligation / ??a right to scrub the toilets .
( 12 ) VALUE ( Y , X ) = = + / -
interest ' . ( This seems to bear a relation to Freud ' s notion of Pleasure
to be defeasible ( ' defeatable ' ) to allow for cases in which other pragmatic
VALUE ( ACT ( X ) , X ) = = +
VALUE ( ACT ( X ) , X ) = = -
There are cases , such as the right / obligation to vote , that one may con -
strue with either value . In the right to vote , we take voting as a desirable
state this as ( 14 ) .
return in section 4 . 8 .
Next let us explore the range of things one can do with rights and obli -
First , one can perform the action to which the right or obligation per -
tion . Notice that the collocations for right and obligation involve different
actions . We will see that such differences pervade the whole range of verbs
Table4.1
What one can do with rightsand obligations(# indicates'not necessarily
felicitous
')
Right Obligation
Perfofllling
Action exercise fulfill
Creating
by Actor # declare , claim undertake
by Authority give, grant impose
Voiding
by Actor renounce # reject
by Authority revoke , take away release, remove
(effect on Actor ) lose be free of
Transfer transfer take on
Conflict
The use of give, transfer , and take away alongside have suggests that
a right might be conceptualized along the lines of a possession, that is, as
an independent entity that one may have, give, or take away . On this
analysis, the verb have in have a right , notated as HA VE in ( 10), is essen-
tially the ordinary have of alienable possession.? This leads to analyses as
in (15) . (INCH is inchoative , or 'coming to pass' .)
The language associated with obligations in table 4.1 has more incon -
sistent and opaque associations . Undertake , impose , remove , and take on
seem to image the obligation as a burden to be borne , as does the phrase
under ( the weight of ) obligation (s) . On the other hand , release, get out of,
and possibly hold to suggest the obligation is imaged as a constraining
force . In particular , the notion of an obligation as a constraint relates it to
force -dynamic expressions ( Talmy 1988): it is a social force that affects
one' s course of action . The expression fulfilling an obligation , through its
association withfill , might suggest an image of the obligation as a container .
The almost synonymous phrase meeting an obligation carries overtones of
Logic of Rights and Obligations 77
Consider more closely the " images" associatedwith rights and obliga-
tions. A theorist in the vein of Lakoff and Johnson (1980) would claim
that rights and obligations are understood " metaphorically" and that
they derive their conceptual properties from another domain, called the
" source domain." According to Lakoff and Johnson's methodology, the
evidencefor identifying the sourcedomain comesprecisely from the col-
locations in which the words in question appear. In this particular case,
we would be inclined to claim that rights and obligations are understood
metaphorically in terms of different source domains- rights as posses-
sions, obligations as burdens or constraints. Yet, as we have already seen
to someextent, and as I will continue to document, rights and obligations
are near-twin concepts, with altogether parallel logic. So there is some-
thing a bit suspiciousabout the metaphor view.
An alternative view is that rights and obligations have their OM'n logic.
This logic is shared superficially with possessionsand burdens, but it is
close enough to draw an associativeconnection. In choosing verbs to
expresswhat one can do with rights, the languageis swayedtoward verbs
of possessionbecauserights, like possessions , generally are of positive
value; verbs relating to obligations are swayed toward verbs of physical
burden and constraint becauseobligations, like burdens and constraints,
generally are of negative value. On this view, one does not understand
rights and obligations metaphorically in terms of possessions and burdensf
constraints. Rather, becauseof what one understandsabout rights and
obligations, one choosesverbal collocations in a motivated fashion. While
acknowledging the insights that Lakoff and Johnson seekto express, this
view turns the notion of metaphorical understanding on its head: it is
becauserights and obligations are understood as they are that the meta-
phorical connection is possible- not the other way about. (For more
detailed discussionof Lakoff and Johnson's approach, seeMurphy 1996;
Jackendoff 1992, chap. 3; Jackendoff and Aaron 1991.)
Looking a little more deeply, what sort of conceptual entities might
rights and obligations be? In the formalization in (9), (10), and (15), the
78 Jackendoff
long pass to the theater gives one the right to enter the theater , but one
retains the right for future occasions. Similarly , one's obligation to obey a
police officer does not go out of existence when one obeys an officer once:
this obligation persists.
We must distinguish , then , between rights and obligations that pertain
to exactly one action and those that pertain to all actions of a given type .
The former are exercised or fulfilled by an appropriate action 's taking
place, at which point they go out of existence. We could think of these
as " existential ," in the sense that if there comes to exist an Action that
satisfies the argument of the right or obligation , the right or obligation
ceases to exist . The latter , by contrast , are " universal " : they pertain to
every Action of the appropriate type . ( Von Wright calls these varieties
particular and general, respectively ; the legal tradition uses the terms in
personam and in rem, respectively .)
This distinction could be encoded by a subscript on the operators RT
and DB : for example , RTEx and OBEx versus RTun and OBun. Inference
rule ( 16) then pertains only to the " existential " variety .
NOT HAVE (XCi, RTEx/ OBEx(ACT (a))) at time t3, where t3 > t2
It is important to our story that this inference rule involves a succession of
times- that is, the principles of rights and obligations require a dynamic
logic . (This temporal dependency is not present in the formalism of von
Wright and his successors, even if they acknowledge it informally .)
It is worth observing that various other concepts have this curious
property . For instance, an intention to perform an action is fulfilled - and
thereby goes out of existence- when the action is performed . Parallel
effects obtain with bodily sensations such as hunger , thirst , and some
itches. So this odd metaphysical property of rights and obligations is
actually more broadly attested among our concepts.
The situation is actually still more complex . One has the right to vote in
every election ; that is, exercising the right does not eliminate it . On the
other hand , one has the right to vote only once in each election ; having
voted eliminates the right till the next election . So this right has a mixed
flavor , partly " universal " and partly " existential ." This suggests that the
simple subscripts Ex and Un are not subtle enough to capture the range of
possibilities ; there is more internal structure to be teased out .
80 Jackendoff
So far , I have not done much to distinguish social/ legal/ contractual rights
and obligations from other kinds of deontic operators expressed by
modals such as may , should, ought to, and must- in particular , from
" moral obligations " and " human rights ," which turn out to be a bit
different in character . Now I turn to what gives social/ legal/contrac -
tual rights and obligations their distinctive flavor : the consequences of
noncompliance .
What happens if one fails to fulfill an obligation ? Very simply , one runs
the risk of getting in trouble . Suppose I have undertaken an obligation -
say, by promising to wash the dishes. Making a promise involves another
individual to whom one has made the promise , who typically will benefit
from having the promise fulfilled . Let us call this individual the Benefi-
ciary of the obligation .
N ow suppose I do not wash the dishes within a reasonable amount of
We may further add that the Beneficiary normally benefits from the
Acti on .
The inference rule for noncompliance now comes out as ( 19); again it is
stated dynamically .
81
Logic of Rights and Obligations
ACT2 ( P )
In the bottom line of (19), ACT 2 is the action that Z has the right to carry
out; the lambda- expression says that this action has a negative value
for X ; the EXCH operator says that this action is in exchangefor X 's
nonperformance.
Rule (19) saysnothing about the appropriate time interval to wait for
compliance. More important , (19) saysnothing about what kind of retal-
iatory act is appropriate- only that it should be somethingthat the Actor
won't like. Many such actions, especially for culturally loaded obliga-
tions, are prescribed in a culture's stock of customs and oral or written
law.8 In particular, there are large classesof obligations, including such
things as debts, for which the appropriate action in the face of non-
compliance is to call in the authorities to determine the appropriate pun-
ishment. In turn, social norms may dictate that the authorities have an
obligation to the Beneficiary to mete out the appropriate punishment-
one of the foundations of legal theory (Stone 1968). I return to the notion
of " the authorities" in section4.9.
In addition to (19), the nonfulfillment of an obligation has a broader
consequence . Roughly speaking, ever} 'one- not just the Beneficiary- is
justified in criticizing the Actor (or thinking less of the Actor ) for failing
to fulfill the obligation. The threat of such criticism seemsto me to con-
stitute the moral dimension of an obligation. Here I would be reluctant to
use the term has a right to describewhat everyonemay do to the Actor ;
something like is mol'ally justified seemsmore appropriate. I will not
attempt to formalize this inference, in part becausean appropriately gen-
eral form is beyond the scopeof this chapter.
Thesetwo inferences, the one social/ contractual, the other moral, seem
both-to be involved in social/ contractual obligations suchas promisesand
debts. The kinds of things we might call " moral obligations," such as the
obligation to preservethe environment, seemto me to invoke only the
latter inference rule.9 It is interesting how the two rules are somewhat
parallel in structure, but not entirely. In particular, only the Beneficiary
has a right of retribution , whereaseveryoneis morally justified in sanc-
tioning the offender.
82 Jackendoff
the usher my ticket . This gives me a right to enter the theater to see the
saying , " You have no right to go in ! " I am thereby entitled to take action
disapproval , since it ' s the rights of the theater ( as corporate body ) , not
to exercise it , and some other party tries to prevent me , I then have the
entails
ACT 2 (P )
at t2 > t1
Again , there are many cultural customs and norms concerning what kind
to demand retaliation . For instance , if the usher doesn 't let me into the
after due remonstration , is to go to the manager , and if that doesn ' t work ,
to the police .
person who violates someone ' s rights . Again , only the Actor has the right
retaliation if the obligation is not met . In the case of rights , there seems to
entitled to retaliation is always the one for whom the potential Action is of
positive value . In the case of a right , the Actor is the potential Beneficiary
and therefore receives the right of retaliation for interference with receiv -
ing the benefit . In the case of an obligation , the Action is of negative value
to the Actor ; the reason the Action is to be performed is to benefit some -
one else . It is that someone else , then , who receives the right of retaliation .
Notice too that this parallelism extends to the moral dimension . Every -
one is morally justified in criticizing the person who exacts the cost from
the intended Beneficiary : the Actor in the case of an obligation , the person
that make rights and obligations what they are . By contrast , a moral /
ethical principle takes the form " One should / should not do such and
carries only what I have called the moral dimension , the fact that every -
legal and judicial systems in a society . So these inference rules lie at the
particular , the Beneficiary of an obligation is felt to have a " passive right "
to receive the benefit . This sense can be stated as inference rule ( 21 ) .
The bottom line of ( 21 ) is a passive right because Z is not the Actor of the
Event satisfies the conditions for the argument of a passive right , as illus -
trated in ( 7e ) and ( 8a ) .
toward X if X does not perform the Action . So the two lines lead to
entails
HAVE ( EVERYONEP ,
someone ' s failing to meet the obligation not to prevent exercise of a right ,
" in return " for someone else ' s action . Those in ( 23 ) describe actions with
changes can felicitously take place only with another person , an entity
Logic of Rights and Obligations 85
This shows that we expect a positively valued action in return for a posi-
tively valued action , and a negatively valued action in return for a nega-
tively valued one.
So far I have spoken of values as only positive or negative . But ex-
change situations show that values are conceived of as roughly quantita -
tive . We find it odd if the two actions related by for do not match in
quantity . The sentences in (26) convey some of this oddness.
c. Fred slashed Lois 's tires for eating too little at dinner .
d . Fred slashed Lois 's tires for murdering his entire family .
(27) [ACT2
EXCH(Z ) )] ]
[ACT1(X
defeasibly presupposes
VALUE (ACT2 (Z ), X ) == VALUE (ACT } (X ), Z )
In practical situations , the equation is not this simple : each participant 's
judgment of the value of his or her own and the other 's actions , both to
himself or herself and to the other , may differ . In particular , there seems
to be a general cognitive bias toward overestimating costs to oneself and
benefits to others , and toward underestimating benefits to oneself and
86 Jackendoff
costs to others . Thus , it often requires negotiation to achieve a " fair " ex-
change, where both participants judge the exchanged acts to be of equiv -
alent value to themselves and to the other . Here is an important point
where " folk theory of mind " and Cosmides ' ( 1989) " cheater detection "
enter : one is more inclined to compromise if one believes the other 's
assertions of value are made in good faith .
The logic of exchange laid out here is a cognitive elaboration of a be-
havioral strategy well documented in the ethological literature , recipro -
cal altruism : " You scratch my back and I ' ll scratch yours ." I leave open
how much of its detail can be attributed to nonhuman primates (not to
mention elephants and bats). What strikes me as particularly human ,
though , is the broad generality of the actions available to be entered into
exchange equations .
Turning back to rights and obligations more specifically , we see in (27)
a more or less formal statement of " The punishment fits the crime " : this
helps guide what actions are appropriate in retaliation for breaking obli -
gations and violating rights in ( 19) and (20). (27) implies that the offend -
ing party should receive retribution : the cost of the retaliatory action to
offenders should equal the cost of their offense to the injured party - that
is, the two parties should end up equally badly off . An alternative to (27)
is that the injured party should receive restitution : the benefit of the re-
taliatory action to the injured should equal the cost of the injury , what -
ever its cost to the offender - that is , the offended party should end up as
well off as before .
which one has a right is of positive value , and being prevented from
exercising the right grants one a right of restitution , then having a right
is a win -win situation , that is, a benefit . So some of the pieces of the logic
of rights and obligations begin to hang together .
4.9 Authority
rights or authority . One can insist on one's own rights or authority ; one
can acknowledge someone else's. On the other hand , there is more com -
plexity in authority , since one can resist another 's authority , but the
phrase resisting anotherJs right makes little sense.
Like all obligations , those imposed by an Authority must have a
Beneficiary . (30) encodes the typical case in which the Beneficiary is the
Authority him - or herself (this is notated by the (Xin the second argument
posiion of OB , bound to Z ) . Thus , in case of noncompliance the Author -
ity also has the right of punishment . Other Beneficiaries are possible- for
instance, when a judge obliges a divorced parent to pay child support to
the ex-spouse. In such a case, the ex-spouse's right of retaliation in case of
noncompliance is typically deteffilined by the judge as well . That is, if
an Authority imposes an obligation on an Actor , with a third individual
as Beneficiary , the Authority retains the right to punish the Actor for
noncompliance , with or without appeal from the Beneficiary . So the logic
becomes still more complex ; I will not attempt to foffilalize it here.
Even with these added complexities , the account in (30) is still missing
an important caveat, in that it is necessary to recognize limitations of
authority . For instance , in our society , we believe that your boss does not
have the right to oblige you to take your clothes off . A more adequate
formalization relativizes authority to a particular class of actions , as in
(31) .
(32) leaves about the right loopholes for social negotiation (and conflict ) :
Over exactly what actions can a given Authority impose obligations ? And
how are those decided? These are issues with which every society must
grapple .
How does one obtain authority ? One way is to be granted it by a
higher Authority , who is then said to be delegating authority . But this
leaves open who grants authority at the top of the pyramid . This problem
Logic of Rights and Obligations 89
of the " apex norm" (Stone 1968, following Hans Kelsen) lies at the root
of a society's conception of itself. Three possible solutions,: despotism,
where the ultimate authority simply assertsauthority without recourse
and maintains it through the exerciseof power; supernatural authority
such as the " divine right of kings," in which the top-ranked personis said
to be granted authority by a deity whose rights in turn require no justifi -
cation; and representative government, in which authority is taken to
arise from the " consentof the governed." In addition, all societiesrecog-
nize the " natural" authority of parentsover children, which seemsto need
no justification . Perhapsthere are other possibilities.
wrong requires more than a blanket invocation of cultural relativism . See Brown
1991 for discussion .
4. Though I gather that during the medieval period there were such things as
trials of pigs for killing children , pushing pigs toward a more responsible status .
5. Sue had a ,~ight /obligation to leave yesterday is of course acceptable . In this case,
the time for which the right / obligation is asserted is yesterday or earlier - not five
minutes ago , for instance .
6. For readers unacquainted with this style of formalization , the point is to have a
canonical and precise way of expressing claims about meaning , which permits us
to state rigorous principles by which meanings may be composed and by which
they may be used to draw inferences . The notation used here can be thought of as
an enriched form of predicate logic . For those uncomfortable with the formalism ,
I will take care to explain the formulas in ordinary English as well .
In ( 10) and succeeding examples I use the predicate HA VE to express posses-
sion , following Pinker 1989. An alternative in line with the practice of Jackendoff
1983 would be (i); I leave it to the interested reader to work out the differences in
the rules throughout the chapter .
(i) BEposs([RT / OB (ACT (ri))], ATposs XIX)
7. There is however a degree of circularity in this suggestion , in that , as men -
tioned at the outset , possession in large part consists of rights . I will not attempt
here to grapple with problems this may raise.
8. We can include among " customs " the sorts of things discussed in " Miss Man -
ners " columns in the newspaper : what do I do if someone doesn ' t fulfill the cus -
tomary obligation of writing a thank -you note for a wedding present?
9. What I am calling here the moral dimension is the main one considered by
Conison ( 1997) , who draws the inference that everyone is entitled to sanction
someone who breaks a promise . Yon Wright ( 1963, 12), however , says, " 'By defi -
nition ' , one could say, promises ought to be kept . But this is only one aspect,
beside others , of the obligation in question . . . . To try to explain the obligation to
keep promises , for example , in terms of the 'normative pressure' of customs seems
utterly out of place ." This is the intuition I am trying to capture here.
10. In certain religious traditions , moral / ethical strictures are taken to be obliga -
tions to a deity , and the deity acquires the right of retaliation . I take this to be a
cultural construct whose purpose is to sharpen ethical norms , giving them the
same " objective " status as laws .
11. " Infringe " : yet another thing one can do with a right . This verb has associa-
tions of treading on another ' s territory , a variation on possession.
12. This section is a particular area where I realize I run a risk of overly pre -
supposing something like the Western democratic tradition , with its stress on the
94 Jackendoff
rights of the individual . If the logic works out differently for different cultures , so
be it .
13 . Authority is a form of social dominance , but not the only one . For example ,
siblings often fall into a dominance hierarchy by age , but that does not necessarily
make it possible for an older sibling to impose obligations on a younger .
14. In particular , I have not dealt with what many take to be the most important
issue concerning rights : the notion of universal human rights . I see some difference
between these and the more mundane type of rights discussed here . Unlike con -
tractual rights , issues of human rights typically arise in the context of claiming
rights that are not acknowledged by governmental authority . In the time of the
American Revolution , such rights were asserted to be granted by higher (divine or
natural ) authority (as in " . . . endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable
rights . . ." ) ; in this century , they have been to some extent acknowledged through
international agreements such as the United Nations Universal Declaration of
Human Rights . In either case , there is to some extent a failure of mutual belief
in the existence of the rights in question , as well as questionable effectiveness in
enforcement on the part of the higher authority .
References
Cheney, D ., and Seyfarth, R. (1990). How monkeyssee the world. Chicago: Uni -
versity of Chicago Press.
Chomsky, N . (1965). Aspectsof the theory of syntax. Cambridge, MA : MIT Press.
Conison, J. (1997). The pragmatics of promise. Canadian Journal of Law and
Jurisprudence, 10, 273- 322.
Cosmides , L . ( 1989). The logic of social exchange: Has natural selection shaped
how humans reason? Studies with the Wason selection task . Cognition , 31, 187-
276.
Stone, J. ( 1968) . Human law and human justice . Stanford , CA : Stanford University
Press .
every philosopher : first , that we deliberate about means not ends; second,
that we deliberate about things that are in our power and can be done
( Nichomachean Ethics 1112a30, 1112bll - 16, 1139b6, 1140a32). I need a
table ; to make a table requires a hammer and saw; I have a hammer but
no saw; so let me go out and buy a saw. Again a doctor , qua doctor , does
not deliberate about whether a patient should be healed, but how to heal
him . No one will disagree with this . To be sure, one can imagine circum -
stances in which a doctor might deliberate over whether a patient should
be healed- say, if there were 1,000 patients and drugs for only 500. But in
this case the doctor isn't really deliberating about ends, but about the
practical problem of how to treat as many people as possible with the
John Macnamara and I talked about many things , over many years, in the area of
practical deliberation and intention . As I write this chapter I imagine his voice ,
objecting , sometimes chiding , but always encouraging , and I dedicate these pages
to the memory of a true friend .
98 McCall
means available . If a doctor were truly to deliberate about ends and ask,
for example , " Is healing worthwhile ?" , the question would fall under
cognitive rather than practical deliberation .
What exactly is deliberation ? In what follows , I try to give a philo -
sophically adequate account of it and to answer some difficult questions .
I finish up by speculating about what sorts of structures and neuro -
physiological functioning in the brain would make possible in real life the
philosophical description of the deliberative process that I have given .
Let 's start off with a concrete example . Marsha has to decide whether
to accept an offer of graduate study in philosophy at UBC , Western
Ontario , or McGill . Call these alternatives A , B , and C . Each one has its
The first step in the deliberative process is to be clear about the alter -
natives , to represent them accurately and keep them in focus . Is the list
exhaustive ? Should she make a last-minute application to McMaster ,
where her sister is studying ? Should she simply do nothing , and not accept
any of the offers? Call this last option D , the do-nothing alternative . Let 's
suppose that A , B , C, and D exhaust the alternatives facing her and that
each one is a " live " alternative in the sense that (a) she can choose it , and
(b) if she chooses it , her choice determines what happens subsequently .
Thus , if she chooses UBC , she goes to UBC . We may imagine that
Marsha has lined up three envelopes on her desk, addressed to UBC ,
Western , and McGill . All she has to do is to put a stamp on one of them
and mail it , or alternatively forget about graduate study . The first re-
quirement for deliberation , then , is the existence of a " choice set," a set of
two or more alternative coursesof action {A , B, C, D , . . .} each of which
it is physically possible for the deliberator to perform or implement , and
whichtogether
exhaust
theavailable
options
.
Once the choice set has been established , the process of deliberation
begins in earnest. Each option has its advantages, which constitute the
reasons for choosing it , and its disadvantages , which constitute the reasons
for not choosing it . I shall call these deliberation reasons. For example ,
UBC has made a generous scholarship offer , but on the other hand has no
staff member who works directly in Marsha 's area of interest . These facts
constitute positive and negative deliberation reasons for A , and there will
be other positive and negative deliberation reasons for B, C, and D . In
deliberation , we weigh deliberation reasons. We compare their relative
strength with the aim of arriving at an overall comparative evaluation .
Deliberation Reasonsand Explanation Reasons 99
The processof evaluation is normally but not invariably the most time-
consuming part of deliberation and ideally should result in a list of the
options ordered by preference.
Once evaluation is completed, it might seemthat the deliberative pro-
cessis at an end. But this is not so. There is one more step, frequently
ignored in studies of rational choice and decision but still essential: the
elementof choice or decisionitself. It may seemdifficult to imagine, once
an ordered evaluation of the options has been made, what more a delib-
erator could need. But supposethe first two alternatives are very close
in the ordering? Supposethey come out equal? What if the deliberator is
faced with a difficult decision? Even in the casewhere an evaluation is
unambiguous, with a clear-cut winner, something elsebesidesevaluation
is neededfor action. The missing element is what Aristotle calls prohai-
resis, deliberative choice.
More needsto be said about prohairesis, but I should first sum up what
has been established so far. The philosophical account of deliberation
given above has distinguishedthree separatecomponentsof the delibera-
tive process, ordered in strict temporal sequence
:
1. Representationof the alternatives
2. Evaluation
3. Choice
With decision, which is choice of one of the alternatives, the deliberative
processends. I turn now to decisionsand the reasonsfor them, the latter
being distinct from the deliberation reasonsfor the different options.
In deliberation we weigh and assessdeliberation reasons, each being a
reasonfor or against one of the alternatives. When eventually we decide,
and chooseone of the options, there is normally also a reason why that
option was selectedover the others. I shall call the latter an explanation
reason, or, occasionally, a decision reason. In the deliberative process
there are deliberation reasons, which are the reasonsfor or against the
different options, but there are also explanation reasons, which are the
reasons why, after examination of the deliberation reasons, one of
the options is chosen.
A principal objective of this chapter is to be clear about the exact dif-
ferencebetweendeliberation reasonsand explanation reasons. Without a
good understanding of the difference, I don't think we can know what
deliberation is. Therefore, I shall spend some time discussingthe rela-
tionship betweenthem.
100 McCall
planation reason? These questions are not easy to answer. Let us start
with Buridan -type situations , in which a choice must or should be made ,
but in which there is absolutely no reason for choosing one thing rather
than another .
Buridan 's ass starved to death halfway between two piles of hay because
there was nothing to incline his choice toward A rather than B .2 Here the
deliberation reasons for A and B are equally balanced , and as a result
no decision is taken . A similar problem , based on fear rather than desire,
is the " railroad dilemma ." 3 What fascinates us in these examples is not
just the specter of decisional paralysis , but the feeling that the outcome -
death by indecision - is in a genuine sense an affront to reason. If the ass
had been rational , or more rational than he was , he would not have
starved . He would have drawn straws and said, " Long left , short right ."
Failing this , if he had been clever enough , he could simply have made
an arbitrary or criterionless choice (Ofstad 1961; McAdam 1965). If you
believe this is impossible , reflect on how you manage to choose one of
a hundred identical tins of tomato soup in a supermarket . The example of
the soup tins was a favorite of Macnamara ' s, and he used it with great
effect in discussion . If you made the mistake of saying that an arbitrary
choice in these circumstances was difficult or impossible , that would in -
dicate that you , like Buridan 's ass, were not very intelligent .
Moving from Buridan -type examples to cases where there is a signifi -
cant difference between the alternatives , but where the deliberation rea -
sons are still equally balanced , the same question arises: can a choice be
made for which there is no explanation or decision reason? If Marsha
finds it difficult or impossible to decide between UBC and McGill because
between them there is " nothing to choose," can she use some tie -breaking
mechanism like a coin and in so doing make a choice that lacks an
explanation reason? Not really . Although in this case the explanation is
different from what it would have been if the evaluation process had
choiceis made for no reasonat all, not evenwith the aid of a randomizing
devicelike a coin as part of the decision-making process, then the decision
cannot be considered rational. Furthermore, even in cases where an
explanation reasonis provided by the deliberator, norms of rationality still
apply to it , and the rational assessmentof a decisionmust take them into
account. For example, if Marsha were to explain her decision to go to
UBC by saying, " BecauseI 'm a Libra ," the relevanceand consequently
the rationality of this supposedexplanation could be questioned. Deci-
sion, therefore, like choice set foffilation and evaluation, is a procedure
that it is appropriate to subject to rational norms, and to judge rational
only if it satisfiesthesenOffilS. The sameapplies, mutatis mutandis, to the
whole deliberative process.
An important question that should be addressedis whether an expla-
nation reason for a decision is a cause of that decision. The immediate
answerwould seemto be no. An explanation reasonfor a decisioncomes
into existenceonly once the decision is made, whereas a cause should
antedatethe thing it causes. The whole question of causality and its role
in the deliberative processis neverthelessof great interest and must be
looked at carefully.
First, our discussionfrom the start has taken us outside the framework
of causaldeterminism, sincethe very existenceof a choice set with two or
more physically realizable alternativesis not consistentwith determinism.
One might attempt to remove the inconsistencyby requiring that in any
choice set one and only one alternative was causally possible, the delib-
erator necessarilybeing ignorant of which one that was. As long as the
deliberator believed (falsely) that each alternative in the choice set was
realizable, deliberation could proceedasusual, the eventualdecisionbeing
taken in favor of the one option that was in fact open. This is deliberation
according to the script that would be written for it by a determinist. The
rewriting does indeed remove the inconsistency, but at the price of (a)
abandoning choice setswith two or more real alternatives and (b) draw-
ing a veil of ignorance over the eyes of deliberators about which is the
sole choosableoption. Behind the veil, " deliberation" can proceed. But
rewriting the script in this way is unnecessary, if it can be shown that it is
simpler and more elegantto abandon determinism.
Since the 1920s, quantum mechanicshas provided the example of a
sciencethat is probabilistic rather than deterministic. As a result, replac-
ing deterministic models of deliberation by indeterministic ones is not
such a daunting or unthinkable project today as it would have been for
104 McCall
Again , the factor J may increase the probability of option A 's being
realized , but can it increase it to unity ? Can any deliberation reason, or
deliberative factor , be of such strength that it makes it physically or
causally impossible for any alternative other than A to be selected? Might
it , before the choice is made, reduce the choice set to a single choosable
option ? This takes us back once more to determinism . One cannot rule
out the possibility that during deliberation something should occur (e.g.,
paralysis or a violent fit ) that restricts the alternatives to one option only .
But such cases are so far removed from the norm as not to qualify as
instances of deliberation at all . At the end of a deliberation , we are left
either with the choice set with which we began, or with a reduced choice
set, or an enlarged one, but in any case a set consisting of at least two
members . The probabilities of these options can change, but if any of
them reaches the value one , deliberation ceases .
Notes
2 . The dilemma antedates Buridan . See Rescher 1959 for why the problem of
" Buridan ' s ass " should more justly be known as " al - Farabi ' s dates ." Buridan 's
3 . You are hiking with your partner through mountainous wooded country and
come to a horseshoe - shaped valley with a railway track at the bottom . While you
are crossing the track , a heavy branch falls on your partner ' s leg , pinning him or
her to the rails ; and while trying vainly to move the branch , you hear the whistle
of an approaching train . Unfortunately , the echoes in the valley make in impos -
sible to tell which direction the train is coming from . Game theory tells us you
have a 50 % chance of saving your partner ' s life if you pick a direction arbitrarily
and run as fast as possible down the track to stop the train , but how many of us
would have the strength of mind to do this as the whistle grows louder and the
uncertainty becomes more agonizing ?
and only J is allowed to vary . In the case of deliberation , however , we are con -
cerned with a single unique process , not in general repeatable , and so this supple -
mental requirement cannot be met . Nor would it be appropriate to require , in
addition to p ( AIJ ) > p ( Alnot -J ) , that the anticipated probabilistic effect A actu -
ally occurs , since if A occurs then in the probability calculus p ( A ) == 1 , and hence
p ( AIC ) == 1 for any C , provided p ( C ) # O.
References
Cartwright , N . ( 1989 ) . Nature 's capacities and their measurement . Oxford : Clar -
endon Press .
Rescher, N . ( 1959). Choice without preference . Kant -Studien, 51, 142- 175.
Suppes, P. ( 1970). A probabilistic theory of causality . Amsterdam : North -Holland .
Chapter
- 6
Truth and Its Negation : David R . Olson
Macnamara ' s Analysis of the
Place of Logic in a Cognitive
Psychology
""' p
which reads something like : ifp implies q, and q is not the case, then p is
not the case either . The question is, what is the status of such a logical
schema? Is it , for example , a law of thought ? Is thinking achieved by
applying rules of logic , or is logic merely a description of how thinking
proceeds, or , yet again , is logic a set of " regulative " or noffilative princi -
ples quite independent of the way people ordinarily think ?
The question has a venerable history , as John Macnamara infoffils us
in his daunting book A Border Dispute ( 1986) . The idea that logic con-
stitutes the laws of thinking is known as psychologism and it is well
expressed in J. S. Mill 's System of Logic , in which the author claims that
the necessary truths of logic are simply those things that we find it impos -
sible to doubt . That is, Mill identified necessity with certainty . Frege in his
Begriffsschrift distinguished the two , arguing that certainty is based on the
facts of experience whereas necessity is connected " with the inner nature
of the proposition considered " ( 1879/ 1967, 5) . As Macnamara points out ,
Parts of this chapter were first published as a review of Macnamara 1986 (see
Olson 1987).
110 Olson
Frege claimed that logic is a " normative " law , a law that states how
thinkers ought to judge , not a description of how they do judge .
Macnamara wants to add a third stage to this history by showing that
logic is not something different and apart from thought but , rather , that
" logic supplies a competence theory for the psychology of human rea-
soning " ( p . 185) . In so doing , he echoes the views of George Boole , his
more famous Irish predecessor, who claimed that the laws of logic " pos-
sess an authority inherent and just , but not always commanding obedi -
ence" ( 1958, 409) .
Macnamara 's line of attack is borrowed from the grammarians rather
than the mathematicians . The work of the logician is somewhat similar to
the work of the grammarian who attempts to spell out the internal rela-
tions within linguistic structures . Since Saussure and especially since
Chomsky , it has been common to think of linguistic structures as con-
stituting the competence of native speakers. Grammars do not just
describe products or sentences; they specify the implicit knowledge of
speakers, knowledge that figures both in the generation of sentences and
in intuitions of grammaticality .
Those developments in linguistics have given us a new respect for the
rich structure of the linguistic system and , consequently , a new respect for
the complexity of structure of the human mind . Rules , representations ,
constituent structure , meaning , propositional structures are all part of
current discourse about mind . There is no longer any talk of tabula rasa.
Why not approach logic this way ? Why not indeed , says Macnamara .
Rather than leave logic to the logicians , he argues that logical competence
is part of the endowment of rational creatures just as linguistic compe-
tence is part of the endowment of verbal ones . And then he sets out to
explicate that competence .
Macnamara spent several of the last few years of his life with logicians
learning about logic and then trying to specify what is logically implied in
children 's learning to do such apparently simple things as refer to objects
by proper names and to make assertions. In the course of this study he
examined the logic of proper names, common names or sortals , kinds ,
existential predicates , truth predicates, and sentential connectives includ -
ing negations . Needless to say, children 's acquisition of these structures is
no small achievement !
member of a category , dog , that the child recognize that dog is a kind of
thing , that the particular individual in front of the child is what is being
named , and that there is some equative relation between the thing pointed
at and the proper name . He convincingly shows how much more a child
brings to the learning of a proper name than Saint Augustine or anyone
else had noticed . And he provides interesting evidence that very young
children distinguish names, expressed by proper nouns , from sortals ,
expressed by common nouns , by the presence or absence of the articles a
and the . Remarkable !
- --
perform the act of judging without knowing that he is judging. But the learner
must
have
106
-107
) the
concept
of
truth
;there
is
noaction
that
can
stand
initsplace
.(pp
.
So Macnamara claims that the predicate is true (in the language of
thought) must be used in judging the sentencetrue any time the child
names an object. Its use implies the presenceof the concept true and its
opposite, not true, that is, false. " Children are endowedby nature with an
understandingof both" (p. 108). Finally , " the conclusion that forces itself
on us is that neither the conceptsof truth and falsity nor the fundamental
principles of logic are learned" (p. 109).
Thus, Macnamara has concluded that children have concepts of
truth and falsity representedin an innate languageof thought that permits
them to learn, among other things, proper names. But are we compelled
by logical argument to grant that young children not only produce utter-
ancesthat are, in fact, true or false, but also that l -year-old children have
concepts of truth and falsity and know the principle of contradiction?
Macnamara claims that we are, the primary reason being that it seems
impossible to him that " logic-free activities can ever yield logical re-
sources" (p. 30). This, of course, is a denial of the Piagetian hypothesis
that representational structures can develop from sensorimotor ones, a
central plank of Piaget' s epigenetictheory.
