Scarfone - The Matter of Time Ingles
Scarfone - The Matter of Time Ingles
Scarfone - The Matter of Time Ingles
807
808 DOMINIQUE SCARFONE
the drives deep inside (Freud 1923)—is not a model that can actu-
ally be put to work. It is a static figure, clearly based on a schemat-
ic model of the human body. Now, while the body is the ultimate
container of all our living processes, including those we approach
from a psychological standpoint, what matters to us most is not
the static body of anatomy, nor, for that matter, the objectified
body of physiology, but rather the living body, the corporeal exist-
ence of a human being carrying on with its life. Space contains liv-
ing and inert bodies alike, but only the living human—hence, the
living psyche—is subjectively concerned with time.2
Following Ockham’s principle of conceptual parsimony, I will
try to leave aside the spatial metaphor (confident as I am that it
will not disappear) and explore the possibility that the temporal
dimension is sufficient for the description of the workings of the
psyche in psychoanalytic terms. In so doing, I will be referring not
to the time of physics, but to the specific dimension faced by hu-
man beings capable of reflective consciousness, as this entails the
potential awareness of our finitude through the “passage of time.”
Consciousness is inseparable from existential time and chronolo-
gy. To be sure, consciousness somehow espouses the “time arrow”
of cosmology in the form of the irreversibility of individual and
collective history; this, however, is achieved at the cost of making
the past a closed chapter within the trajectory of one’s life history.
As we know, the experience of analysis teaches us that reality is
otherwise, and this has a huge impact on how we approach the
functioning psyche.
It would appear that if consciousness is strongly correlated with
the experience of time, Freud’s idea of a timeless unconscious is
a mere logical consequence of unconsciousness itself. But for the
inventor of psychoanalysis, this concept was primarily the result
of clinical observation. The description of memories emerging
2
Freud’s first model of the psyche of course constitutes another example of
a space metaphor, with the theory of the double inscription after the lifting of
repression. Freud (1915b) ponders whether, when repression is lifted, the de-re-
pressed representation “moves” from the unconscious to the preconscious, or if
it merely undergoes a functional change.
A MATTER OF TIME 811
during treatment “with astonishing freshness”—that is, as if time
had not in the least affected them—occurs as early as 1895, in the
Studies on Hysteria (Freud and Breuer 1895, p. 9), and remains a
constant in Freud’s conception of the mind until the very end. It
must be noted, however, that while in the beginning Freud’s con-
ception may have pointed at the return of well-formed repressed
memories, we know, from his paper on screen memories and oth-
er sources, that he did not think of memories as stable recordings
popping up from some repository “in” the unconscious. We there-
fore adhere more specifically to the Freudian theory that memo-
ries are actively constructed in the present time out of repressed
material, through forms that lend themselves to conveying some-
thing of the repressed, even though the latter—i.e., the truly time-
less substratum—is not directly accessible (Freud 1896, 1899,
1915b). The process is actually quite similar to how the manifest
dream borrows figurative material from day residues to reflect
repressed motions of desire.
We have numerous ways of verifying the clinical validity of
Freud’s take on the odd relationship between unconscious proc-
esses and chronological time. Think of the repetition compulsion,
in which redundant patterns keep coming back as if no learning
from experience occurred or no usable trace was left to mark the
time of their return. Another example is the eruption of, as it
were, “untimely” mental contents in the otherwise normal flow of
consciousness, where material that should belong to another time
emerges in the present context as a foreign body. A third example
is the fear of breakdown described by Winnicott, in which some-
thing seems to be threatening to happen in the future, whereas it
has already happened in the past, but there was no ego to register
it. Says Winnicott (1963): “The original experience of primitive ago-
ny cannot be put in the past tense” (p. 91).
Dreaming—and, as we shall see, parapraxes—provide other in-
stances where the unpast (as I would call it) steps in. Confronted
with phenomena such as these, psychoanalysis may be said to work
toward their capture in a time net, or, if one prefers, toward the in-
sertion of ordinary time into their midst.
812 DOMINIQUE SCARFONE
7
From a totally different perspective, the idea of “child as theorist” has also
been put forward by cognitive psychologists Gopnik and Meltzoff (1997).
8
Gantheret (1996) and Pontalis (1997) have expressed a similar criticism of
Winnicott’s view, but Laplanche (1989) is the one who expounded the theoretical
framework that extends beyond the relation to the breast, in his theory of general-
ized seduction.
A MATTER OF TIME 823
yet come together, and therefore do not put the alternating deic-
tic positions into motion. No time is generated from this as a re-
sult, but instead, two timeless postures come into being: that of the
infant with “I am the breast,” and that of the breast with its excita-
tory message.
