Essence and Existence in The Islamic Eas
Essence and Existence in The Islamic Eas
Essence and Existence in The Islamic Eas
!"#"$%&"'%"((%)*+,)-).")/#01%"#)2)345))6.")/#01%"#)2)345)7
8,&"9"(:"%)-);<=>;?>;>==?
@"#0,%"#&"(A:",)A9)-)B=>BC>;=)BDEFG
Scientia Graeco-Arabica
herausgegeben von
Marwan Rashed
Band 7
De Gruyter
!"#"$%&"'%"((%)*+,)-).")/#01%"#)2)345))6.")/#01%"#)2)345)7
8,&"9"(:"%)-);<=>;?>;>==?
@"#0,%"#&"(A:",)A9)-)B=>BC>;=)BDEFG
De Gruyter
!"#"$%&"'%"((%)*+,)-).")/#01%"#)2)345))6.")/#01%"#)2)345)7
8,&"9"(:"%)-);<=>;?>;>==?
@"#0,%"#&"(A:",)A9)-)B=>BC>;=)BDEFG
ISBN 978-3-11-021575-5
e-ISBN 978-3-11-021576-2
ISSN 1868-7172
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
The Arabic, Hebrew and Latin reception of Avicennas Metaphysics /
edited by Dag Nikolaus Hasse and Amos Bertolacci.
p. cm. ! (Scientia graeco-arabica)
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 978-3-11-021575-5 (hardcover : alk. paper)
1. Avicenna, 980!1037. Ilahiyat. 2. Metaphysics 3. Islamic philosophy. 4. Jewish philosophy. 5. Philosophy, Medieval. I. Hasse,
Dag Nikolaus. II. Bertolacci, Amos.
B751.I483A73 2011
110!dc22
2011007822
!"#"$%&"'%"((%)*+,)-).")/#01%"#)2)345))6.")/#01%"#)2)345)7
8,&"9"(:"%)-);<=>;?>;>==?
@"#0,%"#&"(A:",)A9)-)B=>BC>;=)BDEFG
Contents
Preface . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
Jules Janssens
Al-Lawkars Reception of Ibn Snas Ilahiyyat . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
Robert Wisnovsky
Essence and Existence in the Eleventh- and Twelfth-Century Islamic
East (Masriq): A Sketch . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
27
Stephen Menn
Farab in the Reception of Avicennas Metaphysics: Averroes against
Avicenna on Being and Unity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
51
Peter Adamson
Avicenna and his Commentators on Human and Divine Self-Intellection
97
Heidrun Eichner
Essence and Existence. Thirteenth-Century Perspectives in
Arabic-Islamic Philosophy and Theology . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
123
Mauro Zonta
Avicennas Metaphysics in the Medieval Hebrew Philosophical Tradition
153
Resianne Fontaine
Happy is he whose children are boys: Abraham Ibn Daud and
Avicenna on Evil . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
159
Mauro Zonta
Possible Hebrew Quotations of the Metaphysical Section of Avicennas
Oriental Philosophy and Their Historical Meaning . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
177
Amos Bertolacci
On the Latin Reception of Avicennas Metaphysics before Albertus
Magnus: An Attempt at Periodization . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
197
225
Kara Richardson
Avicenna and Aquinas on Form and Generation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
251
!"#"$%&"'%"((%)*+,)-).")/#01%"#)2)345))6.")/#01%"#)2)345)7
8,&"9"(:"%)-);<=>;?>;>==?
@"#0,%"#&"(A:",)A9)-)B=>BC>;=)BDEFG
VIII
Contents
Pasquale Porro
Immateriality and Separation in Avicenna and Thomas Aquinas . . . . .
275
Gabriele Galluzzo
Two Senses of Common. Avicennas Doctrine of Essence and Aquinass
View on Individuation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
309
Martin Pickav!
On the Latin Reception of Avicennas Theory of Individuation . . . . .
339
Giorgio Pini
Scotus and Avicenna on What it is to Be a Thing . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
365
389
Index of Names . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
395
!"#"$%&"'%"((%)*+,)-).")/#01%"#)2)345))6.")/#01%"#)2)345)7
8,&"9"(:"%)-);<=>;?>;>==?
@"#0,%"#&"(A:",)A9)-)B=>BC>;=)BDEFG
1
2
Earlier versions of this paper were presented at the American Philosophical Association,
Eastern Division Meeting, New York (December 2005); at the conference entitled The
Arabic, Hebrew and Latin reception of Avicennas metaphysics, Centro Italo-Tedesco
Villa Vigoni, Menaggio, Italy (July 2008); and as part of McGills Philosophy Department Colloquium series (November 2009). I am grateful for the feedback I received
on those three occasions, as well as to the students and colleagues who participated in
two graduate seminars: the first, at Harvard in 1998, was devoted to issues of ontology in
Islamic philosophy; the second, at McGill in 2009, was devoted specifically to Suhraward. More particularly, Heidrun Eichner first helped me work through Razs position
and graciously shared photocopies of relevant manuscripts that she had acquired; and
Reza Pourjavady and Stephen Menn each made crucial suggestions that largely shaped
the final form of my argument. Needless to say, all mistakes are my own.