Even after severalcareful readings of Macnamara's arguments, I can
see no reason why the predicates true and false could not be acquired
(rather than being presupposed ) . Children do encounter utterances that
are objectively true and others that are objectively false, and they do en-
counter adults' judgments of utterancesas being true or false. Why could
not theseobjective facts be sufficient grounds for children's acquisition of
thesepredicates? I seeno reason that these predicatesare preconditions
for naming any more than that the predicates say and mean are pre-
conditions for saying and meaning things. Admittedly , all predicatespre-
supposesome mechanismfor representingpredicates, but that is not the
issuehere. The issuehere is whether it is a necessarytruth that children
must have predicates for truth and falsity representedin a language of
thought in order for them to learn proper names.
Concepts of truth and falsity (false being not true) do presupposea
conceptof negation, and it is worth asking whether, as Macnamara insists,
the concept of negation is also innate. Negation is fascinating in that it is
clear that negation does not exist in nature. Russell (1948, 520) pointed
out that " the world can be describedwithout the use of the word not."
TruthandIts Negation 113
Geach (1957, 23), too, wrote that " nowhere in the sensibleworld could
you find anything, nor could you draw any picture, that would suitably be
labeled or or not." Yet a mind that could representonly what is the case
would be a mind without logic, hypotheses, or language(Harrison 1972).
Although negations are absent from nature, they are central to lan-
guage. Comparativists have argued that negation is conspicuouslyabsent
from the communication systemsof other animals (Sebeok 1962), and
although nonhuman animals can issuewarnings and register disappoint-
ment, they cannot mark in their communication that someexpectedevent
has not occurred. Visalberghi and Fragaszy (1996, 294) write, " We can
think of no impediment to the use of these forms of negation in non-
humans; but they simply do not use them." Indeed, it is possiblethat an
animal cannot mentally representnegation and that the ability to repre-
sent a cat as " not a dog" is peculiar to language-using humans. Could,
contrary to Macnamara, the concept of negation (and hence falsity) be
acquired as a child acquiresa natural language?
There is a rich literature on children's acquisition of negation in lan-
guage (for a summary, seeHorn 1989) that indicates a clear progression
in understanding and use of negatives beginning with expressionsof
rejection, disappearance , and finally denial, so-called truth-functional
negation. Although rejections, refusals, and prohibitions are not neces-
sarily linguistic- even dogs can reject food or refuse to come- denials
constitute the " linguistic category of negation par excellence" (Tottie
1982, 96). As we shall see, only when children are approximately school-
ageddo negation and falsity come apart in such a way that they canjudge
a sentencecontaining a negation to be true. They come to agree with
Aristotle in the secondpart of the definition mentioned earlier: " To say of
what is not that it is not, is true." Thus, to judge a proposition as true or
false is a late and sophisticatedachievemententirely dependentupon the
acquisition of negation.
Macnamara could say of such a counterargumentthat it confuseslogi-
cal performance with logical competence. It is easy to design tasks that
make it difficult for children to display their underlying logical ability .
The tasks I discussexamine complex judgments about English sentences ,
whereas he discussesthe logical competence that must be present to
account for children's acquisition of names, assertions, and inferences.
So, he may claim, I misunderstand. That, and worse, is what he said
about Piaget. In a comment that is as close as one gets to a call to arms,
114 Olson
Macnamara says, " It is in fact doubtful that Piaget had any sharable
insights into the fundamental processes of cognitive growth " (p . 114).
Piaget 's subjects, he claims , are " faced with a complicated induction
problem and simply become muddled " (p . 116). Piaget 's tasks, he sug-
gests, test only subjects' ability with an algebra for possible combinations
of propositions (he'd say the same of Wason and 10hnson-Laird 's " four -
card " task), whereas he is interested in only " the most basic logical con-
nectives themselves" ( p . 115). Of those basic notions he says, " There is
nothing in [Piaget 's] evidence to even suggest that [the child ] was so
totally lacking in logical intuitions as to knowingly assent to both a
proposition and its negation " (p . 116) .
However , consider the evidence provided by Alison Dewsbury and later
explored in some detail by Janet Astington and myself (Astington and
Olson 1984; Olson 1997) . Four - and five -year-old children are shown a
picture of a man with a hat , accompanied by a series of sentences. They
are asked to put a check mark by the ones that are true , right , correct , or
OK and to put an X by the ones that are false, wrong , or in error . Here is
what children reliably do :
Themanhasa hat. J
Themanhasno hat. J
As if that was not enough , they go on thus . Shown a picture of a cat, and
asked to mark the following sentences, they do thus :
This is a dog . X
This is not a dog . X
References
sity Press .
Geach, P. T. (1957
). Mental acts , their content and their objects . London : Rout -
ledge& KeganPaul.
Harrison, B. (1972). Meaning and structure: An essay in the philosophy of lan -
borrow a page from John and will spend much of this chapter discussing
Given that we can use any of the sentences ( 1 ) - ( 4 ) to talk about the same
entity in the world , we need some kind of account of how it is that these
sentences differ in how they are related to our visual representations of the
entity . As we will see , the simple fact that we can use any of these sen -
tences to talk about the same entity in the world , if taken seriously , leads
addressed the question of how we talk about objects and locations . In this
(4) I have no idea what that is, but it is brown, hard, and weighs 10
pounds.
In each of the sentences(1)- (4), the demonstrative that directs our atten-
tion to a particular part of our environment. Typically , this is a spatio-
temporally bounded solid entity, though this doesnot have to be the case
(e.g., That is a shadow, That is coffee, That is a forest, That is a somer-
sault). Clearly, there are principles of perception that operate to organize
the information available in ways such that particular spatiotemporally
bounded entities are segregatedfrom others. These entities serve as the
natural objects of our attention, action, and understanding. Exactly what
types of information are used and how they are used to define theseenti-
ties, which are the natural objects of our attention, is what a theory of
perception should give us.
Crucially, that which is being attended to can be distinguished from
that which is not being attendedto in purely spatiotemporal terms. This is
what allows for the possibility of a given entity (describedin purely spa-
tiotemporal terms) being understood (in nonspatiotemporal terms) in
more than one way by a given person (e.g., as a table or as somewood),
or in different ways by different people. The fact that we can disagree
about what somethingis, or think about it in more than one way, requires
that we be able to attend to the thing in a manner that is independentof
our understandingof that thing. That is, the perception of an entity has to
be autonomous of its conception (Macnamara and Reyes 1994a). Note
that this claim doesnot rule out the possibility of top-down influencesin
perception; rather, it claims only that it is possibleto perceiveentities in a
manner that is independent of any particular way of understanding the
nature of the thing- how often this happens, or how easythis is to do, is
another matter. In fact, sentencessuch as (4), which are noncommittal
with respectto the nature of an entity, are rare except perhapsin archae-
ological contexts. The claim of autonomy also does not imply that the
perceptualproperties of an entity are not related to how it is conceived; it
only means that there are principles of conception that are distinct from ,
and are not solely determinedby, principles of perception and! or percep-
tual properties.
Names for Things and Stuff 121
in the creation of this particular structure and not some other structure ,
we must cite certain functional properties of the created structure as being
the reason why the carpenter created this structure and not some other
structure .! In the case of natural kinds such as plants or animals , the fact
that they have the particular structures they have can be explained by
citing the fact that these structures allow the organisms to function in var -
ious ways that allow them to grow , maintain , and reproduce themselves.
To summarize , the principle of growth and maintenance (often called
the efficient cause) is responsible for changes in the structure of matter
and is the cause of a determinate structure . This structure (often called the
formal cause), in turn , is the cause of certain functional properties ' being
present. These functional properties (often called the final cause), in turn ,
are the cause of the existence or continued existence of the process of
growth and maintenance . Thus , there is a single formal cause that has
three aspects or components , rather than three independent causes. This
cause is called the substantial form or sometimes just form orformal cause;
but it should be understood that this term does not refer to shape but to
the complex cause discussed above .
The introduction of the formal cause into matter causes it to cease
being matter and become the matter of the object that results. This is not
simply a terminological distinction , but a metaphysical distinction . It
involves a change from something that is essentially matter to something
that is essentially an object . Recall that matter lacks any determinate
structure , and any structure that is present in an amount of matter is
accidental and is not due to its material nature . It follows that any unity
that is found in an amount of matter (e.g., a piece of wood ) is also acci-
dental and not due to its material nature . The unity is merely spatio -
temporal and is not due to its material essence. This is the reason why the
matter would survive as the same matter even if it lost its spatiotemporal
unity (e.g., by being broken into separate pieces). The introduction of the
formal cause into matter changes all this . The structure of the matter
found in an object is not accidental but is due to the substantial form .
Furthermore , the unity found in the matter of an object is not accidental
or merely spatiotemporal but is due to its substantial nature . It is essen-
tially a unitary object . The unity is due to the fact that it is the product of
a process directed at creating a structure of a particular kind that is
essential for its functioning in ways that are responsible for the existence
and/ or continued existence of the process and the object itself .
124 Prasada
7.3 AristotelianEssences
person loses a foot , he or she stops being human ? Clearly not . Aristotle
would agree with our intuitions that a person who loses a foot continues
Another example one might give relates to the problem of essentialism . Here is
a lectern . A question which has often been raised in philosophy is: What are its
essential properties ? What properties , aside from trivial ones like self-identity , are
such that this object has to have them if it exists at all , are such that if an object
did not have it , it would not be this object ? ( Kripke 1971, 178- 179)
Essentialism : Among the properties that things have, some are essential: that is,
they are those properties that make the thing what it is, and without which it
would not be that kind of thing . ( Lakoff 1987, 161; original emphasis)
To see why Aristotle does not pursue this strategy in determining essence,
we must recognize first that the essence, for Aristotle , is not a set of nec-
essary and sufficient properties or a probabilistic cluster of properties .
Instead , an Aristotelian essence is the cause that defines what something
is. This is why it provides an adequate response to the question " What is
it ?" In this respect, the Aristotelian view of essencesis similar to " psycho -
logical essentialism" (e.g., Medin and Ortony 1989; Keil 1989; Gelman ,
Coley , and Gottfried 1994) . Although the exact relation between the
present proposal and psychological essentialism is unclear , one way to
think about the foffi1er is as an explicit proposal concerning what con-
stitutes an essencefor us and the basis upon which we distinguish essential
and nonessential properties .
In the case of an object such as a human being , the essenceis the sub-
stantial foffi1 that , by infoffi1ing the appropriate kind of matter , gives rise
to a human being . Recall that the substantial form is the process of
Namesfor ThingsandStuff 129
and wood in (1) and (2). I propose that the account of objects and matter
developedin this chapter constitutes a plausible theory of the semantic
markers 'object' and 'material' and that an adequateaccount of the ref-
erenceof terms such as table and wood requires thesemarkers.
Given this account, we can characterizewhat is involved in the acqui-
sition of the words table and wood in an ostensivecontext as follows. A
demonstrativedirects the learner's attention to a spatiotemporally defined
entity. Next, the learner must decide(unconsciously) whether the entity is
an object of somesort or simply an amount of matter. Actually , what the
learner really has to decide is whether the speaker, in using the word to
refer to the entity in question, does so with the intention of referring to it
as an object or as some matter. Insofar as the learner makes the wrong
guess, the learner will have interpreted the word " incorrectly." This, of
course, is the reasonwhy as pragmatically competent usersof a language
we would never chooseto teach the word wood through an ostensivedefi-
nition such as (2) in which the entity in question is a table if we knew that
the learner did not know that the name for that kind of object is table. If
we were to teach wood in this context, we would probably do so by first
teaching the object name and then making the relation of the material
name to the object explicit (e.g., " This is a table. The table is made of
wood" ). In general, we would chooseto introduce a material name such
as wood through a sentencesuch as (2) only if the entity in question was
unlikely to be construed as an object, as when the entity is irregularly
shaped and has no obvious structure-dependent properties. Pragmatic
competencemay minimize the probability of miscommunication but does
not, in and of itself, provide us with an analysis of what is involved in
learning a word like table, and how (or if ) this differs from what is
involved in learning a word like wood. In fact, the type of pragmatic com-
petencedescribedhere probably makes crucial use of this infoffi1ation.
In deciding that the entity is essentiallyan object, the learner interprets
the novel word as referring to all objects of that kind . In doing so, the
learner has posited that the entity is essentiallya unit and that the struc-
ture that is present in the entity is (for the most part) the product of a
process directed at creating that structure, which, in turn, functions
in ways that are the reason for the (continued) existenceof the process
itself.9 The decision about whether to think of the entity as an object or
an amount of matter is made upon the evidenceavailable to the learner.
In addition to the perceptual cuesdiscussedin section 7.2, adult learners
can usethe foffi1 classof the entity to deteffi1inewhether the entity should
134 Prasada
something like (7). However , it does not make sense to say something like
(8a,b) .
(8) a. It turns out that tables are ( just ) wood ./ It turns out tables are
(simply ) matter .
b . It turns out that hunks of wood are organisms .
in question to be. The change in belief can be expressed through the use of
sentences such as (9a,b) in which the entities in question are referred to
through the use of thing , which , like entity , is noncommittal with respect
to whether the entity is essentially a unit or not (Macnamara 1994).
Names
for ThingsandStuff 135
(9) a. Those things we thought were tables are simply hunks of wood.
b. Those things we thought were simply hunks of wood are tables.
Note that we may appeal to experts to decidewhen we should make this
type of revision (Putnam 1975); however, nothing experts could tell us
would allow us to meaningfully make statementssuch as those expressed
in (8a,b). The distinct logic of the terms table and wood derivesfrom their
status as namesfor objects and matter that are essentiallyunits and non-
units. Thus, learning words like table and wood requires the ability to
construe entities as essentiallybeing units or nonunits. The Aristotelian
conception of objects and matter allows us to formulate what this ability
consists in, and provides a characterization of what the form of the
essences in the two casesis, such that whether the entity is thought of as a
unit or not follows as a consequence .! 1
7.6 AbstractDefinitionsandtheRepresentation
of Superordinate
Concepts
Notes
4. In this and all other conditions in this and the next experiment, there was no
differencein subjects' preferencefor either of the two massnoun locutions (There
is a piece ofblicket in the tray/ There is blicket in the tray).
5. It is important to quality this claim. There are entities such as those things that
we call clouds, rocks, pebbles, and boulders that we tend to think of as objects
rather than pieces of stuff, and yet we do not believe that these entities are the
result of processesthat are directed at creating the structure that the entities have.
Why is it , then, that we treat theseentities as objectsrather than as piecesof stuff?
There are three possibilities. First, it is possiblethat the above account of what it
meansto conceiveof an entity as an object of somekind rather than as an amount
of solid material is sufficient but not necessaryand thus there are other ways in
which we can conceive of entities as objects of some kind rather than as an
amount of solid material of some kind. Second, it is possible that thesecounter-
examplesshow that the account is wrong and there is a single alternative account
of what is involved in conceiving of entities as objects of somekind rather than as
amounts of material of somekind. Third , it is possiblethat the account accurately
representswhat is involved in our conceiving of entities as objects of some kind
and as amounts of matter; however, the world presentsus with casesthat seemto
fall betweenthesetwo conceptual schemesthat are given by our ontology, and we
assimilate them as best we can. The intermediate casesbetray their problems in
being variable from languageto language, in the existenceof ambidextrouslexical
items within a single language (e.g., a stone/made of stone), and in the largely
arbitrary baseson which thesethings in the world are thought of as objectsand as
stuff (e.g., pebblesf*gravels). Although it remains an open question which of these
possibilities is right, the third has the advantageof providing a natural explana-
tion of various " problematic" aspectsassociatedwith the conceptualization of
theseentities, whereasthe first two would render rocks and stonesequally good
objects as dogs and tables and thus would require some other way of accounting
for their " problematic" aspects.
6. Lakoff does not endorsethis or any other view of essentialism
; however, the
quotation provides a conciseexpressionof the common view of essentialism.
7. The interpretation of genericstatementsinvolves many complexities. Here, I am
concernedonly with using it as a tool to illustrate the manner in which our con-
ceptual systemsdistinguish essentialand nonessentialproperties. For a discussion
of some of the complexitiesinvolved in the interpretation of genericsentences
, see
Chomsky 1975aand the referencescited therein.
8. For an application of this insight to artifact kind terms from a psychological
perspective, seeBloom 1996a.
9. The qualification on the characterization of the structure is necessarybecause
particular substanceshave the structure they do by virtue of their essenceas well
as other causes. Therefore, one of the tasks that facesthe learner is to determine
which aspectsof the structure are causedessentiallyand which are due to other
causes.
Namesfor ThingsandStuff 143
11 . It might be suggested that what is crucial here is the " standard " distinction
between concepts of objects and substance (which presumably are conceived of as
units and nonunits , respectively ) rather than the Aristotelian conception of objects
and substances . The question , of course , is just how this " standard " distinction
between our concept of an object of some kind and a material of some kind is
represented and how the representation entails , rather than stipulates , viewing the
entity as a unit or nonunit . The Aristotelian conception of things and stuff does
just this .
13 . The general idea that the difference between the representation of count and
mass nouns for superordinate categories is related to whether multiple instances of
a category are used for some common function is also found in McCawley 1975 /
1979 , Wierzbicka 1985 , and Wisniewski , Imai , and Casey 1996 ; however , the
present account differs from these proposals in degree of explicitness as well as
substance . Space limitations prevent an adequate discussion of the similarities and
differences .
References
Hall , D . G . ( 1996 ) . Naming solids and nonsolids : Children ' s default construals .
Cognitive Development , 11 , 229 - 264 .
Lakoff , G . ( 1987 ) . Women , fire , and dangerous things : What categories reveal
about the mind . Chicago : University of Chicago Press .
Soja, N . N ., Carey , S., and Spelke, E . ( 1991). Ontological categories guide young
children 's inductions of word meaning : Object tenus and substance terms . Cogni -
tion , 38 , 179 - 211 .
[s]emiotic holds a unique place among the sciences . It may be possible to say that
every empirical science is engaged in finding data which can serve as reliable signs ;
it is certainly true that every science must embody its results in linguistic signs . . . .
The sciences must look to semiotic for the concepts and general principles relevant
to their own problems of sign analysis . Semiotic is not merely a science among
sciences but an organon or instrument of all sciences . ( 1938 , 56 )
logical theory, including modal logic, but also phenomenathat fall within
what theorists such as Jerry Katz regard to be in the domain of semantics.
For Morris , " [s]emanticsdealswith the relation of signs to their desig-
nata and so the objectswhich they mayor do denote" (1938, 21). A word
must be said about 'designatum' and 'denotation'. According to Morris ,
" The designatum of a sign is the kind of object which the sign applies
to . . ." (1938, 5). Morris assimilates'kind' to 'classof objects'. Every sign
must have a designatum, he claims; that is, it must designatea class of
objects. However, it is not necessarythat every sign denote an object.
Consider 'Santa Claus'. This sign, on Morris 's view, designatesthe Santa
Claus unit class, but the class is empty. Hence, 'Santa Claus' does not
denote anything. (In a later work , Morris replaces 'designatum' with
'significatum' and gives it a behavioristic analysis, but it is not necessary
for our purpose to follow him into this dead end.) For every sign, Morris
holds, there is a semanticalrule that " determinesunder which conditions
a sign is applicable to an object or situation" (1938, 23). The form such
rules take is " The sign vehicle 'x' designatesthe conditions a, b, c . . . . . .
under which it is applicable" (1938, 24). If an object or situation, y, meets
the conditions, a, b, c, . . . , then ' x' denotesy . Morris 's view of semanticsis
quite close in many respectsto Carnap's. In recent years, a number of
decisivecriticisms have been raised against this conception of semantics
by Kripke , Putnam, Quine, and others, but I want to pass over these
problems and turn to Morris 's views about pragmatics.
Pragmatics, Morris claims, is " the study [of ] the relation of signs to
interpreters" (1938, 6). To have an understanding of Morris 's view of
pragmatics, we must understandhis use of 'interpreter' and 'interpretant'.
Semiosis, according to Morris , involves four factors: " that which acts as a
sign, that which the sign refers to, and that effect on some interpreter in
virtue of which the thing in questionis a sign to that interpreter" (1938, 3).
This gives us the sign vehicle, the designatum, the interpretant, and the
interpreter. Interpreters are agentsthat " take account" of the designatum
of signs. " Taking account" is a central notion in Morris 's semiotic, to
which he attachesthe technical term 'interpretant'. Morris gives a behav-
ioristic account of this notion. The interpretant of a sign is " the habit of
the organism to respond, becauseof the sign vehicle, to absent objects
which are relevant to a present problematic situation as if they were
present" (1938, 31). This givesrise in pragmatics to a pragmatic rule that
is, Morris says, " the habit of the interpreter to use the sign vehicle under
certain circumstancesand, conversely, to expect such and such to be the
154 Davis
case when the sign is used" ( 1938, 32) . Here we see the tight connection
between Morris ' s views about semiotic and behaviorism . He takes it that
Morris claims that the behavioristic account that he gives of the basic
notions of semiotic is not necessary ( 1938, 6). Well that it is not , since
behaviorism is inadequate for the purpose . Sentences, for Morris , are
signs that are supposed to be connected with interpretants , that is, a habit
of the interpreter to respond . For there to be a habit , there must be con-
ditioning . And for there to be conditioning with respect to a particular
stimulus , there must have been past exposure of the subject to the stimu -
lus. But there can be no such conditioning and thus no such habit , as
Chomsky has taught us, connected with sentences. The reason is that
most of the sentences we hear and use are novel . We have never heard or
uttered them before ; hence , there can be no habit connected to their
comprehension or use.
It might be thought that Morris 's behaviorism can be sustained for
subsentential units . We can imagine that there are habits connected to all
or some of the morphemes in a language . Syntax , then , would be a system
that operates over these habits and composes them into habits connected
to sentences. There are many objections to this compositional behavior -
ism . First , there are many morphemes for which it makes no sense to
connect them with a habit . What , after all , would be the habit connected
with the syncategoric expressions 'the' , 'and ' , or 'but '? Second, the mini -
mum unit of use is a sentence. Therefore , for a morpheme to be connected
with a habit , it must be possible to use it as a one-word sentence. Some
nouns and verbs , like ' red ' , ' chair ' , ' run ' , and ' horse ' , pass the test , but
Unity of Science 155
It does not follow from the inclusion of the study of science within semi-
otic that the phenomena that the scientist studies are themselves signs,
in Morris ' s sense of 'sign' . For example , the solar system itself is not a
system of signs; rather , the theory that describes it is supposed to be such
a system and thus , open to study by semiotic . There is another sense in
which certain theories in the human sciences fall within semiotic . Morris
claims that many of the actual phenomena studied by the human sciences
are themselves systems of signs; for example , various sorts of ritual
156 Da vis
give explanations for a restricted range of data and that are constrained in
various ways by the data they are supposed to explain and by the ordi -
Notes
1 . There is some variation in the term used for the study of signs . Morris uses
semiotic , following Locke and Pierce ; Margaret Mead uses semiotics ; and Roland
semiology . ( For a discussion of these variants , see Morris ' s quotation from Sebeok
in Morris 1971 , 9 .)
2 . It might seem that I am beating a dead horse and that Morris ' s wide view of
pragmatics is only of historical interest . I began the chapter by citing the under -
pragmatics , including Mey , Ostman , and Verschueren ( see Mey 1993 ; Ostman
1988 ; Verschueren 1987 ).
References
Carnap , R . ( 1934 ) . The unity of science . London : Kegan Paul , Trench , Trubner .
Davidson , D . ( 1984 ) . Inquiries into truth and interpretation . New York : Oxford
University Press .
You must inquire into all, both the untrembling heart of well-rounded uncon-
cealment and the opinions of mortals, in which there is no unconcealing assur-
ance. Yet nonethelessthese too you shall learn, as the seemingthings one must
intend to prove to be (though, through it all, all of them transgressall assurances
),
becauseall are pervading everything.
The Goddessof Day to Parmenides
idea what a joyful graduate experience awaited me , for I had never met
him . But I had two good reasons for wanting him to supervise my grad -
uate work . First , out of all the psychological theories on language and
cognition , his were the only ones that really made good sense to me . His
other theories did . Second , when I asked around to find out what his
former graduate students thought of him , I was told , " They adore him ."
I was intrigued .
always seems to point me in the right direction . Many of the insights are taken
wholly from him , including some of the insights regarding the original senses of
ous old works , relevant to changes in these concepts . Further , his comments and
grateful to him . This chapter benefited also from useful comments from David
Alexandre Nicolas , Ray Jackendoff , and Keith Niall . And I thank my dear
departed friend and mentor John Macnamara for creating such beautiful theories
9.1 Theory
The word theory derives from the Greek theoria, 'a viewing' or 'a
beholding'. Ideally, a theory should result from a theorist's viewing or
beholding (or noetic perception) of being,2 and it should permit others
to behold that being. At a minimum, this implies that any conceptguiding
a theorist's thinking and transmitted to others along with a theory must
originate in an authentic and relatively complete conception of being of
some sort, and that the theory must be compatible with each such con-
cept. What a theorist must do (and avoid doing) to ensuretheseoutcomes
will becomeclear.
cannot even state his or her thesis without making covert use of inten -
tions . When Churchland ( 1984) claims that the commonsense (or " folk
psychology " ) conception of the mind as intentional " is a false and radi -
cally misleading conception of the causes of human behavior and the
nature of cognitive activity " ( p . 43; emphasis added), he uses the essen-
tially intentional notions of falsity and a conception . When he says of folk
psychology , considered as " an empirical theory ," that " its ontology is an
illusion " ( 1981, 72; emphasis added), he implies that theories are about
(illusory or real) being and therefore intentional ; and since an illusion is a
type of intentional state (i .e., perceiving something as other than what it
is), one cannot sensibly dismiss the intentional states in the ontology of
the folk theory as illusions . Eliminativists cannot even maintain , without
Scientific
Theories That Unconceal Being 165
The whole of the scientific enterprise involves goals (e.g., the goal of
generating hypotheses from a theory , and the goal of obtaining evi-
dence in support of those hypotheses) and intentions of other kinds (e.g.,
desires for procedural rigor in experiments , perception and a belief in the
veracity of one' s sensesduring observation , and assertions about experi -
mental results) ; as Baker (1987) argues, " Without intentionality science
would be impossible " (p . 173; see also Garfield 1988, 112- 116). More -
over , I cannot see how a scientific theory could be meaningful - some-
thing other than a word game or a kind of dream - unless it permitted the
mind to intend being .
To make sense of what follows , the reader would do well to resist
An inability to refer to the external would also make obscure the meaning
of an indexical or demonstrative such as this, that , here, or there (espe-
cially in discourse contexts in which it had no antecedent) and would
leave us with no way to account for its obvious kinship with (and frequent
concomitance with ) an indexical gesture such as pointing , nodding , or
gazing toward something so as to indicate to another person an object of
thought ; one does not (and cannot ) point , nod , or gaze in the direction of
one's own mental representations . It is apparent that , as Putnam ( 1973)
says, " 'meanings ' just ain 't in the head" ( p . 704).5
Sometimes some relation of a nonsymbolic representation to being is
imagined to ground or give meaning to a symbol or formula . But theorists
fail to characterize this relation in any way that could explain reference or
interpretation , or that would permit scientists to theorize about the being
represented.
This relation to being is most popularly described as a map or function
from the representations to states of affairs in the extrapsychic world (e.g.,
Millikan 1984). But no such function could explain reference because it
presupposes reference. .Unless the mind already had the capacity to refer ,
such a function could not be computed in the mind because, though the
arguments of the function (representations ) could be in the mind , its
values (extrapsychic states of affairs ) could not .
Some (e.g., Palmer ( 1978) seem to think that the mere (objective )
existence of a similarity , correspondence , or isomorphism will , by itself ,
do the trick - that such a correspondence with being is what we really
mean by reference or intention (or at least representation). But that is not
enough . Mental images or models could not , just by means of corre -
spondences, determine what signs signify . For one thing , they would leave
the signified indeterminate because a given one is similar to , corresponds
to , or is isomorphic to many beings or states of affairs , and is similar to ,
corresponds to , or is isomorphic to a given being or state of affairs in
many different ways, " representing " the truth -conditions of many differ -
ent sentences and the referents of many different signs (see Cummins
1996; Fodor 1990; Putnam 1981) . The correspondence to the signified
being that is relevant to reference and truth -conditions would have to
be singled out somehow . It could not be singled out by stipulation (cf .
Morris 1991), since stipulating that the correspondence between this and
this or stipulating that this correspondence between a representation and
being of a given kind is the relevant correspondence presupposes reference
(to the representa ti on , the represented being , and , perhaps, the corre -
Scientific Theories That Unconceal Being 169
earth. In his contemplation, John seemsto have kept his mind in direct
intentional contact with the objects of linguistic intentions. Those who
knew John will know that the earth he turned over most frequently was
the being intended in interpreting the sentenceFreddie is a dog. The late
Freddie was a large black poodle who shared his life with John and his
family . The fact that the sign Freddiecan still be usedto pick out a certain
dog, who is no longer with us, as well as a certain pup who was born in
Montreal, that it can be used to pick out the samedog even in counter-
factual situations (such as one in which Freddie was adopted by other
humans), and other such facts led John to his theory about the nature of
the being into which a proper name is interpreted. The theory accounts
well for the facts of interpretation for proper nouns, and reveals or
unconcealsor brings to light the nature of the being implicitly and sponta-
neously understood to bear a proper name in every instance of the inter-
pretation of a proper name.
John's choice of a declarative sentence(Freddie is a dog) as the focus of
his contemplation may have facilitated his discovery of the nature of that
being. A declarative sentenceis the only type of utterance that can be
judged true or false, and, when true, it unconcealsbeing of some sort to
the mind (which is why the Greeks used the word aletheia, 'unconceal-
ment', for truth ; see Aristotle , On Interpretation 1, 16a9- 18; 4, 16b33-
17a4); and so a true declarative sentencecan bring the mind into direct
intentional or noetic contact with being. Contemplation of an isolated
word may not permit such contact, for a word by itself may not actually
signify; a word uttered or written in isolation, such as " person" or
" green," doesnot seemto aim the mind at any definite or particular being
or beings; it may only potentially signify (i.e., have the potential to signify)
by virtue of one's having conceiveda concept of, or formulated a defini-
tion of, the kind of being it would actually signify in a referring expression
in accordancewith a convention of a speechcommunity. (And this may
explain the Greeks' use of the word dunamis, 'power' or 'potentiality', for
the force of an individual word.)6 When a word is out of context, one
cannot even determine on which side of the use/mention distinction it
falls, that is, whether it is to be interpreted in its signifying function or as a
string of soundsor letters (La Palme Reyeset al. 1993).
1994) . Brentano ( 1838- 1917) was, along with Wilhelm Wundt , one of the
first empirically minded psychologists . Neither Wundt nor Brentano
advocated the use of the methods of the natural sciencesin psychology (see
Macnamara 1992, 1993) . Brentano advocated the use of inner perception
as the proper empirical technique for a genuine science of psychology (see
Brentano 1924) .
Brentano maintained - and quite rightly , I believe- that all and only
psychological phenomena are intentional ; in any psychological phenom -
enon, the mind is turned toward - the attention is focused on- something
as its object . Psychology , then , is the science of the intentional . Brentano
argued that one can study intentions directly only by means of inner per-
ception , which he described thus : 'Only while one's attention is turned
toward another object , it happens that one also incidentally arrives at the
perception of psychical events that are referred toward it [i .e., the other
object ]' ( 1924, 41) .7 In the context of semantics, this means that when
a sign or combination of signs makes one' s mind intend something as
its object , one can perceive or notice or become aware of aspects of the
intention such as the conditions under which it arises , its character , and
this series
. . . . Theserelationscanbe multipliednearlyto infinity by fictions[i.e.,
formationsor inventions ] or reflexionsof the intellect. (1597/1965, 1041
)
A first intention, then, in the original sense, is an aiming of the mind
directly at real being. A secondintention is reflex (reflexus, 'bent back',
directed toward itself ), with the mind turning toward or intending some
of its own contents, namely, concepts; if it turns toward the real being of
which they are concepts, it does so only secondarily. Secondintentions
toward or reflection upon conceptscan give rise to a new concept, which
was also called a secondintention. As Suareznoted, the being of reason
so conceived can then be taken up as the object of further reflexive
intellection to conceive further concepts, as when one conceivesa rela-
tion through reflecting upon the concept of a ratio and conceptsof com-
parative being such as being greater than and being lessthan, where some
of these concepts have themselvesbeen conceived by second intentions
(e.g., the concept of a ratio is conceivedthrough reflection upon the con-
cepts of double, triple, etc.).
How is this distinction betweenfirst and secondintentions relevant to
theorizing? If a being of reason can be the object of an intention in the
reflection that permits new conceptions, then surely it can be the same
in theoretical reflection. Now when a theorist makes use of a second-
intentional concept such as that of a relation, the theorist's mind aims at
this being of reason. If the theorist's mind is to fall upon any real being, it
must then aim toward one of the conceptsthat gave rise to the second-
intentional concept, a concept such as that of being greater than, and it
can only then aim at any being that is an instanceof a relation (just as the
mind, when thinking of the genus ANIMAL , can only fall upon a par-
ticular animal after aiming toward a concept of someparticular speciesof
animal). But the theorist's mind need never be redirected toward any real
being; the theorist may think about a relation without ever thinking about
specificinstancesof it in being, such as the ratio of the magnitude of one
of the long sidesof a certain rectangleto the magnitude of one of its short
sides. Suppose, though, that in someinstancesat least the theorist's mind
doescontinue to be redirecteduntil it comesinto intentional contact with
real being. A conceptis, by necessity, the result of a partial conception (or
a partial taking into the mind) of the real being that gave rise to it , and
especiallyso when the concept is conceivedby secondintentions. When
somereal being is viewed " through" a being of reason or concept (i.e., as
an instance of the being of which it is a concept) , the concept servesas a
kind of filter , focusing the attention so as to limit the experienceof the
Scientific
Theories
ThatUnconceal
Being 177
[" The disciplines ," said I ,] " which we said did lay hold of being to some extent ,
geometry and also those [disciplines ] attending it , are, as we see, dreaming about
being , but a waking vision of it is impossible for them to behold so long as they
leave unstirred the suppositions being used, not being able to offer an account
of them . For when the origin is not examined , and the conclusion as well as the
intervening steps are interwoven out of that which is not examined , what means
178 McPherson
can ever transform taken -for -grantedness such as this into understanding ?"
" None , " said he .
