Pragmatism

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 28

Pragmatism

Pragmatism is a philosophical tradition that began in the United States around 1870.[1] Its origins are
often attributed to the philosophers Charles Sanders Peirce, William James, and John Dewey. Peirce later
described it in his pragmatic maxim: "Consider the practical effects of the objects of your conception.
Then, your conception of those effects is the whole of your conception of the object."[2]

Pragmatism considers words and thought as tools and instruments for prediction, problem solving, and
action, and rejects the idea that the function of thought is to describe, represent, or mirror reality.[3]
Pragmatists contend that most philosophical topics—such as the nature of knowledge, language,
concepts, meaning, belief, and science—are all best viewed in terms of their practical uses and successes.

Contents
Origins
Core tenets
Anti-reification of concepts and theories
Naturalism and anti-Cartesianism
Reconciliation of anti-skepticism and fallibilism
Pragmatist theory of truth and epistemology
In other fields of philosophy
Philosophy of science
Logic
Metaphysics
Philosophy of mind
Ethics
Aesthetics
Philosophy of religion
Neopragmatism
Legacy and contemporary relevance
Effects on social sciences
Effects on public administration
Effects on feminism
Criticisms
List of pragmatists
Classical pragmatists (1850–1950)
Analytic, neo- and other pragmatists (1950–present)
Pragmatists in the extended sense
See also
References
Sources
Further reading
Additional bibliography
External links

Origins
Pragmatism as a philosophical movement began in the United
States in the 1870s. Charles Sanders Peirce (and his Pragmatic
Maxim) is given credit for its development,[4] along with later
twentieth century contributors, William James and John
Dewey.[5] Its direction was determined by The Metaphysical
Club members Charles Sanders Peirce, William James, and
Chauncey Wright, as well as John Dewey and George Herbert
Mead.

The first use in print of the name pragmatism was in 1898 by


James, who credited Peirce with coining the term during the early
1870s.[6] James regarded Peirce's "Illustrations of the Logic of
Science" series (including "The Fixation of Belief" (1877), and
especially "How to Make Our Ideas Clear" (1878)) as the
foundation of pragmatism.[7][8] Peirce in turn wrote in 1906[9]
that Nicholas St. John Green had been instrumental by Charles Peirce: the American
emphasizing the importance of applying Alexander Bain's polymath who first identified
definition of belief, which was "that upon which a man is pragmatism
prepared to act". Peirce wrote that "from this definition,
pragmatism is scarce more than a corollary; so that I am disposed
to think of him as the grandfather of pragmatism". John Shook has said, "Chauncey Wright also deserves
considerable credit, for as both Peirce and James recall, it was Wright who demanded a phenomenalist
and fallibilist empiricism as an alternative to rationalistic speculation."[10]

Peirce developed the idea that inquiry depends on real doubt, not mere verbal or hyperbolic doubt,[11]
and said, in order to understand a conception in a fruitful way, "Consider the practical effects of the
objects of your conception. Then, your conception of those effects is the whole of your conception of the
object",[2] which he later called the pragmatic maxim. It equates any conception of an object to the
general extent of the conceivable implications for informed practice of that object's effects. This is the
heart of his pragmatism as a method of experimentational mental reflection arriving at conceptions in
terms of conceivable confirmatory and disconfirmatory circumstances—a method hospitable to the
generation of explanatory hypotheses, and conducive to the employment and improvement of
verification. Typical of Peirce is his concern with inference to explanatory hypotheses as outside the
usual foundational alternative between deductivist rationalism and inductivist empiricism, although he
was a mathematical logician and a founder of statistics.

Peirce lectured and further wrote on pragmatism to make clear his own interpretation. While framing a
conception's meaning in terms of conceivable tests, Peirce emphasized that, since a conception is general,
its meaning, its intellectual purport, equates to its acceptance's implications for general practice, rather
than to any definite set of real effects (or test results); a conception's clarified meaning points toward its
conceivable verifications, but the outcomes are not meanings, but individual upshots. Peirce in 1905
coined the new name pragmaticism "for the precise purpose of expressing the original definition",[12]
saying that "all went happily" with James's and Schiller's variant uses of the old name "pragmatism" and
that he nonetheless coined the new name because of the old name's growing use in "literary journals,
where it gets abused". Yet in a 1906 manuscript he cited as causes his differences with James and
Schiller.[13] and, in a 1908 publication,[14] his differences with James as well as literary author Giovanni
Papini. Peirce in any case regarded his views that truth is immutable and infinity is real, as being opposed
by the other pragmatists, but he remained allied with them on other issues.[14]

Pragmatism enjoyed renewed attention after Willard Van Orman Quine and Wilfrid Sellars used a revised
pragmatism to criticize logical positivism in the 1960s. Inspired by the work of Quine and Sellars, a
brand of pragmatism known sometimes as neopragmatism gained influence through Richard Rorty, the
most influential of the late twentieth century pragmatists along with Hilary Putnam and Robert Brandom.
Contemporary pragmatism may be broadly divided into a strict analytic tradition and a "neo-classical"
pragmatism (such as Susan Haack) that adheres to the work of Peirce, James, and Dewey.

Core tenets
A few of the various but often interrelated positions characteristic of philosophers working from a
pragmatist approach include:

Epistemology (justification): a coherentist theory of justification that rejects the claim that all
knowledge and justified belief rest ultimately on a foundation of noninferential knowledge or
justified belief. Coherentists hold that justification is solely a function of some relationship
between beliefs, none of which are privileged beliefs in the way maintained by
foundationalist theories of justification.
Epistemology (truth): a deflationary or pragmatic theory of truth; the former is the
epistemological claim that assertions that predicate truth of a statement do not attribute a
property called truth to such a statement while the latter is the epistemological claim that
assertions that predicate truth of a statement attribute the property of useful-to-believe to
such a statement.
Metaphysics: a pluralist view that there is more than one sound way to conceptualize the
world and its content.
Philosophy of science: an instrumentalist and scientific anti-realist view that a scientific
concept or theory should be evaluated by how effectively it explains and predicts
phenomena, as opposed to how accurately it describes objective reality.
Philosophy of language: an anti-representationalist view that rejects analyzing the semantic
meaning of propositions, mental states, and statements in terms of a correspondence or
representational relationship and instead analyzes semantic meaning in terms of notions
like dispositions to action, inferential relationships, and/or functional roles (e.g. behaviorism
and inferentialism). Not to be confused with pragmatics, a sub-field of linguistics with no
relation to philosophical pragmatism.
Additionally, forms of empiricism, fallibilism, verificationism, and a Quinean naturalist
metaphilosophy are all commonly elements of pragmatist philosophies. Many pragmatists
are epistemological relativists and see this to be an important facet of their pragmatism, but
this is controversial and other pragmatists argue such relativism to be seriously misguided
(e.g. Hilary Putnam, Susan Haack).

Anti-reification of concepts and theories


Dewey, in The Quest For Certainty, criticized what he called "the philosophical fallacy": philosophers
often take categories (such as the mental and the physical) for granted because they don't realize that
these are nominal concepts that were invented to help solve specific problems.[15] This causes
metaphysical and conceptual confusion. Various examples are the "ultimate Being" of Hegelian
philosophers, the belief in a "realm of value", the idea that logic, because it is an abstraction from
concrete thought, has nothing to do with the action of concrete thinking.

David L. Hildebrand summed up the problem: "Perceptual inattention to the specific functions
comprising inquiry led realists and idealists alike to formulate accounts of knowledge that project the
products of extensive abstraction back onto experience."[15]:40

Naturalism and anti-Cartesianism


From the outset, pragmatists wanted to reform philosophy and bring it more in line with the scientific
method as they understood it. They argued that idealist and realist philosophy had a tendency to present
human knowledge as something beyond what science could grasp. They held that these philosophies then
resorted either to a phenomenology inspired by Kant or to correspondence theories of knowledge and
truth. Pragmatists criticized the former for its a priorism, and the latter because it takes correspondence
as an unanalyzable fact. Pragmatism instead tries to explain the relation between knower and known.

In 1868,[16] C.S. Peirce argued that there is no power of intuition in the sense of a cognition
unconditioned by inference, and no power of introspection, intuitive or otherwise, and that awareness of
an internal world is by hypothetical inference from external facts. Introspection and intuition were staple
philosophical tools at least since Descartes. He argued that there is no absolutely first cognition in a
cognitive process; such a process has its beginning but can always be analyzed into finer cognitive
stages. That which we call introspection does not give privileged access to knowledge about the mind—
the self is a concept that is derived from our interaction with the external world and not the other way
around (De Waal 2005, pp. 7–10). At the same time he held persistently that pragmatism and
epistemology in general could not be derived from principles of psychology understood as a special
science:[17] what we do think is too different from what we should think; in his "Illustrations of the Logic
of Science" series, Peirce formulated both pragmatism and principles of statistics as aspects of scientific
method in general.[18] This is an important point of disagreement with most other pragmatists, who
advocate a more thorough naturalism and psychologism.

Richard Rorty expanded on these and other arguments in Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature in which
he criticized attempts by many philosophers of science to carve out a space for epistemology that is
entirely unrelated to—and sometimes thought of as superior to—the empirical sciences. W.V. Quine,
instrumental in bringing naturalized epistemology back into favor with his essay Epistemology
Naturalized (Quine 1969), also criticized "traditional" epistemology and its "Cartesian dream" of
absolute certainty. The dream, he argued, was impossible in practice as well as misguided in theory,
because it separates epistemology from scientific inquiry.