Suhraward, Hikmat al-israq, I.3, 59, p. 46,8-ult.
ikmat al-israq I.3, 56, p. 45,1-ult., and 60, p. 47, 1 13. The term
Suhraward, H
i tibar is difficult
to translate into English. In his extended discussion of this issue, T.
Izutsu cites the famous passage in the Madhal (Isagoge) section of the Mantiq (Logic) of
(mahiyya)
Avicenna claims that quiddity
Avicennas Kitab as-Sifa (The Healing) where
has three i tibarat: as a universal existing in the mind; as an essence existing in a concrete
individual; and taken in and of itself, i. e., as neutral with respect to either mental or
concrete existence. In light of this passage, and in light of Suhrawards uses of the term
in the Hikmat al-israq, Izutsu takes i tibar to mean a subjective manner of looking at
a thing, something produced or posited through the analytic work of the reason. It is an
aspect of a thing which primarily appears in the subject and which, then, is projected
onto the thing itself as if it were an objective aspect of the thing. See T. Izutsu, The
Distinction between essentia and existentia, pp. 49 70 at 65. The Avicenna passage is
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
Bereitgestelltvon|DeGruyter/TCS(DeGruyter/TCS)
Angemeldet|172.16.1.226
Heruntergeladenam|02.03.1209:57
28
of existence, his view was later used as an essentialist foil by Mulla Sadra and
other members of that school of Islamic metaphysics which saw itself as
upholding the fundamentality of existence (asalat al-wugud).3
Kitab as-Sifa /Mantiq (1): al-Madhal I.2, p. 15,1 7. J. Walbridge translates i tibarat
4
5
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
Robert Wisnovsky
Bereitgestelltvon|DeGruyter/TCS(DeGruyter/TCS)
Angemeldet|172.16.1.226
Heruntergeladenam|02.03.1209:57
29
what he is clearly referring to in this passage is the extra existence that God, who
is above perfection (fawqa tamam), does not need for Himself and which He
therefore passes on to other, lower beings.6
In a broader sense, Avicennas ontology could doubtless be interpreted as
implying the thesis that existence is superadded to (za id ala) a things quiddity.
As I have discussed extensively in other publications, Avicennas general position
on essence (or quiddity) and existence is that essence and existence are
extensionally identical but intensionally distinct. In other words, every essence
must either be an individual existing in the concrete, extramental world (f
l-a yan), or a universal existing in the mind (f d-dihn). Even so, essence and
existent have different meanings: essence refers to what a thing is, whereas
existence refers to the fact that a thing is. More important for my discussion here
is the series of hints, given by Avicenna, that despite the fact that essence and
existence are co-implied (the term he uses in Kitab as-Sifa /Ilahiyyat I.5 is
mutalazimani), essence nevertheless enjoys some kind of logical priority over
existence. The sense that essence is logically prior to existence is conveyed by
among other clues Avicennas frequent uses of the terms lazim (is logically
entailed [by]), arid (attaches accidentally [to]), lahiq (is a concomitant [of ])
[to]) to describe how existence
connects to essence.7 An
and mudaf (is related
6
7
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
Bereitgestelltvon|DeGruyter/TCS(DeGruyter/TCS)
Angemeldet|172.16.1.226
Heruntergeladenam|02.03.1209:57
30
1184 for Transoxania, where he wrote most of the works in which he claims
that existence is superadded to essence; and because Suhraward finished his
Hikmat al-israq in 582/1186, it is unlikely that Raz himself was in Suhrawards
sights. But regardless of the identity of the particular person whom Suhraward
l as well as Razs father and his As arite circle in
saw himself as opposing (G
Rayy present themselves as possibilities, but further research will be needed in
order to determine this), Suhrawards arguments in favor of the conceptual
nature of existence clearly recapitulate an earlier attack, by the mathematicianpoet Umar Hayyam (d. 517/1123), against the tendency of certain As arite
uwayn (d. 478/1085), to appeal
mutakallimun, such as Imam al-Haramayn al-G
to the theory of modes (ahwal) a theory associated with the Basran Mu tazilite
ubba (d. 321/933) and his followers, the
mutakallim Abu Hasim al-G
Bahsamites as the best way to construe and promote Avicennas concept of
existence.
To begin this story, I must turn first to Avicenna himself. Avicennas two key
metaphysical distinctions were between essence (or more properly, quiddity,
mahiyya) and existence (wugud); and between the necessary of existence in itself
(wagib al-wugud bi-datihi) and the necessary of existence through another
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
Robert Wisnovsky
Ibid.
Bereitgestelltvon|DeGruyter/TCS(DeGruyter/TCS)
Angemeldet|172.16.1.226
Heruntergeladenam|02.03.1209:57
31
existence, al-wugud al-harig). But unlike As ar, who maintained that thing and
(Philosophy for Arud) to its final appearance in the Isarat. More directly relevant
to this chapter is the fact that in addition to articulating each of these two
distinctions in slightly different ways in books that he wrote at various points in
his life, Avicenna appears to have bound the two distinctions more closely
together as his ideas developed over time.9 Thus in the very early al-Hikma al
Arudiyya, the distinction between essence and existence had hardly crystallized,
Ibn Sna, Kitab as-Sifa /Ilahiyyat (1), I.5, pp. 31,5 33,18 and I.6, pp. 37,7 38,5.
