Margaret S. Archer - Realist Social Theory - The Morphogenetic Approach (1995, Cambridge University Press) - 58-76
Margaret S. Archer - Realist Social Theory - The Morphogenetic Approach (1995, Cambridge University Press) - 58-76
Margaret S. Archer - Realist Social Theory - The Morphogenetic Approach (1995, Cambridge University Press) - 58-76
METHODOLOGICAL COLLECTIVISM
21
Gellner, 'Holism versus individualism', p. 264.
22
Gellner, 'Holism versus individualism', p. 264.
48 The problems of structure and agency
without invoking one of them. The first was J. S. Mill's old fear, 23 namely
that to acknowledge emergence was to countenance the existence of a new
'social substance'. The second was that talk about 'societal properties'
was also talk about things produced or generated by society, indepen-
dently of the activities of people and therefore superordinate to actors. In
fact, it appears that both very proper anxieties were really semantic in
origin, turning respectively on the Greek word (ousia) for substance
(which need never be employed in relation to emergence) and the Latin
phrase 'sui generis' (which has been misused in this connection).
The first source of unease is the doubt that any referent of a holistic
concept can have an effect upon concrete individuals, since this seems to
endow an abstraction with some kind of existence which cannot be flesh
and blood and therefore must entail a different substance (from people) if
it is real. As Gellner writes, putting himself in the shoes of the Individual-
ist, 'Surely the insubstantial cannot constrain the substantial? I think we
can provisionally agree to this principle'. 24 In other words, the only two
alternatives seemed to be to credit 'societal properties' with some
mysterious substance or to withhold reality from them. The language of
substances proved as damaging in sociology as ousia has been in the
Tridentine concept of 'transubstantiation', which construes eucharistic
theology in terms of sacramental physicalism. In social science the
problem was identical, only (rightly) sociological physicalism had no
takers. The real problem was that the wrong language was being
employed, even more by the opponents of 'societal properties' than by
their sheepish advocates. In consistency, the Individualist who felt
confident wfien pointing to flesh and blood people, surely did not hold
that they were invoking dubious 'substances' when they (necessarily)
referred to people's personalities, attitudes or dispositions? And if so,
then why should the defenders of'societal facts' be automatically guilty of
invoking such when referring to their 'non-observables' - for neither
could confine their terms of reference to sense-data, which is what
'substance' effectively stood for in this context.
The second source of concern derived from the current (and continu-
ing) mis-assumption that to consider 'societal facts' as being sui generis
entailed reification because it implied that they were generated by society
itself- as a separate and superordinate entity, 'Society'. Literally, the
phrase means nothing more than 'of its own kind'. In this case, 'societal
facts' do not pertain to the genus (class of object) made up of individual
people but belong to a different genus, i.e. the class of objects designated
Hume's heritage
In other words, Collectivists retreated to playing a methodological game
which could never establish their ontological claims. They thus became
closet emergentists but explanatory game players and in the process the
emergent social structure, to which no 'explicit reference' was made,
underwent further diminution. Once again, methodology reacts back to
regulate ontology, in this case fragmenting structure into a series of
discrete properties rather than allowing social structure to be considered
as a distinct stratum of social reality and explored as such. It enters
explanations as a set of social features adduced on an ad hoc basis when
explanation cannot do without them, thus serving to occlude the systema-
tic nature of social structure. But the effects go deeper still, for what now
governs even its ad hoc admission is none other than the Humean model of
causation itself! For structural features are allowed in under the rubric of
(as yet) 'undefined group properties' provided they increase our explana-
tory/predictive power by helping to account for observed regularities. It
is its contribution to accounting for a constant conjunction which gives a
structural property its right of entry. Yet most of the time, in open social
systems, regularities at the level of events are just what emergent features
do not generate. Therefore, the structural elements which can pass the
Humean check-point, only do so on an ad hoc basis but are also atypical 'of
their own kind'! In practice, they are those which approximate to
observability and are in play because of their descriptive indispensability.
Thus, for example, the type of electoral system (proportional represen-
tation or first-past-the-post) will be needed to explain the kind of
34
Gellner, 'Holism versus individualism', p. 255n.
35
Brodbeck, 'Methodological individualisms', p. 303.
Individualism versus Collectivism 55
government to emerge from any election, in addition to statements about
people's political dispositions, which in turn are only identifiable in
relation to Political Parties. These two structural properties earn their
ticket and the Collectivist might even manage to suggest that voters are in
a (pre-structured) situation where their Party affiliation is affected by the
electoral system (i.e. supporting a minority party makes more sense under
proportional representation). However, what Humean gatekeeping will
preclude are propositions about the prior distribution of power having
affected the electoral system in operation, the Parties in existence, let
alone the political dispositions of voters themselves. Yet there may well be
internal and necessary relationships obtaining between all four elements.