Reconciliation of anti-skepticism and fallibilism


Hilary Putnam has suggested that the reconciliation of anti-skepticism[19] and fallibilism is the central
goal of American pragmatism. Although all human knowledge is partial, with no ability to take a "God's-
eye-view," this does not necessitate a globalized skeptical attitude, a radical philosophical skepticism (as
distinguished from that which is called scientific skepticism). Peirce insisted that (1) in reasoning, there
is the presupposition, and at least the hope,[20] that truth and the real are discoverable and would be
discovered, sooner or later but still inevitably, by investigation taken far enough,[2] and (2) contrary to
Descartes' famous and influential methodology in the Meditations on First Philosophy, doubt cannot be
feigned or created by verbal fiat to motivate fruitful inquiry, and
much less can philosophy begin in universal doubt.[21] Doubt,
like belief, requires justification. Genuine doubt irritates and
inhibits, in the sense that belief is that upon which one is prepared
to act.[2] It arises from confrontation with some specific
recalcitrant matter of fact (which Dewey called a "situation"),
which unsettles our belief in some specific proposition. Inquiry is
then the rationally self-controlled process of attempting to return
to a settled state of belief about the matter. Note that anti-
skepticism is a reaction to modern academic skepticism in the
wake of Descartes. The pragmatist insistence that all knowledge
is tentative is quite congenial to the older skeptical tradition.

Pragmatist theory of truth and epistemology


Pragmatism was not the first to apply evolution to theories of
Hilary Putnam asserts that the
knowledge: Schopenhauer advocated a biological idealism as
combination of antiskepticism and
what's useful to an organism to believe might differ wildly from fallibilism is a central feature of
what is true. Here knowledge and action are portrayed as two pragmatism.
separate spheres with an absolute or transcendental truth above
and beyond any sort of inquiry organisms used to cope with life.
Pragmatism challenges this idealism by providing an "ecological" account of knowledge: inquiry is how
organisms can get a grip on their environment. Real and true are functional labels in inquiry and cannot
be understood outside of this context. It is not realist in a traditionally robust sense of realism (what
Hilary Putnam would later call metaphysical realism), but it is realist in how it acknowledges an external
world which must be dealt with.

Many of James' best-turned phrases—truth's cash value (James 1907, p. 200) and the true is only the
expedient in our way of thinking (James 1907, p. 222)—were taken out of context and caricatured in
contemporary literature as representing the view where any idea with practical utility is true. William
James wrote:

It is high time to urge the use of a little imagination in philosophy. The unwillingness of
some of our critics to read any but the silliest of possible meanings into our statements is as
discreditable to their imaginations as anything I know in recent philosophic history. Schiller
says the truth is that which "works." Thereupon he is treated as one who limits verification
to the lowest material utilities. Dewey says truth is what gives "satisfaction"! He is treated as
one who believes in calling everything true which, if it were true, would be pleasant. (James
1907, p. 90)

In reality, James asserts, the theory is a great deal more subtle. (See Dewey 1910 for a "FAQ.")

The role of belief in representing reality is widely debated in pragmatism. Is a belief valid when it
represents reality? Copying is one (and only one) genuine mode of knowing, (James 1907, p. 91). Are
beliefs dispositions which qualify as true or false depending on how helpful they prove in inquiry and in
action? Is it only in the struggle of intelligent organisms with the surrounding environment that beliefs
acquire meaning? Does a belief only become true when it succeeds in this struggle? In Pragmatism
nothing practical or useful is held to be necessarily true, nor is anything which helps to survive merely in
the short term. For example, to believe my cheating spouse is faithful may help me feel better now, but it
is certainly not useful from a more long-term perspective because it doesn't accord with the facts (and is
therefore not true).

In other fields of philosophy


While pragmatism started out simply as a criterion of meaning, it quickly expanded to become a full-
fledged epistemology with wide-ranging implications for the entire philosophical field. Pragmatists who
work in these fields share a common inspiration, but their work is diverse and there are no received
views.

Philosophy of science
In the philosophy of science, instrumentalism is the view that concepts and theories are merely useful
instruments and progress in science cannot be couched in terms of concepts and theories somehow
mirroring reality. Instrumentalist philosophers often define scientific progress as nothing more than an
improvement in explaining and predicting phenomena. Instrumentalism does not state that truth does not
matter, but rather provides a specific answer to the question of what truth and falsity mean and how they
function in science.

One of C. I. Lewis' main arguments in Mind and the World Order: Outline of a Theory of Knowledge
(1929) was that science does not merely provide a copy of reality but must work with conceptual systems
and that those are chosen for pragmatic reasons, that is, because they aid inquiry. Lewis' own
development of multiple modal logics is a case in point. Lewis is sometimes called a proponent of
conceptual pragmatism because of this.[22]

Another development is the cooperation of logical positivism and pragmatism in the works of Charles W.
Morris and Rudolf Carnap. The influence of pragmatism on these writers is mostly limited to the
incorporation of the pragmatic maxim into their epistemology. Pragmatists with a broader conception of
the movement do not often refer to them.

W. V. Quine's paper "Two Dogmas of Empiricism", published 1951, is one of the most celebrated papers
of twentieth-century philosophy in the analytic tradition. The paper is an attack on two central tenets of
the logical positivists' philosophy. One is the distinction between analytic statements (tautologies and
contradictions) whose truth (or falsehood) is a function of the meanings of the words in the statement ('all
bachelors are unmarried'), and synthetic statements, whose truth (or falsehood) is a function of
(contingent) states of affairs. The other is reductionism, the theory that each meaningful statement gets its
meaning from some logical construction of terms which refers exclusively to immediate experience.
Quine's argument brings to mind Peirce's insistence that axioms are not a priori truths but synthetic
statements.

Logic
Later in his life Schiller became famous for his attacks on logic in his textbook, Formal Logic. By then,
Schiller's pragmatism had become the nearest of any of the classical pragmatists to an ordinary language
philosophy. Schiller sought to undermine the very possibility of formal logic, by showing that words only
had meaning when used in context. The least famous of Schiller's main works was the constructive
sequel to his destructive book Formal Logic. In this sequel, Logic for Use, Schiller attempted to construct
a new logic to replace the formal logic that he had criticized in Formal Logic. What he offers is
something philosophers would recognize today as a logic covering the context of discovery and the
hypothetico-deductive method.

Whereas F. C. S. Schiller dismissed the possibility of formal logic, most pragmatists are critical rather of
its pretension to ultimate validity and see logic as one logical tool among others—or perhaps, considering
the multitude of formal logics, one set of tools among others. This is the view of C. I. Lewis. C. S. Peirce
developed multiple methods for doing formal logic.

Stephen Toulmin's The Uses of Argument inspired scholars in informal logic and rhetoric studies
(although it is an epistemological work).

Metaphysics
James and Dewey were empirical thinkers in the most straightforward fashion: experience is the ultimate
test and experience is what needs to be explained. They were dissatisfied with ordinary empiricism
because in the tradition dating from Hume, empiricists had a tendency to think of experience as nothing
more than individual sensations. To the pragmatists, this went against the spirit of empiricism: we should
try to explain all that is given in experience including connections and meaning, instead of explaining
them away and positing sense data as the ultimate reality. Radical empiricism, or Immediate Empiricism
in Dewey's words, wants to give a place to meaning and value instead of explaining them away as
subjective additions to a world of whizzing atoms.

William James gives an interesting example of this philosophical


shortcoming:

[A young graduate] began by saying that he had


always taken for granted that when you entered a
philosophic classroom you had to open relations
with a universe entirely distinct from the one you
left behind you in the street. The two were supposed,
he said, to have so little to do with each other, that
The "Chicago Club" including Mead,
you could not possibly occupy your mind with them
Dewey, Angell, and Moore.
at the same time. The world of concrete personal
Pragmatism is sometimes called
experiences to which the street belongs is American Pragmatism because so
multitudinous beyond imagination, tangled, muddy, many of its proponents were and are
painful and perplexed. The world to which your Americans.
philosophy-professor introduces you is simple, clean
and noble. The contradictions of real life are absent
from it. ... In point of fact it is far less an account of
this actual world than a clear addition built upon it ...
It is no explanation of our concrete universe (James
1907, pp. 8–9)

F. C. S. Schiller's first book, Riddles of the Sphinx, was published before he became aware of the growing
pragmatist movement taking place in America. In it, Schiller argues for a middle ground between
materialism and absolute metaphysics. These opposites are comparable to what William James called
tough-minded empiricism and tender-minded rationalism. Schiller contends on the one hand that
mechanistic naturalism cannot make sense of the "higher" aspects of our world. These include free will,
consciousness, purpose, universals and some would add God. On the other hand, abstract metaphysics
cannot make sense of the "lower" aspects of our world (e.g. the imperfect, change, physicality). While
Schiller is vague about the exact sort of middle ground he is trying to establish, he suggests that
metaphysics is a tool that can aid inquiry, but that it is valuable only insofar as it does help in
explanation.

In the second half of the twentieth century, Stephen Toulmin argued that the need to distinguish between
reality and appearance only arises within an explanatory scheme and therefore that there is no point in
asking what "ultimate reality" consists of. More recently, a similar idea has been suggested by the
postanalytic philosopher Daniel Dennett, who argues that anyone who wants to understand the world has
to acknowledge both the "syntactical" aspects of reality (i.e., whizzing atoms) and its emergent or
"semantic" properties (i.e., meaning and value).

Radical empiricism gives answers to questions about the limits of science, the nature of meaning and
value and the workability of reductionism. These questions feature prominently in current debates about
the relationship between religion and science, where it is often assumed—most pragmatists would
disagree—that science degrades everything that is meaningful into "merely" physical phenomena.

Philosophy of mind
Both John Dewey in Experience and Nature (1929) and half a century later Richard Rorty in his
Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (1979) argued that much of the debate about the relation of the
mind to the body results from conceptual confusions. They argue instead that there is no need to posit the
mind or mindstuff as an ontological category.

Pragmatists disagree over whether philosophers ought to adopt a quietist or a naturalist stance toward the
mind-body problem. The former (Rorty among them) want to do away with the problem because they
believe it's a pseudo-problem, whereas the latter believe that it is a meaningful empirical question.