Time then steps in when the infant notices that there is a mes-
sage from the other (despite its enigmatic nature) and tries to make
sense of it, to translate it. Indeed, translating means differentiat-
ing the bulk of the message into a part that can be assimilated—lit-
erally, made similar to or compatible with the ego—and a part that,
given the infant’s incapacity to fully master the excitatory aspect,
remains incompatible, intractable. Resisting translation, that part
of the message can be said to be repressed (primal repression). As
Freud (1896) wrote: “A failure of translation—this is what is known
clinically as ‘repression’” (p. 208). Thus, difference is imposed up-
on the infant not because of abstract otherness, but by way of the
excitatory character of the message emanating from the Other (in
this instance, the breast, but this is only one possible form).
Taking notice of the enigmatic message (by working at trans-
lating it) amounts to sensing the introduction of some difference,
i.e., perceiving the breach in the continuity of being and realizing
a loss of being. One way of seeing this is that loss already haunts
the object, so to speak, even before it is conceived of as an object
—that is, even prior to differentiation (Scarfone 2003). It is the
Other’s own unconscious that makes for the sheer otherness of its
message and constitutes the actual loss.9
The occurrence of the passage from being to having, the foun-
dational moment of differentiation, means that the infant is some-
what compelled to “acknowledge reception” of the message of the
Other (Scarfone 2002). Acknowledging reception means sensing
the disturbance that impinges on the apparent “going on being”
(Winnicott 1963). By accounting for what was received—that is, by
processing it, partially translating it—the infant is also sensing a
delay: the time it needs for grasping a first meaning and repudiat-
9
This is not unlike Lacan’s (1966) lack in the Other.
824 DOMINIQUE SCARFONE
Both are virtual phrases, and language is not part of the scene.
Translation (C, above) and the message of absence (D) will even-
tually lead toward the ability to create more articulate phrases.
When this is achieved, the deictic dipole and temporality can begin
to operate concurrently with the advent of language. What we see,
then, is that time is introduced along with primal repression, as the lat-
ter separates what is compatible from what is incompatible, un-
A MATTER OF TIME 825
translatable. The birth of time, therefore, occurs in parallel with
the structural differentiation of the psyche.10
It must be stressed that, whereas translation is a primal struc-
turing fact, it nevertheless operates in the psyche all the time. It
is, at any given moment, a matter of articulating—however incom-
pletely—an unarticulated phrase. In Lyotard’s view, it is the task of
taking into account something in excess of lexis or logos, i.e., in
excess of enunciation, something that presents itself as the phônè
—the Greek term for the voice and its timbre or tone. In Freudian
terms, lexis and phônè could be linked with the drives, in that lex-
is amounts to representation, while phônè is related to affect (rep-
resentation and affect being the psychic representatives of the
drives).
The fort/da example reported by Freud (1919) is a good illus-
tration of the emergence of such symbolic function. When the moth-
er leaves, she emits, so to speak, an excitator y message related to
her going away. The baby is not only frustrated by losing sight of
the mother, but also provoked into doing something about it
(translating it), both through gesture and rudimentary speech. The
baby begins by repeating the experience of loss, and only later is
he or she able to symbolize the mother’s departure and return. The
baby can now “have” the mother at will. But loss came first.
10
Hence, psychic conflict is also entering the scene at this point.
826 DOMINIQUE SCARFONE
11
In French psychoanalysis, the term actuel is derived from Freud’s terms Ak-
tuell and Aktual, as in Aktualneurosen, the actual neuroses. I am well aware that in
English, the word actual is already loaded with other familiar meanings, but there
seems to be no better translation available for these German terms.
A MATTER OF TIME 827
merely a measured time span. This is congruent with the fact that
the phrase of affect is itself an act affecting, as it were, our being.
Inasmuch as it is not yet articulate, i.e., not yet translated into the
second kind of phrase, a phrase of affect is impervious to chrono-
logical time and therefore prone to repetition.
We should here refer back to the ever-fresh reminiscences of
the Studies on Hysteria (Freud and Breuer 1895), but also, and
more importantly, to the “actual neuroses”—anxiety neurosis and
neurasthenia—that Freud (1898) considered to be lurking in the
background of unconscious fantasy and therefore not amenable to
analysis (pp. 226-270; see also Freud 1916-1917, pp. 389-ff). In our
present vocabulary, we shall say that, by contrast with the “psycho-
neuroses”—hysteria and obsessive neurosis—the actual neuroses
lack the dimension of the articulate phrase. This explains their
mainly affective (anxiety neurosis) or somatic (neurasthenia) pres-
entation. But at one point, Freud suggested that in psychoneuro-
sis, there is frequently a nucleus of actual neurosis (Freud 1916-
1917, p. 390). This statement might reveal itself to be quite useful
in solving the problem we have just encountered regarding the
timelessness of the unconscious. What if, indeed, Freud’s ideas of
the timelessness of unconscious processes and the actual nucleus
in every “psycho-neurosis” really refer to the same phenomenon?