For a theory to be truly meaningful , the theorist must conduct such a dig
through the layers of sensein any concept that guides the interpretation of
Scientific
Theories
ThatUnconceal
Being 179
a sign used in stating the theory and , having uncovered the original sense,
examine that sense to make sure it is true to carefully sifted intuitions
arising from first intentions - for even the original sense may carry con-
ceptual baggage inherited from earlier thought . And so Husserl (1954/
1970) said,
A theoretical task and achievement . . . can only be and remain meaningful in a
true and original sense if the scientist has developed in himself the ability to inquire
back into the original meaning of all his meaning -structures and methods , i .e., into
the historical meaning of their primal establishment , and especially into the mean-
ing of all the inherited meanings taken over unnoticed in this primal establishment ,
as well as those taken over later on . ( p . 56)
Few theorists currently see the need to inquire back into the original
sense and the acquired sensesof any given concept . A concept 's contem -
porary sense is typically regarded as evident and not in need of examina -
tion , and it is imagined to have been immutable across generations . The
concept gives the impression of what Husserl called Selbstverstiindlichkeit ,
literally 'self-understandability ' or 'self-intelligibility ' . Harvey ( 1989)
describes this " obviousness" as the " taken -for -grantedness" of inherited
ideas. H usserl argued tha t taking a concept for gran ted leads to 'sense
depletion ' (Sinnentleerung); the concept comes to reflect less and less the
being from which it originated .
To the degree to which a concept is sedimented and depleted of sense,
theories that make use of a sign interpreted in keeping with that concept
fail to reveal the nature of being , and the science that permits itself to be
guided by those theories is not sound, for it is not anchored to being . For
this reason, Husserl cautioned scientists against adopting and using sci-
entific concepts and terms in a thoughtless way :
It is easy to see that even in [ordinary ] human life , and first of all in every
individual life from childhood up to maturity , the originally intuitive life which
creates its originally self-evident structures through activities on the basis of sense-
experience very quickly and in increasing measure falls victim to the seduction of
language. Greater and greater segments of this life lapse into a kind of talking and
reading that is dominated purely by association ; and often enough , in respect to
the validities arrived at in this way , it is disappointed by subsequent experience .
Now one will say that in the sphere that interests us here- that of science, of
thinking directed toward the attainment of truths and the avoidance of falsehood
- one is obviously greatly concerned from the start to put a stop to the free play
of associative constructions . In view of the unavoidable sedimentation of mental
cate. An " archaeological dig" into the layers of sensein these concepts
will , moreover, be of benefit to theorists becauseof their wide usein scien-
tific theories. These three concepts are examined together becausesedi-
mentation in the number concept was accompaniedby sedimentationin
the concept of a relation, and the latter contributed to sedimentation in
the concept of a predicate.
I will not attempt to give a complete or fully documented history of
changes in each concept. (See McPherson 1995, apps. A and B, for
somewhat fuller treatments.) I aim only to give the reader a feel for the
ways in which scientific conceptscan changeand what sorts of forces can
drive the changes. I begin, in each case, with a description of the concept
as it was understood in classical Greece, for I have concluded (on the
basisof my studiesof relevant Greek texts) that when theseconceptswere
conceivedby Greek scholars (some of the first thinkers to treat of them
thoughtfully), they arose from these thinkers' own reflections upon con-
cepts arising from first intentions. In each case, the original senseof the
concept will be seen to come from conceptions of things present in or
somehow depending upon real being, whereas the current senseof the
concept is such as to lead to the conclusion that its conception did not
involve any real being; it is, rather, an ensrationis in the most literal sense,
something that can reside only in the mind.
9.7.1 Numbers
Naturalnumbersweremadeby God; the restis the work of man.
LeopoldKronecker
between items being counted , where the items are individual beings of one
species; a monad may have been understood to separate or partition off
one individual as it was added to a collection of individuals already sep-
arated out in counting (as Robert H . Schmidt has argued , in conversa-
tion ; alternatively , a monad may have been understood as a resting -place
or stopping -place, mone, for the movements (say, of a finger or hand )
making up the act of separating out an individual as items are counted in
succession- as the telos or end of one cycle of movements during count -
ing ). This thesis is compatible with Aristotle 's description of counting as
'by parts ' or 'by portions ' (kata meridas), which implies separating some-
thing out and setting it apart or allotting it , and as 'takings in [or addi -
tions ]' (proslambanontes ; Metaphysics M .7, IO82b34- 36), as well as his
description of a count (i .e., a number ;9 arithmos ) as 'a delimited multi -
tude ' (plethos peperasmenon; Metaphysics !! .13, 1020a13) and Eudoxus 's
definition of a count as 'a multitude marked [or separated] out by bound -
aries' (plethos horismenon; see Klein 1934- 1936/ 1968, 51). It is also com -
patible with Aristotle 's characterization of monads as being one after
another or in succession (ephexes; Physics E .3, 227a29- 30), his descrip-
tion of a monad (along with a point , a line , and a plane) as something by
which a body gets marked (or separated) out by boundaries (or bounded ,
defined , or delimited ; ( toutoij horistai to soma; Metaphysics B.5, 1002a4-
6), and his description of a count or counting (arithmos ) as that which
marks (or separates) out by boundaries (or bounds , defines, or delimits )
all things (horizein panta ; Metaphysics ~ .8, 1017b20- 21). The thesis
accords as well with a statement of Nicomachus : 'By means of the monad ,
all the counts having begun from the dyad , being separated out together
one after another , generate the orderly species of that which is multiple in
the proper sequence' (see Klein 1934- 1936/ 1968, 52, for the Greek ).
If monads were, in addition or instead , understood by some mathema -
ticians to be the items of counting themselves, they nonetheless seem not
to have been regarded as separate from real beings, but rather as present
in real beings. 10A monad (monas, 'aloneness' , derived from monos, 'alone '
or 'solitary ') seems sometimes to have been understood as the oneness in
an atomic being as isolated by abstraction in the Greek sense, that is,
what is left over in an atom (e.g., a cat) when all its particular properties
other than its oneness- a oneness concomitant with its indivisibility as
something informed by its eidos or species (or " basic-level kind " ; see
Aristotle , Metaphysics B .3, 999al - 6; ~ .6, 1016b3- 6; M .3, 1078a23- 25)-
are mentally stripped away from it . (See Metaphysics K .3, 1061a29- 35,
Scientific
Theories
ThatUnconceal
Being 183
When the Hindu -Arabic numeric notation became popular in the West ,
late in the twelfth century , the symbols seem initially to have been
understood in just the same way as the Roman numeral V, namely , as
shorthand marks or proxies for collections of strokes on paper that
were counterparts for collections of individuals of any kind whatsoever .
( Leonardo of Pisa- now known as Leonardo Fibonacci - called his book
of 1202 on Hindu -Arabic numeric symbols and algebra Liber Abbaci ,
'Book of the Abacus ' . The new numeric symbols would have brought to
mind an abacus because both the counters on an abacus and the digits
of a Hindu -Arabic numeral were understood as counterparts in a place-
value system.) Alternatively , the symbols may have been understood as
proxies for Roman numerals , which were either counterparts for collec -
tions of individuals or shorthand or proxies for such counterparts
(Schmidt 1986).
Over time , this understanding of the symbols was lost ; mathematicians
began to forget that their symbols were originally intended to be proxies
for counterparts . As a result , the symbols began to lose their conceptual
tie with collections of individuals , and the number concept began to
change correspondingly , losing its basis in multitude .
With collections of individuals no longer consciously guiding the con-
ception of number , the concept became more inclusive . Proper fractions
were reinterpreted as numbers ; ratios (newly interpreted as quotients ) of
whole numbers and of commensurable magnitudes were reinterpreted as
(rational ) numbers ; and ratios of incommensurable magnitudes were
reinterpreted as (irrational ) numbers (or at least this seems to be the way
Scientific Theories That U nconcealBeing 185
cessfully promote their use. Acceptance of this notation could lead one to
believe that there is a number for every possible decimal expansion , so
that the numbers can fill up a continuum .
186 McPherson
All that is just a quantity is not at all a disjunct quantity . Sixty , according as it is
number , is a quantity (that is to say a number ) . Sixty , then , according as it is
number , is not at all a disjunct quantity . As for that which you divide by your
imagination , this proposed unique and whole quantity , into sixty unities [or units]
(which you could divide , by equal reason, into thirty dualities , or twenty trinities ,
etc.), and which then you next define [to be] the divided up , that is not definition of
the proposed of which there is some question : you could similarly divide the pro -
posed magnitude , by the imagination , into sixty parts , and then by equal reason
define it to be discontinuous quantity , which is absurd . ( 1585/ 1958a, 501- 502;
emphasis added)
about the original sense ( see also Schmidt 1986 ) . The Hindu - Arabic
opening the door to the imposition of a new layer of sense upon the
number concept ( with the new sense apparently seeping into mathematics
magnitude , fully covered over the original sense after the introduction
9 . 7 . 2 Relations
number as continuous . The ratio was the prototypical relation for mathe -
magnitude , the object of the relation . A relation of any sort was under -
stood in this way , as an aspect of the being of one individual , its subject ,
( i . e . , the quotient ) . We call the numbers that are identified with the new
as a number whether or not the result was a whole number . Even before
(i .e., for its heliacal rising ). So the word strongly suggests something that
was hidden coming to light or becoming manifest . The same suggestion
comes from another source. As Aristotle pointed out , apophansis is the
only kind of utterance that can be judged true or false; neither an indi -
vidual word or phrase nor a sentence of any other type (e.g., a question , a
prayer , a request, or a command ) can be said to be true or false (see On
Interpretation 1, 16a9- 18; 4, 16b33- 17a4). But the Greek word translated
as 'true ' is alethes (a-leth-es), 'taking out of hiding ' or 'unconcealing ' (or
'unconcealed ') . The privative or negative prefix a- expresses want or
absence , loss , or forcible removal , and the verbal stem contained in this
adjective is that of the verb letho or lanthano , which means 'escape
notice ' , ' be unseen ' , ' be unnoticed ' , or ' be unknown ' ; in the middle and
passive voices, this verb means 'forget ' . So the word usually translated
as 'true ' suggests something failing or ceasing to escape one's notice or
remain unseen; it suggests something that was hidden or forgotten - or
something unknown - being brought to light or revealed. (The Greek
word for false is pseudes, 'deceitful ' or 'lying '; it means giving the im -
pression of unconcealing something without doing so.)
That which predication brings to light is being. This is evident in the
fact that the copula , in any language that has it , is the verb meaning
'be' . In declarative statements, the copula (whether or not it is explicit )-
which is conjugated to agree with the subject (in person and number )-
indicates that being is unconcealed from the subject.2o (When a predicate
and the copula combine with a subject, the being that is shown forth or
unconcealed from the subject- the being that the predicate signifies- is
being that depends for its existence upon the subject, its support and its
origin . When the copula combines with a subject alone , as in Socrates
was, the being unconcealed is that of the subject as a whole .) And so
Aristotle said that the 'is' in an affirmation signifies that it is true or
unconcealing (Metaphysics Ll.7, 1017a31- 34) , that being is the true or
the unconcealed , and that a true affirmation is unconcealing because the
being signified by the predicate is lying together with the being signified
by the subject (Metaphysics 0 .10, 105la34 - 1051b13) .
The nature of the experience of an unconcealment of being is revealed
in the use of the word episteme for the understanding that comes from
hearing a true apophantic utterance or a syllogism or dialectical argument
in which such utterances are properly combined . This noun is derived
from the verb epistamai , which is believed to be an old middle -voice form
of ephistemi; the latter is composed of the prepositional prefix epi, mean-
196 McPherson
ing 'upon ' , and the verb histemi , which has among its intransitive mean-
ings 'stand ', 'stand still ', and 'stand firm ' . And so the most literal meaning
of the nominal episteme (formed with the suffix -me) would seem to be
'standing upon ' , 'standing still upon ', or 'standing firm upon '; what we
call understanding (or standing under ) was called overstanding (or stand-
ing over or upon ). The standing would seem to be the mind 's standing
upon unconcealed being . Aristotle regarded this standing as a stillness or
resting of the mind - resting not in the sense of being slack, but in the
sense of being arrested by a tension in one direction : 'Mental perception
[noesis] is more like a sort of rest [or stillness] and stopping than motion '
( On the Soul A .3, 407a32- 33); 'When the discursive thought [dianoia ] has
come to rest and has come to a standstill , we are said to stand upon [or
understand ; epistasthai] and to intend [or attend ; phronein ]' (Physics H .3,
247bll - 12). The experience Aristotle described is likely the aiming of the
mind that is concomitant with an unconcealment of being ; in intending or
aiming toward being , the mind is necessarily standing firm for so long as
the being is unconcealed - for when it ceases to stand still , it will turn in
other directions , and the being toward which it was aimed will slip out of
awareness, entering into or returning to a state of escaping one's notice or
being hidden or forgotten .
The Aristotelian account of predication and of the apophansis or
showing forth that results from it implies that hearing or reading or
saying to oneself " Cats are furry " makes the being of cats' furriness -
being that originates in and depends upon cats- appear noetically to
the mind as it aims toward that being , which was escaping one's notice ,
hidden from consciousness or forgotten , and which now comes to light
(and remains in the light until the mind ceases to stand firm , aimed
toward it , and turns elsewhere) .
After the Aristotelian theory of predication was forgotten , concepts of
predication were swept every which way with the currents of philosoph -
ical movements , like shifting sediment . For a partial history of the various
views that arose, see McPherson 1995. Briefly , here are a few of those
views : According to nominalists such as William of Ockham , the subject
and the predicate are names for the same thing (and Geach ( 1962) has
thoroughly trounced this view ). In the opinion of Thomas Hobbes , they
are marks that bring to mind thoughts of the same thing . James Mill ,
influenced by Hume ' s and Hartley 's associationism , asserted that they are
names for ideas experienced in succession or concurrently . The theories of
Hobbes and Mill are examples of one general trend . Under the influence
Scientific Theories That Unconceal Being 197
Frege found that retaining the distinction between a subject and a predi -
cate in a formalized language was " obstructive of [his] special purpose "
(p . 4), namely , to model a language of thought on the formalized lan -
guage of mathematics (in which , he said, " subject and predicate can be
distinguished only by doing violence to the thought " (p . 3))- a language
to be used for drawing valid inferences. He therefore dismissed as " slight "
the difference in the sense of an active and a passive statement - a differ -
ence he seems not to have understood , for he thought that the subject is
merely that which occupies the place in the word order that the speaker
wants the hearer " to attend to specially " (p . 3). Frege failed to seethe real
difference in sense: an active predicate signifies action , and a passive one
signifies an undergoing of action . Aristotle characterized these as distinct
types of kategoria , and distinct types of being- and so they are, for to hit
and to be hit , or to defeat and to be defeated, are surely different things .
Unfortunately , Frege's view that active and passive utterances have (more
Scientific Theories That Unconceal Being 199
or less, for his purposes) the same conceptual (or semantic) content came
to be shared by many later thinkers (who saw no difference at all in sense,
irrespective of any purpose). This erroneous way of thinking likely came
to prevail when the modern concept of a relation was incorporated into
the concept of a predicate . Since a relation , in the modern sense (which
includes transitive actions), is not an aspect of the being of any particular
one of the individuals involved (but something outside all of them and
somehow connecting them ), any given relation is often assumed to be
unchanging in nature regardless of which individual involved in it is
chosen as the subject ofa sentence (though the unchanging nature attributed
to it always comes from choosing - sometimes unconsciously or tacitly
- one individual as the subject; with verbs for actions , that individual is
the one acting , so that the nature attributed to the " relation " or " predi -
cate" is active , even when the associated verb is in its passive form ). And
so the sense of defeated can be imagined to be the same in the two sen-
tences The Greeks defeated the Persians and The Persians were defeated by
the Greeks ; the second sentence , like the first , can be taken to be about an
action rather than an undergoing of action . The following consideration
may help highlight the distinct sense of the passive. The passive voice
developed out of the middle voice in ancient languages; the distinct mean-
ing of a passive utterance can thus be seen more clearly through consider -
ing an utterance with a meaning comparable to that of an utterance in the
middle voice : The Persians let themselvesbe (or got themselves) defeated by
the Greeks clearly has a different meaning than The Greeks defeated the
Persians .
. . . Since the foregoing calculus has turned out to be inadequate , we are forced
to seek a new kind of logical symbolism . For this purpose we return to that point
in our discussion at which we first went beyond the sentential calculus . The deci-
sive step there was the division of sentences into subject and predicate . . . . [ We
now ] separate in the rendering of a sentence the objects (individuals ) from the
properties (predicates ) attributed to them and . . . symbolize both explicitly .
This is done by employing functional symbols with argument places (n-adic func -
tional symbols where n is the number of argument places) for the symbolic ren-
dering of predicates , in which symbols representing objects are to be substituted in
the argument places. . . . If the relation of the smaller to the greater is expressed by
the two -place functional symbol , ), then 2, 3) is the symbolic rendering of
the sentence " 2 is less than 3 . " Likewise , the sentence " B lies between A and C "
may be rendered by Z (A , B , C ) .
All mathematical formulas represent such relations among two or more quan -
tities . For example , to the formula x + y == z there corresponds a triadic predicate
S(.,"\", y , z) . The truth of S(x , y , z) means that x , y , and z are connected by the
relation .,"\" + y == z. ( 1938/ 1950, 55- 57)
They pointed out the novelty in their use of the word predicate for the
modern " relation " in a footnote and without explanation :
Hitherto it has been customary in logic to call only functions with one argument
place predicates , while functions with more than one place were called relations .
Here we use the word " predicate " in a quite general sense. ( 1938/ 1950, 57, fn . 1)
Hilbert and Bernays first introduced the new usage of the term as follows :
We understand " predicate ," here and in what follows as well , always in a wider
sense [than the usual], so that even predicates with two or several subjects are
included . Depending on the number of subjects, we speak of " one-place," " two -
place" . . . predicates . ( 1934, 7)
9.8 SomeConsequences
of Sedimentationfor Scientific Theories
Let us not fool ourselves. All of us, including those who think professionally , as
it were, are often enough thought -poor ; we all are far too easily thought -less.
Scientific
Theories
ThatUnconceal
Being 205
templation might benefit from embeddinga word for the being of interest
in true declarative sentences . And sinceapophantic sentencesare the only
linguistic entities that can unconcealbeing, semanticiststrying to discover
the meaning of a word or the schema of meaning for a class of words
(e.g., a class of words belonging to one part of speech) should always
embed the word (or an exemplar of the part of speech) in declarative
sentencesthat they judge to be meaningful (such as Freddie is a dog) and
try to becomeaware of the nature of the being signified.
Becausestatementsin standardmodern mathematicalnotation (whether
algebraic or logical or of another sort) are not (or are not properly)
modeled after apophantic utterances, theoretical work should begin with
nonmathematical statementsand reasoning. When the being under inves-
tigation has been conceived, properly speaking, and a theory developed,
mathematical formulations can then be introduced- but they should be
introduced only with great caution, with the theorist making sure that in
formalizing a theory, he or sheis not importing sedimentedconceptsinto
the theory by virtue of the formalization. Further, if contemplations of
being reveal inadequaciesin existing mathematical conceptsand notation,
mathematical languagescan be revised or constructed so as to provide
adequateformal tools for theorists (as Macnamara (1994) argued).
All of theserecommendationspoint in the samedirection. Becausethe
mind is only in direct (noetic) contact with being in first intentions, these
must be the foundation of theoretical work . If theories are not anchored
to being by first intentions, they will drift in whateverdirections the imagi-
nation and philosophical currents take them. The result is usually a series
of theoretical fads (especiallyin psychologyand the social sciences - in the
Geisteswissenschaften - where the being under investigation- intentions,
as well as the actions that follow from them- is not, strictly speaking,
sensible, and so it does not force one's mind to turn toward it ; it even
resistsits own unconcealmentbecauseintentions are directed away from
themselves , and, being the \JTerystuff of consciousness , their constant
presencein one's waking psyche leads one to take them for granted so
that they typically escapeone's notice).22Faddish theoretical frameworks
often stimulate fruitless debates about issues irrelevant to actual phe-
nomena, which retreat into concealmentto the degreeto which the posi-
tions taken in the debates are accepted as guides to one's thinking . A
genuineresolution of such debatesis rarely found (even though one posi-
tion may come into favor by virtue of the strength of the personalities
supporting it); far more frequently, the debated issuesare forgotten as it
becomesfashionableto follow new currents.
Scientific Theories That U nconcealBeing 207
Notes
1. Edmund Husserl and Jacob Klein made use of many of these insights , either
explicitly or implicitly , in evaluating theories in modern physics and mathematics
(see Husserl1954 / 1970; Klein 1934- 1936/ 1968, 1932/ 1985) .
2. I use being as a general term for that which is, including existent and sub-
stantial beings (where beings is comparable to the Greeks ' ta onta ; it does not
necessarily refer to living things ) as well as matter and the being that inheres in ,
originates in , or otherwise depends upon beings or matter , such as qualities ,
quantities , relations , actions and passions, locations in space and time , and so on
(and being is here understood as a mass noun , comparable to the Greeks ' to
on) . What I refer to as being is not identical with the " Being " of Heidegger and
the Greek philosophers who inspired him . That Being is the proper subject of
philosophy (see Aristotle , Metaphysics r .1, 1003a21- 22; Heidegger 1927/ 1962);
theories in the special sciences deal only with parts of Being ( Metaphysics r .l ,
1003a22- 26). Wherever I use being as a count noun , it implies an individual
informed or individuated atomically by some form (or species), and where I use
being as a mass noun , the context should make clear whether I mean matter or
dependent being alone or whether I mean beings, matter , and dependent being
together .
3. For other mental phenomena , an intention arises under different conditions ,
and it is a qualitatively different kind of aiming at something as an object , origi -
nating not through activation of the noetic faculty , but of some other faculty of
the psyche. In a state of desire, for instance , a person intends something or aims
his or her mind at something by longing for it . In an instance of the perception of
sensible things , he or she intends something by perceiving it sensibly :---"
The notion of an intention entered into Scholasticism through the Islamic phi -
losophy of Al -Farabi and Avicenna . Like intentio , the word these philosophers
used for it , ma 'na (or sometimes ma 'qul ; see Engelhardt 1976), means concretely
the drawing or stretching back of a bow (which brings it into a state of tension ) in
aiming an arrow at a target . This word brings together in one concept the ideas
of aiming and tensing . The tensing that accompanies the aiming might best be
understood as the mind 's standing firm in its aiming - its tensing in that sense. But
the characterization of an intention as a tensing also brings out the fact that it can
vary in intensity , intensifying and remitting ; the standing firm in the aiming can
be more or less firm . Desires , fears , loves , angers , and so on , can be more or less
intense, and thoughts too can in some sense intensify and remit , being entertained
more or less intently , or , one might say, involving more or less attention .
208 McPherson
4. Some theorists (e.g., Chomsky ( 1992, 1995a)) seem to think that a carving up
that involves a human mind necessarily implies that what is carved up cannot be
outside the mind . But the involvement of the mind in the carving no more implies
that the stuff being carved is internal to the mind than the involvement of arms ,
hands, and an axe in chopping up the wood of a tree (an act that violates the tree's
natural boundaries ) implies that the stuff being chopped up does not exist in the
world outside the instruments used in chopping - the arms , the hands , and the
axe. If the members of a speech community collectively delimit , bound , or define
certain beings- say, the beings called DANCERS (defined as people who
dance)- this does not imply that those beings exist in our minds rather than in the
extrapsychic world ; dancers, like the dancing that makes them dancers, and like
the people who underlie them , exist outside our minds (and , unlike mental beings,
may be found performing on a stage) . TIle fact that dancers (as well as firms , con -
sumption , and income ) are not beings with metaphysical primacy (in the sense of
Aristotle 's prole ousia, 'primary beingness' or primary substance)- that is, beings
that underlie all other being - does not mean that they are not extrapsychic beings.
The example of dancers serves to highlight another point . In comparing the carving
up of being to chopping wood , I do not mean to imply that the being to be carved
up is necessarily matter . A dancer is carved from a person , coming into being
when the person takes up dancing , and passing away when the person ceases to
dance. A person is not a portion of matter (though a portion of matter coincides
with a person at any given moment ); the matter in a given person 's body changes
throughout the lifespan . Nor is a person the mereological sum of time -slices of all
the matter that is, was, or will be in his or her four -dimensional (space-time ) body
(a view that Putnam ( 1994) attributes to David Lewis ), for the summation of the
portions of matter that happen to coincide with a given person at different times
presupposes the person , the identity of whom guides the summation .
Being can also be defined relative to other being without implying that it is
unreal or imaginary . If Patricia is taller than Katherine , the fact that reference to
Katherine is necessary to determine Patricia 's being taller than her does not mean
that Patricia 's relative tallness is not really an aspect of her being . And being can
be defined with respect to individual observers and yet reside outside their heads .
That beauty is imaginary is not implied by the fact that beauty is relative to
observers (" in the eye of the beholder " ). If some people judge a painting to be
beautiful , then the aspects of its being that give rise to that judgment are the
components of the beauty they perceive . ( This idea is reminiscent of Locke 's
( 1694) view that to sayan object is red is to say it has the power , by virtue of the
nature of its surface, to give rise to a certain sensation in us. But unlike Locke , I
would not deem redness unreal and the physical property that makes something
look red real ; I would identify the two instead . As Berkeley ( 1710/ 1982) pointed
out , all qualities - not just those that Boyle and Locke called " secondary " - are
experienced the way they are because of properties of the observer . But I do not
conclude , as Berkeley did , that all qualities are secondary and there is no reality
outside our experiences; I conclude , rather , that most qualities are " primary " and
the peculiar and mutable nature of our experiences of them is irrelevant to their
reality . The fact that the appearances we experience may not resemble or be simi -
Scientific Theories That Unconceal Being 209
lar to the qualities that give rise to them does not means that those qualities are
not bona fide qualities of being (cf . Putnam 1981) .)
5. Most of the semanticists who adopt the " It ' s all in your head" view (or what
Jerry Fodor calls " psychosemantics
" )- the view that all linguistic meaning arises
somehow from mental representations - seem, like eliminativists , to be guided pri -
marily by skepticism about the mind 's manifest ability to intend being or beings ,
skepticism motivated by faith in a physicalistic ontology , which , as it is currently
conceived , excludes this ability (see also Baker 1987; Morris 1991) . It is skepticism
of this sort that led Fodor ( 1987) to say, " If the semantic and the intentional are
real properties of things , it must be in virtue of their identity with (or maybe
of their supervenienceon?) properties that are themselvesneither intentional nor
semantic . If aboutness is real , it must be really something else" (p . 97)- which I
would answer with Joseph Butler 's observation that " everything is what it is and
not another thing " (see Kripke 1972, 94) .
Fodor attests to the fact that many cognitive scientists and philosophers " are
repulsedby the idea that intentionality is a fundamental property of mental states
(or , indeed , of anything else- talk about your ontological dangers!)" ( 1990, 313).
He points out that " the deepest motivation for intentional irrealism derives . . .
from a certain ontological intuition : that there is no place for intentional catego-
ries in a physicalistic view of the world ; that the intentional can't be naturalized "
( 1987, 97) .
Such ontological dogmatism seems inappropriate in science, where being comes
to be understood by means of observation and evidence. Evidence from inner
perception and observation of people 's use and interpretation of language clearly
reveals the capacity of the mind to intend being outside the mind in its thoughts ,
perceptions , desires, and so on . If , for instance , a girl asks a salesclerk for an ice-
cream cone, both the girl and the salesclerk understand perfectly well that the girl
desires an ice-cream cone, not a mental representation of one.
6. The dependence of an isolated word 's potential to signify upon a concept or
definition may be one source of the belief of many semanticists that utterances of
all sorts get their meanings solely by virtue of mental representations(where
mental representation seems to be understood as a general term for mental entities
of various sorts, including concepts and definitions ) . Semanticists typically take a
compositional view of sentence meaning , seeing the meanings of sentences as
structured aggregations of the meanings of the words in the sentences. If words
considered individually do not permit the mind to intend being , but have a
" sense" or " meaning " only by virtue of a concept or definition , then a composi -
tionalist could be led to believe that the meanings of sentences are combinations of
mental representations .
But even if a theorist is only interested in the " senses" of individual words - the
mental representations (or concepts or definitions ) of the being they have the
potential to signify - the theorist must nonetheless characterize the being the words
would signify in declarative statements (or , more generally , in referring expres-
sions), for the simple reason that mental representationsare representationsof
being ; one cannot characterize the representations until one has characterized the
being or beings they represent .
210 McPherson
7 . This translation and the other translation of Brentano ' s German are my own ,
as are all the translations in this chapter from classical Greek (i .e., of Aristotle ,
Euclid , Eudoxus , Nicomachus , Parmenides , Plato , and Porphyry ), Latin (i .e.,
of Aquinas , Bradwardine , Descartes , Eustachius a Sancto Paulo , Fredericus ,
Peletier , Stifel , Suarez, Wallis , and Zabarella ), and French (i .e., of Leibniz
and Stevin) . Translations of German authors other than Brentano (i .e., Dede -
kind , Frege , Heidegger , Hilbert and Ackermann , Husserl , and Klein ) are from
the published English editions cited , except for the translation of the passage from
Hilbert and Bernays , which is my own . Wherever a quotation that I have trans -
lated into English is incorporated into the text , I have enclosed it in single quota -
tion marks to distinguish it from direct quotations from works published in
English , which are enclosed in double quotation marks .
8. 'Being of reason' is the standard (and literal ) translation of the Scholastic ex-
pression ens rationis . It refers to a being , such as the concept of a universal , that
exists in the mind (and perhaps only in the mind ) .
9. The Greeks had no word meaning 'number ' per se; their word arithmos is best
translated as 'count ' or 'counting ' (depending on the context ). The Greeks did not
understand numbers to fall under a single idea corresponding to our number
concept , for they did not believe that things that have an order can fall under
a common idea, definition , or genus (see Aristotle , Nicomachean Ethics A .6,
1096a17- 19; On the Soul B .3, 414b22- 28; Metaphysics B .3, 999a6- 10) . And ,
indeed , if numbers are understood as counts , it does not make sense to think of
them as belonging to a genus, since each one contains within it , or is a successor
of , all smaller ones. To count 5 beings, one must first count 2 beings, then 3 beings,
then 4 beings, successively adding 1 being to the collection of beings already
counted . Two is not separate from 3, or from 5 , but rather a part or antecessor of
it . And so even though each number is a species (with , e.g., all counts of 3
belonging to one species), the different species of number are not independent
species that can be included under a common genus.
10. For Plato , monads were separate, nonsensible , noetically perceived beings,
real beings in the realm of the mathematicals ; but , as Klein ( 1934- 1936/ 1968)
pointed out , " the emphasis with which the thesis of 'pure ' monads is propounded
is indicative of the fact that arithmoi were ordinarily , and as a matter of course,
understood only as definite numbers of sensible objects " ( p . 70).
11 . The idea that a monad is that which remains in an atom when all but its oneness
is abstracted away is also consistent with Aristotle ' s comment that a monad , like a
point , is indivisible in any dimension , but whereas a point has position , a monad
has none (Metaphysics A .6, 10I6b24 - 31; and so he calls a monad a point without
position , stigme athetos; Metaphysics M .8, IO84b26- 27); a point is what remains
in a being when its species, its sensible qualities , its matter , and its extension in
every direction are mentally stripped away (Metaphysics K .3, IO6Ia29 - 35; and so
Aristotle describes the objects of geometry as physical , e.g., physical points or
lines drawn on papyrus , but not qua physical ; see Physics B .2, 194a9- 11) .
12. Wallis said, 'Geometry is more or less subordinated to arithmetic , and to that
extent it applies universal assertions of arithmetic specially to its objects ' (Mathesis
Scientific
Theories
ThatUnconceal
Being 211
Univer salis; for the Latin , see Wallis 1657/ 1695, Opera, vol . 1, as cited in Klein
1934- 1936/ 1968, 216) .
13. Descartes ( 1596- 1650) stated that the geometric figures used in his algebraic
geometry as counterparts for magnitudes or quantities of any sort whatsoever (see
Schmidt 1986) 'must exhibit at one time continuous magnitudes , at another time
multitude or number also' ( 1701/ 1966, 452) . By introducing a unit magnitude with
which other magnitudes could be compared , he was able to interpret magnitudes
as numbers : 'Thanks to the unit we have assumed, continuous magnitudes can in
some instances be reduced in their entirety to multitude ' (pp . 451- 452); he also
said, 'If number be the question , we imagine a particular subject [i .e., a figure ]
measurable by a multitude of units ' ( p . 445), and , 'That very division into a plu -
rality of equal parts , whether it be real , or only intellectual , is properly a [mode of ]
measuring in accordance with which we count things ' (pp . 447- 448) .
14. In a later era, Richard Dedekind ( 1831- 1916), who regarded numbers as " free
creations of the human mind " ( 1888/ 1963, 31), stated explicitly that the goal of
introducing irrational numbers is to permit numbers , as points , to fill up a straight
line . After comparing the fact of one rational number ' s being greater than another
to a point ' s being to the right of another on a straight line , and of its being less
than another to a point ' s being to the left of another , and similarly , he said,
To every rational number a, i .e., to every individual in R [the domain of rational numbers ],
corresponds one and only one point p , i .e., an individual in L [the points in a line ]. . . .
Of the greatest importance , however , is the fact that in the straight line L there are
infinitely many points which correspond to no rational number . . . . The straight line L
is infinitely richer in point -individuals than the domain R of rational numbers in number -
individuals .
If now , as is our desire, we try to follow up arithmetically all phenomena in the straight
line , the domain of rational numbers is insufficient and it becomes absolutely necessary that
the instrument R constructed by the creation of the rational numbers be essentially improved
by the creation of new numbers such that the domain of numbers shall gain the same com -
pleteness, or as we may say at once , the same continuity , as the straight line . (1888/ 1963, 8- 9)
The use of the points on a line as a model for numbers was so customary by his
time that Dedekind felt no need to justify the assumption that for every point on a
straight line there must be a corresponding number .
15. Aristotle used these words as if they were standard terms , not commenting on
his use of them , so he may have been borrowing from and developing an existing
theory . But by the third century C.E. at the latest , the words for predicates and
predication that Aristotle used were deemed to have been of his own choosing .
Porphyry (232- 309), in his commentary on the Categories , asked,
Why , since kategorias in customary language is said , in respect of the forensic speeches, of
the [kategorias ] in accusation , to which is opposed the speech for the defendant , did Aristotle ,
not having undertaken to instruct us about how to speak against opponents in the courts of
justice , but [ about ] something else, which very thing is not called by this name among the
Hellenes , choose to make strange [use of language ] by entitling the book kategorias ? (265/
1887, 55)
16. Modem English editions of Aristotle 's logical writings often give 'belong to '
as the translation of huparch6 . Alternative and even more unrevealing translations
212 McPherson
are 'apply to ' and 'hold of ' , which do not correspond to any meanings the word
ever had for the Greeks .