Ethics
Pragmatism sees no fundamental difference between practical and theoretical reason, nor any ontological
difference between facts and values. Pragmatist ethics is broadly humanist because it sees no ultimate test
of morality beyond what matters for us as humans. Good values are those for which we have good
reasons, viz. the Good Reasons approach. The pragmatist formulation pre-dates those of other
philosophers who have stressed important similarities between values and facts such as Jerome
Schneewind and John Searle.

William James' contribution to ethics, as laid out in his essay The Will to Believe has often been
misunderstood as a plea for relativism or irrationality. On its own terms it argues that ethics always
involves a certain degree of trust or faith and that we cannot always wait for adequate proof when
making moral decisions.

Moral questions immediately present themselves as


questions whose solution cannot wait for sensible proof. A
moral question is a question not of what sensibly exists,
but of what is good, or would be good if it did exist. ... A
social organism of any sort whatever, large or small, is
what it is because each member proceeds to his own duty
with a trust that the other members will simultaneously do
theirs. Wherever a desired result is achieved by the co-
operation of many independent persons, its existence as a
fact is a pure consequence of the precursive faith in one
another of those immediately concerned. A government, an
army, a commercial system, a ship, a college, an athletic
team, all exist on this condition, without which not only is
nothing achieved, but nothing is even attempted. (The Will
William James tried to show
to Believe (http://falcon.jmu.edu/~omearawm/ph101willto
the meaningfulness of (some
believe.html) James 1896) kinds of) spirituality but, like
other pragmatists, did not see
religion as the basis of
Of the classical pragmatists, John Dewey wrote most extensively about
meaning or morality.
morality and democracy. (Edel 1993) In his classic article Three
Independent Factors in Morals (Dewey 1930), he tried to integrate
three basic philosophical perspectives on morality: the right, the virtuous and the good. He held that
while all three provide meaningful ways to think about moral questions, the possibility of conflict among
the three elements cannot always be easily solved. (Anderson, SEP)

Dewey also criticized the dichotomy between means and ends which he saw as responsible for the
degradation of our everyday working lives and education, both conceived as merely a means to an end.
He stressed the need for meaningful labor and a conception of education that viewed it not as a
preparation for life but as life itself. (Dewey 2004 [1910] ch. 7; Dewey 1997 [1938], p. 47)

Dewey was opposed to other ethical philosophies of his time, notably the emotivism of Alfred Ayer.
Dewey envisioned the possibility of ethics as an experimental discipline, and thought values could best
be characterized not as feelings or imperatives, but as hypotheses about what actions will lead to
satisfactory results or what he termed consummatory experience. A further implication of this view is
that ethics is a fallible undertaking, since human beings are frequently unable to know what would satisfy
them.

During the late 1900s and first decade of 2000, pragmatism was embraced by many in the field of
bioethics led by the philosophers John Lachs and his student Glenn McGee, whose 1997 book "'The
Perfect Baby: A Pragmatic Approach to Genetic Engineering'" (see designer baby) garnered praise from
within classical American philosophy and criticism from bioethics for its development of a theory of
pragmatic bioethics and its rejection of the principalism theory then in vogue in medical ethics. An
anthology published by The MIT Press, "'Pragmatic Bioethics'" included the responses of philosophers to
that debate, including Micah Hester, Griffin Trotter and others many of whom developed their own
theories based on the work of Dewey, Peirce, Royce and others. Lachs himself developed several
applications of pragmatism to bioethics independent of but extending from the work of Dewey and
James.

A recent pragmatist contribution to meta-ethics is Todd Lekan's "Making Morality" (Lekan 2003). Lekan
argues that morality is a fallible but rational practice and that it has traditionally been misconceived as
based on theory or principles. Instead, he argues, theory and rules arise as tools to make practice more
intelligent.
Aesthetics
John Dewey's Art as Experience, based on the William James lectures he delivered at Harvard, was an
attempt to show the integrity of art, culture and everyday experience (IEP). Art, for Dewey, is or should
be a part of everyone's creative lives and not just the privilege of a select group of artists. He also
emphasizes that the audience is more than a passive recipient. Dewey's treatment of art was a move away
from the transcendental approach to aesthetics in the wake of Immanuel Kant who emphasized the
unique character of art and the disinterested nature of aesthetic appreciation. A notable contemporary
pragmatist aesthetician is Joseph Margolis. He defines a work of art as "a physically embodied, culturally
emergent entity", a human "utterance" that isn't an ontological quirk but in line with other human activity
and culture in general. He emphasizes that works of art are complex and difficult to fathom, and that no
determinate interpretation can be given.

Philosophy of religion
Both Dewey and James investigated the role that religion can still play in contemporary society, the
former in A Common Faith and the latter in The Varieties of Religious Experience.

From a general point of view, for William James, something is true only insofar as it works. Thus, the
statement, for example, that prayer is heard may work on a psychological level but (a) may not help to
bring about the things you pray for (b) may be better explained by referring to its soothing effect than by
claiming prayers are heard. As such, pragmatism is not antithetical to religion but it is not an apologetic
for faith either. James' metaphysical position however, leaves open the possibility that the ontological
claims of religions may be true. As he observed in the end of the Varieties, his position does not amount
to a denial of the existence of transcendent realities. Quite the contrary, he argued for the legitimate
epistemic right to believe in such realities, since such beliefs do make a difference in an individual's life
and refer to claims that cannot be verified or falsified either on intellectual or common sensorial grounds.

Joseph Margolis, in Historied Thought, Constructed World (California, 1995), makes a distinction
between "existence" and "reality". He suggests using the term "exists" only for those things which
adequately exhibit Peirce's Secondness: things which offer brute physical resistance to our movements. In
this way, such things which affect us, like numbers, may be said to be "real", although they do not
"exist". Margolis suggests that God, in such a linguistic usage, might very well be "real", causing
believers to act in such and such a way, but might not "exist".

Neopragmatism
Neopragmatism is a broad contemporary category used for various thinkers that incorporate important
insights of, and yet significantly diverge from, the classical pragmatists. This divergence may occur
either in their philosophical methodology (many of them are loyal to the analytic tradition) or in
conceptual formation: for example, conceptual pragmatist C. I. Lewis was very critical of Dewey;
neopragmatist Richard Rorty disliked Peirce.

Important analytic pragmatists include early Richard Rorty (who was the first to develop neopragmatist
philosophy in his Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (1979),[23] Hilary Putnam, W. V. O. Quine, and
Donald Davidson. Brazilian social thinker Roberto Unger advocates for a radical pragmatism, one that
"de-naturalizes" society and culture, and thus insists that we can "transform the character of our relation
to social and cultural worlds we inhabit rather than just to change, little by little, the content of the
arrangements and beliefs that comprise them".[24] Late Rorty and Jürgen Habermas are closer to
Continental thought.

Neopragmatist thinkers who are more loyal to classical pragmatism include Sidney Hook and Susan
Haack (known for the theory of foundherentism). Many pragmatist ideas (especially those of Peirce) find
a natural expression in the decision-theoretic reconstruction of epistemology pursued in the work of Isaac
Levi. Nicholas Rescher advocates his version of methodological pragmatism, based on construing
pragmatic efficacy not as a replacement for truths but as a means to its evidentiation.[25] Rescher is also a
proponent of pragmatic idealism.

Not all pragmatists are easily characterized. With the advent of postanalytic philosophy and the
diversification of Anglo-American philosophy, many philosophers were influenced by pragmatist thought
without necessarily publicly committing themselves to that philosophical school. Daniel Dennett, a
student of Quine's, falls into this category, as does Stephen Toulmin, who arrived at his philosophical
position via Wittgenstein, whom he calls "a pragmatist of a sophisticated kind" (foreword for Dewey
1929 in the 1988 edition, p. xiii). Another example is Mark Johnson whose embodied philosophy (Lakoff
and Johnson 1999) shares its psychologism, direct realism and anti-cartesianism with pragmatism.
Conceptual pragmatism is a theory of knowledge originating with the work of the philosopher and
logician Clarence Irving Lewis. The epistemology of conceptual pragmatism was first formulated in the
1929 book Mind and the World Order: Outline of a Theory of Knowledge.

French pragmatism is attended with theorists such as Bruno Latour, Michel Crozier, Luc Boltanski, and
Laurent Thévenot. It is often seen as opposed to structural problems connected to the French critical
theory of Pierre Bourdieu. French pragmatism has more recently made inroads into American sociology
as well.[26][27][28]

Philosophers John R. Shook and Tibor Solymosi said that "each new generation rediscovers and
reinvents its own versions of pragmatism by applying the best available practical and scientific methods
to philosophical problems of contemporary concern".[29]

Legacy and contemporary relevance


In the twentieth century, the movements of logical positivism and ordinary language philosophy have
similarities with pragmatism. Like pragmatism, logical positivism provides a verification criterion of
meaning that is supposed to rid us of nonsense metaphysics; however, logical positivism doesn't stress
action as pragmatism does. The pragmatists rarely used their maxim of meaning to rule out all
metaphysics as nonsense. Usually, pragmatism was put forth to correct metaphysical doctrines or to
construct empirically verifiable ones rather than to provide a wholesale rejection.

Ordinary language philosophy is closer to pragmatism than other philosophy of language because of its
nominalist character (although Peirce's pragmatism is not nominalist[14]) and because it takes the broader
functioning of language in an environment as its focus instead of investigating abstract relations between
language and world.

Pragmatism has ties to process philosophy. Much of their work developed in dialogue with process
philosophers such as Henri Bergson and Alfred North Whitehead, who aren't usually considered
pragmatists because they differ so much on other points. (Douglas Browning et al. 1998; Rescher, SEP)
Behaviorism and functionalism in psychology and sociology also have ties to pragmatism, which is not
surprising considering that James and Dewey were both scholars of psychology and that Mead became a
sociologist.

Utilitarianism has some significant parallels to Pragmatism and John Stuart Mill espoused similar values.