Ibn Sna, Kitab as-Sifa /Ilahiyyat (2), VIII.4, pp. 343,10 347,16.
Ibn Sna, Kitab al-Isarat wa-t-tanbhat, pp. 138,2 139,13 and pp. 140,12 141,2.
9
10
11
12
13
14
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
Bereitgestelltvon|DeGruyter/TCS(DeGruyter/TCS)
Angemeldet|172.16.1.226
Heruntergeladenam|02.03.1209:57
32
Why did Avicenna decide to bind the two distinctions together in his
middle and later works? I maintain that it is because he realized, during the
process of writing the Ilahiyyat of the Sifa , that he could use the intensional
distinctiveness between quiddity and existence to show how beings other than
God were composites, that is, composed of quiddity and existence. God, by
contrast, could be held to be simple by virtue of the identity of quiddity and
existence in Him. Because every composite needs a composer to bring its
components together, and because of the impossibility of an infinite regress, the
chain of composites and composers must originate in a non-composite
composer, namely, God. Partly because Avicennas use of the quiddity-existence
distinction to support the intrinsically necessary-extrinsically necessary distinction was most obvious in the Isarat, and partly because of that works
abbreviated and allusive style, which invites decompression and commentary,
the Isarat received more attention from subsequent Muslim philosophers
(including the mutakallimun) than any other of Avicennas writings at least
until the sixteenth century CE, when the attention of commentators shifted to
the Sifa .
Avicennas pressing of the essence-existence distinction into the service of his
intrinsically necessary-extrinsically necessary distinction was a crucial event
in the history of metaphysics. This is because it provided a method of
distinguishing God from both eternal and non-eternal beings that was based on
Gods simplicity and all other beings compositeness; and because, when
understood as the Necessary of Existence in itself, whose essence is not even
conceptually distinct from its existence, Avicennas God enjoyed a more
watertight simplicity than that of the Neoplatonists, whose God as One could be
held to be conceptually distinguishable from their God as Good. 15 As will
become apparent, Fahraddn ar-Razs ontology can be seen as a continuation of
Theological Ramifications
To be sure, it was not Avicennas proof of Gods existence from the
distinctiveness (and hence compositeness) of essence and existence in all beings
other than the Necessary of Existence in itself, which first made Avicennas
metaphysics attractive to Sunni mutakallimun (specifically, those of the As arite
and Maturdite schools) from the two or three generations immediately
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
Robert Wisnovsky
15 On this see my Final and Efficient Causality in Avicennas Cosmology and Theology,
pp. 97 123, and Avicennas Metaphysics in Context, pp. 181 95.
Bereitgestelltvon|DeGruyter/TCS(DeGruyter/TCS)
Angemeldet|172.16.1.226
Heruntergeladenam|02.03.1209:57
33
following his death. Instead, it was the use that they could make of Avicennas
distinction between intrinsically and extrinsically necessary existence in order to
solve some serious problems with their theology, and particularly with their
conception of how Gods attributes (sifat) were related to the divine self (dat).
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
Bereitgestelltvon|DeGruyter/TCS(DeGruyter/TCS)
Angemeldet|172.16.1.226
Heruntergeladenam|02.03.1209:57
34
uniqueness. For if Gods attributes were meaningfully distinct from Gods self
in this case, distinct enough that each of the attributes could itself be seen as a
subject of which the predicate eternal holds then the attributes would share
the quality of eternality with Gods self, and a picture would emerge of a
pleroma of eternal, and hence quasi-independent, divine beings, rather than of a
single God, isolated in His sole possession of eternality. In a vain attempt to preempt this Mu tazilite critique, early Sunnis tended to stick to Ibn Kullabs
formula neither identical to God nor other than Him (la hiya llahu wa-la hiya
gayruhu).19
The first problem facing Sunni mutakallimun, therefore, was that Gods
eternality did double-service, both as a first-order predicate of Gods self and as
a second-order predicate of Gods other attributes. As soon as the other
attributes themselves became subjects of which eternal was predicated, God no
longer enjoyed the complete isolation He had before, since each of His eternal
attributes had become sufficiently real and distinct that Sunni theology had
opened itself up to the criticism of polytheism. Just as serious was the danger of
positing an infinite regress of eternalities. For if each attribute is eternal, is it
eternal in itself, or through a further eternality? If the Sunni mutakallim answers
that each attribute is eternal in itself, then he will have made an explicit claim
that the attributes really are independent entities in their own right, and this in
turn will provide his Mu tazilite competitor with clear evidence of polytheism.