Another way of putting this is that certain emergent effects may get
through the gate, but no emergent mechanism will. Included purely
insofar as they boost predictive power, some structural factors can be
added to statements about individuals to improve the correlation coeffi-
cient. In this way, all that is asserted is that the two together yield better
predictions. What cannot be asserted or even explored in terms of
constant conjunctions is how the explanatory factors interact together to
generate a given outcome. The explanatory formula is 'individual dispo-
sitions' plus some indispensable 'structural property', where the 'plus' is
predictive rather than real (i.e. two independent factors which together
predict better than one alone, rather than as inter-dependent variables).
Consenting to play a purely methodological game according to
Humean rules gradually undermines the Collectivist programme. We
have just charted the fragmentation of structure into disparate 'factors'
and indicated that it is immediately followed by the exclusion of the
interplay between 'structure and agency'. Yet this interaction had been
just what early emergentists looked towards and saw profit in social
theory exploring. Mandelbaum had argued that to hold 'that societal facts
are not reducible without remainder to facts concerning the thoughts and
actions of specific individuals, is not to deny that the latter class of facts
also exists, and that the two classes may interact'.36 Moreover he had begun
to spell out how they do so, by sketching in exactly the kind of mechanism,
or still better process, which constant conjunctions literally cannot ack-
nowledge (for to Hume all we can ever say is that (a) and (b) are regularly
observed to coincide). On the contrary, Mandelbaum proposed that 'if we
wish to understand many of the dilemmas by which individuals are faced,
we can do no better than hold to the view that there are societal facts which
exercise external constraints over individuals no less than there are facts
concerning individual volition which often come into conflict with these
36
Mandelbaum, 'Societal facts', p. 234.
56 The problems of structure and agency
37
Mandelbaum, 'Societal facts', p. 234.
Individualism versus Collectivism 57
with and how to explain it. All social theory is ontologically shaped and
methodologically moulded even if these processes remain covert and
scarcely acknowledged by the practitioner. This is inescapable because
theories logically entail concepts and concepts themselves include certain
things and exclude others (at the methodological level) and denote some
aspects of reality whilst denying others (at the ontological level). Any who
think they can avoid both fall into the trap of instrumentalism: those
believing that the use of 'heuristic concepts' in explanation saves them
from making any ontological commitment fail to recognise that terming
something 'heuristic' is itself a matter of ontology.
Yet the concepts on offer from Individualism and Collectivism were
fundamentally unsatisfactory. Individualism supplied an unacceptably
atomistic concept of the individual, shorn of any relationship with the
social context yet inexplicably bulging with social attributes; a conception
of the social structure as a mere aggregate of individual activities whose
every tendency was the responsibility of current actors, plus the unwork-
able method of reduction as the means for linking 'structure and agency'.
On the other hand, Collectivists proffered a fragmented conception of
structure, defined residually as that which defied reduction, an equally
fragmentary concept of agency represented by individuals plus their
social context, and they refrained from specifying the processes linking
the two together. Insofar as working social theorists took Individualist
concepts on board, this served to perpetuate the fallacy of upwards
conflation in social theorizing. If they drew upon Collectivism instead,
then the missing two-way link between structure and agency continued to
foster the equally fallacious form of downwards conflation in social
theory.
Of course much of this went on in the state of inarticulate unawareness
and often consisted in practical analysts cutting their theoretical cloth to
suit their coat or vice versa. 38 Thus, at one extreme interpretative
sociologists undertook small-scale interactional studies and simply
placed a big etc. after them, implying that the compilation of enough
sensitive ethnographies would generate an understanding of society by
aggregation. At the other, large-scale multivariate analyses pressed on
towards some predictive goal without reference to the interactional
processes generating their variables. However, it has already been
stressed that the scope of the problem or size of entity is not what actually
38
Tactual trends may certainly be detected with respect to the preferred, strategic field of
empirical inquiry. In particular, those who focus on small groups, or microsociological
phenomena, are more often than not reductionistically orientated, and those who study
the comprehensive historical processes, or macrosociological phenomena, tend toward
antireductionistic interpretations'. Piotr Sztompka, Sociological Dilemmas. Academic
Press, New York, 1979, p. 92.