17. As Plato pointed out (Sophist 262d- 263a), a simple declarative sentence such
as Theaetetus sits has two aspects, which he captured in the expressions peri hou
esti and hotou esti, 'whom /what it is about ' and 'whosever it is' : ( 1) Viewed as a
rhema (a verb or an adjective ) mingled (kekramenon ) or intertwined (sumplekes)
with a noun (or as a predicate intertwined with a noun phrase), the simple sen-
tence reveals something about something (i .e., the subject , or Theaetetus in this
case)- some determination (logos) of the subject . (Plato said that intertwining a
rhema with a noun tiperainei , 'brings something to an end', 'limits something ', or
'determines something ' , and that for this reason we call this combination of in -
tertwined word a logos (see 262d) . Robert H . Schmidt has argued , in conversation ,
that the original meanings of lego as 'lay (to rest)' and 'gather (together )' suggest
that a logos was understood as a gathering together that lays to rest. The gathering
together of words in an intertwining of a verb with a noun (through conjugation
for person and number ) gives a sense of completion and thus brings the mind to
a rest or standstill , whereas a word or a phrase by itself does not do so. A verb
intertwined with a noun determines or brings to an end in that sense. The inter -
twining of a verb with a noun , or of a predicate with a noun phrase, also limits or
defines the being of the subject that is shown forth from the subject .) (2) Viewed as
that which has laid down together (suntheis) a noun (or a noun phrase) with a
rhema (or a predicate ), a logos (or 'determination ') is seen to belong to something ,
or be of something (i .e., the subject , Theaetetus) . The two aspects correspond to
two roles as answers to questions of two sorts, exemplified by " What is Theaetetus
doing ?" (or " What is it about Theaetetus ?" ) and " Who sits?" (or " Who is it who
sits?" ) . Both can be answered with " Theaetetus sits" ; this utterance both reveals
something about Theaetetus (namely , that he sits) and lets it be known that the
particular determination of the subject (namely , the sitting ) is the determination of
Theaetetus (the possessor of the sitting ). But since predication , or affirming or
denying something about a subject , is the intertwining of a predicate with a (pre-
supposed) noun phrase, it brings into being an utterance with the former role or
aspect- one that reveals something about the subject .
18. This description reveals the error in the claim of scholars , at least since
Boethius (480- 524), that the categories other than ousia- literally 'beingness' but
conventionally translated as 'substance'- are supposed to be categories of " acci-
dental " being , for Aristotle explicitly contrasted the being of the categories , or
being that is kalh ' hauto , with accidental being , or being that is kala sumbebekos-
'because of (or in accordance with ) concomitance ' (see Metaphysics 11.7).
19. Here , phasis seems to mean primarily 'denunciation ' or 'a charge laid '- a
bringing to light in that sense
; the prepositional prefix kata in kataphasisimplies a
charge being laid against someone (or something ), and apo, which appears also in
apologia and apologeomai ('speak in one's defense'), as well as in apopsephizomai
('vote a charge away from ' or 'acquit '), implies a charge being removed .
(Alexander of Aphrodisias , in his commentary on Aristotle 's Topics , said that
apophasis is anairesis, which means 'taking up ' or 'taking away ' ; in legal contexts ,
Scientific Theories That Unconceal Being 213
the mind as a mechanical system (e.g., Hume 's associationism , where " ideas" are
governed by laws of " attraction " or association analogous to Newton 's law of
gravitation ), the mind as " Poof !" (behaviorism , or the mind 's retreat into com -
plete concealment ), the mind as a computer (the " information -processing " model
of the mind , functionalism ), and the mind as a brain (" neural -network " models ).
Psychology can only begin to be a genuine science when theoretical approaches
based on such metaphors - crude attempts to naturalize psychology - are aban -
doned and we begin in earnest to study the mind as a mind - when the nature of
the being in psychology 's domain (namely , intentional being) is allowed to guide
our choices in classifying phenomena , our choices of terminology , our choices of
problems to address, and the ways we choose to go about solving them , including
methods and theoretical approaches , as that being gradually unconceals its nature
to us (as Husserl ( 1954/ 1970) urged ) .
References
Aquinas , St. T . ( 1970). Summa theologiae [The sum of theology ]: Vol. 17. Psy-
chology of human acts ( T . Gilby , Ed . and Trans .). Cambridge : Blackfriars . ( First
published 1266)
Baker , L . R . ( 1987). Saving belief A critique of physicalism . Princeton , NJ :
Princeton University Press.
Berkeley , G . ( 1982) . .4 treatise concerning the principles of human knowledge ( K . P.
Winkler , Ed .). Indianapolis , IN : Hackett . ( First published 1710)
Bradwardine , T . ( 1955) . Tractatus proportionum sue De proportionibus veloc -
itatum in motibus [Treatise on ratios , or On the ratios of the speeds of motions ].
In H . L . Crosby , Jr . (Ed . and Trans .), Thomas of Bradwardine , his Tractatus
de proportionibus [Treatise on ratios ]: Its significance for the development of
mathematical physics ( pp . 64- 140) . Madison , WI : University of Wisconsin Press.
(Written in 1328)
Brentano , F . ( 1924). Psych% gie vom empirischen Standpunkt [Psychology from
an empirical standpoint ] (Vol . 1, 2nd ed., O . Kraus , Ed .). Leipzig : Verlag van
Felix Meiner .
Heath , T . L ., Sir ( Ed . and Trans .) . ( 1956) . The thirteen books of Euclid 's Elements :
Vol. 2. Books III - IX (2nd ed.) . New York : Dover .
Heidegger , M . ( 1962) . Being and time (J. Macquarrie and E . Robinson , Trans .).
San Francisco : Harper & Row . (Original work published 1927)
Hilbert , D ., and Ackermann , W . ( 1950). Principles of mathematical logic (R . E .
Luce , Ed ., L . M . Hammond , G . G . Leckie , and F . Steinhardt , Trans .). New York :
Chelsea. (Original work , as a 2nd edition , published 1938)
Hilbert , D ., and Bernays , P. ( 1934) . Grundlagen der Mathematik [Foundations of
mathematics ] (Vol . 1). Berlin : J. Springer .
Hockett , C . F . ( 1958) . A course in modern linguistics . New Yark : Macmillan .
Houghton , D . ( 1997) . Mental content and external representations . The Philo -
sophical Quarterly , 47, 159- 177.
Husserl , E . ( 1939). Die Frage nach dem Ursprung der Geometrie als intentional -
historisches Problem [The inquiry into the origin of geometry as an intentional -
historic problem ] ( E . Fink , Ed .). Revue lnternationale de Ph ilosoph ie, 1, 203-
225 .
' -
218 McPherson
proper names , count nouns and mass nouns . In J . Macnamara and G . E . Reyes
( Eds .) , The logical foundations of cognition ( pp . 144 - 176 ) . New York : Oxford
University Press .
Maxwell , J . C . ( 1877 ) . The kinetic theory of gases [ Review of the book A treatise
deep structure . Papers from the Regional Meeting , Chicago Linguistic Society , 4,
71 - 80 .
versity , Montreal .
view of the principles of evidence , and the methods of scientific investigation ( Vol . 1,
3rd ed .) . London : John W . Parker .
Morris , M . ( 1991 ) . Why there are no mental representations . Minds and Machines ,
1 , 1 - 30 .
and B . B . Lloyd ( Eds . ) , Cognition and categol "ization ( pp . 259 - 303 ) . Hillsdale , NJ :
Erlbaum .
and semantics : Vol . 7 . Notes / rom the linguistic underground ( pp . 201 - 225 ) . New
Yark : Academic Press .
Putnam , H . ( 1984 ) . Is the causal structure of the physical itself something physical ?
Putnam , H . (1994). Logic and psychology : Comment on 'Logic and cognition .'
In J. Macnamara and G . E . Reyes ( Eds .), The logical foundations of cognition
( pp . 35- 42). New York : Oxford University Press.
Pylyshyn , Z . W . (1984) . Computation and cognition : Toward a foundation for
cognitive science. Cambridge , MA : MIT Press.
Rispoli , M . ( 1995) . Missing arguments and the acquisition of predicate meanings .
In M . Tomasello and W . E . Merriman ( Eds .), Beyond 'Namesfor things ': Young
children 's acquisition of verbs ( pp . 331- 352). Hi1lsdale , NJ : Erlbaum .
Schank , R ., and Kass , A . ( 1988) . Knowledge representation in people and ma -
chines. In U . Eco , M . Santambrogio , and P. Violi ( Eds.), Meaning and mental
representations ( pp . 181- 200) . Bloomington , IN : Indiana University Press.
Schmidt , R . H . ( 1986) . On the signification of mathematical symbols: Repairing the
number/numeral breach with the restored Renaissance counterpart concept. Annap -
olis , MD : Golden Hind Press .
Searle, J. R . ( 1980). Minds , brains , and programs . Behavioral and Brain Sciences,
3 , 417 - 457 .
mental representations
(pp. 221- 237). Bloomington
, IN : Indiana University
Press
.
Wynn, K . (1992). Evidenceagainstempiricistaccountsof the originsof numerical
knowledge . Mind & Language , 7, 315- 332.
Zabarella,J. (1966). De rebusnaturalibus
,. In Aristotelislibrosdeanima[On natu-
ral things; On Aristotle's bookson the soul]. Frankfurt: Minerva. (Works first
publishedposthumously in 1590and 1605 )
Chapter 10
part of language and a part of cognition , and about the possibility that
mothers , odd numbers , and the vertebrate class Aves . Family resemblance
example , the category " chair " includes objects that have legs and that
lack them ( e .g . , beanbag chairs ) , and objects that can be sat upon and that
the family resemblance category " bird " than an eagle is ; and a penguin is
a worse example .
John Macnamara was a man of extraordinary wit , wisdom , and warmth . His
insights on the relations among cognition , logic , and the world greatly influenced
the thinking that went into this chapter . It is an honor to contribute to a volume in
his memory .
The order of authors is arbitrary . We thank Ned Block , Paul Bloom , Ray
J ackendoff , and Ed Smith for comments . Preparation of this chapter was sup -
ported
- by- National Institutes of Health grant HD 18381 .
A longer version of this chapter may be found in Communication and Cognition ,
29 , 307 - 361 .
222 Pinker and Prince
sometimes but not always an actual exemplar of the category . The more
similar other members are to the prototype , the better examples they are .
The sparrow , which is used to illustrate the entry for " bird " in many dic -
. There can be unclear cases - objects that mayor may not be members
characterized by one paleontologist as a " poor reptile , and not very much
" vegetable , " as is ketchup , as we saw in the famous controversy that fol -
broccoli , but not carrots or cauliflower ; stems and bunches of florets are
and Medin 1981 ; Rosch 1973 , 1978 , 1988 ) that has been taken to show
find necessary and sufficient conditions for most natural concepts that are
list of exemplars with respect to a category that are reliable and in close
prototypes and unclear cases . Third , these judgments are not unanalyz -
able gut feelings but can be predicted in a systematic way using a feature
tures can be quickly abandoned , even by young children . Children say that
three - legged dogs are dogs , and that raccoons with stripes painted down
their backs are raccoons , not skunks ( Rey 1983 ; Armstrong , Gleitman ,
not driven by the similarity criteria that define family resemblance cate -
gories ( see Murphy 1993 ; Medin 1989 ; Kelly 1992 ; Smith , Langston , and
Nisbett 1992 ; Rips 1989 ; Rey 1983 ) . For example , when people are asked
which two out of three belong together - white hair , gray hair , black
hair - they say that black is the odd hair out , because aging hair turns
gray then white . But when asked about a white cloud , a gray cloud , and a
black cloud , they say that white is the odd cloud out , because gray and
quarters have to be standardized but pizzas can vary . Most people , upon
butterfly that the caterpillar turns into , feel that the caterpillar and the
butterfly are " the same animal , " but that the caterpillar and the centipede
10.1.3 PossibleResolutions
This conflicting evidencecan be resolvedin severalways.
First, human concepts could basically pick out family resemblance
categories. Classical categorieswould be special casesor artifacts result-
ing from explicit instruction, such as in formal schooling. Alternatively ,
human concepts could basically pick out classical categories. Family
resemblancecategorieswould be artifacts of experimental tasks asking
subjects for graded judgments or asking them to make categorization
decisionsunder time pressure. A third , compromise position would say
that human conceptscorrespondto both classicaland family resemblance
categories. Classical categories are the " core" of the concept, used for
reasoning. Family resemblancecategoriesare " identification procedures"
or " stereotypes," usedfor identification of categoryexemplarson the basis
of available perceptual information , or for rapid approximate reasoning.
Although most theorists have tended toward compromise positions,
something close to the mainly-family-resemblanceview can be found in
Nature of Human Concepts 225
Lakoff 1987, Rosch 1978, and Smith , Medin , and Rips 1984; something
close to the mainly -classical-category view can be found in Rey 1983,
Fodor 1981, and Armstrong , Gleitman , and Gleitman 1983; and tentative
proposals favoring the core-plus-identification -procedure compromise can
be found in Smith and Medin 1981, Armstrong , Gleitman , and Gleitman ,
and Osherson and Smith 1981 .
English verbs come in two types: those that have regular past tense forms ,
and those that have irregular past tense forms . Consider them as two
categories : " regular verbs," such as walk /walked, talk /talked, jog /jogged ,
pat /patted , kiss/kissed, and play /played , and. " irregular verbs," such as hit /
hit , go/went, sleep/slept, make/made, ring /rang, bring /brought , stink /stank ,
andfiy /fiew .
In fact , the irregular verbs are not a single class but a set of subclasses,
which can be subdivided according to the kind of change that the stem
undergoes to form the past tense (see Pinker and Prince 1988 for a full
list ). Here are some examples:
. Lax the vowel : bleed, breed, feed , lead, mislead, read, speed, plead, meet,
hide, slide, bite, light , shoot
. Lax the vowel , add a -t: lose, deal, feel , knee/, mean, dream, creep, keep,
leap, sleep, sweep, weep, leave
. Change the rhyme to -ought: buy, bring , catch, fight , seek, teach, think
226 PinkerandPrince
. Change / 1/ to / ref or / AI: ring, sing, spring, drink, shrink, sink, stink,
sM-'im, begin, cling, fling , sling, sting, string, swing, wring, stick, dig, win,
spin, stink, slink, run, hang, strike, sneak
. Changethe vowel to /u/ : blow, grow, know, throw, draw, withdraw, fly ,
slay
Let us consider someproperties of the irregular subclasses
.
s C C i [Velar nasal ]
whereC standsfor a consonant . Thisprototypeis maximallysimilarto
mostmembers of theexistingsubclass , but moreinterestingly , it predicts
subjects' generalization of the/1/ -+ /AIchange to novelverbs . Bybeeand
Moderaskedsubjects to ratehownaturala varietyof putativepasttense
formssounded for eachof a setof noncestems . Theindependent variable
wasthesimilarityof thestemto theprototypelistedabove . Theyfound
that subjects wereextremely likelyto acceptthevowelchange for stems
like spling, strink, andskring , whichmatchtheschema for theprototype
exactly. Theywereonly slightlylesswillingto acceptstruckandskrum
asthepastof strickandskrim, whichdifferfrom theprototypein one
feature. Somewhat lowerin acceptability werespruvfor spriv,andsimilar
pastformsfor sking , smig, piing, andkrink. Glick, krin, plim, shinkwere
evenlesslikelyto admitof thevowelchange , andtrib, vin, andsid, the
formsfurthestfrom theprototype , weretheleastacceptable of all. The
resultshavebeenreplicatedby Prasadaand Pinker(1993 ), and with
analogous Germanformsby Marcuset al. (1995 ).
being completely ungrammatical either (cf. *keeped). This effect has been
documentedby Ulhnan (1999; seealso Pinker 1991and Pinker and Prince
1994), who asked subjectsto rate the naturalnessof irregular and regu-
larized past tense fonns for verbs whose irregular pasts are somewhat
fuzzy in goodness. The two setsof ratings were negatively correlated.
We now put aside this reciprocity effect due to blocking and try to
detennine whether the regular class has family-resemblance -category
properties independent of those of the irregular subclasseswith which it
competes.
it is not just that there already exist regular verbs in the language that
live in irregular phonological neighborhoods; the regular class can add
membersthat violate any irregular membershipcriteria. The reason has
been spelled out by Kiparsky (1982a,b), Pinker and Prince (1988, 1994),
Kim et al. (1991), and Kim et al. (1994). Irregular forms are verb roots,
not verbs. Not all verbs have verb roots: a verb that is intuitively derived
from a noun (e.g., to nail ) has a noun root. A noun or an adjectivecannot
be marked in the lexicon as having an " irregular past," becausenouns
and adjectivesdo not have past tenseforms at all; the notion makes no
sense.Therefore, a verb createdout of a noun or adjectivecannot have an
irregular past either. All suchverbs are regular, regardlessof their phono-
logical properties.
(3) He braked the car suddenly. i = broke
He flied out to center field. i = flew
He ringed the city with artillery . *rang
Martina 2-settedChris. *2-set
He sleigheddown the hill . *slew
He de-ftea'd his dog. *de-fled
He spitted the pig. *spat
He righted the boat. *rote
He high-sticked the goalie. *high-stuck
He grandstandedto the crowd. * grandstood
This makes it possible, in principle, for any sound sequencewhatsoever
to becomea regular verb. There is a lexical rule in English that convertsa
name into a verb prefixed with out, as in Clinton hasjinally out-Nixoned
Nixon. Like all verbs derived from nonverbs, it is regular. Since any lin-
guistically possiblesound can be someone's name, any linguistically pos-
sible sound can be a regular verb, allowing there to be regular homo-
phonesfor any irregular. For example:
(4) a. Mary out-Sally-Rided Sally Ride.
*Mary out-Sally-Rode Sally Ride.
b. In grim notoriety, Alcatraz out-Sing-SingedSing-Sing.
*In grim notoriety, Alcatraz out-Sing-Sang Sing-Sing.
*In grim notoriety, Alcatraz out-Sing-Sung Sing-Sing.
This effect has been demonstrated experimentally in several popula-
tions. Kim et al. (1991) asked subjectsto rate the regular and irregular
past tense foffi1s of a set of verbs that were either derived from nouns
that were homophonous with an irregular verb or were derived directly
232 Pinker and Prince
from the irregular verbs . For verbs with noun roots , the regular form was
give higher ratings ; for verbs with verb roots , the irregular form was
college - educated subjects ( Kim et ale 1991 ), children ( Kim et ale 1994 ),
Perfectly natural - sounding regular past tense forms exist not only when
existing regular roots and hence lacks a prototype that would serve as
replicated Bybee and Moder ' s ( 1983 ) study but also presented novel reg -
example , plip is close to one of the prototypes for regular verbs in English ,
because it rhymes with slip , flip , trip , nip , sip , clip , dip , grip , strip , tip , whip ,
and zip , whereas smaig rhymes with no existing verb root , andploamph is
forms with the same probability when they had to produce them .
tense forms , regular past tense forms do not suffer in well - formedness on
syntactic contexts . In earlier work ( Pinker and Prince 1988 ) , we noted that
sounding in its past tense form than it is in its stem form ; there is no
still have a regular past tense form that is judged as no worse than the
verb itself . Though fleech , fleer , and anastomose are unknown to most
good as the past tense forms of those verbs . These observations have been
pasts correlated highly with their ratings of the corresponding stems , but
not with the frequency of the past form ( partialing out stem rating ) . In
contrast , ratings of irregular pasts correlated less strongly with their stem
ratings but significantly with past frequency , partialing out stem rating .
Unlike what happens with irregular verbs , when a regular verb gets
makes it no worse. For example, the verb eke is seldom used outside
contexts such as She ekes out a living, but She eked out a living, unlike
forwent thepleasureof, doesnot suffer becauseof it . Similarly: He crooked
hisfinger; Shestinted no effort,' I broachedthe subjectswith him,. The news
auguredwellfor his chances . The regular verb to afford, like the irregular
verb to stand, usually occursas a complementto can't, but when liberated
from this context its past tenseforn1 is perfectly natural: I don't know how
she afforded it . Similarly, both She doesn't suffer fools gladly and She
neversufferedfools gladly are acceptable.
These phenomenashow why the apparent gradednessof acceptability
for regular forn1slike pleaded or weepedcan be localized to the graded-
nessof the correspondingirregulars becauseof the effectsof the Blocking
Principle and are not inherent to the regular verbs per se. The gradedness
of certain irregulars generally comesfrom low frequency combined with
similarity to the prototypes of their subclasses(Ullman 1993). But for
regular verbs that do not compete with specific irregular roots, there is
no complementary landscapeof acceptability defined by phonology and
frequency; all are equally good.
10.3 Psychological
Implications
10.3.1 PsychologicalReality
First, both family resemblancecategoriesand classicalcategoriescan be
psychologically real and natural. Classical categories need not be the
product of explicit instruction or formal schooling: the regular past tense
alternation doesnot have to be taught, and indeed every English-speaking
child learns it and begins to use it productively in the third year of life
(Marcus et al. 1992). The fact that children apply the regular alternation
even to high-frequency irregular stems such as come and go, which they
also use with their correct irregular pasts much of the time, suggeststhat
children in some way appreciate the inherently universal range of the
regular rule. And like adults, they apply the regular suffix to regular verbs
regardlessof the degree of the verbs' similarity to other regular verbs
(Marcus et ale 1992), and to irregular-sounding verbs that are derived
from nouns and adjectives (Kim et ale 1994). Gordon (1985) and
Stromswold (1990) have shown that children as young as 3 make quali-
tative distinctions between regular and irregular plural nouns related to
their different formal roles within the grammar, without the benefit of
implicit or explicit teaching inputs (seeMarcus et ale 1992and Kim et ale
1994for discussion).
The regularization-through-derivation effect (flied out, high-sticked)
provides particularly compelling evidencethat classicalcategoriesdo not
have to be the product of rules that are explicitly formulated and delib-
erately transmitted. The use of the regular rule as a default operation,
applying to any derived verb regardlessof its phonology, is a grass-roots
phenomenon whose subtleties are better appreciated at an unconscious
level by the person in the street than by those charged with formulating
prescriptive rules. Kim et al. (1991) found that non-college-educatedsub-
jects showed the effect strongly, and in the recent history of English and
other languagesthere are documented casesin which the language has
accommodatedsuchregularizationsin the face of explicit opposition from
editors and prescriptive grammarians. For example, Mencken (1936)
notes that the verb to joyride, first attaining popularity in the 1920s, was
usually given the past tenseform joyrided, as we would predict given its
derivation from the noun a joyride . Prescriptive grammarians unsuccess -
fully tried to encouragejoyrode in its place. Similarly, Kim et al. (1994)
showed that children display the effect despite the fact that most have
rarely or never heard regularized past tenseforms for irregular-sounding
verbs in the speechof adults.
Natureof HumanConcepts 235
10.3.2 PsychologicalFunction
A further corollary is that classical categories and family resemblance
categories do not have to have different psychological functions such
as careful versus causal reasoning, or reasoningversus categorization of
exemplars. What is perhapsmost striking about the contrast betweenthe
regular and irregular verbs is that two kinds of entities live side by side in
people's heads, servingthe samefunction within the grammar as a whole:
regular and irregular verbs play indistinguishable roles in the syntax and
semanticsof tense in English. There is no construction, for example, in
which a regular but not an irregular verb can be inserted or vice versa,
and no systematic difference in the temporal relationships semantically
encodedin the past tenseforms of regular and irregular verbs.
More specifically, it is difficult to make senseof the notion that family
resemblancecategoriesare the product of a set of identification proce-
dures used to classify exemplars as belonging to core categorieswith a
more classical structure. The suggestionthat " irregulars are used in per-
ceptually categorizingmembersof the regular class" makesno sense.The
irregulars are a classof words that display one kind of category structure;
the regulars do not display it .
Perhapsa closer analogy would be betweenmembershipconditions for
the irregular subclassesand the operation on the stem that generatesthe
past tenseform . One might say that a family resemblancestructure char-
acterizesthe membershipof each subclass, but once an item is a member
(for whatever reason), it is transformed into a past tenseform by a clas-
236 PinkerandPrince
sical all-or-none operation such as laxing the vowel. But even here, the
core/identification distinction does not easily apply, becausethe changes
that the member stemsof a class undergo, and not just the properties of
the stems, have a heterogeneousstructure. Within the subclassof irregu-
lars ending in ing/ink, sing goesto sangwhile sting goesto stung and bring
goesto brought. Similarly, within the subclassthat adds a / d/ to the past
tense form, some verbs have their vowellaxed (e.g., hear/heard), some
have their final consonant deleted (e.g., make/made, have/had), some
undergo the e - 0 ablaut that is frequent across the various subclasses
(e.g., sell/sold), and one undergoesa unique vowel change (do/did). In
sum, both the membershipconditions and the operations of the irregular
subclassesdisplay family resemblancecategoryeffects. Later we will show
that the core/identification distinction does not work well for conceptual
categorieseither.
10.3.4 ComputationalArchitecture
The acquisition of English past tensemorphology has been implemented
in a widely discussedcomputer simulation model by Rumelhart and
McClelland (1986; see also Pinker and Prince 1988, 1994; Lachter and
Bever 1988; Sproat 1992; Prasada and Pinker 1993; Marcus et al. 1992,
1995). The Rumelhart- McClelland (RM ) model makes use of a pattern
associator architecture, which is paradigmatic of the parallel distrib-
uted processing (PDP) or connectionist approach to cognitive science
(Rumelhart and McClelland 1986; McClelland and Rumelhart 1986;
Pinker and Mehler 1988). Two properties of pattern associators are
238 Pinker and Prince
explanation for why the regular class has such different properties from
the irregular classes ; it falsely predicts that the regular classshouldjust be
a larger and more generalprototype subclass.
Moreover, the pattern associatorfails to acquire the regulars properly.
In earlier work (Pinker and Prince 1988), we pointed out that the model is
prone to blending. Competing statistical regularities in which a stem par-
ticipates do not block each other; they get superimposed. For example,
the model produced erroneousforms in which an irregular vowel change
was combined with the regular ending, as in seppedas the past of sip or
brawnedfor brown. It would often blend the It I and lidl variants of the
regular past tense fonn , producing stepted for step or typted for type.
Sometimesthe blends were quite odd, such as membled for mailed or
tourederfor tour.
Furthermore, we noted that in contrast to the default nature of the
regular rule, the RM model failed to produce any past form at all for
certain verbs, such asjump, pump, glare, and trail . Presumably this was
becausethe model could not treat the regular ending as an operation that
was capable of applying to any stem whatsoever, regardlessof its prop-
erties; the ending was simply associatedwith the features of the regular
stemsencounteredin the input . If a new verb happenedto lie in a region
of phonological spacein which no verbs had previously been supplied in
the training set (e.g., jump and pump, with their unusual word-final con-
sonant cluster), no coherent set of output features was strongly enough
associatedwith the active input features, and no response above the
background noise could be made. Our diagnosis was tested by Prasada
and Pinker (1993), who presentedtypical-sounding and unusual-sounding
verbs to the trained network. For the unusual-soundingitems, it produced
odd blends and chimeras such as smairf/sprul'ice, trilbltreelilt , smeejf
leefloag, andfrilgffreezled.
Finally , the model is inconsistent with certain kinds of developmental
evidence. Children first use many irregulars properly when they use them
in a past tenseform at all (e.g., broke), then begin to overregularizethem
occasionally(e.g., broke and breaked) before the overregularizationsdrop
out years later. Sincepattern associatorsare driven by pattern frequency,
the only way the RM model could be made to duplicate this sequence
was first to exposeit to a small number of high-frequency verbs, most of
them irregular, presenteda few times each, followed by a large number of
medium-frequency verbs, most of them regular, presentedmany times
each. Only when the model was swampedwith exemplarsof the regular
240 PinkerandPrince
note that the world contains a set of objects in which these properties
cluster and to use the presenceof one subset of properties to infer the
likely presenceof others.
Just as irregular subclasseswere shapedby both divergent and conver-
gent historical processes , so in the domain of conceptual categoriesthere
is a convergent processthat can causeobjects to cluster around natural
modes even if the objects are not linked as descendantsof a more homo-
geneous ancestral population. For example, there is no genealogical
account of chairs that parallels the oneswe give for languagesor species .
The similarities among chairs are causedsolely by a convergentprocess,
in which a set of properties repeatedly arises becauseit is particularly
stable and adaptive in a given kind of environment, and severalhistori-
cally unrelated entities evolve to attain that set. Examples from biology
include nonhomologous organs such as the eyes of mammals and of
cephalopods, the wings of bats and of birds, and polyphyletic groups
such as cactuslikeplants (which have evolved succulentleaves, spines, and
corrugated stemsas adaptations to desert climates in severalparts of the
world). As in the caseof divergent evolution discussedabove, there is a
mixture of shared and distinct properties that are respectively caused
by law-governed adaptation and historical accident, though here the
influencesare temporally reversed. For example, although vertebrate and
cephalopod eyesare strikingly similar, in vertebratesthe photoreceptors
point away from the light sourceand incoming light has to passthrough
the optic nerve fibers, whereasin cephalopodsthe photoreceptors point
toward the light in a more sensiblearrangement. The differenceis thought
to have arisen from the different evolutionary starting points defined by
the ancestorsto the two groups, presumably relating to differencesin the
embryological processesthat lay down optic and neural tissue. Artifacts
such as chairs develop via a similar process; for a chair to be useful, it
must have a shapeand material that is suited to the function of holding
people up, but it is also influenced by myriad historical factors such as
style, available materials, and ease of manufacture with contemporary
technology. Social stereotypes, arising from the many historical accidents
that cause certain kinds of people to assumecertain roles, are another
example.
We might expect family resemblancecategoriesto be formed whenever
there is a correlational structure in the properties that people attend to
among sets of objects they care about, and that the world will contain
opportunities for such clustersto form whereverthere are laws that cause
254 PinkerandPrince
people are able to seethese laws peeking through the clutter and try to
capture them in idealized systems, the elementsof thesesystemsmay be
seento apply to many of the objects belonging to the family resemblance
clusters that were independently formed through simple observation of
the correlational structure displayed by frequently encountered exem-
plars. In such cases, languagesappear to assignthe sameverbal label to
both. This is what leads to the ambiguity of A penguin is a perfectly good
bird, one of whosereadingsis true, the other false. It also is what leadsto
such paradoxesas the behavior of Armstrong, Gleitman, and Gleitman's
subjects, who could assert both that odd numbers form an all-or-none
category tolerating no intermediate degreesof membershipand that 13 is
a better example of it than 23.
The fact that these systemsare distinct is at the heart of Putnam's
(1975) and Kripke 's (1972) well-known argument that natural kind terms
are not defined by a set of conditions that pick out the members of the
category in the world . Thus, even though we think of " animal" as a nec-
essarypart of the definition of cat, if we were to discoverthat cats were in
fact robots controlled from Mars, we would not conclude that cat no
longer referred to the entities formerly called cats, or that it did refer to
catlike entities on someother planet that really were animals. Rather, the
label cat is rigidly assignedto a set of objects in the world . According to
Putnam, people have a " stereotype" of such objects that helps them with
tentative identification, but they will defer to an expert in establishing
category membershipmore definitively.
Schwartz (1979) points out that such intuitions about natural kind
terms are driven by a belief that their membershave an " underlying trait "
in common. People act as if they believe in the existenceof such a trait
even if they are prepared to accept that their current belief about the
nature of the trait is incorrect, even if they have no idea of the nature of
the trait , indeed even if no one knows the nature of the trait . Schwartz's
analysissuggeststhat people's intuitions are influencedby a metatheory, a
kind of essentialism,that assertsthat the varying forms that an object can
assumeare causally related in terms of their relation to a hidden trait
or essence . These essencesare clearly not family resemblancecategories
since it is possible, indeed typical, that they are not associatedwith any
properties of the relevant objects at all, let alone a cluster of frequently
co-occurring properties (that is, if Putnam and Kripke are correct, there is
no property associatedwith the concept underlying " cat" or " gold" that
cannot be relinquished by a person while he or she still believesthe con-
256 PinkerandPrince
10.5 Conclusion
Note
1. There are also problems with the model ' s treatment of these phenomena (see
Pinker and Prince 1988; Lachter and Bever 1988; Sproat 1992) .
References
Bybee, J. L ., and Slobin , D . I . ( 1982a). Rules and schemes in the development and
use of the English past tense. Language , 58, 265- 289.
Bybee, J. L ., and Slobin , D . I . ( 1982b) . Why small children cannot change
language on their own : Suggestions from the English past tense. In A . Ahlqvist
( Ed .), Papers from the 5th International Conference on Historical Linguistics
(Current Issues in Linguistic Theory Vol . 21; Amsterdam Studies in the Theory
and History of Linguistic Science IV ) . Philadelphia : John Benjamins .
258 PinkerandPrince
Lachter , J., and Bever , T . G . ( 1988) . The relation between linguistic structure and
associative theories of language learning : A constructive critique of some con -
nectionist learning models . Cognition , 28, 195- 247.
Lakoff , G . ( 1987) . Women, fire , and dangerous things: What categories reveal
about the mind . Chicago : University of Chicago Press.
MacWhinney , B ., and Leinbach , J. ( 1991). Implementations are not conceptuali -
zations : Revising the verb learning model . Cognition , 40, 121- 157.
Marcus , G . F . ( 1995) . The acquisition of inflection in children and multilayered
connectionist networks . Cognition , 56, 271- 279.
Marcus , G . F ., Brinkmann , U ., Clahsen , H ., Wiese, R ., and Pinker , S. ( 1995) .
German inflection : The exception that proves the rule . Cognitive Psychology , 29,
189 - 256 .
Pinker , S., and Prince , A . ( 1994). Regular and irregular morphology and the psy-
chological status of rules of grammar . In S. D . Lima , R . L . Corrigan , and G . K .
Iverson ( Eds.), The reality of linguistic rules. Philadelphia : John Benjamins .
Plunkett , K ., and Marchman , V . ( 1991) . U -shaped learning and frequency effects
in a multi -layered perceptron : Implications for child language acquisition . Cogni -
tion , 38 , 43 - 102 .
260 Pinker and Prince
Brain Sciences , 11 , 1 - 74 .
MIT .
Ullman , M . ( 1999 ) . Judgments of English past tense forms : Implications for the
Xu , F . , and Pinker , S . ( 1995 ) . Weird past tense forms . Journal of Child Language ,
22 , 531 - 556 .
Chapter 11
Some Evidence for Impaired Myrna Gopnik
Grammars
Over the last few years, specific language impairment (SLI ) has become a
hot topic because it may have the potential to tell us something about the
biological basis of language . I am afraid that comments about this
research, on both sides, have often generated more heat than light . If we
are really interested in the science of it all , then it is important to get the
issues out on the table and seewhich ones we can agree about , which ones
are still outstanding , and how we could resolve them . This chapter is
intended to make a stab at clarifying some of the issues.