But if an eternal attribute is eternal through yet another eternality, then each of
the second-order meta-eternalities will itself be eternal through a third-order
eternality, and an infinite regress will ensue.20
uwayn and other
As if this first challenge was not enough of a headache, G
Sunni mutakallimun had to address another weakness. The traditional kalam
proof of Gods existence relied on the contradictory nature of the opposition
between eternal (qadm) and originated (muhdat). Since everything that is
originated needs an originator (muhdit) to bring it into existence, and since an
infinite series of originators and originated things is impossible, the chain of
originators and originated things will originate in an originator that is not itself
originated; and since everything in the world is either eternal or originated, this
non-originated originator will be eternal. That eternal originator is God. This
proof worked fine for the Mu tazilites, who, as mentioned above, collapsed
Gods attributes into the divine self.21 But the Sunnis commitment to the
21 See, for example, the Basran Mu tazilite Abd al-Gabbars (d. 415/1025) description of
ubba s (d. 303/915) position, in al-Mugn f abwab athis predecessor Abu Al al-G
tawhd wa-l- adl, V, p. 233,5.
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
Robert Wisnovsky
Bereitgestelltvon|DeGruyter/TCS(DeGruyter/TCS)
Angemeldet|172.16.1.226
Heruntergeladenam|02.03.1209:57
35
eternality of the divine attributes entailed that God, for them, was not the only
eternal thing in the universe: the divine attributes were eternal too. This meant
that the Sunnis found themselves with a category of beings the divine
attributes that were in one sense eternal but which were not themselves
originators. With the sudden appearance of this shadowy middle ground, the
traditional proof no longer works, since the opposition between eternal and
originated is now one between contraries, not between contradictories.22 If the
proof is to work, there must be an identity between eternal and non-originated
originator; but now there seem to be eternal, non-originated things the divine
attributes that are not originators.
Faced with philosophical challenges such as these, it is not surprising that
uwayn desperately sought tools to
Sunni mutakallimun such as Baqillan and G
help them confront or at least side-step the problematic implications of their
doctrinal commitments. One of those tools was Avicennas distinction between
intrinsically and extrinsically necessary existence. Since necessity can be
construed as modifying the predication itself, as opposed to serving as a
second-order attribute in the way eternality had, Sunni mutakallimun could
come up with a new formula that did not predicate second-order attributes of
the first-order attributes, and hence was in less danger of inadvertently positing
the attributes as subjects or selves. Thus a Sunni mutakallim could assert the
modal propositions God is necessarily an existent and God is necessarily a
knower, and thereby avoid stating that God is necessary and Gods knowledge
is necessary a pair of attributions that would create the same infinite-regress
problem with necessity that God is eternal and Gods knowledge is eternal had
created earlier with eternality.23 Nevertheless, the new formulas raised further
challenges, one of which was explaining how the divine attribute of existence
(wugud) connected to the divine self or essence (dat) in such a way that it
Bereitgestelltvon|DeGruyter/TCS(DeGruyter/TCS)
Angemeldet|172.16.1.226
Heruntergeladenam|02.03.1209:57
22 As the As arite mutakallim al-Baqillan (d. 403/1013) appears to admit; see his Kitab atTamhd, pp. 29,17 30,2.
uwayn, as-Samil f usul ad-dn, p. 292,19 20, p. 308,9 10,
23 See, for example, al-G
uwayn credits Baqillan for this move);
p. 358,11 13 and p. 365,7 11 (where G
al- Aqda an-nizamiyya, p. 23,4 5; and Luma f qawa id ahl as-sunna wa-l-gama a,
p. 137,9 10.
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
36
when the event described by the verb is taking place. Thinking of a divine
attribute as a hal, as a mode which describes God in His act of being, allowed
Abu Hasim to hold (unlike the early Mu tazilites) that Gods being powerful
(kawnuhu qadiran) is semantically distinct from, say, His being alive (kawnuhu
hayyan), just as the hal riding in Smith came riding (ga a Zaydun rakiban) is
semantically distinct from the hal walking in Smith came walking (ga a
Zaydun masiyan); but without implying (as the Sunnis had) the separate
existence of real entities such as power and life or riding and walking.
In recent decades, scholars focus has extended from the theological
motivations and implications of mode theory to its ontological motivations and
uwaynis prime concern in appropriating
implications.24 Similarly, although G
aspects of Bahsamite (i. e., Abu Hasims) mode-theory was theological rather
than ontological, his appropriation had implications beyond an analysis of the
uwaynis most extensive
relationship between Gods self and His attributes. G
discussion of modes comes in his Kitab al-Irsad, where he states baldly that The
mode is an attribute which belongs to an existent and which is [itself ] qualified
uwayn held that
by neither existence or non-existence.25 To be precise, G
knowledge, power and speech are real objects (ma an) that are possessed by a
being God and in which the modes (ahwal) being-a-knower, being
24 See A. Alami, Lontologie modale; the classic treatments are by R. Frank, Abu Hashims
Theory of States, and more generally, Beings and Their Attributes; and most
comprehensively as well as most comprehensibly, H. Wolfson, The Philosophy of the
Kalam, pp. 167 234.