Pragmatism emphasizes the connection between thought and action. Applied fields like public
administration,[30] political science,[31] leadership studies,[32] international relations,[33] conflict
resolution,[34] and research methodology[35] have incorporated the tenets of pragmatism in their field.
Often this connection is made using Dewey and Addams's expansive notion of democracy.

Effects on social sciences


In the early twentieth century, Symbolic interactionism, a major perspective within sociological social
psychology, was derived from pragmatism, especially the work of George Herbert Mead and Charles
Cooley, as well as that of Peirce and William James.[36]

Increasing attention is being given to pragmatist epistemology in other branches of the social sciences,
which have struggled with divisive debates over the status of social scientific knowledge.[5][37]

Enthusiasts suggest that pragmatism offers an approach which is both pluralist and practical.[38]

Effects on public administration


The classical pragmatism of John Dewey, William James, and Charles Sanders Peirce has influenced
research in the field of Public Administration. Scholars claim classical pragmatism had a profound
influence on the origin of the field of public administration.[39][40] At the most basic level, public
administrators are responsible for making programs "work" in a pluralistic, problems-oriented
environment. Public administrators are also responsible for the day-to-day work with citizens. Dewey's
participatory democracy can be applied in this environment. Dewey and James' notion of theory as a tool,
helps administrators craft theories to resolve policy and administrative problems. Further, the birth of
American public administration coincides closely with the period of greatest influence of the classical
pragmatists.

Which pragmatism (classical pragmatism or neo-pragmatism) makes the most sense in public
administration has been the source of debate. The debate began when Patricia M. Shields introduced
Dewey's notion of the Community of Inquiry.[41] Hugh Miller objected to one element of the community
of inquiry (problematic situation, scientific attitude, participatory democracy): scientific attitude.[42] A
debate that included responses from a practitioner,[43] an economist,[44] a planner,[45] other public
administration scholars,[46][47] and noted philosophers[48][49] followed. Miller[50] and Shields[51][52] also
responded.

In addition, applied scholarship of public administration that assesses charter schools,[53] contracting out
or outsourcing,[54] financial management,[55] performance measurement,[56] urban quality of life
initiatives,[57] and urban planning[58] in part draws on the ideas of classical pragmatism in the
development of the conceptual framework and focus of analysis.[59][60][61]
The health sector's administrators' use of pragmatism has been criticized as incomplete in its pragmatism,
however,[62] according to the classical pragmatists, knowledge is always shaped by human interests. The
administrator's focus on "outcomes" simply advances their own interest, and this focus on outcomes often
undermines their citizen's interests, which often are more concerned with process. On the other hand,
David Brendel argues that pragmatism's ability to bridge dualisms, focus on practical problems, include
multiple perspectives, incorporate participation from interested parties (patient, family, health team), and
provisional nature makes it well suited to address problems in this area.[63]

Effects on feminism
Since the mid 1990s, feminist philosophers have re-discovered classical pragmatism as a source of
feminist theories. Works by Seigfried,[64] Duran,[65] Keith,[66] and Whipps[67] explore the historic and
philosophic links between feminism and pragmatism. The connection between pragmatism and feminism
took so long to be rediscovered because pragmatism itself was eclipsed by logical positivism during the
middle decades of the twentieth century. As a result, it was lost from femininist discourse. The very
features of pragmatism that led to its decline are the characteristics that feminists now consider its
greatest strength. These are "persistent and early criticisms of positivist interpretations of scientific
methodology; disclosure of value dimension of factual claims"; viewing aesthetics as informing everyday
experience; subordinating logical analysis to political, cultural, and social issues; linking the dominant
discourses with domination; "realigning theory with praxis; and resisting the turn to epistemology and
instead emphasizing concrete experience".[68] These feminist philosophers point to Jane Addams as a
founder of classical pragmatism. In addition, the ideas of Dewey, Mead, and James are consistent with
many feminist tenets. Jane Addams, John Dewey, and George Herbert Mead developed their philosophies
as all three became friends, influenced each other, and were engaged in the Hull-House experience and
women's rights causes.

Criticisms
In the 1908 essay "The Thirteen Pragmatisms", Arthur Oncken Lovejoy argued that there's significant
ambiguity in the notion of the effects of the truth of a proposition and those of belief in a proposition in
order to highlight that many pragmatists had failed to recognize that distinction.[69] He identified thirteen
different philosophical positions that were each labeled pragmatism.

Franciscan monk Celestine Bittle presented multiple criticisms of pragmatism in his 1936 book Reality
and the Mind: Epistemology.[70] He argued that, in William James's pragmatism, truth is entirely
subjective and is not the widely accepted definition of truth, which is correspondence to reality. For
Bittle, defining truth as what is useful is a "perversion of language".[70] With truth reduced essentially to
what is good, it is no longer an object of the intellect. Therefore, the problem of knowledge posed by the
intellect is not solved, but rather renamed. Renaming truth as a product of the will cannot help it solve the
problems of the intellect, according to Bittle. Bittle cited what he saw as contradictions in pragmatism,
such as using objective facts to prove that truth does not emerge from objective fact; this reveals that
pragmatists do recognize truth as objective fact, and not, as they claim, what is useful. Bittle argued there
are also some statements that cannot be judged on human welfare at all. Such statements (for example the
assertion that "a car is passing") are matters of "truth and error" and do not affect human welfare.[70]

British philosopher Bertrand Russell devoted a chapter each to James and Dewey in his 1945 book A
History of Western Philosophy; Russell pointed out areas in which he agreed with them but also ridiculed
James's views on truth and Dewey's views on inquiry.[71]:17[72]:120–124 Hilary Putnam later argued that
Russell "presented a mere caricature" of James's views[71]:17 and a "misreading of James",[71]:20 while
Tom Burke argued at length that Russell presented "a skewed characterization of Dewey's point of
view".[72]:121 Elsewhere, in Russell's book The Analysis of Mind, Russell praised James's radical
empiricism, to which Russell's own account of neutral monism was indebted.[71]:17[73] Dewey, in The
Bertrand Russell Case, defended Russell against an attempt to remove Russell from his chair at the
College of the City of New York in 1940.[74]

Neopragmatism as represented by Richard Rorty has been criticized as relativistic both by other
neopragmatists such as Susan Haack (Haack 1997) and by many analytic philosophers (Dennett 1998).
Rorty's early analytic work, however, differs notably from his later work which some, including Rorty,
consider to be closer to literary criticism than to philosophy, and which attracts the brunt of criticism
from his detractors.

List of pragmatists

Classical pragmatists Analytic, neo- and other pragmatists


(1850–1950) (1950–present)
Name Lifetime Notes Name Lifetime Notes
Charles 1839– was the founder Richard J. 1932– Author of Beyond Objectivism and
Sanders 1914 of American Bernstein Relativism: Science,
Peirce pragmatism Hermeneutics, and Praxis, The
(later called by New Constellation: The Ethical-
Peirce Political Horizons of
pragmaticism). Modernity/Postmodernity, The
He wrote on a Pragmatic Turn
wide range of
topics, from Author of What Pragmatism Was
mathematical (2013), Dewey's New Logic (1994).
logic and His work interprets contemporary
F. Thomas
semiotics to 1950– philosophy of mind, philosophy of
Burke
psychology. language, and philosophical logic
through the lens of classical
influential American pragmatism.
psychologist and
theorist of Philosopher of Science who
religion, as well proposed the Natural Ontological
Arthur Fine 1937–
as philosopher. Attitude to the debate of scientific
William 1842– First to be widely realism.
James 1910 associated with
Literary and Legal Studies
the term
pragmatist. Criticizes Rorty's and
"pragmatism"
Stanley Posner's legal theories as "almost
due to Peirce's 1938–
lifelong Fish pragmatism"[75] and authored the
unpopularity. afterword in the collection The
Revival of Pragmatism.[76]
prominent
philosopher of A student of Rorty's, has
education, developed a complex analytic
John 1859– Robert version of pragmatism in works
referred to his 1950–
Dewey 1952 Brandom such as Making it Explicit,
brand of
pragmatism as Between Saying and Doing, and
instrumentalism. Perspectives on Pragmatism.

Oliver a leading authority on symbolic


U.S. Supreme Clarence 1883–
Wendell 1841– logic and on the philosophic
Court Associate Irving Lewis 1964
Holmes, 1935 concepts of knowledge and value.
Justice.
Jr.
still proudly defends the original
one of the most Pragmatists and sees his recent
important work on Cultural Realism as
F. C. S. 1864– pragmatists of Joseph extending and deepening their
1924–
Schiller 1937 his time, Schiller Margolis insights, especially the contribution
is largely of Peirce and Dewey, in the
forgotten today. context of a rapprochement with
Continental philosophy.