The fact that we would even be discussing language and biology in the
same breath would have been unimaginable when I was an undergraduate
in 1955 (though Darwin , himself , did suggest that learning language might
be an instinct ). Over the last 40 years the picture has changed radically .
Research has shown that all languages, despite their seeming differences,
are built on the same general plan and that most children acquire their
native language as easily as they learn to walk upright , without explicit
teaching and with no apparent effort . Newborns can't do it , but it appears
in the first year of life , and the necessary precursors for this achievement
seem to be there at birth . Experiments with very young babies have shown
that humans come equipped with special abilities to selectively pay
attention to and process language ( KuhI1991 ; Kuhl and Meltzoff 1997) .
These data suggest that there is a biological basis to language . It follows
that if language is part of the biological endowment of humans , then
humans must have some genetic properties that build the particular kinds
of brain circuitry that are specialized for human language . If this is true ,
then it would not be surprising to find that some change in this genetic
endowment can interfere with the way brain circuitry is built and thereby
impair the ability to acquire or use language in the normal way . And in
fact this does happen . Though most children do acquire language without
264 Gopnik
any consciouseffort, there are some children who have real trouble with
language, and their linguistic problems persist into adulthood. What
makes this population particularly interesting is that this disorder seems
to be associatedwith some geneticfactors and neurological anomalies. If
this is true, then this situation provides a ready-made natural experiment
to investigatevarious hypothesesabout the biology of language.
This " ready-made" looks easier than it is, however. There are lots of
piecesto the argument that have to be put together, linguistic, psycholin-
guistic, genetic, and neurological, before we can be sure about what we
are seeing. The first problem is to show that at least some casesof this
disorder are really genetic.
11.1 Genetics
look similar. If , on the other hand, the pattern is due to genetic factors,
then the twins with the samegenesshould be more alike than those who
are merely siblings genetically but have shared a similar social context.
Severalindependentstudieshave shown that this disorder is significantly
more concordant in monozygotic twins than in dizygotic twins (Bishop,
North , and Donlan 1995; Tomblin 1997; Tomblin and Buckwalter 1998).
Therefore, both the epidemiological data and the twin studiesstrongly
suggestthat genetic factors are associatedwith this disorder. But genes
do not code for behavior such as language. They code for proteins that
control developmentthat, in turn, may have consequences for the way in
which languagedevelops. To really understandwhat is going on, then, we
have to find somelikely consequences that the geneticfactors could have
for development; and sincelanguagehappensin the brain, the most likely
place to look is neurology.
11.2 Neurology
11.3 Neuropsychology
11.4 Linguistics
Our research goals in linguistics over the years have been clear: to
describethe grammatical systemthat producesthe pattern of errors that
are observed. After 10 years and almost 100 language-impaired subjects
and well more than 100 controls representingfour different native lan-
guages(English, French, Greek, and Japanese ), the data convergeto tell
us that the language-impaired subjects cannot construct normal repre-
sentations for grammatically complex words and they therefore cannot
use rules that depend on the content of theserepresentations. For exam-
ple, though they appear to have no problems with the larger grammatical
categoriesof languagelike noun and verb, they are unable to recognize
that words can be composedof roots and affixes. They therefore do not
construct abstract linguistic features such as tense, number, aspect, case,
or gender, and they do not recognizethat there are linguistic rules that
operate on these features. But this does not mean that they cannot use
words that, from the point of view of the nonnal grammar, have these
features. For example, in spontaneousspeechthey usually use the correct
forms such as " books" or " walked." They can do this becausethey
memorize theseforms as unanalyzed chunks that in their lexicon simply
encodethe semanticmeaning of " more than one" or " in the past" rather
than the sublexicalfeatures" plural" or " past." They are more accuratein
Evidencefor Impaired Grammars 269
using the " more than one" forms than the " in the past" forms. This is
probably becausein English the relationship between the form with the
plural marker and the semanticcontext of " more than one" is very regular
and direct and therefore is easy to memorize. However, the relationship
between the past-marked forms and temporal past context is extremely
complicated and not at all regular or direct (Shaer 1996), and therefore it
is more difficult to assign a consistentmeaning relationship betweenthe
inflected foffi1 and the meaning of pastnessby any rote means.
How do we know that theseindividuals do not construct complex rep-
resentations? We have two sourcesof evidence, linguistic and psycholin-
guistic. The linguistic evidencecomesboth from spontaneousspeechand
from a wide seriesof linguistic tests. One of the things that makesparents
notice that their children have difficulties with languageis that they make
mistakes in spontaneousspeechin foffi1s like past tensesand pronouns
long after their playmates and siblings have got the systemfigured out.
And these problems persist into adulthood. But as these individuals get
older, they do not make theseerrors very often. Many of them get tense
right over 80% of the time. This is in contrast to the control subjects, who
get tense right virtually all of the time. Marking tense in your native
language is an automatic, unconsciousprocess, not something that you
get wrong. And this leads us to a very interesting problem. Is someone
who gets tenseright 80% of the time impaired, or simply absent-minded?
Let's put it another way. Generally speaking, people get their own name
right all of the time. If someonegot his or her name right 80% of the time,
we might begin to wonder. What our model suggestsis that the language-
impaired subjects, in fact, never get tense right . They do not have the
category " tense" in their grammar. What they do 80% of the time is
produce a word that has the samesurfaceform as the marked foffi1 in the
normal grammar. It looks like they get tensemarking right most of the
time, but they get there by a very different route- by memorization or by
explicit rule (Paradis and Gopnik 1997).
The only way to figure out what these individuals really know about
language is to give them linguistically significant tests. The data from
thesediagnostic testsconvergeto tell us that the pattern of what they can
do and what they cannot do is strikingly similar in all of the five pop-
ulations- speakersof English from Canada and England, and speakersof
French, Greek, and Japanese - that we have looked at (seefigure 11.1).
These tests show that the language-impaired speakershave significant
problems with grammaticality judgments, tense production, and deriva-
Evidencefor Impaired Grammars 271
Table 11.2
Ability to produce tense marking (% correct). Subjects were given items like
" Every day I walk to school. Just like every day, yesterday I ." This task
requiresthe subject to recognizethat the temporal context specifiedin the second
sentencerequires a particular verb form .
English English French Japanese Greek
(England) (Canada) (Canada)
Language-impaired
subjects 38.3 52.3 46.7 48.1 20.0
Controls 91.7 93.5 96.4 97.9 87.1
tional morphology.2 They have fewer problems with a pointing task that
requires them to auditorily distinguish between words like " book" and
" books" or " books" and " cooks." These general diagnostic tests have
beensupplementedby much more detailed testsdesignedto test particular
hypotheses. For example, we have data about tense from spontaneous
speech, grammaticality judgment tasks, grammaticality rating tasks,
storytelling, and tenseproduction; and theseresults are consistentover a
wide range of types of stimuli and responses - oral, aural, written, point-
ing, and so on (Gopnik 1994). We also have results that show that these
speakershave problems with plurals and comparatives.
One question was whether theseproblems with tensein English could
be accountedfor by the fact that regular past tensein English is encoded
by a form that has been described as " phonologically vulnerable"
(Fletcher 1990) or by somespecialand particular problems with our first
set of English-speaking subjects, who all came from one particularly
interesting family . In order to resolvethis question, we decidedto look at
more English-speaking subjects and at subjects whose native language
was not English. These data show that the problem with tenseis unique
neither to our first subjectsnor to English. It showsup in every popula-
tion we have looked at (seetable 11.2; seealso Fukuda 1994; Dalalakis
1996; Gopnik et al. 1996; Royle 1996; Gopnik 1998; Ullman and Gopnik ,
to appear) . All of thesepopulations have similar problems with produc-
ing correct tense forms, no matter how tense is encoded in their native
language- in a final stressedsyllable as in French or in a three-syllable
element like " mashita" in Japanese . Interestingly, both the Greek con-
trol and language-impaired subjects have lower scores than the other
subjects; this happens becauseeach verb in Greek has more than 60
272 Gopnik
Table 11 .3
Singular Plural
(A similar rule holds for forming diminutives . For the details , seeDalalakis
1996.) The subjects were shown pictures and told (in Greek ), for exam-
ple, " This is a mouse (pondikos ) and this is a man (anthropos ) that be-
comes a mouse. We would call him a 'mouseman ' (pondikanthropos )."
They were asked to form similar compounds in response to other pictures .
The language -impaired subjects had significantly more difficulty with this
task than did the controls (see table 11.4) . Sometimes the language -
impaired subjects produced fonDs in which the first root was shorter
than required (2a), and sometimes they produced forms in which it was
longer (2b).
(2) a. anthrop -fagh -os -+ * anthrofaghos
man eater masc.sing. man -eater
nom .
Table 11 .4
Language -
impaired Young Age-matched
sub,jects controls controls
Compounding 16 95 99
Diminutivization 38 100 100
274 Gopnik
these speakers produce forms that look " inflected " by very different
means than the normal grammar .
So far , all of our hypotheses about the way that the language-impaired
subjects must be representing words in their grammar have been inferred
from their performance on linguistic tests. But there is another , more direct
way to look at their mental lexicon . Eva Kehayia conducted a series of
on-line psycholinguistic tests to probe the way in which language-
impaired subjects were processing complex words . It might be the case
that these subjects have normal representations for the inflected forms ,
but some processing difficulties make these forms unavailable to them in
spontaneous speech or elicited production tasks. Psycholinguistic research
on aphasics shows that though they make errors in spontaneous speech
and in linguistic tests, their mental representations appear to be intact
( Kehayia and Jarema 1994; Kehayia , in press) . The language-impaired
276 Gopnik
I
278 Gopnik
Table 11 .7
Language-impaired
subjects(Greek) Controls (Greek)
N onword compounds
kigofaghos 817 870
(" kigoeater " ; like
English " wugeater " )
Navel compounds
migofaghos
(' 'flyeater " )
Existing compounds
hortofaghos
(" vegetable eater" ==
" vegetarian " )
The results of the experimentsin this study clearly show that the per-
formance pattern of the language-impaired subjects is significantly dif-
ferent from that of the control subjects on word and nonword targets
for inflection, derivation, and compounding. The controls in this study
behavejust as reported elsewherein the literature (Taft and Forster 1975;
Laudanna, Badecker, and Caramazza 1989; Kehayia and Jarema 1994).
They processproductively formed complex words by meansof decompo-
sition, and they processsimple and idiosyncratic complex words by means
of whole-word access . The language-impaired subjectsappear to process
111111111I1
1111111111
these individuals , it is by no means the only one they have trouble with .
The question that is still open is whether their prosodic and syntactic dif -
ficulties are directly related to the same out -of -order linguistic system that
causes their problems in morphology or whether these other language
problems are an independent result of their general pattern of neurologi -
cal damage . The answer to this question would shed light on the relative
independence of the three levels of grammar . Though there is abundant
evidence that this disorder is associated with some genetic factors , no one
yet knows what these factors are . And even if the genes associated with
this disorder were found , it would not follow necessarily that these same
genes would be the ones that guide the normal linguistic system to develop ;
the factors that make a system function in the normal case might not be
the same as those that can cause the system to break down . Of course ,
there is much more to find out . Weare only at the beginning of this
intellectual journey , but it does appear that it will turn out that Darwin
was right that language is part of the biological nature of humans .
Notes
1 . This family has been the subject of much debate ( Fletcher 1990; Vargha -
Khadem et al . 1995) . For a d'etailed discussion of some of these disputes , see
Gopnik and Goad 1997. From the data , it is clear that the language impair -
ment seen in this family is not caused by oral apraxia or low performance IQ .
Moreover , as I will show , the same pattern of impairment is found in English -
speaking subjects in Canada as well as in French -, Greek -, and Japanese-speaking
subjects.
2. Since Japanese does not have a rich , productive system of derivational mor -
phology , we did not test the Japanese-speaking subjects on this task .
3. They also make errors in syntax and in some phonological processes such as
prosody , but discussing these in detail would take us too far afield here (van der
Lely and Harris 1990; van der Lely 1997; Clahsen 1992; Piggott and Kessler 1994;
Rice , Wexler , and Cleave 1995; Goad , in press) .
References
Kuhl , P . K . ( 1991 ) . Human adults and human infants show a " perceptual magnet
effect " for the prototypes of speech categories , monkeys do not . Perception &
Psychophysics , 50 , 90 - 107 .
tics } lO } 16 - 23 .
38 , 850 - 863 .
Royle , P . ( 1996 ) . Verb production in French DLI subjects . Unpublished Master ' s
Shaer , B . ( 1996 ) . Making sense of tense : Tense , time refel ' " ence and linking theory .
Mahwah , NJ : Erlbaum .
University Press .
188 - 199 .
I have been working on different drafts of this chapter for over five years; the
version presentedhere is a very modified version of what I presentedin my doc-
toral dissertation (Bloom 1990a, chap. 3). I thank SusanCarey, LouAnn Gerken,
Lila Gleitman, Jane Grimshaw, Lisa Menn, and StevenPinker for discussionof
theseissues, and Ellen Courtney, Ray Jackendoff, and Karen Wynn for extensive
comments on a previous draft. I am particularly grateful to John Macnamara,
who first introduced me to the study of mind and language, and encouragedand
guided me in the years that followed.
Preparation of this chapter was supportedby grants from the SpencerFounda-
tion and from the Sloan Foundation.
286 Bloom
" good boy " and " nice hat . " Since these rules cannot account for much
of what children hear ( e . g . , " good story " and " nice smile " ) , they are
word " until they correspond to syntactic categories such as " noun ." As
( Grimshaw 1981 ; Pinker 1984 ) , which posits that children possess a lan -
guage acquisition device ( LAD ) that leads them to categorize names for
versals of grammar , children parse some of the utterances they hear and
thereby learn some language - particular rules of grammar . After they have
acquired such rules , they can use them to categorize new words that do
not fall under the syntax - semantics mappings , such as nouns that do not
I will begin by defending the premise that children learn the syntactic
I ' ll also argue that neither of the two approaches summarized above is
tive for the study of word learning , and conclude with some more general
remarks .
12 . 1 Why Semantics ?
One alternative to the view that children use semantics to solve the boot -
strapping problem is that they group words and phrases together accord -
sentence , what inflections they appear with , and what words they precede
and follow . Under this view , a child comes to understand that " dog " and
" door " belong to the same linguistic class because they can each follow
" the , " can precede the suffix " - s" and the word " is , " and so on . In the
phrases are irrelevant ( e .g . , Maratsos and Chalkley 1981 ; see also Harris
1954 ) .
find semantic definitions for syntactic categories . For instance , there are
count nouns that do not name physical things ( e .g . , " joke " ) and verbs
Solving the Bootstrapping Problem 287
that do not name actions (e.g., " know " ) . Although child language does
have a semantically transparent flavor , with a high proportion of nouns
describing things , and verbs describing actions (Macnamara 1982), even
1- and 2-year-olds know words that do not fit this pattern (Nelson ,
Hampson , and Shaw 1993; Pinker 1984) . The possibility that children
might use prosodic information to carve up sentences into grammatically
relevant units (Gleitman and Wanner 1982; Hirsh -Pasek et al . 1987) as
well as phonological information to distinguish function morphemes
from members of open-class categories (Gerken , Landau , and Remez
1989) introduces further sources of evidence that a nonsemantic learning
proced ure could use.
Nevertheless , it has long been known that an unconstrained distribu -
tional learning model has serious limitations as a solution to the boot -
strapping problem (Gordon 1982, 1985; Pinker 1979, 1984, 1987). There
are an enormous number of surface correlations that children could en -
code. A child exposed to " Look at the dog " could note that " look " is the
first word of the sentence , that it appears to the immediate left of " at ,"
two words to the left of " the," three words to the left of " dog," and so on
for each of the other words in the sentence . But most of these facts are
they tended to interpret the count noun as naming the kind of doll , but
treated the NP as a proper name for that specific doll . Two - and 3-year-
aIds are also sensitive to contrasts between subclasses of nouns . In par -
ticular , they can focus on the difference between count nouns and mass
nouns (e.g., between " a wug " and " some wug " ) when inferring properties
of word meaning . They will tend to construe a novel count noun as
referring to a kind of individual and a novel mass noun as referring to
a kind of nonindividuated entity ( Bloom 1994; Brown 1957; Soja 1992).
Finally , certain early categorization errors , such as treating object mass
nouns like " furniture " and " toast " as count nouns ( Bloom 1994), are best
explained in terms of childrens using semantics as a clue to category
membership .
Other linguistic domains yield similar findings . For instance , N aigles
( 1990) found that 24-month -olds attend to the distinction between NP -V
and NP -V -NP contexts when inferring aspects of the meanings of verbs.
290 Bloom
system. For another , generalizations such as " Names for kinds of discrete
physical objects are nouns " are likely candidates for descriptive universals
of language ( Bloomfield 1933; Macnamara 1986). However , this theory
leaves certain semantic aspects of syntactic categories unexplained . It is
hardly an accident , for instance, that words such as " day ," " nightmare ,"
and " conference " are nouns and not prepositions or modals . Further -
more , even 3 -year - olds appear to be sensitive to the semantic correlates
12.3 A MappingTheory
The scope of the alternative is modest . It will focus mostly on the acqui -
the nature of the syntax - semantics mappings that are used to learn the
In Pinker ' s and Grimshaw ' s theory , the mappings children use are part
learning are instead derived from syntax - semantics mappings that exist as
the nominal system . Nouns are words that refer to kinds , whereas NPs are
words or phrases that can refer to individuals . Thus , " dog " itself does not
can refer . For instance , " that dog " picks out a particular individual that is
a dog , " those big dogs " picks out a set of dogs that are big , and so on .
Pronouns and proper names are lexical NPs because , unlike words such as
" dog , " they inherently pick out individuals , not kinds .
Solving the Bootstrapping Problem 295
The notion that NPs, and not nouns, refer to individuals is familiar
from work within formal semantics, where nouns are sometimesviewed
as predicates, which must combine with determinersto establishreference
(e.g., Barwise and Cooper 1981). More generally, the notion is that nouns
are semantically incomplete (or " unsaturated" ; seeHigginbotham 1983);
only NPs are semanticallycomplete. As such, only NPs can participate in
certain forms of semanticinteraction, such as having thematic roles, par-
ticipating in coreferencerelations, and being able to refer to entities in the
world .
Although the lexical/phrasal contrast within nominals may not hold
across all languages, one could posit as a universal of language the
following :
NPs refer to individuals .
to. For instance, the numerical contrast between" two cookies" and " five
cookies" is identical to the contrast between" two jokes" and " five jokes,"
and the same properties of binding theory apply regardlessof whether
the referring expressionsrefer to material (" the cookie" ) or nonmaterial
(" the joke" ) entities. In general, the semanticstructuresof languagedon't
care whether or not the individuals denoted by nominals are physical
objects.
In light of this, it might be most parsimonious to view the child's ten-
dency to construe phrasesthat describeobjectsas NPs as a specialcaseof
the mapping that statesthat NPs can refer to individuals. In particular,
children might possessthe following bias concerning the relationship
betweenlinguistic semanticsand nonlinguistic cognition:
Physical whole objects are canonical individuals.
There is considerablesupport for the claim that children are biased to
construe whole objects as individuals, support that is quite independent
from considerationsof syntactic development. When children hear a word
(especially a count noun) used to describe a novel object, they show a
strong bias to take the word as referring to the kind of object, not to a
part, or property, or anything else (seeMarkman 1989). Related to this,
Shipley and Shepperson(1990) askedpreschoolersto count different sorts
of entities. For instance, they showedchildren a picture of five forks, one
of them broken into two pieces, and asked, " Can you count the forks?"
Most of the children said, " Six," presumably becausethere were six dis-
cretephysicalobjectsin front of them- although only five forks. Shipleyand
Sheppersoncall this the " discretephysical object" bias, which is equivalent
to the above claim that, when it comesto quantifying over individuals,
objectsare highly salient. Note also that a considerableamount of knowl-
edgeabout objectsappearsto be innate in humans (Spelkeet al. 1992).
Although objects are salient individuals, even infants and young
children can quantify over individuals that are not objects. In one study,
infants were exposedto either two sounds or three soundsand then pre-
sentedwith two pictures: one with two objectsand one with three objects.
Even 6-month-olds tended to look longer at the picture that showed the
same number of objects as there were sounds, providing some evidence
that infants possessnotions of " two individuals" and " three individuals,"
where " individual " encompasses both discretesoundsand discreteobjects
(Starkey, Spelke, and Gelman 1990). When there are no salient objects
present, 2-year-olds have no problem counting sounds or actions; this
Solving the Bootstrapping Problem 297
capacity emerges at the same time that they are able to count objects
( Wynn 1990 ) .
describe nonobject kinds , such as parts ( " hand " ) , events ( " race " ) , and
periods of time ( " hour " ) ( Nelson , Hampson , and Shaw 1993 ) . Finally ,
children can use syntactic cues to learn count nouns that fOffi1 NPs
1995 ) .
NPs and objects is not direct . Instead , even young children possess an
abstract semantic notion of " individual " that maps onto NPs . Objects are
discrete sound . One factor that determines what can count as a possible
can refer to entities like puddles ( Soja 1992 ) and discrete sounds ( Bloom
single causal role - if adults see a group of objects moving together and
the objects as a single individual , but if the objects are stationary , the
ent perspectives on the category of " individual " and constraints on pos -
object . But children must somehow use this knowledge to categorize the
NPs they are exposed to . Further , they must categorize other parts of
further aspects of phrase structure . The problems with this view motivate
an alternative , which is that children start off parsing sentences they hear
into phrases , perhaps with the aid of prosodic information , and use
can be co-opted to serve other semantic roles (as in the case of expletives),
they can only enter the lexicon via the syntax -semantics mapping . If this is
so, children would not be capable of learning the expletive " it " unless
they had already acquired " it " as a referential prnoun .
This leads to two predictions : ( 1) children should use an NP as an
expletive only after they have acquired its referential meaning , and (2) no
language should have NPs that are solely expletive and have no referen-
tial double life , because children would never be able to acquire such
words . Nishigauchi and Roeper ( 1987), who present a similar theory of
the acquisition of expletives , argue that both predictions hold , but admit -
tedly the evidence is relatively scanty .
What about verbs ? The discussion above has focused on NPs and parts
of NPs , but children must also acquire other parts of speech. No doubt
syntax -semantics mappings can apply in these domains as well . Just as
there is a mapping between individuals and NPs , so there may be similar
mappings between events and VPs, propositions and sentences, and so on .
The semantic bootstrapping theory also posits such mappings , although ,
as with nominals , these are presumed to be independent of more general
linguistic knowledge .
It is also likely that once children have categorized some words or
phrases as NPs , principles of grammar could lead them to categorize
words belonging to other syntactic categories, even in the absence of any
prior knowledge of what these words mean . Consider a child who knows
(through the procedure discussed above) that " Mary " and " Joe" are NPs
that refer to individuals , and then hears these NPs used with the novel
word " kissed" (e.g., " Mary kissed Joe" ). Assuming that children can de-
teffi1ine whether a string of words is a sentence as opposed to a fragment ,
and that they expect semtences to express propositions , the utterance
would be semantically encoded as follows , using a notation based on
Jackendoff 's ( 1990) :
PR 0 POSITION
can categorize " kissed " as a predicate ( since there must be something
licensing these NPs and this is the only candidate ) and give it the follow -
ing representation :
EVENT
already knowing its linguistic category , and these are worth considering
here .
At first blush , it is not obvious where the problems lie . All children
must do is hear a word or phrase ( e .g ., " Freddie " ) , follow an adult ' s gaze
or point , and note that the adult is intending to refer to an object (e .g .,
to Freddie ) . Since Freddie is an object , the child will construe it as an
individual , and since NPs refer to individuals , " Freddie " must be an NP .
Along these lines , note that even 12 - and 13 -month - olds are drawn to
focus on the individual when exposed to a new word that describes an
object - and will do so regardless of whether the word is a noun or an
adjective , suggesting that overt syntactic cues are not essential at this early
stage of word learning , at least not for the acquisition of names for object
kinds ( Waxman 1994 ) .
However , there are situations in which children cannot be assured
of exposure to ostensive labeling . For instance , Kaluli mothers do not
engage in labeling behavior with their children . Instead , they provide their
children with extensive training in conversational interaction , often mod -
eling sentences for them ( Schieffelin 1985 ; see also Heath 1983 ) . Despite
this difference in input , Kaluli children acquire words at much the same
rate as children acquiring languages such as English . To see the problem
Solving the Bootstrapping Problem 303
this raises, imagine such a child seeinga bird in the sky and hearing, for
example, " Zav goop wicket mep." By hypothesis, the child knows no
words at this point, no inflections, and nothing about the syntax. (And
in fact, it is optimistic even to assumethat she is capable of parsing
the utterance into distinct words and phrases; if not, she will hear
" Zavgoopwicketmep." ) Which word or string of words (if any) does the
child construe as referring to the bird? How do Kaluli children learn any
word meanings?
There are two possibletypes of solutions. The first is that children per-
form a constrained distributional analysis; they store sentence -situation
pairs in memory and then look for correlations between specific words
or phrases and discrete aspectsof meaning. For instance, if the same
child hears" Blub mendle wicket mep" to refer to another bird, shemight
assumethat " wicket mep" (which was present in both sentences ) is used
to refer to birds and is thus an NP . The analysis might be simplified if
children only store strings of stressedphrases(instead of whole sentences )
and representationsof relevant individuals (instead of entire situations).
But such an analysis might conceivably lead to problems. Imagine a
child who seesone bird, hears the equivalent of " Isn't that pretty?" , sees
another bird, and hears the equivalent of " That's also pretty." Such a
child, using the procedure above, would infer that " pretty" is an NP re-
ferring to the bird. Such errors hardly ever occur with real children.
Nevertheless, if children only hear NPs in the context of sentencesthat
include other phrases, some such proceduremust be applying.
The alternative is to deny the premise above. Perhapsall children are
exposedto somewords in isolation, and thesecan be categorizedas NPs.
One candidate class of words is proper names, as there is evidencethat
these are privileged in lexical acquisition. They appear among the very
first words of children learning a range of different languages(Gentner
1982)- including Kaluli children. Further, proper namesmight be the one
classof words that all children are guaranteedof having been exposedto
in isolation, or at least in some special stressedcontext. Regardlessof a
society's beliefsconcerninghow children learn namesfor kinds of entities,
it is unlikely that any culture assumeschildren are born knowing the
proper namesof the peoplesurrounding them. Thesemust be taught, even
to other adults.
This predicts that even in cultures in which adults do not standardly
label objects for children, proper nameswill be taught to children. Look -
ing at Kaluli children, we find this to be the case. Schieffelin (1985, 534)
notes,
304 Bloom
names . This is primarily due to the linguistic ideology of the culture . It is only
in families who are acquiring literacy that one sees any attention paid to saying
the names of objects , and this activity is initiated by the child when the mother
is looking at books . When extended by the child to other contexts , the mother ' s
response is disinterest .
names and kinterms of the individuals with whom they interact , Kaluli children
Perhaps every cu ~ture has some class of nominals that are special with
broad class , including virtually all object and substance names ; within the
is the class of deictic pronouns , like " this " and " that ." These are also
universal , show up early in child language , and serve to draw children ' s
In sum , it might be that all cultures use some NPs that refer to
either strong extrinsic constraints ( all cultures use some nominals in iso -
lation ) or a powerful learning mechanism ( one that can learn words that
in teres t .
12 .5 Conclusion
syntax within linguistic theory as having " perished or been transformed "
in that the initial considerations in favor of autonomy " seem to have been
The same sort of transfoffi1ation has not yet occurred in the field of
language development , where it is often assumed that " semantic " theories
data are interpreted as favoring one sort of theory over the other . Child -
( Levy 1988 ) .
into this research program , as it posits that innate mappings from syntax
categories like " individual " and cognitive notions like " discrete physical
object " - are used by children to determine the syntactic categories that
rization of new words , and syntactic categories are available at the outset ,
syntactic development runs from phrase to word , not vice versa . This
problem , one that can apply across different languages and that is con -
Notes
1 . One specific problem involves homophony ( Pinker 1979 ) . Many of the words
children learn can appear as both nouns and verbs . Full grammatical knowledge
of English requires knowing that " drink " is a verb when used to describe an action
and a noun when used to describe a substance . To this extent at least , the syntactic
2 . This is related to Pinker ' s ( 1984 ) own proposal , which treats the acquisition of
the plural morpheme . The difference is that Pinker proposes that the segmentation
of " the " and " dog " is the result of initially analyzing " the - dog " as a single noun ,
3 . Mass nouns can be used to form NPs that establish reference to individuals
when they appear with constructions that supply a principle of individuation over
the kind that the mass noun refers to , as in " a grain afsand " or " a glass afwater "
(see Macnamara 1986).
References
Barwise , J., and Cooper , R . ( 1981) . Generalized quantifiers and natural language .
Linguistics and Philosophy , 4, 159- 219 .
Bickerton , D . ( 1981) . Roots o/ language. Ann Arbor , MI : Karoma .
Bloom , P. ( 1990a). Semantic structure and language development. Unpublished
doctoral dissertation , MIT .
Fodor , J. ( 1966) . How to learn to talk : Some simple ways . In F . Smith and
G . Miller ( Eds.), The genesis of language. Cambridge , MA : MIT Press.
Gentner , D . ( 1982). Why nouns are learned before verbs : Linguistic relativity
versus natural partitioning . In S. A . Kuczaj ( Ed .), Language development: Vol. II
Language } thought } and culture . Hillsdale , NJ : Erlbaum .
Gerken, L . A ., Landau, B., and Remez, R. E. ( 1989). Function morphemesin
young children 's speech perception and production . Developmental Psychology ,
27 , 204 - 216 .
University Press .
Pinker , S . ( 1994 ) . How could a child use verb syntax to learn verb semantics ?
dissertation , MIT .
Singleton , J ., and Newport , E . ( 1993 ) . When learners surpass their models : The
University of Rochester .
Valian , V . ( 1991 ) . Syntactic subjects in the early speech of American and Italian
children . Cognition , 40 , 21 - 81 .
6 , 423 - 446 .
In his analysisof nameslike " Freddie" (the name of the new family dog),
John focusedon severalproperties of proper nouns (PN s): They designate
individuals, which they pick out across all times, places, and counter-
factual worlds. The identities of the individuals are traced by means of
sortals, which denote kinds. Finally , the referencesof PNs are not medi-
ated by a Fregeansense(Kripke 1972).
A PN is often learnedthrough ostension; the mother points out the new
puppy and says, " This is Freddie." In order to learn the PN from such
312 Carey and Xu
input, toddlers must have the ability to refer and to understand when
others are referring. They must have someother meansof identifying the
bearer of the name- a demonstrativesuchas " this" or " that," a point, or
a gaze could all do the trick . They must understand the is of identity,
which specifiesthe relation between this and Freddie. And they must
know a sortal conceptthat tracesthe identity of Freddie through time and
counterfactual situations. Note that identity plays two roles in this
account: (1) the identity of Freddie and the individual picked out by the
demonstrative, point, or gaze, and (2) the identity of Freddie over time,
determinedby the criteria of identity supplied by the sortal dog.
13.2 Sortals
To see the role sortals play in our conceptual life , consider these two
questions : ( 1) How many are there in this room ? ( 2 ) Is that the same as
what was here before ? We cannot begin to answer either question without
legs , fingers , or shirts , but we can ' t count the red , the sleeping , or the
wood . Only sortals provide criteria of individuation . Similarly , " same , " in
the sense of numerical identity , means same one , and a sortal is needed to
specify the individual being traced through time . The body we see on the
floor is the same one that existed just before Freddie died , but Freddie ,
whose identity is traced by the sortal dog , not the sortal body , has ceased
from the criteria of numerical identity . To see this , consider two dogs ,
Freddie and George . As you conceptualize them playing on the lawn , the
viduals there , and if they go behind a wall and reemerge , the sortal dog
reemerging from behind the wall was the first dog to disappear . Although
the criteria for individuation establish two individuals each time , criteria
for numerical identity are needed in order to determine which dog was
which .
We agree with John ' s characterization of what is learned when one learns
a PN or a count noun . But John assumed that as soon as a child produced
or comprehended a word like " Freddie " or " dog , " the child had mastered
young infants are sensitive to similarity among exemplars of toy dogs and
differentiate these from exemplars of toy trucks suggests that even pre -
linguistic infants have a sortal concept dog or stuffed dog ( Cohen and
words that differ markedly , even qualitatively , from those adults establish
for the same words .
314 CareyandXu
In order for a child to learn the meaning of a sortal term like " dog " or a
PN like " Freddie ," more is required than an understanding of reference,
intentionality , and demonstratives . The child must represent sortal con-
cepts, specifically the sortal dog. When do sortal concepts become avail -
able to the 'child ? Our focus here is the state of evidence that children
possess a sortal such as dog that provides criteria of individuation and
identity of Freddie . Even John , strong continuity theorist as he was, did
not think that the sortal concepts themselves, such as dog, table, and book ,
are innate . So how and when are they acquired ?
John explicitly denied that there is an unlearned expression synony -
mous with dog in the language of thought . Rather , he thought the origin
of the sortal dog is a gestalt supplied by vision , a prototype abstracted
from experience with dogs. Indeed , prototype abstraction is a powerful
psychological process (Posner and Keele 1968) available to infants
(Cohen and Younger 1983; Quinn 1987). John 's idea was that the psy-
chological representation of basic-level sortals such as dog is equivalent to
same kind as [ gestalt of dog J .
familiarization set (e.g., Quinn, Eimas, and Rosenkrantz 1993; Eimas and
Quinn 1994). In thesestudies, infants as young as 3 months of age succeed
in categorization at the basic level (e.g., distinguishing dogs from cats).
Also, Mandler and her colleagueshave carried out an extensiveseriesof
studies with older babies, using the manual habituation procedure pio-
neered by Ruff (1986), in which infants examine a series of toys from
a single category (e.g., a bird, a turtle, a dog, a fish) and then are given
either a new animal (e.g., an elephant) or a new exemplar from a novel
category (e.g., a car) to play with . Again, novelty preferenceis a measure
of categorization. With this technique, infants show evidenceof catego-
rization at the more superordinatelevel (what Mandler calls the " global
level" ) by 7 months of age, and at the basic level by 9 months of age (see
also Mandler, Bauer, and McDonough 1991; Oakes, Madole, and Cohen
1991; Waxman and Markow 1995).
John was aware, of course, that these data do not prove that infants
representsortals such as dog, stuffeddog, animal, vehicle, or car. He asked
of a study using a manual hab'ituation procedure (Cohen and Caputo,
cited in Cohen and Younger 1983) whether one could be sure that infants
had formed a concept such as stuffed animal, animal, or toy animal, as
opposedto basing their responseon a perceptual feature common to all
11 toys in the study, such as texture or shape. But he clearly meant his
question to be rhetorical, for he answeredit , evidently to his own satis-
faction, with the observation that anyone familiar with 7-month-olds
has the distinct impression that they already know many categoriesof
objects- animals, bowls, cups, hands, bottles, and so forth . By that age,
they behavedifferently toward cups and toward their contents.