25 Cf. al-Irsad f usul al-i tiqad, transl. and ed. J. Luciani, Paris, 1938, p. 80,6 13 and
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
Robert Wisnovsky
Bereitgestelltvon|DeGruyter/TCS(DeGruyter/TCS)
Angemeldet|172.16.1.226
Heruntergeladenam|02.03.1209:57
37
powerful and being-a-speaker are grounded (mu allala). While the attributes
understood as ma an really exist in the being that possesses them, the attributes
understood as ahwal are neither existent nor non-existent.
(lazim) of the
accidental ( arad) to it; that which is a necessary concomitant
characterized thing, and that which is not; and last but not least, that which is
separable from the characterized thing only in the faculty of estimation (mufariq
bi-l-wahm) that is, conceptually and that which is separable in the faculty of
estimation as well as in (concrete) existence (mufariq bi-l-wahm wa-bi-lwugud).27
This last division of attributes is most relevant to my argument, because it
lays the ground for Hayyams distinction between attributes that are conceptual
are existential (wugud). Existential attributes are real in
(i tibar) and those that
the sense that they exist concretely in the characterized thing, whereas
conceptual attributes are not real, because they do not exist concretely in the
characterized thing, but instead attach to it only in our minds. Hayyams
with
example of an existential-accidental ( arad wugud) attribute is black
attribution
uwayns hal) is an existential
that black (i. e., corresponding to G
uwayns ma na) is
(wasf wugud), whereas blackness (i. e., corresponding to G
an existential attribute (sifa wugudiyya). Hayyam takes the real existence of this
26 Umar Hayyam, Risala f l-wugud, ed. R. Ridazada-yi Malik, pp. 398,9 403,10. This
Bereitgestelltvon|DeGruyter/TCS(DeGruyter/TCS)
Angemeldet|172.16.1.226
Heruntergeladenam|02.03.1209:57
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
38
grounded.
However, when he treats the type of attribute he calls essential-conceptual
uwayn. Hayyams example is being-a(dat i tibar), Hayyam departs from G
color,
for blackness.
Hayyam reasons that colorness
(lawniyya) is not an
as blackness is indeed
something superadded, in concrete reality, to the black
thing itself (fa-amma l-qismu l-wugudiyyu l- aradiyyu fa-huwa ka-wasfi l-gismi bi wugudiyyatun ay huwa
za idun ala dati l-aswadi mawgudun f l-a yani). But in the case of a conceptual
essential attribute
such as the fact that blackness is a color, the attribute colorness
is not an attribute superadded in concrete reality to the blackness itself (waamma l-qismu l-i tibariyyu d-datiyyu fa-huwa ka-wasfi s-sawadi bi-annahu
bi-sifatin za idatin ala
dati s-sawadiyyati f
lawnunwal-lawniyyatu laysat
l-a yani). Hayyam proceeds directly to criticizing those who neglect this crucial
distinction between conceptual and existential attributions:
Those investigating this topic who do not take these conceptual attributions [awsaf
i tibariyya] into account have erred very far indeed, as is the case with some reckless
moderns [al-muta assifna l-muta ahhirna], who posit colorness and accidentality
and existence [my italics] and similar states as modes (ahwal) that obtain in what can
be characterized by neither existence or non-existence. The doubt that makes them
fall into this grave mistake pertains to the greatest of First Premises: that there is no
middle ground between negation and affirmation, the self-evident nature of which
needs no discussion by us, nor is there any way for idiots to contradict it or explain
it away.28
of the
insistence in another treatise that Avicenna
is to be regarded as the best
29
Modern [philosophers] (afdal al-muta ahhirn); given that Hayyam is
(admittedly,
one who is known forembellishdescribed by a bio-bibliographer
ing his notices with apocrycphal anecdotes) as having gotten himself into
trouble by defending Avicenna against Abu l-Barakat al-Bagdads (d. 560/1165)
attacks;30 and given that Avicenna himself attacked the Mu tazilite conception of
See al-Bayhaqs notice on Ala ad-Dawla Faramarz, King of Yazd, in Tatimmat siwan al
hikma, pp. 110,7 111,11.
28
29
30
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
Robert Wisnovsky
Bereitgestelltvon|DeGruyter/TCS(DeGruyter/TCS)
Angemeldet|172.16.1.226
Heruntergeladenam|02.03.1209:57
39
ahwal for violating the law of the excluded middle;31 Hayyams use of ahwal
by implication ma an) in the passage above makes it likely that his target
(and
and non-existence. For example, Ibn Hazm (d. 456/1064), a Magrib near uwayn (and thus almost certainly referring here to alcontemporary of G
Baqillan), stated in his Fisal that One piece of As arite nonsense is their claim
that people can believe in modes and objects (al-ma an) which are neither
existent nor non-existent.33 One generation after Umar Hayyam, as-Sahrastan,
Guwayns pupils were among Hayyams rivals for Selguq infrastructure-funding, with
some money from the Selguq court going to the new Nizamiyya madrasas (where
uwayn was employed), and other Selguq money going to Malik-Sahs new observatory
G
in Isfahan (where Hayyam was employed).