Important protopragmatists or Hilary 1926-


in many ways the opposite of Rorty
and thinks classical pragmatism
related thinkers Putnam 2016
was too permissive a theory.
Richard 1931– famous author of Philosophy and
Rorty 2007 the Mirror of Nature.
John J.
Stuhr
Willard van pragmatist philosopher, concerned
1908–
Orman with language, logic, and
2000
Quine philosophy of mathematics.
Mike 1961– Applied Rorty's neopragmatism to
Sandbothe media studies and developed a
new branch that he called Media
Philosophy. Together with authors
such as Juergen Habermas, Hans
Name Lifetime Notes Joas, Sami Pihlstroem, Mats
Bergmann, Michael Esfeld, and
George 1863– philosopher Helmut Pape, he belongs to a
Herbert 1931 and group of European Pragmatists
Mead sociological who make use of Peirce, James,
social Dewey, Rorty, Brandom, Putnam,
psychologist. and other representatives of
American pragmatism in
colleague of Continental philosophy.
James at
Harvard who Richard
1949- philosopher of art.
employed Shusterman
pragmatism in
an idealist Defends a pragmatist form of
metaphysical Jason contextualism against semantic
1969–
framework, he Stanley varieties of contextualism in his
was Knowledge and Practical Interest.
Josiah 1855–
particularly defends an epistemological
Royce 1916
interested in conception of democratic politics
the philosophy that is explicitly opposed to
of religion and Deweyan democracy and yet
community; Robert B. rooted in a conception of social
his work is 1970–
Talisse epistemology that derives from the
often pragmatism of Charles Peirce. His
associated work in argumentation theory and
with neo- informal logic also demonstrates
Hegelianism. pragmatist leanings.
although he student of Wittgenstein, known
eschewed the Stephen 1922–
especially for his The Uses of
label Toulmin 2009
Argument.
"pragmatism"
and called it a in The Self Awakened: Pragmatism
"heresy", Unbound, advocates for a "radical
several critics pragmatism", one that 'de-
argue that he naturalizes' society and culture,
George 1863–
applied and thus insists that we can
Santayana 1952 Roberto
pragmatist 1947– "transform the character of our
Unger
methodologies relation to social and cultural
to naturalism, worlds we inhabit rather than just
especially in to change, little by little, the
his early content of the arrangements and
masterwork, beliefs that comprise them."
The Life of
Reason. a prominent New York intellectual
Sidney 1902–
and philosopher, a student of
Hook 1989
student of Dewey at Columbia.
James at
Harvard who seeks to apply pragmatist thinking
Isaac Levi 1930–
applied in a decision-theoretic perspective.
pragmatist
teaches at the University of Miami,
principles to
Susan sometimes called the intellectual
his 1945–
Haack granddaughter of C.S. Peirce,
W. E. B. 1868– sociological
known chiefly for foundherentism.
Du Bois 1963 work,
especially in advocates a methodological
The Nicholas
1928– pragmatism that sees functional
Philadelphia Rescher
efficacy as evidentiating validity.
Negro and
Atlanta
University
Studies. Pragmatists in the extended sense

Additional figures
Name Lifetime Notes Name Lifetime Notes
Giovanni 1881– Italian essayist, Cornel 1953– thinker on race, politics, and religion;
Papini 1956 mostly known West operates under the sign of "prophetic
because James pragmatism".
occasionally
mentioned him. broad thinker, attacked mainstream
Wilfrid 1912–
variants of foundationalism in the
Sellars 1989
Italian analytic analytic tradition.
Giovanni 1863–
and pragmatist
Vailati 1909 Frank P. 1903– author of the philosophical work
philosopher.
Ramsey 1930 Universals.
Chinese
intellectual and Karl-Otto 1922– author of "Charles S. Peirce: From
reformer, Apel 2017 Pragmatism to Pragmaticism (1981)"
student and
1891– Randolph 1886– author of the 1917 pragmatist anti-
Hu Shih translator of
1962 Bourne 1918 war essay "Twilight of Idols"
Dewey's and
advocate of author of Sociology and Pragmatism:
pragmatism in C. Wright 1916–
the Higher Learning in America and
China. Mills 1962
was a commentator on Dewey.
American Jürgen author of "What is Universal
philosopher and 1929–
Habermas Pragmatics?"
theologian,
Reinhold 1892– inserted
Niebuhr 1971 pragmatism into
his theory of
Christian
realism.

See also
American philosophy
Charles Sanders Peirce bibliography
Doctrine of internal relations
Holistic pragmatism
New legal realism
Pragmatism as a tradition of communication theory
Pragmatic model
Realpolitik

References
1. Hookway, Christopher (August 16, 2008). "Pragmatism" (https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pr
agmatism/). In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2010
ed.).
2. Peirce, C. S. (1878), "How to Make Our Ideas Clear", Popular Science Monthly, v. 12, 286–
302. Reprinted often, including Collected Papers v. 5, paragraphs 388–410 and Essential
Peirce v. 1, 124–41. See end of §II for the pragmatic maxim. See third and fourth
paragraphs in §IV for the discoverability of truth and the real by sufficient investigation.
3. William James (1909). The Meaning of Truth (http://www.gutenberg.org/files/5117/5117-h/5
117-h.htm). Retrieved March 5, 2015.
4. Susan Haack; Robert Edwin Lane (April 11, 2006). Pragmatism, old & new: selected
writings. Prometheus Books. pp. 18–67. ISBN 978-1-59102-359-3.
5. Biesta, G.J.J. & Burbules, N. (2003). Pragmatism and educational research. Lanham, MD:
Rowman and Littlefield.
6. James, William (1898), "Philosophical Conceptions and Practical Results", delivered before
the Philosophical Union of the University of California at Berkeley, August 26, 1898, and first
printed in the University Chronicle 1, September 1898, pp. 287–310. Internet Archive Eprint
(https://archive.org/stream/philosophicalcon00jameuoft#page/n4/mode/1up). On p. 290 (http
s://archive.org/stream/philosophicalcon00jameuoft#page/290/mode/1up):

I refer to Mr. Charles S. Peirce, with whose very existence as a philosopher I


dare say many of you are unacquainted. He is one of the most original of
contemporary thinkers; and the principle of practicalism or pragmatism, as he
called it, when I first heard him enunciate it at Cambridge in the early [1870s] is
the clue or compass by following which I find myself more and more confirmed
in believing we may keep our feet upon the proper trail.

James credited Peirce again in 1906 lectures published in 1907 as Pragmatism: A New
Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking, see Lecture 2, fourth paragraph.

7. See James (1897), Will to Believe (which James dedicated to Peirce), see p. 124 and
footnote via Google Books Eprint (https://books.google.com/books?id=wRMXL4uYEegC&p
g=PA124):

Indeed, it may be said that if two apparently different definitions of the reality
before us should have identical consequences, those two definitions would
really be identical definitions, made delusively to appear different merely by the
different verbiage in which they are expressed.¹
¹ See the admirably original "Illustrations of the Logic of Science," by C. S.
Peirce, especially the second paper, "How to make our Thoughts clear," [sic] in
the Popular Science Monthly for January, 1878.

See also James's 1907 Pragmatism: A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking, Lecture
2, fourth paragraph.
8. In addition to James's lectures and publications on pragmatist ideas (Will to Believe 1897,
etc.) wherein he credited Peirce, James also arranged for two paid series of lectures by
Peirce, including the 1903 Harvard lectures on pragmatism. See pp. 261–4, 290–2, & 324 in
Brent, Joseph (1998), Charles Sanders Peirce: A Life, 2nd edition.
9. Peirce, C. S., "The Founding of Pragmatism", manuscript written 1906, published in The
Hound & Horn: A Harvard Miscellany v. II, n. 3, April–June 1929, pp. 282–5, see 283–4,
reprinted 1934 as "Historical Affinities and Genesis" in Collected Papers v. 5, paragraphs
11–13, see 12.
10. Shook, John (undated), "The Metaphysical Club", the Pragmatism Cybrary. Eprint (http://ww
w.pragmatism.org/research/metaphysical_club.htm).
11. Peirce, C. S. (1877), The Fixation of Belief, Popular Science Monthly, v. 12, pp. 1–15.
Reprited often, including Collected Papers v. 5, paragraphs 358–87 and Essential Peirce v.
1, pp. 109–23).
12. Peirce, on p p. 165 (https://books.google.com/books?id=j6oLAAAAIAAJ&pg=PA165)–166 in
"What Pragmatism Is", The Monist, v. XV, n. 2, April 1905, pp. 161–81, reprinted in
Collected Papers v. 5, paragraphs 411–37, see 414.
13. Manuscript "A Sketch of Logical Critics", Essential Peirce v. 2, pp. 451–62, see pp. 457–8.
Peirce wrote:

I have always fathered my pragmaticism (as I have called it since James and
Schiller made the word [pragmatism] imply "the will to believe," the mutability of
truth, the soundness of Zeno's refutation of motion, and pluralism generally),
upon Kant, Berkeley, and Leibniz. ...