John's responsemissesthe mark in two ways. First of all, it is not clear
that there are good data on this point . What data there are suggestthat
knowing what to do with membersof kinds, at least newly encountered
kinds, is not robust until 12 months and later. Baldwin, Markman , and
Melartin (1993) asked when infants would project a distinctive action
relevant to a kind of object (e.g., turning it a certain way to produce a
sound) on the basis of kind membership, and found only shaky and weak
evidence for this ability at 9 months, in the face of definitive success
at ages 12 and 14 months. Second, supposewe did grant the point (that
babies of this age know that to do with bottles). Babiescould simply rec-
ognize examples of bottleness, bottlehood, or bottle-shape, and have
associatedthis property with other properties such as containing milk or
juice. As Quine so rightly pointed out, recognizing a shapeand associat-
318 Carey
andXu
1. Screen introduced
"' cc ct
.\
_c/)"J!c
"<
2. Object 1
\c
--";~
_C brought out
3. f - Object 1
returned
4.
T
~:- Object
brought
2
out
5. Object 2
returned
Screen removed ,
revealing
,~il? "t ;~J
111111111111
6. Expected outcome
or
"',",-- II
'
,"
i
'\ 0-
- rw
: Y !
Unexpected outcome
Figure 13.1
Schematic representation of the property fkind condition in Xu and Carey 1996
320 CareyandXu
failed to draw the inference that there should be two objects behind the
screen, whereas 12-month -olds succeeded in doing so. Further controls
established that the method was sensitive for 10 -month - olds as well as
HABITU
ATI0N
"' ~
,'
-
r
oil
' ~ ~CC
)
tJf ,
APART
(EXPECTED
)
\I.,iCc
(1 ~c):~
('
,coccc
TOGETHER
(UNEXPECTED
)
C'/!f;\) 8
;~
)\Z1
g
Figure 13.2
Schematic representation of the duck -car experiments in Xu , Carey , and Welch
1998
car . However , it is also possible that there is only one , the top half of
which resembles a duck and the bottom half of which resembles a car .
When adults parse the object into two , they are using their knowledge of
the sortals duck and car to do so .
We asked when infants would segment an ambiguous object such as
that in figure 13.2 into two separate objects , the duck and the car . Here
the kind distinction is at the globallev ,el (an animal and a vehicle ) . We
also examined a display consisting of two familiar functional kinds (a cup
on top of a shoe ) . We again used a violation -of -expectancy looking -time
paradigm . Infants were habituated to the ambiguous duck / car display , or
to the ambiguous cup / shoe display , with a hand poised a few centimeters
above it . After the habituation , the hand grasped the top object and lifted ,
revealing either the expected outcome (for adults ) of just the top object
coming up (figure 13.2 , bottom left ) or the unexpected outcome (for
adults ) of the single duck / car or cup / shoe object being lifted as a single
piece (figure 13.2 , bottom right ) . Notice that in this experiment , no short -
term memory demands are placed on the child . Both the duck and the car ,
322 Carey
andXu
or the cup and the shoe, are fully visible at all times when the ambiguous
display is in view. We found exactly the sameage effectsas we reported
in Xu and Carey 1996. Ten-month-olds failed to use the kind contrasts
betweenthe duck and the car, or the cup and the shoe, to infer that there
were two separateindividual objects in this display; they did not look
longer at the unexpectedoutcome of the single object being raised as a
piece. Twelve-month-olds, in contrast, succeededat the task, confirming
both that 12-month-olds have constructed relevant sortals and that the
task sensitively reflects such representations. The sensitivity of the task
was further confirmed by the finding that if the 10-month-old infants were
given spatiotemporalevidenceconcerning the number of objects in this
display (if the objects were briefly moved, laterally, relative to each other
at the beginning of each habituation trial ), they succeeded ; they looked
longer if the object moved as a singlepiece (Xu , Carey, and Welch 1998).
Thus, data from two quite different paradigms, which place very dif-
ferent information-processing demands on the child, converge on the
sameconclusion. Even though infants can discriminate ducks from cars,
cups from shoes, contrasts such as these do not provide criteria for
individuation until sometimebetween10 and 12 months of age.
The two studiesreviewedabove dependupon a rather indirect measure
of how many objects infants take to be involved in these events- their
pattern of looking times at outcomes of one or two objects, compared
to baseline preferencesfor these same outcomes in the absenceof any
habituation of familiarization . Other, more direct measuresof how many
objectsinfants believeto be involved in someevent can be imagined. One
cannot ask the babies, for they obviously cannot talk . But we could have
them reach for hidden objects and measurehow often and persistently
they reach as a function of how many objects are in a box and as a func-
tion of what kind of evidencethey have had concerning this matter. This
is the approach taken in our third line of studies in this series. In these
experiments, on two object trials infants watched the experimenterpull
out an object (say, a toy telephone) from a box, return it to the box, then
pullout a secondobject (say, a duck), and return it to the box. On one-
object trials, the experimenterpulled out one object (say, the telephone),
twice. Infants were then allowed to reach into the box (the opening of the
box was well covered with fabric so the infants could not seewhat was
inside) to retrieve the objects. Infants at both 10 and 12 months always
reachedin and retrieved the first object, which they were allowed to play
with for some time before it was removed from them. Unbeknownst to
Sortals and Kinds 323
them , the second object had been removed from an opening at the rear of
the box , so they could not have felt it when they retrieved the first object .
At issue was what happened then . At 12 months , infants reached persis-
tently for the second object on two -object trials , exploring the inside of
the box , apparently trying to find it . On one-object trials they either did
not reach a second time at all , or did so only cursorily (after all , there was
nothing else to do ; the box was left in place and the first object had been
taken away). At 10 months of age, the pattern of reaching was identical
on one-object and two -object trials : cursory reaching in both cases. At
10 months , however , infants succeeded in a condition in which they were
given spatiotemporal evidence that there were two objects on two -object
trials . ( Twelve -month -olds succeeded in this condition as well , of course.)
If both objects had been shown together before being replaced in the box ,
babies of both ages reached persistently for the second object , differ -
entiating these trials from the one-object trials ( Prevor 1997; Van de
Walle , Prevor , and Carey 1998) .
Note that this is exactly the same pattern of results as in the first
two series of studies. Twelve -month -olds succeeded in establishing repre-
sentations of two objects on the basis of kind differences, whereas 10-
month -olds did not . At both ages babies succeeded when provided
spatiotemporal evidence that there were two objects in the box .
The first lesson we draw from these widely different studies of object
individuation is that John was wrong in the inference he drew from young
infants ' success at categorizing dogs or animals together and differ -
entiating them from cats or vehicles, or from young infants ' knowing
what to do with a cup , ball , bottle , or shoe . These achievements do not
mean that young infants represent the relevant sortal concepts . If we are
right in our interpretation of our results, we have provided evidence
against John 's continuity thesis: infants 10 months of age and younger are
clearly capable of seeing animals as similar to each other , but they do not
represent a sortal animal . Coming to represent one's first sortals for kinds
of objects would be a good candidate for the construction of a new rep-
resentational resource .
So far , we have drawn two conclusions from the above data : ( 1) 10-
month -olds do not represent sortals for kinds of objects, and (2) 12-
month -olds do represent sortais for kinds of objects
. The inferencefrom
324 Carey and Xu
for physical objects . Recall our argument above that same kind as [ gestalt
the sortal physical object . This insight provides part of the answer to the
question John posed concerning how infants learn sortals like dog , but it is
only part of the answer . So far , we have shown that at 10 months , infants
can represent both the sortal physical object and the perceptual [ gestalt of
dog ] without having the sortal dog , since [ gestalt of dog ] does not pro -
objects . But before we offer our speculations about what else the infant
recruits for this task , we must address another issue . John would certainly
not have accepted our friendly amendment of his expression same kind as
cal object specifying the relevant individual . And that is because he , like
what follows , we sketch why he and others hold this position , and we
( 1975 ) , Gupta ( 1980 ) , and Hirsch ( 1982 ) , John denied that object or thing
is a sortal . Their arguments have three parts . First , they claim that people
do not have clear intuitions about the criteria for judging something as the
same object or the same thing . More importantly , if object / thing is a sortal ,
then questions arise concerning the relations between this general sortal
and more specific ones . Perhaps there are no more specific sortals such as
car , cup , or dog - these more specific sortals might now be construed as
predicates of the general sortal object / thing , thus undermining the enter -
In A Border Dispute , John used the following example to illustrate " the
weakness of our intuitions about how to trace identity under the descrip -
tion ' the same thing ' " ( p . 52 ) . Suppose that all of the atoms constituting
Sortals and Kinds 327
Ronald Reagan's body when he was the governor of California were re-
placed by new ones and the old oneswere reassembledto foffi1 the body
of Walter Mondale in 1984. According to John, if we trace identity under
the sortal thing, we would encounter the following problem of the tran-
sitivity of identity: Governor Reagan is identical with PresidentReagan,
Governor Reagan was identical with a set of atoms, and the sameset of
atoms is identical with Walter Mondale; therefore, by transitivity of iden-
tity , Governor Reagan was also identical with Mondale. SinceGovernor
Reagan is also identical with PresidentReagan, we would conclude that
Reaganwould stand for election against himself, " which is preposterous,
and not just on political but logical grounds" (p. 53). The solution, said
John, is to trace the identity of Reagan under the sortal person, which is
not identical with a set of atoms.
Similarly, in The Logical Foundationsof Cognition (Macnamara and
Reyes 1994), John argued that thing/object does not provide criteria for
what to count as one instance of something; that is, it does not provide
principles of individuation . If one were to count the things in the room,
one could count the chair as a chair, four legs, plus one top, hence six
things altogether!
It may indeed be the casethat the English words, " object" or " thing,"
are not sortals, given people's vague intuitions about their criteria for in-
dividation and identity. However, physical object, or Spelke-object, which
is any entity that is three-dimensional, is bounded, and retains its bound-
aries as it moves through spaceand time, is a sortal. It provides princi-
ples of individuation and identity, and it does not eliminate the necessity
for postulating other more specificsortals such as cup or dog. Finally , in
John's formalism for categories, a natural extension can be made to
specify the relation betweenphysical object and sortals such as cup and
dog, an extensionthat dissolvesthe paradoxesof identity (seeXu 1997for
further discussionof theseissues).
Let's go back to John's two examplesabove and seehow applying this
more restricted senseof object- namely, physical object- can help us
dissolvethe problems.
John's first example, involving Reagan, Mondale, and the set of atoms
constituting Reagan, is a caseof the generalproblem of the transitivity of
identity. Note that becauseJohn believed that intuitions about the same
object or the samething are vague, he stipulated that thing/ object is equal
to the set of atoms constituting Reagan. However, the more restricted
senseof object, physical object, is not the sameas a set olatoms . The set
328 Carey and Xu
of atoms constituting an object could change; the object still remains the
sameobject. Therefore, the problem of transitivity of identity disappears
when we apply the sortal object to Reagan, just as it disappearsif we
apply the sortal personto Reagan, as argued by John.
John's second example illustrates how our concept of thing/ object
is vague. Indeed, one could think of the top and the legs of a chair as
objects. However, it seemsunlikely that if one were asked to count the
things/ objectsin the room, a chair would be counted as six things/ objects.
Instead, most people would agreethat a chair is one thing or one object.
Why is this so? Our intuition is that although in everydayspeech, a leg (of
the chair) is a thing/object, when asked to count in this fashion people
spontaneouslyapply the more restricted senseof object/thing (namely,
physical object) , which eliminates the ambiguity, and the result is a count
of one thing/object given one chair.
Clearly, if physical object is a sortal, one must show that it provides
principles of individuation and numerical identity. From the empirical
work reviewed above, we seethat physical object doesprovide such crite-
ria: (1) one object cannot be in two places at the same time (e.g., two
identical cups in two distinct locations simultaneously are two numeri-
cally distinct cups); (2) objectstravel on spatiotemporally connectedpaths
(e.g., if an object appears to have "jumped" from point A to point B
without traversing a continuous path in between, there must be two dis-
tinct objects); (3) objects maintain their boundariesand move as a whole
(e.g., if one part of an object moves independentlyof the rest, there must
be two distinct objects). Thesecriteria are well specified, and both adults
and infants deploy them.
What about the second, deeperworry that if thing/object is a sortal, all
the other more specificsortals can be construed as predicatesof this gen-
eral sortal? The existenceof such a general sortal is damaging for advo-
cates of the sortal view since this general sortal may be the only one
needed. At the sametime, there are good reasonsto believethat cup, dog,
and rock are sortals since they provide principles of individuation and
identity above and beyond the principles provided by the sortal physical
object. A dog ceasesto exist when it dies, but its body continues to exist
and it is the samebody as before. The problem is in fact a rather general
one sincemore than one sortal can be applied to any given entity; besides
being an object, that thing over there (indicating Freddie) is also a pet, a
poodle, a mammal, an animal, a body, a set of atoms.
What is the relation among thesesortals? Macnamara and Reyes(1994)
argue that contrary to classicallogic, it is not one of class inclusion and
Sortals and Kinds 329
identity. For example, the set of atoms constituting a dog could change,
but one would still have the samedog; in casesof metamorphoses, a dog
could change into a mouse, or a frog into a prince, and one would still
have the same animal or the same living thing. Macnamara and Reyes
(1994) present a fonnalism for characterizingthe relations among sortals
by means of underlying maps. An underlying map is a function that
maps membersof a setA to membersof a set B. For example, a passenger
from set A is mapped onto a person from set B by an underlying map u:
passenger~ person. A member of the kind passengeris identified with,
but not identical to, a member of the kind person through the mapping
process. Similarly, a member of the kind dog is identified with a member
of the kind animal by the samemapping process. This fonnalism can be
extended to allow members of the kinds dog/animal/car to be identified
with membersof the kind physical object.
In sum, we have shown that a more restricted senseof object- namely,
physical object- is a sortal for both infants and adults, and one can
specify the relation betweenthe sortal physical object and the more spe-
cific sortals such as dog or chair by underlying mapping, thus avoiding
long-standing problems regarding transitivity of identity. Postulating the
sortal physical object is part of the solution to how infants construct sor-
tals such as dog or chair, and the hypothesisthat young infants represent
it is supported by empirical evidence.
Before infants are 10 months of age, they are able to abstract a visual
prototype from a set of dogs, and they representat least one sortal con-
cept, physical object, yet they have not constructed the sortal dog. And ,
we have argued, they have constructedsomesortal that individuates dogs,
or at least toy dogs, from other kinds of objects by 12 months of age.
How do they do so?
John posed the question in the context of word learning, asking how
children learn the meaning of a sortal term like " dog." His answer was
that infants bring to the word-learning task an understanding of refer-
ence, demonstratives, the is of identity, the sortal kind, and a sortal that
covers dogs: same kind as [ gestalt of dog] . We have offered a crucial
friendly amendment to his proposal: that the sortal that covers dogs is
same kind of physical object as [ gestalt of dog) . Physical object, in this
330 Carey and Xu
We have not yet dwelt upon John ' s proposal that the child 's ability to
learn specific sortals requires a prior sortal , kind . When we mentioned this
proposal in section 13.2, we gave only John 's logical justification for it :
the child must eventually distinguish concepts that cover kinds of in -
dividuals , groups of individuals , individuals themselves , and properties of
individuals , and so must have some way of representing these distinctions .
We certainly agree with this logical point , and we offered empirical evi-
dence in section 13.6 that infants have distinguished kinds of objects from
properties of objects by 12 months of age.
But here we wish to emphasize the importance of the prior sortal kind
to the learning of sortals for kinds of objects. Suppose children not only
know that there will be kinds of objects, but also have expectations about
kinds that help them identify candidate kinds in their experience of the
world . It is an open question what these antecedently represented expec-
tations will be. We tentatively offer the following suggestions: ( 1) kinds are
determined by deep, often hidden properties , which determine some of the
surface properties of objects, (2) the deep properties that determine kinds
influence many intercorrelated surface properties , (3) the deep properties
that determine kinds are causal and thus interpreted in terms of whatever
causal understanding the child has constructed , (4) object kinds do not
change over time , whereas surface properties may , and (5) object kinds
are named by adults . Notice that these are properties of substance sortals
like dog and animal , not stage sortals like pet and passenger. But stage
sortals are acquired late , and children 's first interpretation of a count
noun .applied to a novel object is that it is a basic-level substance sortal
( Hall 1993).
The sortal physical object enables infants to pick out individuals and
trace them through time , so that they can observe which properties change
with time and which remain stable, and so that they can observe stable
intercorrelated properties . Such observation would help identify kinds , if
the baby is looking for them . There is now evidence that some of these
Sortals and Kinds 331
grounds, that John's solution will not work : samekind as [ gestalt ofdogj
is not a sortal that covers dogs. Also neededare (1) an individual that
provides the first criteria of individuation and identity and (2) a stronger
notion of kind than can be provided by shape similarity. Regarding the
first, we offer the sortal physical object. And regarding the second, we
offer severalexpectationsabout kinds that infants might bring to the task
of constructing their first sortals and some tentative evidencethat these
expectationsmay actually playa role in this achievement.
Notes
1. Throughoutthe chapter, mentionsof words are in quotation marks and
mentionsof mentallyrepresented conceptsor sortalsarein italics.
2. Childrenthis younghavedifficultydisengaging attention. Followingeyegaze
requiresdisengaging attentionfrom a visibleface. In Hood, Willen, and Driver's
procedure , 3-month-old infantssucceededwhentheywerelookingat a schematic
facewhoseeyesmovedand whichthendisappeared from the screen , leavingthe
infantsfreeto follow the gaze.
References
and attentional focus : Evidence from language and emotion . In C . Lewis and
P . Mitchell ( Eds .) , Children 's early understanding of mind ( pp . 133 - 156 ) . Hove ,
England : Erlbaum .
Hillsdale , NJ : Erlbaum .
Eimas , P., and Quinn , P. ( 1994) . Studies on the formation of perceptually -based
basic-level categories in young infants . Child Development , 65, 903- 917.
Geach , P. ( 1957) . Mental acts: Their content and their objects. London : Routledge
and Kegan Paul .
Gibbard , A . ( 1975) . Contingent identity . Journal of Philosophical Logic , 4,
187 - 221 .
Gupta , A . ( 1980) . The logic of common nouns. New Haven , CT : Yale University
Press .
Poster presented at the biennial meeting of the Society for Research in Child
Development , Washington , DC .
Scaife , J . F . , and Bruner , J . S . ( 1975 ) . The capacity for joint visual attention in the
infant . Nature , 253 , 256 - 257 .
257 - 302 .
old infants . Paper presented at the 22nd Boston University Conference on Lan -
guage Development .
Xu , F . ( 1997 ) . From Lot ' s wife to a pillar of salt : Evidence that physical object is a
Xu , F ., and Carey , S. ( 1996). Infants ' metaphysics : The case of numerical identity .
Cognitive Psivchology, 30, 111- 153.
Xu , F ., Carey , S., and Quint , N . ( 1997) . Object individuation at 12 months : Shape
and other properties . Poster presented at the biennial meeting of the Society for
Research in Child Development , Washington , DC .
Xu , F ., Carey , S., and Welch , J. ( 1998). Infants ' ability to use object kind infor -
mation for object individuation . Manuscript submitted for publication .
Chapter 14
Semantics and the D . Geoffrey Hall
Acquisition of Proper Names
Having a proper name (e.g., " Tom ," " Dick ," or " Harry " ) is a funda -
mental property of being human , so basic that it has been called a uni -
versal right in a number of international declarations and covenants . For
example , Article 7-1 of Convention of the Rights of the Child , adopted
by the General Assembly of the United Nations in 1989, states that " [t]he
child shall be registered immediately after birth and shall have the right
from birth to a name" ( Valentine , Brennen , and Bredart 1996). As the
epigraph to this chapter reveals, countries may even impose restrictions
on what counts as an acceptable proper name , indicating the seriousness
with which humans treat the act of naming people .
According to ethnographers , all human societies confer proper names
upon their members (Alford 1987), and linguists have noted that proper
names crop up in all the world 's languages (Hockett 1966). Nonetheless ,
there are many striking crosscultural differences in practices associated
with naming people . For example , societies differ in terms of whether
people receive one or more first names in addition to one or more sur-
names; whether names are bestowed at birth or after a period of weeks,
This chapter was written with the support of a Natural Sciencesand Engineering
ResearchCouncil of Canada operating grant. I thank Paul Bloom, SusanGraham,
and Ray Jackendoff for their very helpful comments on previous versions. I am
immensely grateful"to John Macnamara for all that he taught me during the 10
years that I had the great fortune to have him as a teacherand friend.
338 Hall
months, or even years; whether proper names are drawn from a large
and diverse set of possibilities or a small stock of conventional options;
whether names given near birth are used throughout life or changed at
important points (e.g., puberty); and whether proper names are used
freely in public discourseor kept private (Alford 1987). In addition, the
universality of proper names for humans does not mean that people are
the only bearers of these labels. Among other things, humans routinely
name animals (e.g., dogs), artifacts (e.g., boats), places(e.g., cities), media
products (e.g., movies), events (e.g., hurricanes), and institutions and
facilities (e.g., companiesand schools) (Hall , Veltkamp, and Turkel 1997;
Valentine, Brennen, and Bredart 1996).
This chapter examineshow children learn proper names. The task of
learning these expressionshas at least two components. First, children
must learn the mappings between individual proper names and their
appropriate interpretations in the particular languagethey are acquiring,
becausethe inventory of proper namesdiffers from languageto language.
For example, children learning English must somehow learn that the
word " Tom" should be interpreted as referring to an individual (i.e.,
Tom) in a specificmanner. Second, children must acquire knowledge of
how the syntax and morphology of their particular languagetreat proper
names, becauseproper names behave as a coherent class grammatically
within a language but do not accept the same affixes or appear in the
same serial positions within sentencescrosslinguistically. For example,
English learners must somehow discover that the word " Tom" shares
important grammatical featureswith " Mike " and " Bill " that it does not
sharewith " bike" or " mill ."
How do children learn the links between proper names and their
appropriate interpretations, and how do they gain knowledgeof the gram-
matical properties of expressionsof this class? The answer proposed in
this chapter is that children do so by exploiting implicit semanticknowl-
edgethat they possesswhen they begin to acquire language. This knowl-
edge consists of an understanding of the semantic definition of proper
names, along with an expectation that expressionsused under certain
conditions (related to this definition) should be interpreted as belonging to
this class. Children exploit this knowledge in the following way: As they
hear novel labels used by speakersto refer to things in the world , they
interpret some of them as satisfying conditions that imply they should be
taken to be proper names; as a result, children take them to be proper
names, assigningthem interpretations that are consistentwith the seman-
Semantics
andProper
Names 339
14.1.1 Grammar
One way to identify proper names is through their morphology and
syntax. Even though the class of proper namesis universal, the environ-
ments in which these labels can appear within sentencesvary from lan-
guageto language. In English, proper namesare expressionsthat do not
normally take the plural morphemeand do not usually follow determiners,
quantifiers, or adjectives. For example, we may speak of " Tom" but not
" Toms" (unlesswe mean, for example, " people named Tom" ). In addi-
tion, we do not say " a Tom" or " severalToms" without leaving some-
thing to be specified (e.g., " a person named Tom" or " several people
named Tom" ). Finally , we rarely use adjectives to premodify proper
names (e.g., " happy Tom" ), restricting this practice to a pragmatically
340 Hall
14.1.2 Semantics
Another way to identify proper namesis via their semantics. Unlike their
morphological and syntactic properties, which differ acrosslanguages, the
semanticproperties of proper namesappear to be universal (e.g., Kripke
1980; Macnamara 1986; Macnamara and Reyes 1994). Specifically, a
proper name is an expressionthat refers to an individual (in a kind), in
all the situations in which that individual appears, regardlessof the con-
ditions under which it is used. In this way, proper names contrast with
expressionsfrom other classes , such as count nouns (which refer to kinds
of individuals; e.g., " person," " dog" ). For example, the proper name
" Bill Clinton " is a label that refersto the individual , Bill Clinton, and can
be used to pick him out in all the contexts in which he figures. These
might be real situations (e.g., those associatedwith his childhood in
Arkansas or his current adulthood serving as president of the United
States), or they might be counterfactual (e.g., those associatedwith a
childhood spent in Iceland, had he moved there when he was a baby, or
an adulthood working as a veterinarian, had he chosennot to becomea
politician). An important consequenceof this fact is that proper names
Semantics
andProperNames 341
are not synonyms for definite descriptions . For example , the proper name
" Bill Clinton " cannot be defined by the description " the president of the
United States raised in Arkansas ," even though that description (in fact )
picks out the individual , Bill Clinton , uniquely . If a proper name were
simply synonymous with such a description , then it would be impossible
to account for the intuition that the individual can be picked out using
that proper name in situations where the description does not apply (e.g.,
the intuition that " Bill Clinton " can be used to pick out Bill Clinton in the
situation in which he had chosen to treat sick animals for a career and had
lived his whole life in Reykjavik ) (see Kripke 1980; for different versions
of the descriptivist view of proper names, see Frege 1892; Russell 1905;
Searle 1958) .
" Bill Clinton " also picks out the same individual regardless of who
happens to be speaking and regardless of the context in which that person
happens to be situated . Of course, there may be more than one person
named " Bill Clinton ," and so there is a sense in which the interpretation
of a proper name does depend upon the occasion of its use (see Barwise
and Perry 1983). Yet the context -specificity associated with interpreting
proper names seems to stem more from the fact that there are not enough
of them to go around than from any feature of their semantics . To ap -
preciate this argument , note the contrast between proper names and other
noun phrases, such as pronouns (e.g., " I " ) or definite descriptions (e.g.,
" the president of the United States" ) . These other expressions also can be
used to refer to individuals , even to Bill Clinton , but they require that the
context be specified in order for their referents to be fixed . For example ,
the referent of the pronoun " I " varies in a systematic way with the situa-
tion (e.g., who happens to be speaking) . Similarly , a definite description
like " the president of the United States" depends crucially upon the con -
text in which it is uttered for its referent to be identified (e.g., if the con -
versation were about the Civil War , the referent might be Lincoln ; if it
were about Watergate , Nixon ; or if it were about Whitewater , Clinton )
(see Macnamara and Reyes 1994).
Finally , a proper name refers to an individual that is typed by a kind
of individual . (In languages like English , kinds of individual are named
by count nouns - for example , " person ," " dog ." ) Macnamara ( 1986;
Macnamara and Reyes 1994) has argued that a proper name needs the
support of such a kind in order to specify the individual and in order to
account for the tracing of that individual 's identity across situations .
Consider pointing to a man who is sitting in the Oval Office in the White
342 Hall
House and saying , " That is Bill Clinton ." What is the " that " that the
proper name " Bill Clinton " is meant to name ? The answer is a person .
Yet without a kind (e.g., PERSON ) to make this specification , it is im -
possible to know whether the name should pick out Bill Clinton 's entire
body , or just his visible surface, or the set of molecules of which he is
presently constituted , or whether to include his clothing and the pen in his
hand . A kind serves to tell which individual a proper name designates. In
addition , in order for " Bill Clinton " to function as referring to the same
person when it is used to pick out both a little boy in Arkansas and a
president in the White House , there must be something to provide for the
identity of the boy with the president . This something is, again , a kind like
PERSON . By supporting statements in which the name " Bill Clinton "
appears, a kind enables a proper name to do its job of picking out one
persisting individual across these situations (e.g., the 2-year-old and 51-
year-old bearers of the name " Bill Clinton " ) . In sum, proper names form
a discrete semantic class, distinct even from other noun phrases, as
expressions that refer to individuals (typed by kinds ) in all the situations
in which they appear , regardless of the context .
Second , 2 -year - old children seem to know the relation between some of
the syntactic and semantic properties of proper names. Specifically , they
appear to understand that a novel word applied to an object in a proper
name syntactic context (e.g., " This is X " ) refers to an individual . In a
seminal study , Katz , Baker , and Macnamara ( 1974; Macnamara 1982)
showed two groups of children a pair of dolls differing in hair color . One
group heard a novel label presented syntactically as a proper name (e.g.,
" This is ZA V " ) for one of the dolls . The children 's task was then to
choose one of the two dolls to perform requested actions formulated using
the novel word (e.g., " Can you give me ZA V ?" ; " Can you show your
mother ZA V ?" ) . The dependent measure was the percentage of actions
performed with the named doll . The main finding was that children (girls
as young as 17 months ; boys as young as 27 months ) showed a strong
tendency to select the named doll in response to the requests: they chose it
about three quarters of the time . This result suggests that they typically
took the label to refer to an individual , consistent with their having
interpreted it as a proper name .
To demonstrate that children do not believe that all types of words
refer to individuals , Katz , Baker , and Macnamara ( 1974) presented the
same label for the same doll to a second group of children . For this group ,
however , they modeled the label in a sentence context that was appropri -
ate for a count noun (e.g., " This is a ZA V " ) . Count nouns , recall , do not
refer to individuals ; they refer to kinds of individuals . These children
heard requests to perform actions formulated in sentences that supported
a count noun interpretation of the label (e.g., " Can you give me a ZA V ?" ;
" Can you show your mother a ZA V ?" ) . This group showed no tendency
to favor the named doll in performing the actions : they chose it only
about half the time ; the remainder of the time , they picked the other
doll . This outcome is consistent with the possibility that these children
interpreted the word as naming the kind , DOLL , or the particular kind of
doll . (It is also, of course, consistent with the possibility that children were
simply guessing.) Children thus seemed to expect that a word named an
individual only if it was modeled in a proper name sentence context , not if
it appeared in a count noun sentence environment .
In another part of the study , Katz , Baker , and Macnamara (1974)
labeled one of two differently colored blocks , rather than one of two dolls ,
for two other groups of children . These children selected the named block
only about half the time in response to the experimenter 's requests,
regardless of whether the experimenters modeled the novel word as a
344 Hall
proper name (as they did for one group) or a count noun (as they did for
the other group). These results are consistent with the possibility that
children interpreted the label as naming the kind, BLOCK , or the specific
kind of block (as well as with the possibility that they guessed ) . The dif -
ferencebetweenchildren's interpretation of an intended proper name for
a doll and their interpretation of the sameword for a block suggeststhat
their willingnessto treat a word as a name for an individual dependednot
only on the syntactic context in which the word appeared, but also on the
specifickind of object (or properties of the object) being labeled.
To follow up the study by Katz, Baker, and Macnamara (1974; Mac-
namara 1982), Gelman and Taylor (1984) conducted a similar study but
changedthe method in severalways. They testedgroups containing both
boys and girls; children's averageage was about 2 1/2 years. They used
unfamiliar (previously unlabeled) toys as target stimuli, two surrogatesof
animate objects (animal-like stuffed toys) and two inanimate objects
(blocklike plastic toys). In addition, they presentedchildren with all four
objects at once. Half the time, the animals servedas target stimuli (i.e.,
one of them receiveda label modeled as a proper name or a count noun)
and the blocklike toys were distractors. The remainder of the time, the
blocklike toys played the role of target stimuli (i .e., one of them received
the label modeled as either a proper name or a count noun) and the ani-
mals served as the distractors. Adding two distractors to the two target
stimuli in the array of object choices enabled Gelman and Taylor to do
something that Katz, Baker, and Macnamara could not: clearly distin-
guish guessing (in which case, children should have chosen randomly
among all four objects) from other, more systematicinterpretations, such
as a kind of object (in which case, children should have selectedrandomly
betweenthe two target stimuli).
Gelman and Taylor 's main result replicated that of Katz, Baker, and
Macnamara. They observed the strongest tendency to select the named
toy in the group that heard the label modeled syntactically as a proper
name for an animal-like toy. This result suggeststhat children in that
group took the word to name that individual . In addition, Gelman and
Taylor found evidencethat children interpreted the novel word modeled
syntactically as a count noun, for either an animal-like or a blocklike
object, as naming a kind of object, becausechildren in thesegroups chose
randomly betweenthe two target stimuli, ignoring the two distractors. In
fact, children tended to selectone of the distractors only if they heard a
label that was presentedsyntactically as a proper name and the named
Semanticsand Proper Names 345
object was blocklike . In that group , some children appeared to forget the
act of labeling and selected exclusively one of the animal -like distractors ,
as if they interpreted the label as referring to that individual . Other chil -
dren in this group chose randomly between the two blocks , as if they took
the label to refer to a kind , such a BLOCK . Like the children in Katz ,
Baker , and Macnamara 's study , the children in Gelman and Taylor 's
study thus appeared to show an understanding of a link between proper
name syntax (e.g., " This is X " ) and proper name semantics (e.g., " X "
refers to an individual ), but only for some kinds of objects (or objects with
certain properties ) .
Liittschwager and Markman ( 1993) clarified an interpretive issue raised
by the results of the preceding studies. They argued that the earlier
findings do not , in fact , unambiguously show that children think that a
novel word modeled in the sentence context " This is X " is a proper name
wearing); neither object now had that property, and so children should
have chosenrandomly betweenthe objects. Alternatively, children might
have taken the word to name some other property of the original object
(e.g., its shapeor color); both objectsnow had the sameproperties, and so
again children should have chosen either object. However, if children
thought that the label named the original object as an individual , then
they should have picked it , despitethe loss of its distinctive property, the
changein its location, and the fact that it was indistinguishable from the
new 0bject.
Liittschwager and Markman found that 3-year-olds did show a strong
tendency to pick the originally named object as the referent of the novel
word; subsequentanalysessuggestedthat this tendencywas specificto the
animate surrogatesthey used (i.e., bears and trolls) and did not extend
to the inanimates they used (i .e., shoesand baby bottles). These results
suggestthat children did, as previously claimed, interpret the novel word
modeled in the sentencecontext " This is X " for an animate surrogate
as naming an individual . Confirming that children do not treat words
modeled in all sentencecontexts in this way, the authors also found that
another group of 3-year-olds who heard the samenovel word modeled in
a count noun sentential context (e.g., " This is a DAX ," followed by the
test question " Where's a DAX ?" ) showedno preferencefor the originally
named object, regardlessof whether it was animate or inanimate, consis-
tent with their having interpreted the label as naming a kind of object (or,
of course, with their having guessed ).