wa-l-ahwa wa-n-nihal, no ed., (Cairo: 1317 1327 H.), vol. IV,
33 Kitab al-Fisal f l-milal
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
Bereitgestelltvon|DeGruyter/TCS(DeGruyter/TCS)
Angemeldet|172.16.1.226
Heruntergeladenam|02.03.1209:57
40
(i tibar dihn).36 In the Nihaya Sahrastan also reports that Baqillan and
uwayn appropriated Abu Hasims mode-theory; and in the Milal he
G
complains that mode-theory is vulnerable to al-As ars own criticism that
ahwal violate the law of the excluded middle.37
and Guwayn and Qad Abd al-Gabbar from among the As arites (sic; Abd al
abbar is almost certainly
G
a mistaken scribal insertion after Qad, which in
because only one of Gls writings, a treatise on the fourth figure of the syllogism,
appears to have survived) followed the late trend in Avicennas metaphysics
towards pressing the essence/existence distinction into the service of the
intrinsically necessary/extrinsically necessary distinction. Motivated by his desire
to reinforce the compositeness of contingent beings by hardening the distinction
between essence and existence in them, by his Sunni theological commitment to
the distinctiveness between self (or quiddity) and attribute, and by his
commitment to the univocity of existence (on which more below), Raz recast
vol. II, pp. 458,19 459,1; at Abkar al-afkar, vol. II, p. 604,6 9, Amid claims
that
Baqillan flip-flopped on the issue of the ahwal, sometimes affirming them and other
to Hayyams discussion, al-Amid groups
times denying them. In an apparent reference
are superadded to quiddity: G
ayat
wugud with lawniyya on the basis of the fact that both
al-maram p. 32,4 6, and Abkar al-afkar, vol. II, p. 607,5 8. Razs and Suhrawards
Magrib contemporary Ibn Rusd (d. 595/1198) says in his Tahafut at-Tahafut that those
who reject modes (al-ahwal) reject the belief in existence in general and color in general,
modes say that existence in general and color in general are
whereas those who affirm
neither existent nor non-existent: Tahafut at-Tahafut, vol. III, ed. M. Bouyges, Beirut,
1930, p. 258,10 11; cited by Wolfson, Philosophy of the Kalam, pp. 170 171.
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
Robert Wisnovsky
Bereitgestelltvon|DeGruyter/TCS(DeGruyter/TCS)
Angemeldet|172.16.1.226
Heruntergeladenam|02.03.1209:57
41
40 For a discussion of Razs writings and his intellectual development, see A. Shihadeh,
From al-Ghazal to al-Raz, pp. 141 79; Shihadeh offers a chronology in his The
Teleological Ethics of Fakhr al-Dn al-Raz, pp. 4 11. As Shihadeh admits, his chronology
is tentative because it is based mainly on internal cross-references in Razs writings,
references that may have been inserted not during the actual composition of a given
work, but at a later date, when Raz was revising that work. Developments in Razs ethics
are treated in Shihadehs book passim.
41 To my knowledge the only extended discussion of the development of Razs ontology is
M. A. Zarrukan, Fahraddn ar-Raz wa-ara uhu al-kalamiyyah wa-l-falsafiyyah, Cairo,
1963, pp. 170 74; cited by the editors of two of Razs works: Sarh al-Isarat wa-ttanbhat, ed. Nagafzadeh, pp. 47 51 and al-Mabahit al-masriqiyyah, ed. M.M. al are Sarh al-Isarat wa-t-tanbhat,
Bagdad, p. 114, n. 1. The passages I am summarizing
and pp. 199,4 204,7;
no ed. [ad Namat 4: F al-wugud wa- ilalihi], pp. 190,7 192,13
ad-dn, pp. 53,22 58,20; and ar-Risalat al-kamaliyya f l-haqa iq al-ilahiyya, pp. 33,5
34,19.
42 Although see Asas at-taqds (The Basis for Glorifying [God]), p. 89,8 17, for an attack on
the Karramiyyas claim of strong univocity between the visible (as-sahid) and the invisible
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
Bereitgestelltvon|DeGruyter/TCS(DeGruyter/TCS)
Angemeldet|172.16.1.226
Heruntergeladenam|02.03.1209:57
42
the Kullabite line by arguing, against Avicenna and the Mu tazilites, that Gods
existence, like the other divine attributes, cannot simply be subsumed in the
divine self. But Raz also argues, in open opposition this time to As ar, that the
existence of each being is distinct from its quiddity. Raz outlines three possible
positions on the relation between existence and quiddity, positions that he takes to
be exhaustive. The first possible position is that (a) existence is identical to
quiddity (al-wugud nafs al-mahiyya or al-wugud dat al-mahiyya); the second is
that (b) existence is extrinsic to quiddity (al-wugud harig an al-mahiyya); and the
general;43 and position (c) to no one, it being just a logical possibility.44 Raz then
argues as follows in favor of position (b):
i. quiddity (mahiyya) is the principle of difference;
ii. existence (wugud) is the principle of identity, on the basis of the Avicennian
doctrine which Raz accepts and promotes that all beings share
existence, or have existence in common (musarakat al-wugud);
iii. given i and ii, existence will not be identical to quiddity, and hence position
(a) is incorrect;
iv. given i and ii, existence will not be part of quiddity, and hence position (c)
is incorrect;
v. given that positions (a), (b) and (c) are the only possible positions, and
given that positions (a) and (c) are incorrect, it follows that position (b) is
correct, and that existence is therefore extrinsic to quiddity.