14. Peirce, C. S. (1908) "A Neglected Argument for the Reality of God", Hibbert Journal 7,
reprinted in Collected Papers v. 6, paragraphs 452–85, Essential Peirce v. 2, 434–50, and
elsewhere. After discussing James, Peirce stated (Section V, fourth paragraph) as the
specific occasion of his coinage "pragmaticism", journalist, pragmatist, and literary author
Giovanni Papini's declaration of pragmatism's indefinability (see for example "What Is
Pragmatism Like", a translation published in October 1907 in Popular Science Monthly v.
71, pp. 351–8, Google Books Eprint (https://books.google.com/books?id=DKkWAAAAYAAJ
&pg=PA351)). Peirce in his closing paragraph wrote that "willing not to exert the will (willing
to believe)" should not be confused with "active willing (willing to control thought, to doubt,
and to weigh reasons)", and discussed his dismay by that which he called the other
pragmatists' "angry hatred of strict logic". He also rejected their nominalist tendencies. But
he remained allied with them about the falsity of necessitarianism and about the reality of
generals and habits understood in terms of potential concrete effects even if unactualized.
15. Hildebrand, David L. (2003). Beyond realism and antirealism: John Dewey and the
neopragmatists (https://archive.org/details/beyondrealismant0000hild). The Vanderbilt
library of American philosophy. Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press. ISBN 082651426X.
OCLC 51053926 (https://www.worldcat.org/oclc/51053926).
16. Peirce, C. S. (1868) "Questions Concerning Certain Faculties Claimed For Man", Journal of
Speculative Philosophy v. 2, n. 2, pp. 103–114. Reprinted Collected Peirce v. 5, paragraphs
213–263, Writings v. 2, pp. 193–211, Essential Peirce v. 2, pp. 11–27, and elsewhere.
Peirce.org Eprint (http://www.peirce.org/writings/p26.html). Google Books Eprint (https://boo
ks.google.com/books?id=YHkqP2JHJ_IC&pg=RA1-PA140).
17. Kasser, Jeff (1998), "Peirce's Supposed Psychologism" in Transactions of the Charles S.
Peirce Society, v. 35, n. 3, summer 1999, pp. 501–527. Arisbe Eprint (http://www.cspeirce.c
om/menu/library/aboutcsp/kasser/psychol.htm).
18. Peirce held that (philosophical) logic is a normative field, that pragmatism is a method
developed in it, and that philosophy, though not deductive or so general as mathematics,
still concerns positive phenomena in general, including phenomena of matter and mind,
without depending on special experiences or experiments such as those of optics and
experimental psychology, in both of which Peirce was active. See quotes under "Philosophy
(http://www.helsinki.fi/science/commens/terms/philosophy.html)" at the Commens Dictionary
of Peirce's Terms. Peirce also harshly criticized the Cartesian approach of starting from
hyperbolic doubts rather than from the combination of established beliefs and genuine
doubts. See the opening of his 1868 "Some Consequences of Four Incapacities", Journal of
Speculative Philosophy v. 2, n. 3, pp. 140–157. Reprinted Collected Papers v. 5, paragraphs
264–317, Writings v. 2, pp. 211–42, and Essential Peirce v. 1, pp. 28–55. Eprint (http://www.
cspeirce.com/menu/library/bycsp/conseq/cn-frame.htm).
19. Skeptcism and Content Externalism (https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/skepticism-content-ex
ternalism/) provides a definition of anti-skepsis
20. Peirce (1902), The Carnegie Institute Application, Memoir 10, MS L75.361-2, Arisbe Eprint
(http://www.cspeirce.com/menu/library/bycsp/l75/ver1/l75v1-04.htm#m10).
21. Peirce, C. S. (1868), "Some Consequences of Four Incapacities", Journal of Speculative
Philosophy v. 2, n. 3, p p. 140 (https://books.google.com/books?id=YHkqP2JHJ_IC&pg=RA
1-PA140)–57, see opening pages. Reprinted Collected Papers v. 5, paragraphs 264–317,
Writings v. 2, pp. 211–42, Essential Peirce v. 1, pp. 28–55. Peirce.org Eprint (http://www.peir
ce.org/writings/p27.html).
22. Sandra B. Rosenthal, C. I. Lewis in Focus: The Pulse of Pragmatism, Indiana University
Press, 2007, p. 28.
23. Pragmatism – Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy (https://www.iep.utm.edu/pragmati/)
24. Unger, Roberto (2007). The Self Awakened: Pragmatism Unbound. Harvard University
Press. pp. 6–7. ISBN 978-0-674-03496-9.
25. Nicholas Rescher, "Methodological Pragmatism", Journal of Philosophy 76(6):338–342
(1979).
26. Simko, Christina (2012). "Rhetorics of Suffering". American Sociological Review. 77 (6):
880–902. doi:10.1177/0003122412458785
(https://doi.org/10.1177%2F0003122412458785).
27. Dromi, Shai M.; Stabler, Samuel D. (2019). "Good on paper: sociological critique,
pragmatism, and secularization theory". Theory and Society. Online First (2): 325–350.
doi:10.1007/s11186-019-09341-9 (https://doi.org/10.1007%2Fs11186-019-09341-9).
28. Cohen, Andrew C.; Dromi, Shai M. (February 15, 2018). "Advertising morality: maintaining
moral worth in a stigmatized profession" (http://osf.io/h6kvu/). Theory and Society. 47 (2):
175–206. doi:10.1007/s11186-018-9309-7 (https://doi.org/10.1007%2Fs11186-018-9309-7).
29. Shook, John R.; Solymosi, Tibor (April 2013). "Pragmatism: key resources" (https://www.res
earchgate.net/publication/271041927). Choice. 50: 1367–1377 (1367).
30. Patricia M. Shields. 2008. "Rediscovering the Taproot: Is Classical Pragmatism the Route to
Renew Public Administration?" Public Administration Review 68(2), 205–221
31. Ansell, Christopher. 2011. Pragmatist Democracy: Evolutionary Learning as Public
Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press
32. Weber, Eric Thomas. 2013. Democracy and Leadership: On Pragmatism and Virtue. New
York: Lexington Books.
33. Ralston, Shane (Ed). 2013. Philosophical Pragmatism and International Relations: Essays
for a Bold New World. New York: Lexington.
34. Caspary, William. 2000. Dewey on Democracy. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
35. Shields, Patricia and Rangarjan, N. 2013. A Playbook for Research Methods: Integrating
Conceptual Frameworks and Project Management. [1] (https://books.google.com/books?id=
tVYbAgAAQBAJ&printsec=frontcover&dq=inauthor:%22Patricia+M.+Shields%22&hl=en&sa
=X&ei=c3iIU6X7HdOYyASjlIDwBw&ved=0CC4Q6wEwAA#v=onepage&q&f=false).
Stillwater, OK: New Forums Press. Shields relies primarily on Dewey's logic of Inquiry.
36. Stryker, S. (1980). Symbolic Interactionism: A Social Structural Version..
Benjamin/Cummings Publishing.
37. Baert, P. (2004). "Pragmatism as a philosophy of the social sciences." European Journal of
Social Theory, 7(3), 355–369.
38. Cornish, F. & Gillespie, A. (2009). A pragmatist approach to the problem of knowledge in
health psychology (https://gcal.academia.edu/FloraCornish/Papers/107681/A-pragmatist-ap
proach-to-the-problem-of-knowledge-in-health-psychology) Journal of Health Psychology,
14(6), 1–10.
39. Patricia M. Shields. 2008. Rediscovering the Taproot: Is Classical Pragmatism the Route to
Renew Public Administration? Public Administration Review 68(2), 205–221
40. Hildebrand, David L. 2008. Public Administration as Pragmatic, Democratic and Objective.
Public Administration Review. 68(2), 222–229
41. Shields, Patricia 2003. The community of Inquiry: Classical Pragmatism and Public
Administration." Administration & Society 35(5): 510–538. abstract (http://aas.sagepub.com/
cgi/content/abstract/35/5/510)
42. Miller, Hugh. 2004. "Why Old Pragmatism Needs an Upgrade. Administration & Society
36(2), 234–249.
43. Stolcis, Gregory 2004. "A view from the Trenches: Comment on Miller's 'Why Old
Pragmatism needs and upgrade" Administration & Society 36(3):326–369
44. Webb, James "Comment on Hugh T. Miller's 'Why old Pragmatism needs and upgrade'.
Administration & Society 36(4), 479–495.
45. Hoch C. 2006. "What Can Rorty teach an old pragmatist doing public administration or
planning? Administration & Society. 38(3):389–398. abstract (http://aas.sagepub.com/cgi/co
ntent/abstract/38/3/389)
46. Evans, Karen. 2005. "Upgrade or a different animal altogether?: Why Old Pragmatism
Better Informs Public Management and New Pragmatism Misses the Point." Administration
& Society 37(2), 248–255.
47. Snider, Keith. 2005. Rortyan Pragmatism: 'Where's the beef' for public administration."
Administration & Society 37(2), 243–247.
48. Hildebrand, David. 2005. "Pragmatism, Neopragmatism and public administration."
Administration & Society 37(3): 360–374. abstract (http://aas.sagepub.com/cgi/content/abstr
act/37/3/345)
49. Hickman, Larry 2004. "On Hugh T. Miller on 'Why old pragmatism needs an upgrade."
Administration & Society 36(4):496–499.
50. Miller, Hugh 2005. "Residues of foundationalism in Classical Pragmatism." Administration &
Society. 37(3):345–359.
51. Patricia M. Shields. 2004. "Classical Pragmatism: Engaging practitioner experience."
Administration & Society, 36(3):351–361
52. Patricia M. Shields. 2005. "Classical Pragmatism does not need an upgrade: Lessons for
Public Administration." Administration & Society. 37(4):504–518. abstract (http://aas.sagepu
b.com/cgi/content/abstract/37/4/504)
53. Perez, Shivaun, "Assessing Service Learning Using Pragmatic Principles of Education: A
Texas Charter School Case Study" (2000). Applied Research Projects. Texas State
University Paper 76. http://ecommons.txstate.edu/arp/76
54. Alexander, Jason Fields, "Contracting Through the Lens of Classical Pragmatism: An
Exploration of Local Government Contracting" (2009). Applied Research Projects. Texas
State University. Paper 288. http://ecommons.txstate.edu/arp/288
55. Bartle, John R. and Shields, Patricia M., "Applying Pragmatism to Public Budgeting and
Financial Management" (2008). Faculty Publications-Political Science. Paper 48.
http://ecommons.txstate.edu/polsfacp/48
56. Wilson, Timothy L., "Pragmatism and Performance Measurement: An Exploration of
Practices in Texas State Government" (2001). Applied Research Projects. Texas State
University. Paper 71. http://ecommons.txstate.edu/arp/71
57. Howard-Watkins, Demetria C., "The Austin, Texas African-American Quality of Life Initiative
as a Community of inquiry: An Exploratory Study" (2006). Applied Research Projects. Texas
State University. Paper 115. http://ecommons.txstate.edu/arp/115
58. Johnson, Timothy Lee, "The Downtown Austin Planning Process as a Community of inquiry:
An Exploratory Study" (2008). Applied Research Projects. Paper 276.
http://ecommons.txstate.edu/arp/276.
59. Patricia M. Shields and Hassan Tajalli (2006), "Intermediate Theory: The Missing Link in
Successful Student Scholarship," Journal of Public Affairs Education 12(3):313–334.
https://digital.library.txstate.edu/handle/10877/3967
60. Patricia M. Shields (1998). "Pragmatism as a Philosophy of Science: A Tool for Public
Administration," Research in Public Administration. Volume 4: 195–225. (Online (https://digit
al.library.txstate.edu/handle/10877/3954).)
61. Patricia M. Shields and Nandhini Rangarajan (2013). A Playbook for Research Methods:
Integrating Conceptual Frameworks and Project Management (https://archive.is/201307190
14203/http://www.academia.edu/4044051/A_Playbook_for_Research_Methods_Integrating
_conceptual_frameworks_and_project_management). Stillwater, OK: New Forums Press.
62. Gillespie, A. & Cornish, F. (2009). A pragmatist approach to the problem of knowledge in
health psychology (https://lse.academia.edu/AlexGillespie/Papers/1347647/A_pragmatist_a
pproach_to_the_problem_of_knowledge_in_health_psychology). Journal of Health
Psychology, 14, 800–809
63. Brendel, David. 2006. Healing Psychiatry: Bridging the Science/Humanism Divide.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
64. Seigfried, C.H. (2001). Feminist interpretations of John Dewey. University Park:
Pennsylvania State University Press; Seigfried, C.H. (1996). Pragmatism and feminism:
Reweaving the social fabric. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press; Seigfried, C. H.
(1992). Where are all the pragmatists feminists? Hypatia, 6, 8–21.
65. Duran, J. (2001). A holistically Deweyan feminism. Metaphilosophy, 32, 279–292. Duran, J.
(1993). The intersection of pragmatism and feminism. Hypatia, 8
66. Keith, H. (1999). Feminism and pragmatism: George Herbert Mead's ethics of care.
Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 35, 328–344.
67. Whipps, J. D. (2004). Jane Addams social thought as a model for a pragmatist-feminist
communitarianism. Hypatia, 19, 118–113.
68. Seigfried, C.H. (1996). Pragmatism and Feminism: Reweaving the Social Fabric. Chicago:
The University of Chicago Press. p. 21
69. "The Thirteen Pragmatisms (https://books.google.com/books?id=0ATV5bb3ZsQC&pg=PA1
59&lpg=PA159&dq=Arthur+Lovejoy+%22Thirteen+Pragmatisms%22&source=bl&ots=y5fb_
zAjG_&sig=yTplB16a_MPxBvqvJPvEPanm8AA&hl=en&ei=9g5dSpCLBYvysgOW7ZCvCg&
sa=X&oi=book_result&ct=result&resnum=4), The Journal of Philosophy, Psychology, and
Scientific Methods, now The Journal of Philosophy, Part I, 2 January 1908, pp. 5–12. Part II,
16 January 1908, pp. 29–39
70. Bittle, Celestine Nicholas Charles (1936). Reality and the Mind: Epistemology. New York:
The Bruce Publishing Company. OCLC 1017084 (https://www.worldcat.org/oclc/1017084).
71. Putnam, Hilary (December 1992). "The permanence of William James". Bulletin of the
American Academy of Arts and Sciences. 46 (3): 17–31. doi:10.2307/3824783 (https://doi.or
g/10.2307%2F3824783). JSTOR 3824783 (https://www.jstor.org/stable/3824783).
72. Burke, F. Thomas (1994). Dewey's new logic: a reply to Russell. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press. ISBN 0226080692. OCLC 29844394 (https://www.worldcat.org/oclc/298443
94).
73. Goodman, Russell (October 20, 2017). "William James" (https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ja
mes/). In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2017 ed.).
74. Edwards, Paul (1957). "How Bertrand Russell was prevented from teaching at the College
of the City of New York". In Russell, Bertrand (ed.). Why I am not a Christian, and other
essays on religion and related subjects. New York: Simon and Schuster. pp. 207–259 (http
s://books.google.com/books?id=pc0x2bxOSUgC&pg=PA207). ISBN 0671203231.
OCLC 376363 (https://www.worldcat.org/oclc/376363).
75. In: Stanley Fish, There's No Such Thing as Free Speech, Oxford University Press, 1994.
76. Ed. Morris Dickstein, Duke University Press, 1998