We have seen that those processes that were not yet inscribed
in a time sequence (past-present-future) tend to repeat themselves
—that is, to occur in an ever-present form; they are presentations
instead of re-presentations, acts (Agieren) instead of thoughts, or
phrases of affect instead of articulate phrases. In this perspective,
the psychoanalytic endeavor of articulating—translating, trans-
forming—the phrase of affect is tantamount to working through
actual time—the time of the act, the time of repetition—and trans-
ferring it, however incompletely, into psychic representation.
Something amenable to articulation can and must be extracted
from the ore of inarticulate phrases of affect. In other words, we
work to transpose the now, the actual time of the unconscious, in-
to the realm of chronological time.
A phrase of affect can engender time because the actual or the
now quality of the inarticulate phrase is in itself a form of time, al-
828 DOMINIQUE SCARFONE
for the name of the pianist resulted from the impulse provided by
the dream, as I shall now explain.
After listening to the series of surnames that came up as possi-
bly being the pianist Claudio’s, I did not know what to think of
them, so I jotted them down in a column on a sheet of paper:
ABBAU
ABBADO
ARRAU
In looking at the column, I then felt that the three names could
be superimposed, and wondered what would result if one erased
all the letters that were common to the three words. So I barred
the letters A, B, and U, which left a DO and an RR:
ABBAU
ABBADO
ARRAU
I then mentioned this to Florence, while noting (at first only
to myself) that DO was the first syllable of my first name, and that
RR felt like the growl of some hungry/angry animal. When I add-
ed this last bit of information to what I had already told Florence,
she was startled: the Great Dane of her dream had popped up, this
time not as a representation, but as something actual—not a
dream figure, but a vibrant, expressive form: a phrase of affect, or
phônè. The voracious dog was not simply evoked; it was there, in the
phônè carried over by her double slip from the actual time of her
unconscious, presenting itself as a threatening growl just when
Florence was searching for a pianist with a gentle touch.
In the following sessions, we were led, thanks to other dreams,
to the anorexia of the patient’s adolescence, as well as to the
strange illness that broke out in her mouth after her mother com-
mitted suicide—a rare ailment that threatened her with the loss
of all her teeth. These were stories she well knew—stories of re-
pressed devouring and problematic introjections—but they were
stories that, like the Great Dane of her dream, needed to be
brought back to life in the flesh (Gantheret 1996) in order to be ar-
ticulated.
A MATTER OF TIME 831
The devouring thrust that presented itself in the transference
through the dream and within the parapraxes (where they were
more deeply embedded, but even more effective) was not (or not
yet) something evoking the past, nor was it at first really present.
The thrust was actual, and as such it was a phrase of affect that
acted on Florence’s thought processes. Only through the classic
compromise formation of her slip could this unconscious thrust
become represented in the transference. Her effort at articulating
her desire formed a word representation conveying the menacing
growl while hiding it from view. The analysis—the dislocation—of
the slip would in turn bring us down to the level of presentation of
the actual unconscious thing. Conflating the three words of Flor-
ence’s consecutive slips was only possible and productive insofar
as they belonged to another form of time. Their unconscious sta-
tus yielded the final RR by allowing them to be superimposed—
i.e., to be treated not as words with a spatially distributed sequence,
but as the timeless vehicles of something that cannot really be put
in writing: the growl of a hungry/angry beast.
My aim in presenting this vignette is not to introduce some
purportedly new psychoanalytic technique—actually, it does not
represent any customary procedure of my practice—but to illus-
trate a more general idea: the idea that parapraxes—or, for that
matter, remembering and gaining insight in analysis—do not re-
sult from simple shifts between well-organized and meaningful rep-
resentations. Rather, they are driven by what has been inarticulate,
closer to force than to meaning—tending toward meaning, to be
sure, but with no preexisting meaning that would lie there under-
cover, waiting to be found. Meaning is introduced de novo, along
with time.
CONCLUDING REMARKS
In trying to make metapsychology reside only in the dimension of
time, we have come to observe that the idea of timeless uncon-
scious processes must be questioned. How could something hu-
man escape the grip of time? We have seen, however, that for
Freud, timelessness meant at one point that repressed contents
832 DOMINIQUE SCARFONE
Acknowledgments: The author wishes to thank Lewis Kirshner, M.D., and Dawn Skor-
czewski, Ph.D., for their help with a preliminary version of this paper.
REFERENCES
e-mail: [email protected]