(al-ga ib). For a brief but helpful sketch of how the distinction between istirak ma naw
and istirak lafz maps onto the distinction between univocal and equivocal, see T. Mayer,
Fakhr ad-Dn ar-Razs Critique, n. 48.
43 It is possible that in articulating position (b) as al-wugud harig an al-mahiyya, Raz may
have thought he was reverting to a classical Avicennian formula, since in addition to
appearing in the Ta lqat passage mentioned earlier, the same phrase is used by Avicennas
favorite student, Bahmanyar, in his Tahsl (viz., fa-inna kawna l-wugudi ma nan harigan
(p. 77,2122),
Raz quotes
Avicenna as denying that existence is intrinsic to (dahil f)
essence. In his Epitome of the Metaphysics (I, pp. 34 43 and III, pp. 34 48), Averroes
cites Aristotle, Metaph. 3, as denying that being and unity are parts of the being of a
thing.
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
Robert Wisnovsky
Bereitgestelltvon|DeGruyter/TCS(DeGruyter/TCS)
Angemeldet|172.16.1.226
Heruntergeladenam|02.03.1209:57
43
Razi further asserts that the correct way to articulate position (b) the position
that existence is extrinsic to quiddity is that existence is superadded to
quiddity (za id ala l-mahiyya). Raz clearly sees himself as extrapolating from,
and in some sense systematizing, Avicennas ontology. In his Commentary on the
Pointers I.11, Raz interprets the term mudaf (related [to]), which Avicenna
had used in the passage being commented upon to describe how existence is
connected to quiddity, in a stronger and less neutral sense, as superadded:
Given Razs hard line on the univocity of existence, and given his apparent
desire to oppose Mu tazilite theology by placing himself in the Kullabite
tradition of holding that the divine attributes are somehow meaningfully
distinct from the divine self, we should not be surprised by his argument that in
the case of God, as with other beings, existence is also distinct from and
superadded to quiddity. But in contrast to a contingent being, which needs a
cause to bring its quiddity and existence together, Gods quiddity is sufficient to
cause its own existence.46
It is worth noting that Razs position is in direct opposition to the doctrine
of his school founder, As ar. As ar held that in created beings, quiddity and
existence were intensionally as well as extensionally identical; and by some
accounts As ar also treated the attribute of existence as an exception to Kullabite
attribute-theory, by maintaining that in the case of God, too, quiddity and
existence were intensionally as well as extensionally identical. Razs departure
from As ar is perhaps less surprising than it might first appear, since in the 12th
century, when Raz was active, the strong identification of essence and existence
was associated with a newly formed branch of the Mu tazilites as well as with
As ar. These Mu tazilites were the followers of Abu l-Husayn al-Basr (d. 436/
(p. 76,1415) that we have discussed in our other books decisive proofs
that Gods
essence (haqqa) is identical to His existence (wugud).
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
Bereitgestelltvon|DeGruyter/TCS(DeGruyter/TCS)
Angemeldet|172.16.1.226
Heruntergeladenam|02.03.1209:57
44
Qad Abdalgabbar (d. 415/1025), and they subjected it to many of the same
critiques that Hayyam and Sahrastan and others had directed at the
such as Baqillan and G
uwayn.47
Bahsamizing Sunnis
What might Razs motivations have been for embracing Avicennas
ontology in the case of contingent beings, while rejecting it in the case of
God? Raz may have been unconvinced by Avicennas radical understanding of
divine simplicity, which Avicenna safeguards by completely identifying essence
and existence in God. For Avicenna, Gods simplicity, and thus His noncompositeness, ensures that He is the only uncaused being, in contrast to all
other beings, whose composition of essence and existence requires a composer
and hence a cause. For Avicenna, in other words, Gods simplicity explained His
causal self-sufficiency, His immunity from causedness. But Gods causal
productivity, His causation of other beings, was another matter. At most, it
could be said that on Avicennas account, Gods being wagib al-wugud (necessary
of existence) conveyed a weak form of transitivity that was perhaps implicit in
the active participle wagib (necessary). But even if we were to construe wagib as
synonymous with the more clearly transitive fourth-form active participle mugib
(necessitating), the kind of transitivity conveyed by w-g-b remained one of
syllogistic necessitation rather than one of causal production let alone one of
voluntary agency. And Gods necessitating the world just as a true premise
necessitates the conclusion that follows from it, was not a robust enough notion
of divine causation for Raz. Avicennas theology immunized God from
causedness very convincingly. But it made Gods causation of the world too
automatic, too mechanistic. By contrast, holding as Raz does that Gods
quiddity is sufficient to cause His existence, allowed God to retain His attribute
of will (irada) and thereby be plausibly seen as a voluntary agent (fa il) rather
than as a necessitator. In sum, while Raz adopts Avicennas ontology, he rejects
Avicennas theology by maintaining that Gods quiddity is not identical to His
existence.