Sources
Baldwin, James Mark (ed., 1901–1905), Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology, 3
volumes in 4, Macmillan, New York, NY.
Dewey, John (1900–1901), Lectures on Ethics 1900–1901, Donald F. Koch (ed.), Southern
Illinois University Press, Carbondale and Edwardsville, IL, 1991.
Dewey, John (1910), How We Think, D.C. Heath, Lexington, MA, 1910. Reprinted,
Prometheus Books, Buffalo, NY, 1991.
Dewey, John (1929), The Quest for Certainty: A Study of the Relation of Knowledge and
Action, Minton, Balch, and Company, New York, NY. Reprinted, pp. 1–254 in John Dewey,
The Later Works, 1925–1953, Volume 4: 1929, Jo Ann Boydston (ed.), Harriet Furst Simon
(text. ed.), Stephen Toulmin (intro.), Southern Illinois University Press, Carbondale and
Edwardsville, IL, 1984.
Dewey, John (1932), Theory of the Moral Life, Part 2 of John Dewey and James H. Tufts,
Ethics, Henry Holt and Company, New York, NY, 1908. 2nd edition, Holt, Rinehart, and
Winston, 1932. Reprinted, Arnold Isenberg (ed.), Victor Kestenbaum (pref.), Irvington
Publishers, New York, NY, 1980.
Dewey, John (1938), Logic: The Theory of Inquiry, Henry Holt and Company, New York, NY,
1938. Reprinted, pp. 1–527 in John Dewey, The Later Works, 1925–1953, Volume 12:
1938, Jo Ann Boydston (ed.), Kathleen Poulos (text. ed.), Ernest Nagel (intro.), Southern
Illinois University Press, Carbondale and Edwardsville, IL, 1986.
James, William (1902), "Pragmatic and Pragmatism", 1 paragraph, vol. 2, pp. 321–322 in
J.M. Baldwin (ed., 1901–1905), Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology, 3 volumes in 4,
Macmillan, New York, NY. Reprinted, CP 5.2 in C.S. Peirce, Collected Papers.
James, William (1907), Pragmatism, A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking, Popular
Lectures on Philosophy (http://www.gutenberg.org/etext/5116), Longmans, Green, and
Company, New York, NY.
James, William (1909), The Meaning of Truth, A Sequel to 'Pragmatism (http://www.gutenbe
rg.org/etext/5117), Longmans, Green, and Company, New York, NY.
Lundin, Roger (2006) From Nature to Experience: The American Search for Cultural
Authority (https://www.amazon.com/gp/product/0742521745) Rowman & Littlefield
Publishers, Inc.
Peirce, C.S., Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, vols. 1–6, Charles Hartshorne
and Paul Weiss (eds.), vols. 7–8, Arthur W. Burks (ed.), Harvard University Press,
Cambridge, MA, 1931–1935, 1958. Cited as CP vol.para.
Peirce, C.S., The Essential Peirce, Selected Philosophical Writings, Volume 1 (1867–1893),
Nathan Houser and Christian Kloesel (eds.), Indiana University Press, Bloomington and
Indianapolis, IN, 1992.
Peirce, C.S., The Essential Peirce, Selected Philosophical Writings, Volume 2 (1893–1913),
Peirce Edition Project (eds.), Indiana University Press, Bloomington and Indianapolis, IN,
1998.
Putnam, Hilary (1994), Words and Life, James Conant (ed.), Harvard University Press,
Cambridge, MA.
Quine, W.V. (1951), "Two Dogmas of Empiricism", Philosophical Review (January 1951).
Reprinted, pp. 20–46 in W.V. Quine, From a Logical Point of View, 1980.
Quine, W.V. (1980), From a Logical Point of View, Logico-Philosophical Essays, 2nd edition,
Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1980.
Ramsey, F.P. (1927), "Facts and Propositions", Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume
7, 153–170. Reprinted, pp. 34–51 in F.P. Ramsey, Philosophical Papers, David Hugh Mellor
(ed.), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK, 1990.
Ramsey, F.P. (1990), Philosophical Papers, David Hugh Mellor (ed.), Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge, UK.
Rescher, N. (1977), Methodological Pragmatism, Oxford: Blackwell, 1977.
Rescher, N. (2000), Realistic Pragmatism, Albany, SUNY Press, 2000.

Further reading
Surveys

John J. Stuhr, ed. One Hundred Years of Pragmatism: William James's Revolutionary
Philosophy (Indiana University Press; 2010) 215 pages; Essays on pragmatism and
American culture, pragmatism as a way of thinking and settling disputes, pragmatism as a
theory of truth, and pragmatism as a mood, attitude, or temperament.
Important introductory primary texts
Note that this is an introductory list: some important works are left out and some less monumental works
that are excellent introductions are included.

C. S. Peirce, "The Fixation of Belief" (paper)


C. S. Peirce, "How to Make Our Ideas Clear" (paper)
C. S. Peirce, "A Definition of Pragmatism" (paper as titled by Menand in Pragmatism: A
Reader, from Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce v. 8, some or all of paragraphs
191–195.)
William James, Pragmatism: A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking (especially
lectures I, II and VI)
John Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy (https://books.google.com/books?id=ZUg8AAAA
IAAJ&printsec=frontcover)
John Dewey, "Three Independent factors in Morals" (lecture published as paper)
John Dewey, "A short catechism concerning truth (https://web.archive.org/web/2006123108
4020/http://spartan.ac.brocku.ca/~lward/Dewey/Dewey_1910b/Dewey_1910_06.html)"
(chapter)
W. V. O. Quine, "Two Dogmas of Empiricism (http://www.ditext.com/quine/quine.html)".
(paper)

Secondary texts

Cornelis De Waal, On Pragmatism


Louis Menand, The Metaphysical Club: A Story of Ideas in America
Hilary Putnam, Pragmatism: An Open Question
Abraham Edel, Pragmatic Tests and Ethical Insights (https://web.archive.org/web/20061207
201054/http://crvp.org/book/Series01/I-11/chapter_i.htm)
D. S. Clarke, Rational Acceptance and Purpose
Haack, Susan & Lane, Robert, Eds. (2006). Pragmatism Old and New: Selected Writings.
New York: Prometheus Books.
Louis Menand, ed., Pragmatism: A Reader (includes essays by Peirce, James, Dewey,
Rorty, others)
For a discussion of the ways in which Pragmatism offers insights into the theory and
practice of urbanism, see: Aseem Inam, Designing Urban Transformation New York and
London: Routledge, 2013. (https://www.amazon.com/Designing-Urban-Transformation-Asee
m-Inam/dp/0415837707) ISBN 978-0415837705.