To summarize: By the time children are 2 or 3 years old, they possessat
least some elementsof a mature understanding of proper names. Two-
year-olds produce proper names in appropriate sentential contexts (i .e.,
not following adjectives) (Bloom 1990). In addition, 2-year-olds and 3-
year-olds appear to interpret a novel word modeled in a sentential envi-
ronment appropriate for proper names (i .e., " This is X " ) and applied to
an animate surrogate object (a doll or an animal) as referring to an indi-
vidual (Gelman and Taylor 1984; Katz, Baker, and Macnamara 1974;
Liittschwager and Markman 1993; Macnamara 1982).
object cannot ? On the one hand , some evidence suggests the answer might
be no . In many cultures , including our own , there are far fewer proper
names than there are proper name bearers. For example , Anderson (1977,
cited in Alford 1987) estimated that there are 6 million men named
" John " and 4 million women named " Mary " in the United States. On the
other hand , anecdotal evidence suggests that children do make the
assumption . For example , Macnamara ( 1982) made the following obser-
vations about his son , Kieran :
For a time he seemed to assume that proper names were uniquely paired with in -
dividuals . The reason for believing so is that when he met his first " doppelganger "
he refused to accept the name . He was at the time [ 16 months and 13 days old ] and
had met a cousin of his , Lisa . He was then introduced to a girl of about the same
age as Lisa also called Lisa . They played for half an hour , yet , most unusual for
him , he refused to say her name , no matter how often anyone said it or urged him .
Shortly after he met three girls all named Aimee and he accepted the name for all
three . (p . 28)
He has a friend Rebecca at the sitters ' that he loves to play with very much . He
calls her Becca because it ' s easier for him to say . I have a friend who has a three -
month old daughter named Rebecca, and Matthew will not call her by her name .
I introduced him to her saying that her name was Rebecca, and he said " No
Becca!" He has since been calling her " baby ."
Figure14.1
Sampleschematic
targetstimulifrom Hall 1996
would interpret the expression as a proper name (e.g., " Fido " ), given that
it was applied to only one object , given that the syntax of the sentence
allowed a proper name interpretation , and given that the object was an
animate surrogate . The other group heard the same label applied sepa-
rately to drawing of two different objects (e.g., two dogs with the same
novel striped pattern ). Here I expected that children would be more
reluctant to interpret the novel word as a proper name, because it was
applied to two objects . Instead , I suspected that they would take the word
to be an adjective (e.g., " striped " ) naming a property , because the word
could also be disambiguated in this way . (See figure 14.1.)
To assess the interpretation of the novel label , I showed children in
both groups a set of object drawings , including ( 1) the labeled object or
objects (e.g., the original striped dog or dogs), (2) an object of the same
kind that lacked the named object 's (or objects') salient property (e.g., a
different stripeless dog), and (3) an object of a different kind that pos-
sessed the labeled object 's (or objects') salient property (e.g., a striped
umbrella ). I then asked whether children would extend the novel label to
each of these objects in turn (e.g., " Is this dog ZA VY ?" , " Is this umbrella
352 Hall
quenceof this fact is that two proper namesfor one individual would both
have the same interpretation. Given independent evidencethat learners
do not like to acquire more than one word with the sameinterpretation
(e.g., they tend to assumethat words contrast in their interpretations;
Clark 1987), they should be more likely to seea novel word as a proper
name if it is used to refer to an object that does not already have one of
theselabels than if it is used to refer to an object that does. For example,
they should view the existenceof one dog labeled both " Fido " and " Ro-
ver" to be inconsistent with the possibility that both these words are
proper names.
Notice that the semanticredundancyassociatedwith two proper names
for one individual would not be true in the case of multiple words from
other lexical categoriesfor the sameindividual . For example, the seman-
tic function of an adjective is to refer to a property of an individual , and
any individual has many properties. As a result, learnersshould be willing
to interpret a novel label as an adjective if it is applied to an object that
has already been labeled with another adjective. For example, learners
should view the existence of one dog designated both " spotted" and
" furry " as consistent with the possibility that both these words are
adjectives. In addition, becauseproper names and adjectiveshave differ-
ent semantics, learnersshould find the existenceof two words for the same
object, one from each of theseclasses , to be consistentwith thesewords'
belonging to thesetwo classes . For example, they should seethe existence
of one dog labeledboth " Fido" and " furry " to be consistentwith the pos-
sibility that thesewords are a proper name and an adjective, respectively.
Do children assumethat a label used to refer to an object can be inter-
preted as a proper name if the object lacks a proper name, but not if it
already has one? Some evidencesuggeststhe answermight be no. There
are societiesin which different people refer to the sameperson by using
entirely different proper names (Valentine, Brennen, and Bredart 1996),
and in our own culture, different people may refer to the sameindividual
using distinct variants of the individual 's name (e.g., in decreasingfor-
mality , we might use a surnamealone, a surnameplus first name, a first
name, and somediminutive form ofa first name) (Alford 1987). However,
some recent experimental evidencesuggeststhat young children do make
the assumption. One way to test for its existencewould be to compare
how two groups of children interpret a novel label modeled as a proper
name, using a design like that describedin Hall 1996. One group would
hear the new label used to refer to an object previously labeled with
354 Hall
another proper name ; the other group would hear it used to refer to the
same object previously labeled not with a proper name but with a word
from a different class. A proper name interpretation of the new label
should be more likely if the referent object had no previous proper name
than if it did . Susan Graham and I took another , more indirect approach
(Hall and Graham , in press). We presented children with a novel label
modeled as a proper name, along with a choice of two referents , one of
which had been previously labeled either with a proper name or with a
word from a different class . If children assumed that a label could be a
proper name if it was applied to an object that lacked a proper name (but
not if it was applied to one that had one), then we predicted that they
would choose the previously labeled object only if the previous label was
not a proper name .
In one of the studies, we taught one group of4 -year-old children a novel
word modeled unambiguously as a proper name for a familiar object
(e.g., a stuffed dog). For example , we said, " This dog is named ZA VY ."
We taught another group of 4-year-olds the same word for the same
object but modeled it unambiguously as an adjective . For example , we
said, " This dog is very ZA VY ." (See the top half of figure 14.2.) We then
brought out a second object that looked identical to the first (e.g., another
stuffed dog). We placed it to the side of , and several inches behind , the
first object , but still within the child 's easy reach. Now we provided a
second word modeled unambiguously as a proper name and asked chil -
dren to choose its referent . For example , we said, " Show me a dog that is
named DAXY ." (See the bottom half of figure 14.2.)
If children believe that a novel word can be taken as a proper name
only if it is used to refer to an object that has not already been labeled
with a proper name (e.g., one dog cannot be both " Fido " and " Rover " ),
then we predicted that those in the group who had learned a proper name
for the first object (dog A in figure 14.2) would select the second object
(dog B in figure 14.2) . In contrast , if children assume that a novel word
can be interpreted as a proper name if it is used to refer to an object that
either has or has not previously been labeled with an adjective (e.g., one
dog can be both " spotted " and " Rover " ), then we predicted that those in
the group who had learned an adjective for the first object would show no
strong tendency to select the second object . This is, in fact , what we
found . Children strongly favored the second object as the referent of the
second word (a proper name) if they had learned a proper name for the
first object , but not if they had learned an adjective .
356 Hall
Figure14.4
Sampleschematic
targetstimulifrom Hall 1991
label , I brought out three other stuffed animals . One was from the same
kind of object as the named one (either another cat or another monster of
the same kind ) but wore differently colored clothes . The other two were
distractors from different kinds . The task was similar to the one used by
Gelman and Taylor ( 1984) : to select one of the four toys in response to a
series of requests formulated using the new word (e.g., " Can you put ZA V
on top of your head?" ; " Can you point to ZA V ?" ). As in Gelman and
Taylor 's study , the main dependent measure was the percentage of trials
on which children chose the labeled object . A higher percentage of named
object choices suggested a stronger tendency to interpret the label as a
proper name for that individual .
Children in both familiar and unfamiliar groups showed , overall , a
strong tendency to select the named toy . This finding was not surprising ,
because both the familiar and unfamiliar labeled objects were animate
surrogates , and both were described with a word modeled syntactically
as a proper name . However , as predicted , children who learned the word
for the familiar object (the cat) were significantly more likely than those
who learned it for the unfamiliar object (the monster ) to select the named
object (i .e., to make a proper name interpretation ). Those who heard the
word for the unfamiliar object often selected the other object of the same
kind as the labeled object in response to the requests, suggesting that they
had misinterpreted the word as a name for the kind (as a count noun ). In
addition , children ' s spontaneous comments transcribed from tape record -
ings of the test sessions provided further evidence that those in the famil -
iar group were more likely than those in the unfamiliar group to interpret
the word as a proper name . In the familiar group , children sometimes
asked the experimenter what the unlabeled cat was " named " or " called ,"
suggesting that they had taken the word for the labeled object as a proper
name . In the unfamiliar group , children did not ask these questions ;
instead , they often made comments revealing that they had misconstrued
the intended proper name as a count noun . For example , after hearing the
intended proper name (e.g., " This is ZA V " ) for the labeled monster ,
children often pointed to the other monster of the same kind and
described it using the novel word , but they placed the word in sentence
contexts reserved for count nouns , such as " two ZA V s" or " another
ZA V ."
The second study included two new groups of 2-year-olds and used a
similar procedure , but different familiar (i .e., dogs) and unfamiliar (i .e.,
novel monsters of a different kind ) animate surrogates as test stimuli . The
366 Hall
14.3.5 Summary
This section explored the idea that learners should be more likely to
interpret a novel label as a proper name if certain conditions of using the
word are met than if they are violated. These conditions, inspired by the
semantic definition of proper names (i.e., expressions that refer to
individuals in kinds in all situations in which the individuals appear,
regardlessof the context), are that the label be applied to only one object;
that the label be applied to an object that has not already been labeled
with a proper name; that the label be applied to an object that is marked
as important as an individual in some way (e.g., by being animate and
possessedby someone); and that the label be applied to an object for
368 Hall
14.4 Discussion
that matches children '8 assumptions about which labels they hear in
speech should be interpreted as belonging to this class. However , Tracey
Burns and I are currently planning some studies to try to answer it .
Another important issue for future work to address is the origin of
children 's understanding . If young children do have knowledge of the
universal semantic definition of proper names, along with knowledge that
labels used under certain conditions (related to this definition ) should be
interpreted as proper names, then where does it come from ? The results of
the demonstrations described in this chapter are consistent with the pos-
sibility that young children possessthis understanding between the ages of
2 and 4 years, during , the period of rapid vocabulary development that
occurs in the preschool years. Yet the relatively advanced age (in terms of
the time course of language acquisition ) of the children in these studies
precludes making strong claims about the origins of this knowledge .
Further research with infants and young toddlers (i .e., those at least as
young as the 17-month -olds in the study reported in Katz et al . 1974) may
shed light on whether any or all of the knowledge also exists in children
on the brink of learning language . Evidence of the presence of this
understanding in very young children would bolster support for the view
that children initially acquire these expressions (e.g., make mappings
between them and their interpretations ; learn their grammatical proper -
ties as a class) via an unlearned semantic competence .
References
Gordon , P. ( 1985) . Evaluating the semantic categories hypothesis : The case of the
count -mass distinction . Cognition , 20, 209- 242.
Gupta , A . ( 1980) . The logic of common nouns. New Haven , CT : Yale University
Press .
Hall , D . G . ( 1991). Acquiring proper names for familiar and unfamiliar ani -
mate objects : Two -year -olds' word learning biases. Child Development , 62, 1442-
1454 .
Hall , D . G ., and Graham , S. A . (in press). Lexical form class information guides
word -to -object mapping in preschoolers . Child Development .
Hall , D . G ., and Moore , C . E . ( 1997). Red bluebirds and black greenflies: Pre-
schoolers' understanding of the semantics of adjectives and count nouns . Journal
afExperimental Child Psychology 67, 236- 267.
Hall , D . G ., Veltkamp , B ., and Turkel , W . ( 1997). Proper namable things.
Unpublished manuscript , Department of Psychology , University of British
Columbia .
When I came to McGill as a graduate student, John was writing his book
Namesfor Things. John told me to read a draft of his chapter on pro-
nouns I and you for my first presentation in his graduate seminar. Since
then, I have been fascinated by the problem of indexicals, particularly
personalpronouns. I decidedto pursuethe problem of how children learn
English personal pronouns as my Ph.D . research. John gently guided me
on how to analyze the problem and showed me the complexities of the
problem that children must solve. Understanding the mind of children
solving such a complex problem is most interesting and challenging. I am
deeply grateful to John for opening my eyesto such an exciting area of
study and for sendingme off on an endlessbut fascinating inquiry of true
understanding. This chapter is about what I have learned about children's
learning of personal pronouns since I began my investigation with John.
The basic theoretical framework presentedhere was developedas part of
my Ph.D . researchand has been the guide for empirical studies I have
carried out sincethen. John helped me greatly with the philosophical lit -
erature and deepenedmy understandingof referenceand meaning.
I begin in section 15.1 by describing the problems that confront chil-
dren in learning first and secondperson pronouns in English, grammati-
cally as well as semantically. Then I analyze the semanticaspectsof per-
sonal pronouns based on Kaplan's theory of indexicals. In section 15.2,
using Kaplan's theory as a foundation, I propose a psychological theory
15 . 1 . 1 Grammatical Aspects
The third person pronouns substitute for noun phrases or proper names ,
not for nouns ( Lyons 1983 ; Macnamara 1982 ) . First and second person
Oshima - Takane 1993 ; Oshima - Takane and Derat 1996 ) . Unlike count
proper names or count nouns when they learn personal pronouns ( Bloom
15 . 1 . 2 Semantic Aspects
The sentence " Mommy is reading a book " expresses the same proposition
whether the mother or the child utters it . In order to judge whether the
know whether or not the mother is reading a book when the sentence is
uttered . On the other hand , the sentence " I am reading a book " expresses
tence " I am reading a book " is true or false , we should know not only
who is reading a book when the sentence is uttered but also who utters the
sentence . This does not deny that the sentence " I am reading a book " has
a fixed meaning . The sentence has the same meaning whether the mother
or the child utters it , just as the sentence " Mommy is reading a book "
like the girl . When we hear the utterance " Mary is coming soon," the
character of the proper name Mary tells us that it refers to the individual
named Mary , whoever utters it . The content of the proper name Mary
must be the same individual at all times and in all places in which the
individual exists and in all circumstances in which the individual might
possibly exist . In this sense, a proper name is a rigid designator (Kripke
1980).1 However , there is more than one Mary in the world and the
character of the proper name is not sufficient to determine the content on
a particular occasion . Knowledge of the context is also necessary. Count
noun phrases like the girl or the dog running over there are called definite
descriptions, and we use them to refer to a particular object of which the
description is true . In order to determine the content of a definite
description in a particular context of use, again knowledge of the context
is necessary unless there is only one object in the world that fits the
description . Hence , proper names and definite descriptions as well as
personal pronouns are all dependent on the context of use. However , the
way personal pronouns depend on the context is systematically different
from the way proper names or definite descriptions do .
In order to capture such differences , we should break the context fur -
ther into three features , following Barwise and Perry (1983). These fea-
tures of the context , which are used in different ways in getting from the
character of an expression to its content on a particular occasion of use,
are discourse situation , connections , and resource situations .
A discourse situation is a situation in which an utterance occurs ; " it
involves who is speaking , when , and where , what words are being uttered ,
and to whom " ( Barwise and Perry 1983, 121) . If the mother says to her
child , " I am reading a book ," the utterance (" I am reading a book " ), the
speaker (the mother ), the addressee (the child ), the time of the utterance ,
and the location of the utterance are the elements of discourse situation .
The role of the facts of discourse situations in fixing the content is usually
referred to as indexicality , and the content of any indexical must be
among the elements of the discourse situation .2 Particular elements in the
discourse situation that are of crucial relevance to the first and second
person pronouns are the speaker and the addressee. On the other hand ,
the contents of proper names or definite descriptions are not necessarily
among the elements of the discourse situation and do not change so sys-
tematically with the discourse situation . In order to determine the content
of proper names or the contents of definite descriptions , we use the
speaker's connections and resource situations .
378 Oshima-T akane
We are related to various things in the world . For example, there are
many Marys and many dogs in the world, but we know only someof the
Marys and some of the dogs. In other words, we have connections to
certain Marys and certain dogs in the world . When we use the proper
name Mary or the definite description the dog, we refer to a particular
Mary among the Marys we know (or perceive) or we refer to a particular
dog among the dogs we know (or perceive). Connections that link an
utterance to its content on a particular occasion of use are called the
speaker's connectionsin the utterance. The addresseemust find out these
connectionsto get from the character of the utterance to its content on a
particular occasionof use, and the speakermust believethat the addressee
can recover them. For example, if a child says, " Mommy is reading a
book," the mother would think that her child refers to her by Mommy,
whereasif the boy next door saysthe samesentence , shewould think that
he refers to his mother, not to her. To determine the content of Mommy
used by her child, therefore, the mother uses her child's connections,
whereasto determine the content of Mommy used by the boy next door,
she uses the boy's connections. The character of an expression simply
givesus a generalrule to refer to things to which we and other people are
connected.
Although there are many different expressionsthat refer to the same
thing, not all of them are available to the speakerand the addresseeall the
time. For example, when I tell a friend somethingabout Mary , I can refer
to her by her name, Mary . But if I cannot rememberher name or if my
friend does not know Mary , I cannot use M al"y to refer to her. However,
if my friend and I seeMary standing at the door, I can usethe description
the girl standingat the door to refer to Mary . In this case, I am using the
fact that Mary is standing at the door to refer to Mary . This fact about
Mary is called a resourcesituation that allows me to use the description
the girl standing at the door as referring to Mary , and my own and my
friend's perceptual connections to this resource situation allow me to
successfullyrefer to Mary by that description. However, if I am talking to
my friend over the telephoneand my friend cannot seeMary standing at
the door, I have to use different resourcesto refer to Mary . For example,
if my friend knows Mary 's father, Mr . Clark, I may use the description
Mr . Clark's daughter to refer to Mary . Here I use the fact that Mary 's
father is Mr . Clark as a resource situation, and my connections to this
resourcesituation and my friend's connection to Mr . Clark allow me to
successfullyrefer to Mary by this description.
First and SecondPersonPronouns 379
learns the singular first and second person pronouns ? It tells us that the
child has to learn at least two things : ( 1) the character of each pronoun
(i .e., the semantic rule that is used to determine the content of the pro -
noun on each occasion of use), and (2) the elements of discourse situations
that are relevant to pronouns . The characters of the singular first and
second person pronouns are given by the following rules ( Barwise and
Perry 1983; Kaplan 1977) :
(I ) A first person pronoun , in each utterance , refers to the person who
uses it .
The elements of the discourse situation relevant to the first and the second
Children learn most of their words from hearing other people using them
in the course of normal conversation . The personal pronouns are no
exception . Many normally developing children master the first and second
person pronouns with few errors by the age of 3, without explicit teaching
(Clark 1978; Macnamara 1982, 1986; Oshima -Takane 1985, 1988; Shipley
and Shipley 1969; Strayer 1977) . This suggests that children learn the
meaning of personal pronouns from hearing the pronouns used in the
speech of others . Following Kaplan ' s analysis of indexicals , I assume that
each personal pronoun has a fixed meaning (character ), but the referent
380 Oshima
-Takane
(content) of the pronoun shifts depending on the context of use, that is,
who is speakingand who is spoken to. Starting from this premise, I have
proposed that the child's task of learning personal pronouns consists of
the following two parts (Oshima-Takane 1985): (1) to correctly determine
the content of pronouns used by others in each instance of use (i.e., to
comprehendpronouns correctly), and (2) to induce the correct semantic
rules- character- that would lead to the correct production of pronouns
as well as correct comprehension. In this section, I will analyze what
abilities each presupposeson the part of the child and propose a psycho-
logical theory of how children learn first and secondperson pronouns.
that some of the earliest uses of pronouns by children are part of a set
phrase such as " I do it ," and pronouns are not differentiated from other
words in utterances (Charney 1980b; Clark 1978).
Although children may not segment out the pronoun forms in the
utterances from the beginning , they must do so at a certain point in order
to figure out the character of the pronouns . The data reported in the lit -
erature show that before beginning to use any personal pronouns , all
normally developing children correctly use some nonpronominal terms
for others such as Mommy , Daddy , Jamie , and some count nouns such as
doggie, car, ball (Macnamara 1982; Nelson 1973). Further , some children
correctly use their own names and even use two -word sentences like
" Mommy sit" or " More milk ." These data suggest that personal pro -
nouns are not the first words they learn . It is possible, then , that they can
use their knowledge of the words they have already acquired to segment
out the personal pronoun forms . Interchangeable uses of proper names
and pronouns by parents (e.g., " That ' s you . That 's David " ) may also help
a child identify the pronoun foffi1s in utterances (Macnamara 1982, 1986;
Oshima -Takane 1985; Strayer 1977) .
There is abundant evidence that children use kinship terms such as
Mommy and Daddy and some proper names for others before using
any personal pronouns ( Nelson 1973; Oshima -Takane 1985; Seki 1992;
Smiley and Huttenlocher 1995). However , most children start to use their
own names at about the same time they start to use a personal pronoun to
refer to themselves. Some children call themselves by their own names
before they start to use any personal pronouns ; other children use per-
sonal pronouns to refer to themselves before they start to use their own
names (Macnamara 1982; McNeill 1963; Oshima -Takane 1985; Schiff -
Myers 1983; Strayer 1977) . Comprehension and production data on
proper names and personal pronouns that I collected for my Ph.D . research
indicated that most of the children who used personal pronouns in refer -
ence to themselves but did not yet use their own names responded to their
own names correctly in comprehension tests (Oshima -Takane 1985) .
Further , studies with Japanese children provide some evidence suggesting
that children understand their own names correctly before they begin to
use their names or any pronouns designating themselves. Uemura ( 1979),
who observed 19 Japanese children from 1 month to 20 months of age in
experimental as well as natural settings, reported that they understood
their names used by others about two months before they started to use
their names themselves. For example , from 15 months on, one child
382 Oshima-Takane
child to identify what parents are referring to, parents rarely point to
people when they use personalpronouns (Wales 1979).
How, then, do children come to identify a person referred to by a pro-
noun? Macnamara (1986) arguesthat to identify the referent of a personal
pronoun, the child must have accessto the basic-level kind PERSON.
Kinds supply a principle of individuation , a principle of identity, and a
principle of application for what they are true of. In the caseof the kind
PERSON, the principle of individuation specifieswhat counts as an indi-
vidual person. The principle of identity provides the criteria for deciding
whether individuals considered at different points in time are the same
person or different persons. The principle of application picks out an
individual person from all other things that are not a person. Macnamara
emphasizesthat accessto the kind PERSON is particularly important
becauseit is a person that is the referent of a personalpronoun, not just a
person's face, nose, or visible surface. The ability to recognize an indi -
vidual as a member of the kind PERSON is presupposed.
Application of the kind PERSON to an individual presupposesthat the
child is able to pick out a person from all other animate and inanimate
objects and to assignthe person as a member of the kind . Thus, having
accessto the kind PERSON helps the child figure out that a pronoun
picks out a person. In fact, if the child were not able to recognizea person
as distinct from all other animate and inanimate objects, the child would
never be able to correctly determine what a personal pronoun refers to.
Recent evidencesuggeststhat children can make global kind distinctions
(e.g., animal/artifact, vehicle/ animal) and basic-level kind distinctions
(e.g., bottle/ball, cup/book) before they talk (Mandler, Bauer, and
McDonough 1991; Xu and Carey 1996). But how do children know that,
when they hear a pronoun usedby others, it refersto an entire person, not
a body part such as a nose or an object other than a person such as a
chair? This is what children must discoverby observinghow other people
use pronouns. As just noted, children are sensitiveto the speaker's inten-
tion and actively search for cues to understanding what the speaker is
expressingwith an utterance. Linguistic and nonlinguistic contexts in
which the pronouns are used may help them discover the referents. Fur-
ther, parents' interchangeableuseof personalpronouns and proper names
should help them discover that a pronoun refers to a person, not a body
part or an object other than a person (Macnamara 1986; Oshima-Takane
1985). For example, if a child already knows the word Mommy to refer to
his mother, who is a member of the kind PERSON, and if the child hears
384 Oshima-Takane
her hand toward the child ) ," the child will be more likely to take me as
referring to his mother , rather than referring to a body part such as her
hand .
In order to induce the correct semantic rules , children must not only
determine the referent of the pronouns used by others but also discover
the relationship between the pronoun and the speech role of the person it
names interchangeably when they talk to their child , and this practice
may help the child understand what pronouns refer to . However , this
practice does not necessarily help the child figure out the correct use of the
pronouns . This is because when children use pronouns , they must reverse
what they hear . Even if a child correctly determines the content of the
for pronouns are logically possible . Children may think that first person
pronouns are used to refer to another person with whom they talk , or that
first person pronouns are used to refer to others who are speaking but
cannot be used to refer to themselves even when they are speaking , or that
must discover the correct relationships between the pronouns and the
speech roles from such variously interpretable data and induce the
semantic rules .
What abilities does this task presuppose on the part of the child ?
Obviously , the child must be able to identify at least two elements of the
discourse situation : who the speaker is and who the addressee is . This
cholinguists claim that children first distinguish the speaker from others ,
based on the observation that children initially come to use first person
pronouns correctly , then second person pronouns , and finally third person
determine whether children identify the speaker , the addressee , and the
First and SecondPersonPronouns 385
use of you and the father 's use of you both refer to the same person (the
child ), the child must be able to identify herself as herself over time . Sim-
ilarly , in order to understand that the mother 's use of me and the father 's
use of you both refer to the same person (the mother ), the child must be
able to identify the mother as the same person over time . This does not
mean, however , that mistakes cannot happen , as when an adult or a child
fails to identify a person when the person looks like someone else or the
person's appearance has changed dramatically .
Macnamara ( 1986) argues that as in the case of proper names (for
persons), access to the kind PERSON is necessary for learning personal
pronouns , since it not only helps the learner understand that the referent
of a personal pronoun is a whole person but also helps the learner handle
the identity of the person over time . This means that when children learn
personal pronouns or proper names, the kind PERSON must be available
to them and can be used to trace the identity of members of that kind . It is
likely that this knowledge is implicit in children who are learning pro -
nouns ; that is, they can recognize an individual as a member of the kind
PERSON but do not know the count noun person . Macnamara noted
First and SecondPersonPronouns 387
that his son, Kieran, did not usethe count noun person, which denotesthe
kind PERSON, until long after he used many proper namesfor persons
and personal pronouns (Macnamara 1986). Consistent with this obser-
vation, examinations of children's early vocabularies indicate that the
count noun personis not among the first 50 words (Nelson 1973; Oshima-
Takane 1985). It is possible that children correctly interpret person used
by others even though they do not produce it , although, as far as I am
aware, no systematic investigation has attempted to determine when
children come to understand this word. In any event, we have some evi-
dence indicating that children correctly use others' names and also cor-
rectly understand or use their own names before they start to use any
personal pronouns. Becausechildren cannot understand or use others'
names and their own nameswithout identifying the personsnamed over
time, the proper name data suggestthat children can trace both their
own identity and other people's by the time they start to use personal
pronouns.
Some researchers(see, e.g., Smiley and Huttenlocher 1995) have sug-
gestedthat children may initially fail to include themselvesin the kind
PERSON becausethey have limited accessto " physical appearanceof the
whole self (except in the mirror )" (p. 41). This is certainly possible, but
physical appearanceis not the only infoffi1ation children use when cate-
gorizing objects into different kinds (Baldwin, Markman , and Melartin
1993; Xu and Carey 1996). Perhaps children categorize themselvesin
the samekind as their parents but not in the samekind as dogs and cats
becausethey notice that they behave like their parents but unlike dogs
and cats. The point is that children must be able to recognizethemselves
as membersof the kind PERSON by the time they master personal pro-
nouns, eventhough they may initially fail to do so. As Macnamara (1986)
has argued, unless children know that they are also persons, it will be
difficult for them to realize that they can usefirst personpronouns to refer
to themselves .
15.2.3 Summary
The above analysis shows that the learning of first and second person
pronouns presupposesthat children have the following abilities:
. To identify the speaker, the addressee, and the nonaddresseein a dis-
coursesituation;
. To understandthe speaker's intention;
388 0 shima-T akane
The crucial requirement for understanding and using first and second
person pronouns- what one needs beyond what is needed for dealing
with other referring expressions such as proper names and definite
descriptions- is noticing the regularities in their shifting referents. I have
proposedthat overheard speechprovides situations important for discov-
ering the systematic relationships between pronouns and speech roles
(Oshima-Takane 1985, 1988). This proposal has challengeda prevailing
view in the Western literature on child language, becauseit attributes to
children the ability of analyzing overheardspeech. Much of Westernchild
language research has emphasizedthe importance of specially adapted
speechthat mothers use in child-directed talk . Overheard speechis not
consideredan important source of input from which children learn lan-
guage, becauseutterancesnot addressedto children are generally longer
and more complex than those addressedto them (see Oshima-Takane,
Goodz, and Derevensky 1996for more detailed discussionon this issue).
My argument is this: If we assumethat, without explicit teaching, children
are able to understand that the same personal pronouns (in particular,
secondperson pronouns) can be used to refer to different persons, and
that different personal pronouns (i .e., first person and secondperson pro-
nouns) can be usedto refer to the sameperson, then we must also assume
that children are able to analyze overheard speech(nonaddressedspeech )
as well as child-directed speech(addressedspeech). If children do not
First and SecondPersonPronouns 389
15.4 EmpiricalEvidence
directed speech. His problem was that he had induced the incorrect
semantic rules, which were based solely on the information provided in
child -directed speech (see Oshima -Takane 1985, 1992 for more detailed
discussions) .
A subsequent longitudinal study of 10 girls (Oshima -Takane and Oram
1991) provides further evidence that children determine the referent of
pronouns used by others before they learn the relationship between pro -
nouns and speech roles . Children 's comprehension and production data
were collected at three different ages: 21, 24, and 30 months . Compre -
hension was tested both when the child was an addressed listener and
produced correct pronouns earlier than firstborns, even though the two
groups of children did not differ on other languagemeasuressuchas mean
length of utteranceand vocabulary size. Our argument is that secondborn
children acquire the correct usageof pronouns earlier than firstborn chil-
dren becausethey have relatively more opportunities to hear pronouns
used in overheard speech, that is, in conversation between their parents
and their older siblings. A correlational analysisof secondbornchildren's
input and pronoun development (Oshima-Takane 1997) provides more
direct evidence for the importance of overheard speech in pronoun
acquisition. The more frequently the secondbornsheard first person pro-
nouns in overheard speech, the earlier they mastered the use of these
pronouns. Furthermore, the fewer unconventional nominal references
(e.g., useof Mommy or the older sibling's name instead of first and second
person pronouns) the mothers or older siblings used in overheard speech,
the earlier the child masteredthe use of secondperson pronouns.
In sum, the evidencereviewedso far is consistentwith the proposal that
children first determine the referentsof the pronouns used by others and
then induce semanticrules. Experimental and observational studies pro-
vide converging evidence that, in inducing the correct semantic rules,
children benefit from observing shifting referenceof pronouns in over-
heard speech. Furthermore, observational studies have shown that some
children make pronominal errors in production becausethey hold incor-
rect semantic representations, and thesemirror the way first and second
person pronouns are used in child-directed speech: me refers to any other
person and you refers to themselves . Another important finding is that
although a proper name interpretation for second person pronouns
appearsto be common among children at an earlier stage, many of them
do not show production errors becausethey produce proper names in-
steadwhen referring to themselvesas speakerand to others as addressee .
Nonetheless, the evidence that children induce the incorrect, reversed
rules (i.e., me means any other person and you means themselves ) by
observing pronouns in child-directed speechis limited. This is becausein
the teaching experiment, there were more children in the addresseecon-
dition who showedan inconsistenterror pattern than thosewho showeda
consistenterror pattern. Further, the number of children in the addressee
condition who showed the consistent error pattern was not significantly
greater than the number of children who showedthis pattern in the non-
addresseecondition. One problem with the teaching experiment is that
children who observedpronoun models in the addresseecondition could
First and SecondPersonPronouns 397
15.5 ComputerModeling
For ethical reasons, we cannot manipulate the linguistic input outside the
teaching experiment in such a way that children in the addresseecondi-
tion are not exposedto any overheard speech. Further, even though we
analyze the children's task in order to specify the prior knowledge or
abilities that they must have, we cannot directly test the effects of the
hypothesizedprior knowledge or abilities in empirical studies. Computer
modeling may provide a way to complement such limitations associated
with human empirical studies. One advantage of computer modeling is
that we can test hypothetical learning mechanismsby setting up ideal
environmental conditions that would be ethically impossible with human
children. In this section, I present evidence obtained from computer
modeling studies that I have been conducting with my collaborators
(0 shima-Takane, Takane, and Shultz 1995, 1996; Shultz, Buckingham,
and 0 shima-Takane 1994). In thesestudies, we have concentratedon the
secondpart of children's task in learning pronouns: how children induce
the semanticrules of first and secondperson pronouns after determining
I
the content of a pronoun in the speechof others. In particular, the studies
were designedto obtain more clear-cut evidencethat children induce the
incorrect, reversedrules by observing pronouns used in addressedspeech
only, whereasthey induce the correct rules by observingpronouns usedin
nonaddressedspeech. In addition, we examined the role of knowing the
kind PERSON in this induction process.
We used the cascadecorrelation (CC) learning algorithm (Fahlman
and Lebiere 1990), with which networks can grow dynamically to adapt
to more complicated problems. The algorithm starts with a network
without hidden units. It first tries to improve its performance within a
given network topology by adjusting the connection weights. When it can
no longer improve its performance by merely adjusting the weights, it
changesthe network topology by adding a hidden unit that is good at
398 Oshima-T akane
inducing the correct semantic rules, networks trained with addressee pat -
terns (i .e., patterns in which the child was always addressed) during phase
I training would learn the incorrect , reversed rules by the end of this
training and would need phase II training to master the correct child -
speaking patterns . By contrast , networks trained entirely with non -
addressee patterns (i .e., patterns in which the child never was addressed)
during phase I training would learn the correct rules and would produce
the correct child -speaking patterns without phase II training . However , if
the notion of the kind PERSON plays an important role in this induction
process, as assumed in the present proposal , then even networks trained
with nonaddressee patterns would not induce the fully correct semantic
rules . They would need at least some phase II training to produce the
correct child -speaking patterns . The results support the latter prediction .
N one of the networks trained with nonaddressee patterns in the first set of
simulations could learn to produce the correct child -speaking patterns
without requiring explicit error -correcting feedback (phase II training ),
although they corrected errors quickly . On the other hand , the networks
trained with addressee patterns learned the incorrect , reversed rules and
needed extensive phase II training to correct their errors .