Individualism versus Collectivism 59
differentiates between Individualism and Collectivism; to the former, the
macroscopic is just the 'large group'; to the latter, a dyad like husband and
wife or doctor and patient is unidentifiable without reference to the social
context. Thus the above connections were ones of superficial theoretical
affinity, but once forged the concepts used then transmitted their own
deficiencies into practical theorizing. Alternatively, in some specialisms,
theorizing would begin on the basis of concepts taken from one camp,
realize the limitations of the concepts, and then swap to the other camp,
only to repeat the process. Thus, for example, the 'old' sociology of
Education (Collectivist) gave way to the 'new' (Individualist), eventually
leaving practitioners calling for synthesis.
Yet as we have seen, synthesis or compromise is the one deal which
cannot be struck, which is why I have continuously resisted the notion of a
via media between the two programmes, consisting of conceding Descrip-
tive Individualism to the Individualist and Explanatory Emergence to the
Collectivist. Further modifications or revisions, such as 'situational
individualism', undertaken with the same conciliatory aim in view, have
not been discussed, because like the via media they fail - as they must - to
reconcile contradictory premises. I have stuck to the pure lines of the
debate, as articulated in the 1950s because if, as I maintain, there are
intimate and indissoluble connections between ontology, methodology
and practical social theory, then this is what we have been stuck with ever
since - a choice between the two alternatives, replete with their deficien-
cies which are merely replicated at the practical level, which ever is
chosen. This was the reason for saying 'don't choose', but it was almost
impossible advice to follow when positivism was in full flood and
empiricism itself was responsible for the intrinsic defects of the only two
options available.
Only after the empiricist hegemony had been challenged and the
closely associated domination of positivism had been similarly under-
mined did siding with neither Individualism nor Collectivism become a
genuine option. For with the progressive demise of empiricism, not only
were the terms of the old debate between them rejected, but the debate
itself was re-cast in entirely different ones. These transcended the original
antinomy between the 'study of wo/man' and the 'science of society' by
re-conceptualizing 'structure' as intimately rather than truistically
'activity-dependent' and the 'individual' as intrinsically rather than
extrinsically the subject of 'social constitution'.
What did not disappear, despite the vastly premature celebration of a
new consensus by many commentators, was the enduring necessity of
making a choice. For the new terms in which 'structure and agency' were
re-conceptualized and linked together were again represented by two
60 The problems of structure and agency
Thus in the new conspectus which I have called Emergentism (and can
now be seen to be defined here as a realist ontology and a morphogenetic
methodology), it is vital to distinguish between
such causal inter-dependency, which is a contingent feature of the process
concerned, from existential intransitivity, which is a priori condition of any
investigation ... For although the processes of production may be interdepen-
dent, once some object ... exists, if it exists, however it has been produced, it
constitutes a possible object for scientific investigation.41
A realist ontology which upholds transfactual structures and intransi-
tive cultural properties, and encourages their investigation as emergent
entities, is thus at variance with the Elisionists' view which holds, (a) that
such properties only possess a 'virtual existence' until, (b) they are
'instantiated' by actors, which (c) means these properties are neither fully
real nor examinable except in conjunction with the agents who instantiate
them, and only then through an artificial bracketing exercise since the two
are inseparable in reality.
In conclusion, their consistent insistence upon the differentiation and
stratification of the social world leads Emergentists to separate 'parts' and
'people' in order to examine their distinctive emergent properties. As
Bhaskar noted of Peter Berger's early and idealist version of an elisionist
theory, its fundamental error is that 'People and society are n o t . . . related
"dialectically". They do not constitute two moments of the same process.
Rather they refer to radically different things'. 42 Precisely the same
criticism can be levelled at later versions like structuration theory, which
repeats this 'fallacy of the two moments', and will only entertain 'unack-
nowledged conditions of action', withholding the status of emergent
properties from them by rendering them merely matters of 'knowledgea-
bility' on the part of agents.
Hence, the separability/inseparability issue represents the ontological
parting of the ways between Emergentists and Elisionists. For the
Emergentist,
The importance of distinguishing, in the most categorical way, between human
action and social structure will now be apparent. For the properties possessed by
social forms may be very different from those possessed by the individuals upon
whose activity they depend ... I want to distinguish sharply then between the
genesis of human actions, lying in the reasons, intentions and plans of human
beings, on the one hand; and the structures governing the reproduction and
transformation of social activities, on the other.43
Why? Not simply because ontologically they are indeed different
41 42
Bhaskar, Naturalism, p. 47. Bhaskar, Naturalism, p. 33
43
Bhaskar, Reclaiming Reality, Verso, London, 1989, p. 79.
64 The problems of structure and agency