Criticism texts
Edward W. Younkins, Dewey's Pragmatism and the Decline of Education (http://rebirthofrea
son.com/Articles/Younkins/Deweys_Pragmatism_and_the_Decline_of_Education.shtml).
Pragmatism (http://aynrandlexicon.com/lexicon/pragmatism.html), Ayn Rand Lexicon.
Albert Schinz, Anti-Pragmatism: An Examination into the Respective Rights of Intellectual
Aristocracy and Social Democracy. Boston: Small, Maynard and Company, 1909.

Additional bibliography
IEP – Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy (http://www.iep.utm.edu)
SEP – Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (http://plato.stanford.edu)
James Sloan Allen. William James on Habit, Will, Truth, and the Meaning of Life. 2014.
Elizabeth Anderson. Dewey's Moral Philosophy (http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/dewey-mor
al/). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Douglas Browning, William T. Myers (Eds.) Philosophers of Process. 1998.
Robert Burch. Charles Sanders Peirce (http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/peirce/). Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
F. Thomas Burke. What Pragmatism Was (http://www.iupress.indiana.edu/catalog/806840).
2013.
John Dewey. Donald F. Koch (ed.) Lectures on Ethics 1900–1901. 1991.
Daniel Dennett. Postmodernism and Truth (http://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/papers/postmod.tru.
htm). 1998.
John Dewey. The Quest for Certainty: A Study of the Relation of Knowledge and Action.
1929.
John Dewey. Three Independent Factors in Morals. 1930.
John Dewey. The Influence of Darwin on Philosophy and Other Essays (https://web.archive.
org/web/20070126081521/http://spartan.ac.brocku.ca/~lward/Dewey/Dewey_1910b/Dewey
_1910_toc.html). 1910.
John Dewey. Experience & Education. 1938.
Cornelis De Waal. On Pragmatism. 2005.
Raff Donelson. "Ethical Pragmatism" (https://doi.org/10.1111/meta.12253). Metaphilosophy
48(4): 383-403. 2017.
Abraham Edel. Pragmatic Tests and Ethical Insights (https://web.archive.org/web/20061207
201054/http://crvp.org/book/Series01/I-11/chapter_i.htm). In: Ethics at the Crossroads:
Normative Ethics and Objective Reason. George F. McLean, Richard Wollak (eds.) 1993.
Michael Eldridge. Transforming Experience: John Dewey's Cultural Instrumentalism. 1998.
Lorenzo Fabbri. The domestication of Derrida: Rorty, pragmatism and deconstruction (http
s://www.academia.edu/998044/The_Domestication_of_Derrida_Rorty_Pragmatism_and_De
construction). 2008
Richard Field. John Dewey (1859-1952) (http://www.iep.utm.edu/d/dewey.htm#H5). Internet
Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Peter H. Hare, Michel Weber, James K. Swindler, Oana-Maria Pastae, Cerasel Cuteanu
(eds.), International Perspectives on Pragmatism (https://www.academia.edu/280925/Intern
ational_Perspectives_on_Pragmatism), Newcastle upon Tyne, Cambridge Scholars
Publishing, 2009 (ISBN 978-1-4438-0194-2).
David L. Hildebrand. Beyond Realism & Anti-Realism. 2003.
David L. Hildebrand. The Neopragmatist Turn. Southwest Philosophy Review 19(1). 2003.
William James. Pragmatism, A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking, Popular
Lectures on Philosophy (http://www.gutenberg.org/etext/5116). 1907.
William James The Will to Believe (http://arquivo.pt/wayback/20090714151749/http://falcon.j
mu.edu/~omearawm/ph101willtobelieve.html). 1896.
George Lakoff and Mark Johnson. Philosophy in the Flesh : The Embodied Mind and Its
Challenge to Western Thought. 1999.
Todd Lekan. Making Morality: Pragmatist Reconstruction in Ethical Theory. 2003.
C.I. Lewis. Mind and the World Order: Outline of a Theory of Knowledge. 1929.
David Macarthur. "Pragmatism, Metaphysical Quietism and the Problem of Normativity,"
Philosophical Topics Vol. 36 no.1, 2009.
Keya Maitra. On Putnam. 2003.
Joseph Margolis. Historied Thought, Constructed World. 1995.
Louis Menand. The Metaphysical Club. 2001.
Cheryl Misak (ed.) The New Pragmatists. Oxford University Press, 2007
Hilary Putnam Reason, Truth and History. 1981.
W.V.O. Quine. Two Dogmas of Empiricism (http://www.ditext.com/quine/quine.html).
Philosophical Review. January 1951.
W.V.O. Quine Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. 1969.
N. Rescher. Process Philosophy (http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/process-philosophy/). The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Richard Rorty Rorty Truth and Progress: Philosophical Papers. Volume 3. 1998.
Stephen Toulmin. The Uses of Argument. 1958.
Michel Weber (ed.), After Whitehead: Rescher on Process Metaphysics (https://www.acade
mia.edu/279952/After_Whitehead_Rescher_on_Process_Metaphysics), Frankfurt / Paris /
Lancaster, Ontos Verlag, 2004 (ISBN 3-937202-49-8).
Michel Weber, Whitehead's Pancreativism. Jamesian Applications (https://www.academia.e
du/392183/Whiteheads_Pancreativism._Jamesian_Applications), Frankfurt / Paris, Ontos
Verlag, 2011.
William Egginton/Mike Sandbothe (Eds.) The Pragmatic Turn in Philosophy. Contemporary
Engagement between Analytic and Continental Thought. 2004.
Mike Sandbothe. Pragmatic Media Philosophy. 2005.

Papers and online encyclopedias are part of the bibliography. Other sources may include
interviews, reviews and websites.

Gary A. Olson and Stephen Toulmin. Literary Theory, Philosophy of Science, and
Persuasive Discourse: Thoughts from a Neo-premodernist. Interview in JAC 13.2 (https://we
b.archive.org/web/20060901100934/http://jac.gsu.edu/jac/13.2/Articles/1.htm). 1993.
Susan Haack. "Vulgar Rortyism" (https://web.archive.org/web/20181005061750/https://ww
w.newcriterion.com/archive/16/nov97/menand.htm). Review in The New Criterion.
November 1997.
Pietarinen, A. V. "Interdisciplinarity and Peirce's classification of the Sciences: A Centennial
Reassessment," Perspectives on Science, 14(2), 127–152 (2006).

External links
General sources

Pragmatism (https://philpapers.org/browse/pragmatism) at PhilPapers


Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). "Pragmatism" (https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/).
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
"Pragmatism" (http://www.iep.utm.edu/pragmati/). Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Pragmatism (https://inpho.cogs.indiana.edu/idea/461) at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology
Project
Pragmatism (https://www.bbc.co.uk/programmes/p003k9f5) on In Our Time at the BBC
A short film about the pragmatist revival (https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=GlrEbffVVjM)
on YouTube

Journals and organizations

There are several peer-reviewed journals dedicated to pragmatism, for example

Contemporary Pragmatism, affiliated with the International Pragmatism Society (http://intern


ational.pragmatism.org/)
European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy (http://lnx.journalofpragmatism.
eu/), affiliated with the Associazione Culturale Pragma (Italy) (http://www.associazioneprag
ma.com/)
Nordic Studies in Pragmatism (http://www.nordprag.org/nsp/), journal of the Nordic
Pragmatism Network (http://www.nordprag.org/)
Pragmatism Today (http://www.pragmatismtoday.eu/), journal of the Central European
Pragmatist Forum (CEPF) (http://www.cepf.sk/)
Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society (https://web.archive.org/web/2007101106572
4/http://peircesociety.org/transactions.html), journal of the Charles S. Peirce Society (http://
www.peircesociety.org/)
William James Studies (http://williamjamesstudies.org/), journal of the William James
Society (http://www.wjsociety.org/)

Other online resources and organizations

Pragmatist Sociology (https://web.archive.org/web/20160630214911/http://pragmatistsociol


ogy.org/)
Pragmatism Cybrary (http://www.pragmatism.org)
Arisbe: The Peirce Gateway (http://www.cspeirce.org/)
Center for Dewey Studies (https://web.archive.org/web/20041031172701/http://www.siuc.ed
u/~deweyctr/)
Centro de Estudos sobre Pragmatismo (CEP) (http://www.pucsp.br/pragmatismo/) —
Center for Pragmatism Studies (CPS) (http://www.pucsp.br/pos/tidd/ciep/ndexciep.html)
(Brazil)
Charles S. Peirce Studies (http://www.peirce.org/)
Dutch Pragmatism Foundation (http://www.pragmatisme.nl/)
Helsinki Peirce Research Center (http://www.helsinki.fi/peirce/) (Finland), including:
Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms (http://www.helsinki.fi/science/commens/dictiona
ry.html) — see Pragmatism (http://www.helsinki.fi/science/commens/terms/pragmatism.h
tml), Pragmaticism (http://www.helsinki.fi/science/commens/terms/pragmaticism.html),
and Pragmatism: Maxim of (http://www.helsinki.fi/science/commens/terms/pragmatismm
axim.html)
Institute for American Thought (https://web.archive.org/web/20100123080821/http://liberalar
ts.iupui.edu/iat/)
John Dewey Society (http://doe.concordia.ca/jds/)
Neopragmatism.org (http://neopragmatism.org)
Peirce Edition Project (http://www.iupui.edu/~peirce)
Society for the Advancement of American Philosophy (http://www.american-philosophy.org/)

Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Pragmatism&oldid=935392072"

This page was last edited on 12 January 2020, at 08:11 (UTC).

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License; additional terms may apply. By using
this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia
Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.

You might also like