The second set of simulations was designed to test whether adding prior
knowledge of the kind PERSON , the information that the child (self ) is a
member of the same kind as mother and father (other ), would facilitate
the induction of the correct semantic rules without error -correcting feed-
back (Oshima -Takane , Takane , and Shultz 1995, 1996). We used analog
coding to implement prior knowledge about PERSON . That is, the child
was coded as 0 , the mother was coded as + 2 , and the father was coded
as - 2. One output unit was used to code me (+ .5) and you (- .5) . The
analog coding allows us to represent members and the class to which they
belong by assigning a number to the members on the same unit .4 Further ,
the distinction between self (child ) and others can be derived from the
regularities of pronoun use in the training patterns . With the previous
binary distributed coding , on the other hand , the networks treat each
person as a distinct object with no relation to other objects in the training
patterns . In the second set of simulations , we also investigated whether
experiencing many examples involving various persons was another
important factor facilitating induction of the correct semantic rules . To
do this , we added two other persons, coded as + 1 and - 1, respectively .
We compared the conditions in which the networks heard only two other
persons using pronouns (3-person conditions ) with those in which they
400 Oshima-Takane
15.6 ConcludingRemarks
theory of how children learn the semantic rules as they observe other
people use such pronouns. That is, children first determine the person
referred to by a pronoun in each instanceof use and then make generali-
zations about the semanticrules for first and secondperson pronouns. In
order to induce the correct semanticrules, children must observeshifting
reference of pronouns in overheard speech. Child -directed speechis a
source of pronominal reversal errors; children who do not have enough
opportunities to observe shifting pronominal reference in overheard
speechinduce the incorrect, reversedrules.
The empirical studies together with the computer modeling studies
provide converging evidencein support of this proposal. The data indi-
cate that children determinewhich person a pronoun usedby others refers
to in each context of usebefore they discover the relationship betweenthe
pronouns and speechroles. There is no indication that children map pro-
nouns directly onto speechroles. Further, the empirical studies demon-
strate that children even younger than 2 can extract information given in
overheard speechto induce the correct semanticrules for first and second
person pronouns. The computer modeling studies also provide clear-cut
evidencethat children induce the incorrect, reversedrules by observing
pronouns used in addressedspeechonly, whereasthey induce the correct
rules by observingpronouns usedin nonaddressedspeech.In addition, the
studiesdemonstratethat knowing the kind PERSON and being exposed
to many examplesinvolving various personsas the referents of the pro-
nouns are important in this induction process.
In this chapter, I have not dealt with the problem of how children
determine the content of pronouns in the speechof others. However, this
does not mean that I assumethat children have no problem in determin-
ing the content of the pronouns used by others. As discussedin section
15.1, there are severalproblems children must solve in order to correctly
determine the content of pronouns used by others, and none of these
problems is as simple as it looks. I have assumedthat children use their
prior knowledgeof proper names(their own name and others' names) and
of the kind PERSON in determining the content of personal pronouns
used by others. Prior knowledge of proper namesis important in several
respectsfor determining the content of pronouns used by others. First, if
children know their own and other people's names, we can assumethat
they are able to trace their own identity as well as that of others over time
before they learn personal pronouns. Second, we can assumethat the
interchangeableuse of proper names and personal pronouns by parents
First and SecondPersonPronouns 403
helps children identify both the pronoun forms in utterancesand the ref-
erentsof the pronouns. Knowing the kind PERSON is important because
children's ability to recognizethemselvesand others as members of the
same kind PERSON is essential for understanding that personal pro-
nouns refer to a person.
This doesnot mean, however, that with accessto their prior knowledge
of proper names and the kind PERSON, children have no problem in
determining the content of pronouns used by others. For instance, one
mother, who participated in the teachingexperimentdescribedabove, told
me that her son appearedto think that me referred to a neck, probably
becauseshe and the father pointed toward their neck when they played
the me-me game (0 shima-Takane 1985). Since this boy had already
called himself by his name and his parents by Daddy and Mommy, his
problem was not that he did not know any word that designatedhim or
his parents as a whole person. Instead, he did not yet seemto have dis-
covered that the particular word me refers to a whole person, not just a
person's neck. Interestingly, this boy seemedto solve this problem the
day after the final sessionof the me-me game. His mother's diary stated
that when she went to her son's bedroom in the morning, he began
pointing to himself and said, " Joe, me" several times with a confident
look . This was the first time he used the pronoun me with his name, Joe.
The mother interpreted this event as indicating that her son discovered
that when he uttered me, it picked out himself as an entire person, just like
his name. Sinceparentsused me only in the me-me game and did not use
names along with me at all, the boy must have discovered the corefer-
ential relationship between names and the pronoun me used by adults
outside the teaching experiment. In normal conversations, unlike the
teachingexperiment, the boy could hear pronouns usedin sentences ; thus,
syntactic cues, too, might have helped him reject the body part interpre-
tation. Further, the experienceof observinghis mother and father playing
the me-me game with each other (i .e., in the nonaddresseecondition)
might have helped him to discover that me refersto the person who utters
it . Perhapshis implicit assumption that he is of the samekind PERSON
as his parents might have led him to use me to refer to himself without
hesitation. Unless children actively search for cues to the speaker's in-
tention, as this boy did, they will never be able to arrive at the correct
interpretation.
The present approach does not assumeany fast mapping mechanisms
specific to word learning as do the special lexical constraints approaches
404 Oshima-T akane
popular in psychology (e.g., the object -kind bias or the mutual exclusivity
assumption - Markman 1989; Merriman and Bowman 1989). Findings
from the studies described here suggest that the learning of personal pro -
nouns is gradual and cannot be explained by these fast mapping mecha-
nisms. It could be that the constraints and biases posited to be specific to
word learning are not yet fully developed during the early stage of pro -
noun learning . Or these constraints may be operating only for certain
types of word learning . Logical analysis of children 's task in learning
words other than personal pronouns and detailed empirical studies of
their solutions to the task such as those discussed here will elucidate the
early language -learning process and will provide further insights into the
ability children bring to language learning .
Notes
1. Note that other referring expressions such as indexicals and definite descrip -
tions refer rigidly (i .e., the referent is taken as fixed for all possible circumstances ),
once the referent is detennined . Kaplan uses directly referential for these referring
expressions (see Kaplan 1989) .
2. In the case of the direct -quotational use of indexicals , as in " Teddy Bear said ,
'I 'm sleepy,' " the person who reports what Teddy Bear said does not use the
words in quotation marks but mentions them . Thus , the discourse situation of the
expression being quoted is the one Teddy Bear was in when he uttered it .
3. This does not mean that we cannot use a personal pronoun to refer to a thing
other than a person . In fact , people often talk to a dog or a cat or even an inani -
mate object using personal pronouns . However , it is considered that animals and
inanimate objects in such cases are personified , and second person pronouns are
used to refer to them .
References
Akhtar , N ., and Tomasello , M . ( 1996). Two -year -olds learn words for absent
objects and actions . British Journal of Developmental Psychology , 14, 79- 93.
Andersen , E . A ., Dunlea , A ., and Kekelis , L . S. ( 1984) . Blind children 's language :
Resolving some differences . Journal of Child Language , 11, 645- 664.
Baldwin , D . A . (1991). Infants ' contribution to the achievement of joint reference.
Child Development , 62, 875- 890.
First and SecondPersonPronouns 405
Brener , R . ( 1983) . Learning the deictic meaning of third person pronouns . Journal
of Psycho linguistic Research, 16, 330- 352.
Brown , R . ( 1973) . A first language: The early stages. Cambridge , MA : Harvard
University Press.
Charney , R . ( 1980a) . Pronoun errors in autistic children : Support for a social
explanation . British Journal of Disorders of Communication , 15, 39- 43.
Charney , R . ( 1980b) . Speech roles and the development of personal pronouns .
Journal of Child Language , 7, 509- 528.
Chiat , S. ( 1981). Context -specificity and generalization in the acquisition of pro -
nominal distinctions . Journal of Child Language , 8, 75- 91.
Chiat , S. ( 1986) . Personal pronouns . In P. Fletcher and M . Garman ( Eds .),
Language acquisition : Studies in first language development (2nd ed., 339- 355) .
Cambridge : Cambridge University Press.
Clark , E . V . ( 1978) . From gesture to word : On the natural history of deixis in lan -
guage acquisition . In J. S. Bruner and A . Garton ( Eds .), Human growth and devel-
opment: Wolfson College Lectures ( pp . 85- 121) . Oxford : Oxford University Press.
Cole , E ., Oshima -Takane , Y ., and Yaremko , R . ( 1994). Case studies of pronoun
development in two hearing -impaired children : N onnal , delayed , or deviant ?
European Journal of Disorders of Communication , 29, 113- 129.
de Villiers , P. A ., and de Villiers , J. G . ( 1974) . On this , that , and the other : Non -
egocentrism in very young children . Journal of Experimental Child Psychology , 18,
438 - 447 .
Durkin , K ., Rutter , D . R ., Room , S., and Grounds , P. ( 1982) . Proper name usage
in maternal speech: A longitudinal study . In C . E . Johnson and C . L . Thew ( Eds.),
Proceedings of the Second International Congressfor the Study of Child Language
( pp . 405- 412) . Washington , DC : University Press of America .
Durkin , K ., Rutter , D . R ., and Tucker , H . ( 1982) . Social interaction and language
acquisition : Motherese help you . First Language , 3, 107- 120.
Fahlman , S. E ., and Lebiere , C . ( 1990) . The cascade correlation learning architec -
ture . In D . S. Touretzky ( Ed .), Advances in neural information processing systems 2
( pp . 524- 532) . San Mateo , CA : Morgan Kaufmann .
406 Oshima-Takane
Hall , D . G . ( 1994). How children learn common nouns and proper names. In
J. Macnamara and G . E. Reyes ( Eds.), The logical foundations of cognition
( pp . 212- 240) . New York : Oxford University Press.
Hall , D . G ., and Waxman , S. R . ( 1993). Assumptions about word meaning :
Individuation and basic-level kinds . Child Development , 64, 1550- 1570.
Issler , D . ( 1993). Comprehension of spatial points of view and acquisition of
personal pronouns in Brazilian Portuguese. Unpublished master ~s thesis, Pontifical
Catholic University of Rio Grande do SuI, Brazil .
Kaplan , D . ( 1977) . Demonstratives . Paper read at a symposium on demonstratives
at the March 1977 meetings of the Pacific Division of the American Philosophical
Association .
Macnamara , J. (1986
). A borderdispute
. The place of logic in psychology . Cam -
bridge, MA : MIT Press .
First and SecondPersonPronouns 407
48 , 385 - 394 .
Shipley , E . F . , and Shipley , T . E . ( 1969 ) . Quaker children ' s use of thee : A rela -
tional analysis . Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior , 8 , 112 - 117 .
Smiley , P . , and Huttenlocher , J . ( 1995 ) . Conceptual development and the child ' s
early words for events , objects , and persons . In M . Tomasello and W . Merriman
( Eds . ) , Beyond names for things : Young children ' s acquisition o / verbs ( pp . 21 - 61 ) .
Hillsdale , NJ : Erlbaum .
Snow , C . E . ( 1976 ) . Mother ' s speech . In W . von Raddle - Engel and Y . Lebrun
( Eds . ) , Baby talk and infant speech ( pp . 263 - 264 ) . Amsterdam : Swets and
Zeitlinger .
Tager - Flusberg , H . ( 1989 ) . An analysis of discourse ability and internal state lex -
( Ed . ) , The perceived self ( pp . 174 - 184 ) . New York : Cambridge University Press .
Uemura
. ,M.(1979
44 ).Development
ofego
ininfancy
.Shinrigaku
Hyoron
,22
,28
-
First and SecondPersonPronouns 409
(T1) Each individual has exactly one mother and exactly one father,
who are also individuals.
the obvious right -action that increases length by 1, giving its cohesiveness
and variation ; in particular , the empty string 1I is the generic individual ,
all of whose ancestors are distinct . A concrete individual in a society X is
any morphism I ---+ X ; in particular , the infinitely many endomorphisms
I ~ I are easily seen to be in one-to -one correspondence with the strings
in I . Composing with the two endomorphisms m and f , which correspond
to the two strings of length 1, completely describes, in the context of the
whole category , everything we need to know about the particular internal
structure of X : the actions xm , x f are realized as special cases of the
compositionof morphisms
. The conditionthat everymorphismX ! Y
in the topos must satisfy is then seen to be just a special case of the asso-
ciative law of composition , namely , the special case in which the first of
the three morphisms being composed is an endomorphism of I . The facts
stated in this paragraph constitute the special case of the Cayley -Y oneda
lemma , applied to the small category W that has one object , whose
endomorphisms are the strings in two letters , composed by juxtaposition ;
a category with one object only is often referred to as a monoid .
With loss in precision we can say that x ' is an ancestor of x in case there
exists some endomorphism w of I for which x ' == xw . In the particular
society X , the w may not be unique ; for example , xmff == xfmf might
hold. But the precision is retained in the category W/ X , discretelyfibered
over W, which is essentially the usual genealogical diagram of X . The
correlation of the reproductive process in X with past solar time could be
given by an additional age functor from this fibered category to a fixed
ordered set; a construction of Grothendieck ( 1983) would permit inter -
nalizing such a chronology too in Tl 'S topos .
N ow we can explain the truth -value system. The subsets of I in the
sense of our topos are essentially just sets A of strings that , however , are
not arbitrary but subject to the two conditions that if I ~ A is a member
of A , then also wm and wf must be members of A . Thus , A can be
thought of as all my ancestors before a certain stage, the antiquity of that
stage depending however on the branch of the family . These As constitute
the truth -values! To justify that claim , we must first define the action of m
andfon As ; this is what is often thought of as " division " :
A : m == { w s W : mw sA } ,
A : f == { w G W : fw GA } .
It is easily verified that these two are again subobjects of I if A is. Note
that A : f consists of all my [ather 's ancestors who were in A . The truth -
Kinship and Mathematical Categories 417
value true is A :=: W, the whole set of strings, and union and intersection
A u B, A n B are the basic propositional operations or, and on truth -
values. The operation not A of negation does not satisfy all the Boolean
laws, sinceit must again yield a subobjectof I :
not A == { WB W : for all v B W, wv does not belong to A }
is the set of all my ancestorsnone of whose ancestorswere in A, so (A
or not A) is usually much smaller than true. Why does the object Q thus
defined serveas the unique notion of truth -value set for the whole topos?
Consider any subset X ~ Y in the senseof the topos; then there is a
unique morphism Y ~ Q such that for all individuals I ~ Y in Y,
y G~ if and only if cjJ
(y) == true.
The value of </>on any elementy is forced to be
tj>(y) == { W8 W : yw 8 ~} .
Thisis themeasuredanswer , to the question''Preciselyhow Irish is y?"
ovrer the past 2 , 000 years . But this collapsing of the remote ancestors A to
the case where A is connected , IIoA == 1 . Then the construction has given
" point " ( = = figure of shape 1) in a topos like ours ? Since m and fact
xm == x == xi .
logical bookkeeping .
individual ' s mother is female , and every individual ' s father is male .
a topos and in fact have a direct relation to the topos of TI ' Na ~ ely , in
the first topos there is a particular object G with only two individuals
called male andfemale and where the two structural operations act as the
constant maps . Our refined topos has objects that may be described as
for which Jtj ; == y ; the codomain of this triangle is defined to be the pair Y ,
J . The conditions
y ( xm ) == ( yx )m
and
y ( xf ) = = ( yx ) f
in the new sense is really the " locus of a point moving virtually between m
e f = = a f = = a & em = = am = = e .
different Eve / Adam pair for each of the mutually oblivious subsocieties
16.5 Moieties
16.6 Congealing
Becominginto Being
for any given w in Wand any two individuals Zl , Z2 in E . This " separable
like the Eve / Adam pair , we obtain toposes that have instead the qualita -
tive character of pure being ; for example , the Habsburg era had a certain
monoid homomorphisms
W ~ M
symbols that are two - sided inverses of operator symbols coming from W ,
topos , namely , the one consisting of all those systems X satisfying the
epimorphic functors
W / G ~ D
and
W / Gx C ~ E
ing subcategories , although toposes , are not subtoposes but " quotient
functor p * ( the obvious inclusion in our example ) and two forward func -
tors p ! and p * that are respectively left and right adjoint to p * in the sense
PIX - * Y Z - * p * X
X - * p * Y p * Z - * X
between morphisms , for all sets X defined over the big situation and all
Y , Z defined over the smaller one . Note that the notion of morphism is
the same in both situations ; that is what it means to be full and faithful .
Kinship and Mathematical Categories 421
arena in which becoming can take place. In particular , some such spaces
T can measure time intervals and hence a particular motion in X during T
may give rise to a morphism T ~ X describing the result of the becoming
process; that is, if T is connected , if we can distinguish two instants I 4 T
called to , tl and if jltk == Xk for k == 0 , 1, then we can say that Xo became
Xl during the process 11; this is the common practice in mathematical
engineering (at least for certain categories within which it has, in effect,
become customary to work in the past 300 years). But then if we consider
tl as a subobject of T, its characteristic map from T to the truth -value
space will be a process along which false becomes true ; this in turn implies
that the truth -value space is itself connected since T is , and because of the
propositional structure of truth -values, it follows that indeed the hyper -
space, whose points parameterize the subspaces of X , is connected too . On
the other hand , in any topos any object X is embedded as a subobject of
its hyperspace via the " singleton " map . Taking T == I , it follows that in
the cases under discussion every object can be embedded in an object that
is not only connected , but moreover has no holes or other homotopical
irregularities . Note that now each individual I ~ X involves also a pro -
cess in his or her society. There are many such situations , but what can
such a process mean ?
m3 == mlm == m2
and
Given any object L in a topos, one can form a new topos of objects fur-
ther structured by a given labeling morphism to L . However, it is worthy
of note that in our examples, one L == G (leading to T2) and the other one
L == G x C (leading to T3), these labeling objects belong to a much
restricted subcategory(quotient topos) within the topos of all Tl -objects.
Although the Tl topos, consisting of all right actions of the free monoid
Won two symbols, is too vast to hope for a complete survey of its objects
(as is borne out by theorems of Vera Trnkova stating that any category
can be embeddedas a full subcategoryof it ; seePultr and Tmkova 1980),
by contrast thesesmaller toposesare more tractable.
Consider first the case G of gender in itself. It belongs to the sub-
category correspondingto W - + W3, the three-element monoid in which
xl == I , xm == m for all three x == 1, I , m. If we restrict attention to the
right actions of W3 only, we seethat the genericindividual I in the sense
of that topos has only one nontrivial subobject, which is G itself. There-
fore, the truth -value space.Q3for that topos (in contrast to the infinite .Q
for W) has only three elements also. The most general " society" X is
a sum of a number of noninteracting nuclear families, some with two
parents and somewith a single parent, and a society is determined up to
isomorphism by the double coefficient array that counts families of all
possiblesizesof thesetwo kinds. Cartesian products are easily computed.
Second, consider the simple moiety-labeler C in itself; it belongsto the
quotient topos determinedby W - + W2, the two-elementgroup generated
by I with 12 == 1, where we moreover interpret m as 1. Here C is itself
the generic individual and has no nontrivial subobjects, so that 02 is the
two-element Boolean algebra. All right W2-actions are of the form X ==
a + bC, where a is the number of individuals fixed, and b half the number
moved, by ! Theseobjectsare multiplied by the rule c2 == 2C.
Third , we can include both G and C in a single subcategoryas follows:
the infinite free monoid W maps surjectively to each of W3 and W2;
therefore, it maps to the six-element product monoid W3 x W2, but not
surjectively since the image Ws is a five-element submonoid (the missed
elementis the only nonidentity invertible elementin the product monoid).
The category of right Ws-setscan be probed with the help of its generic
individual I , which again (surprisingly) has only three subobjectsso that
Qs has again three truth-value-individuals. In I (i.e., Ws) there are besides
me my four distinct grandparents, the Tl -structure coming from the fact
424 La wvere
make explicit that which , in a larger sense , is the theme of this book , the
References
Montpellier , France .
ized graphs . In J . Gray and A . Scedrov ( Eds .) , Logic , categories , and computer
Mathematical Society .
17.1 Introduction
relate to determinersand quantifiers. One can say 'a dog', 'another dog',
'many dogs', 'two dogs'; one cannot correctly say *'a matter', * 'another
matter', * 'many matter', * 'two matter'. It seemsthat the distinction in
English grammar was first describedby Jespersen(1924, 198).
Languagesdiffer in morphology, agreementrules, and phrasestructure,
so one does not expect to find in every natural language a count/mass
distinction with the same linguistic correlates as in English. Although
many European languagesare like English in this connection, not all
are. Irish and Latin , for example, lack the indefinite article, and so one
cannot distinguish CN s from MN s in those languagesby the possibili ty
or impossibility of adding the indefinite article to the noun. Japanesehas
neither definite nor indefinite articles and lacks a uniform way to build
plurals. Yet Japaneserequires classifiers to license the application of
certain quantifiers such as numerals to nouns. Thus, in order to apply the
numeral 'ni' ('two') to the noun 'inu' ('dog'), the classifier'hiki ' is required
to form the expression'Inu-ga ni-hiki iru ' ('There are two dogs'). This
classifier is required also for words denoting fishes and insects, although
not for words denoting birds, for which the classifier 'wa' is required. On
the other hand, with almost any count noun denoting inanimate entities
the classifier 'tsu' is required, as in the expression'Ringo-o yo-tsu tabeta'
('I ate four apples'). This classifiercannot be usedwith massnouns. With
mass nouns such as 'mizu' ('water'), a different classifier 'hai' or 'bai' is
required to form expressions such as 'Mizu-o san-bai (hai) nonda'
('I drank three glassesof water'). This classifiercannot be usedwith count
nouns or with other massnouns such as 'nendo' ('clay'). Thus, the correct
use of some classifiers seemsto require a count/mass (as well as an
animate/inanimate) distinction at the level of nouns. (We owe the details
about Japaneseto Yuriko Oshima-Takane.)
Incidentally, if we inquire what guides linguists to the decision that
there are common nouns in languagesother than English, the answer
cannot simply be grammar. As just illustrated, grammar varies greatly
from language to language. Something other than grammar must be
contributing to the decision. We submit that the type of referencefor
prototypical words plays a major role. We think that acrossvariations in
grammar there is a semantic uniformity in the interpretation of at least
such prototypical count nouns as 'dog' as well as in the interpretation of
such prototypical mass nouns as 'matter' and that this semantic unifor-
mity is a good guide to the relevant grammatical facts in each language.
We propose to exploit the semanticuniformity as far as possible.
Count Nouns and Mass Nouns 429
(1985, 45- 46), for example, allows that in the actual physical extensions
of many MN s there are minimal parts, but dismissesthe fact as linguisti-
cally irrelevant. Quine (1960), Parsons(1970), Gillon (1992), and others
reject this claim for the reason that we formulate as follows. It may well
be that for many centuries users of the English word 'water' have not
realized that there are minimal portions of water- namely, molecules-
whoseparts are not water. (Notice how both questions, already discussed ,
are here confounded.) The effective use of the word does not depend on
knowledge of that scientific fact. This seemsto have led some writers to
the conclusion that the facts of the matter have no bearing on the exten-
sions of common nouns. But extension is extension, independentof our
knowledge. There is a truth of the matter that there are minimal parts
in extensionsof some MNs at least: witness the examples of 'footwear'
and 'furniture' already discussed . Thus, we do not seereasonsto set limi -
tations a priori to extensions of MN s. Furthermore, excluding atomic
extensionswould rule out the possibility of considering plurals as MN s.
Not only is there linguistic evidenceto considerplurals as MN s, discussed
by Carlson and Link (see below), but we will see that the plural con-
struction may be viewed as a basic link between CN sand MN s. The
fruitfulness of this approach will be apparent in the chapter.
example is the plural formation that takes the CN ' dog ' into ' dogs ' . Since
the extension of this term obviously has the property of cumulative refer -
ence , we categorize ' dogs ' as a MN . Carlson ( 1977 ) and then Link ( 1983 )
called attention to the affinity between plurals and MNs . In fact , this
such combinations as * 'a dogs ' and * ' another dogs ' are ungrammatical .
those of J / t JV , that is , between the category of sets , Sets , and the category
of sup - lattices , st .
The nominal theory and its interpretation will be used in this chapter for a
In the first premise , ' claret ' is a NP ( noun phrase ) and ' is a wine ' a VP
( verb phrase ) ; in the second , ' wine ' is a NP and ' is a liquid ' a VP . In the
conclusion , ' claret ' is a NP ( as in the first premise ) and ' is liquid ' is a VP .
The NPs in this example are , however , like PNs ( proper names ) or
fact , in French , one uses the expression ' Ie bordeaux ' , and French does
' claret ' as a descriptive noun phrase ( DNP ) , that is , as a NP whose inter -
Reyes 1994a , we consider ' is a wine ' as a predicable derived from the term
' wine ' (a CN , as indicated by the occurrence of ' a ' ) . The second premise
Count Nouns and Mass Nouns 433
17.2 TheNominalTheory
[~~~~J~ [~~~~J'
436 La Palme Reyes~Macnamara~Reyes~and Zolfaghari
and
[_
-amammal
I~ Iananimal
I,
we obtain
[~~ ~i ] ~ I ananimal
!.
Similarly
~ ,~,~,JV
~isthe
,~category
whose
andobjects
are
whoseMNsof
such
morphisms
are as
the[:~~!~!J,
form
~ ~ ~ ,
~ ~ ~ .
Identity morphisms and composition of morphisms are as above .
The maps p and u are assumed to be functorial . The functoriality ofp
amounts to saying that from
~ ~ ~ ,
rA : l are ru "; l
~ ~ ~ .
As an example , from
~ ~ ~,
we obtain
Count Nouns and Mass Nouns 437
In particular , from
~ ~ ~ ,
we obtain
both categories. Thus, we may say 'Claret is a wine' and 'More wine was
served after the dessert'. In the first sentence
, 'wine' appears as a CN ,
whereasin the second, it appearsas a MN . At the level of the nominal
theory, this meansthat we have two objects:
The case of wine is not an isolated one . Another example is ' metal ' .
Thus , we can say ' Iron is a metal ' , but also ' Iron is metal ' . Once again , the
connection between the two occurrences of 'metal ' is expressed in the
nominal theory by a morphism in CC.. IV:
[~~~~~!~J-.!!-. u[~~~!~!].
Equivalently , we may express the connection by a morphism in JI: t .. IV:
not equivalent in general ( although the second implies the first ) . This
fact seems to contradict a widespread belief . As an example , consider
' Living room sets are items of furniture ' and ' A living room set is an item
of furniture ' . The first is true ; the second is false .
f : (M , :::;;, V ) - t (N , :::;;, V )
such that P ~ U . P is the (covariant ) power set functor and U is the for -
getful functor . More precisely , P is the functor that associates with a set
X the sup-lattice P X of the subsets of X , and with a function / : X --+ Y
the function :Jf : P X --+ P Y defined above . This is clearly a Sf-morphism .
On the other hand , U is the functor that associates with a sup - lattice
pliu p11
u
JIit JV - --~-_.- + SI
This meansthat the objects and the morphisms of C (i/AI" are interpreted
as setsand morphisms betweenthesesets, the objects and the morphisms
of JI{ % as objectsand morphisms of Sl. Furthermore, the interpretations
should " behave well" with respect to functors of the nominal category.
Thus, for instance, PI == Ip meansthat if the interpretation of [ ~~~~~J is
the set of dogs, then the interpretation of ~ should be the set of sets
of dogs, and so on. (It is worthwhile to notice that axioms in the nominal
theory are interpreted not as truth-valuesbut as maps.)
Functoriality of I : rc% ~ Setsmeansthat the interpretation of 'is' in
the axiom
[~~~~~J~ [~~~~J
is the identity map ; and so on .
categories . In the appendix we will show that the target category of the
and MNs should have these properties . Ours is just one such determina -
been studied in the literature ( Pelletier and Schubert 1989 ) . The notion of
validity for syllogisms is the usual Tarski 's notion of truth , defined by
that is the
morphIsm
are wine ' in the nominal theory . This morphism is interpreted as a map
f : W -jo O( W ) , which to w associates f (w), a portion of wine in O( W ).
Similarly , the morphism 'liquids are liquid ' is interpreted as a map
g : L -jo O(L ).
Since E-coincidence implies O(S)-coincidence , from the premises we
may conclude
On the other hand, the first syllogism is not valid, even if O(L ) is
homogeneous : 'an O(S)-portion of a liquid , although liquid , need not be
a liquid ' . In fact , proceeding in this way , we can prove the following :
THEOREM
1 If the interpretation O(L ) of 'liquid ' is homogeneous, then
the syllogisms 2, 3, 6, and 8 are valid , and the syllogisms I , 4, 5, and 7 are
not valid .
Appendix
F ( i ) ~
F (a ) 1 ~ A
F (j )
<I > : ( A , { h } i ) - + ( B , { gi } i )
to be a morphism of d , <I > : A - + B , such that <I > 0 1; = gi for all i E .!f .
commutes .
446 La PalmeReyes
, Macnamara
, Reyes
, andZolfaghari
F
(F
i(a
))l~
-:~
..y
.I!A
for all i:
i~-~
commutes, there is a unique morphism () : A --+ BEd
-
.7 B
such that OJ; == gi
F(j)':~ ...
We say that the category d is cocompleteif every functor F : .!Ii -1- d ,
.!f being a small category, has a colimit .
REMARK6 (1) Since terminal objects are unique up to unique iso-
morphism, we are justified in talking about " the" colimit of a functor. (2)
Dually , we can define conesand limits in a category by considering dop ,
rather than d . We say that d is completeif every functor F : J1 - + d , .!f
being a small category, has a limit .
A.2 Exactness
Propertiesof SetsandSl
THEOREM 2 The category of sets, Sets, is complete, cocomplete, and dis-
tributive in the strong sensethat coproducts commute with pull-backs.
Furthermore, surjectionsare stable.
Proof All of this is well known (see, e.g., Mac Lane 1971).
As an example of colimits, let .!Ii == C(6..;v and F == I : C(6..;v -j. Setsbe an
interpretation of the category of CN s. The colimit of I may be described
as follows:
I (i) ~ Eo.uE,
Count Nouns and Mass Nouns 447
Proof This is again well known (see, e.g., Joyal and Tierney 1984) .
Recall that a category is linear if it has the following properties :
1. C(i has finite products and coproducts (including terminal and initial
objects : 1 and 0, respectively ) .
2. The unique morphism 0 - + 1 is an isomorphism with inverse 1 - + o.
3. The canonical morphism A + B - + A x B obtained from the mor -
phisms
( 1A, 0AB) : A - 4 A x B
and
(0BA, 1B) : B - t A x B
(M
,~M
,V)
Products are diagrams
/
(M x N, :S, V )
~ (N , ::::; N , V )
V i ( Xi , Yi ) == ( V iX i , V iY i ) , n M ( x , Y) == x , n N ( X, Y) == Y .
(M , ~ M , V )
~
/ " (M x N , ::::; , V )
/ iN
(N , ~ N , V )
(E, ~ E, V ) '-t
e (M, ~ M, V ) ~fg (N, ~ N, V )
such that
e f
E ' -tM4N
g
where
i
Q == { z EN : Vx E M (f (x ) ::::; Z +-+ g (x ) S z) } '-;). N
IS
I([~~~!~!J)xI(~ )
by the smallest sup - lattice congruence relation == such that
O ( S ) == { ( b , c ) E 1 ( [ ~~ ~ ! ~ ! J ) x l (~ ) :
~ a E l (~ ) ( u ( a ) S b ~ v ( a ) s c ) }
and q ( b , c ) = = the smallest ( b ' , c ' ) E 0 ( 8 ) such that b s b ' and c s c ' .
Proof This is well known ( see , e .g . , Mac Lane 1971 ) . The theorem says
f (A ) == V f (a)
aEA
since
] mustpreserve
V 's andA = UaEA
{ a}. (Of courseonemustprove
that the map , so defined , is sup-preserving .)
THEOREM
5 There is a unique map e : E - + 0 (8) such that for each i the
diagram
{}
l (i) ~
IPI (i) 1== IIp (i)1
canI
(~ E ()
~~CanIP(j)I
I0 ( 8 ) 1
is commutative .
I (i ) _ _il -- t IP I ( i ) I
I(a)1 113
/(1)I X
I (j ) - { } -t IPI (j ) 1
PI (i) ==Ip (i )
------~ ~
3I(a)=/p(a)1 - - - --:=---_..~ 0 (S) can Ip ( j )
P l ( j ) == Ip (j )
(i)10{ } , which
thereis a uniqueE ~ 10(8)\ suchthat eo canI(i) == ICanlp
is the conclusion of the theorem .
References
Gillon , B . S. ( 1992) . Towards a common semantics for English count and mass
nouns . Linguistics and Philosophy , 15, 597- 639.
Jackendoff , R . ( 1991) . Parts and boundaries . Cognition , 41, 9- 45 .
Jespersen, O . ( 1924). The philosophy of grammar . London : Allen and Unwin .
Joyal , A ., and Tierney , M . ( 1984) . An extension of the Galois theory of Gro-
thendieck (Memoirs of the A .M .S., 309) . Providence , RI : American Mathematical
Society .
La Palme Reyes, M ., Macnamara , J., and Reyes G . E . ( 1994a) . Functoriality and
grammatical role in syllogisms . Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic , 35, 41- 66.
La Palme Reyes, M ., Macnamara , J., and Reyes, G . E . ( 1994b) . Reference, kinds
and predicates . In J. Macnamara and G . E . Reyes ( Eds .), The logicalfoundations
of cognition (pp . 91- 143) . Oxford : Oxford University Press.
La Palme Reyes, M ., and Reyes, G . E . (to appear) . Generic figures and their
glueings: A constructive approach to functor categories .
Lawvere , F . W . ( 1992) . Categories of space and of quantity . In J. Echeverria , A .
Ibarra , and T . Mormann ( Eds .), The space of mathematics (pp . 14- 30) . Berlin : de
Gruyter .
Lawvere , F . W ., and Schanuel , S. ( 1997). Conceptual mathematics . Cambridge :
Cambridge University Press.
Link , G . ( 1983) . The logical analysis of plurals and mass terms : A lattice -theoretic
approach . In R . Bauerle , C . Schwarze, and A . von Stechow ( Eds.), Meaning , use
and interpretation of language ( pp . 302- 323) . Berlin : de Gruyter .
Lonning , J. T . ( 1987) . Mass terms and quantification . Linguistics and Philosophy ,
10 , 1- 52 .
Mac Lane , S. ( 1971) . Categories for the working mathematician . New York :
Springer -Verlag .
Magnan , F ., and Reyes, G . E . ( 1994). Category theory as a conceptual tool in the
study of cognition . In J. Macnamara and G . E . Reyes (Eds .) , The logical founda -
tions of cognition ( pp . 57- 90) . Oxford : Oxford University Press.
McPherson , L . M . P. ( 1991) . A little goes a long way : Evidence for a perceptual
basis of learning for the noun categories count and mass. Journal of Child Lan -
guage , 18 , 315 - 338 .
452 La Palme Reyes, Macnamara, Reyes, and Zolfaghari