With this Razan background in our minds, we can now turn back to
Suhraward, from whence we started, and examine, with fresh eyes, his critique
of the notion of existence put forward by the followers of the Peripatetics. To
recapitulate: given that Avicenna was not explicitly committed to the thesis that
47 See Ibn al-Malahim, Kitab al-Fa iq f usul ad-dn, pp. 46,3 48,ult. (F anna wuguda
s-say i hal huwa datuhu aw halatun zaidatun ala datihi) and pp. 68,10 76,15 (F
by Samarqand
as
al-mutakallimn f r-radd ala l-falasifa, pp. 61,19 62,19. As ar is cited
holding the view that in God essence and existence are identical: as-Saha if al-Ilahiyya,
p. 298,56.
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
Robert Wisnovsky
Bereitgestelltvon|DeGruyter/TCS(DeGruyter/TCS)
Angemeldet|172.16.1.226
Heruntergeladenam|02.03.1209:57
45
such as Guwayn and Raz. Not only does Suhraward, like Hayyam, deny that
reality; he later
existence is an attribute superadded to quiddity in concrete
reproduces Hayyams distinction between attributes that are merely conceptual
that are real as well as conceptual.48 In a brief passage in his
and attributes
Talwhat, Suhraward also attacks the theory of modes, on the basis of its
of the law of the excluded middle; and the example he gives of a
violation
mental construct (i tibar dihn) that falls into this trap is colorness (lawniyya)
the same example that Hayyam had given before him. Finally, Suhraward
Bereitgestelltvon|DeGruyter/TCS(DeGruyter/TCS)
Angemeldet|172.16.1.226
Heruntergeladenam|02.03.1209:57
48 fa-idani s-sifatu kulluha tanqasimu ila qismayni sifatin ayniyyatin wa laha suratun f l- aqli
ifatin
wuguduha f l- ayni laysa illa nafsuwugudiha f d-dihni wa-laysa
laha f gayri
wa-s
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
46
famously places his main attack on the conception of existence put forward by
the followers of the Peripatetics, in the section of his Hikmat al-israq that is
too may have been
devoted to exposing sophistries and logical fallacies. This
anticipated by Hayyam, given the prominent appearance of hadayan (bab 49 Avicenna
art in Arabic sophistics, in Hayyams discussion.
bling), a term of
also uses h-d-y (specifically, ma hadaw bihi min aqawlihim) in a well known
Ilahiyyat I.5 of his Sifa , when referring to the Mu tazilites
passage from
inconsistency on the issue of whether a non-existent (ma dum) is a thing (say ).50
These Avicennian uses of h-d-y, and particularly that contained in the
to have a common
Risalat al-Wugud. For Hayyam and Avicenna appear
target:
those who commit some sophism by, in this case, violating the law of the
excluded middle. In Avicennas case, it is the early Mu tazilites whose nonexistent thing neither is nor is not. In Hayyams case, it is the Bahsamizing
As arites, whose position that existence is superadded to quiddity entails that
existence be construed as a mode (hal) (or more precisely, the grounds [ma na]
49 Risala f l-wugud 401,11. H-d-y is one of a cluster of roots (the others are h-d-r, h-t-r, h-g
r, h-m-z and h-m-r) used to render
Aristotles term !dokeswe?m, for example in Yahya ibn
Ads translation of Aristotle, Sophistical Refutations (SE 3:165b15): see, ad loc., Mant
iq
Aristu, vol. III, ed. A. Badaw. In the corresponding section of the Safsata (Sophistics)of
his Sifa (I.1, 7,5), Avicenna paraphrases Aristotle but uses the terms al-had
ayan wa-t
takrr; Kitab as-Sifa /Mantiq (6): as-Safsata, ed. A.F. al-Ahwan; see also SE 13:173a31
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
Robert Wisnovsky
Bereitgestelltvon|DeGruyter/TCS(DeGruyter/TCS)
Angemeldet|172.16.1.226
Heruntergeladenam|02.03.1209:57
47
and criticizing those skeptics for recklessness (ta assuf ) the same flaw that
Hayyam had seen in the Bahsamizing Sunni mutakallimun. 51
Conclusion
The two opposing positions on this issue largely determined the metaphysical
doctrines of the following century. Razs Avicennian understanding of existence
as something superadded to quiddity is embraced in toto by as-Samarqand (fl.
ca. 690/1291) and al-Baydaw (d. ca. 716/1312), who follow Raz in ontology
as well as in theology; and Razs ontology (though not his theology) is accepted
by al-Qazwn al-Katib (d. 675/1276) as well as by al-Abhar (663/1264), at
least during one phase of his career.52 As was seen above, Suhrawards
commentators Ibn Kammuna, Sahrazur and Qutbaddn Sraz all endorse
Suhrawards view. But it would be a mistake to label this simply as the Israq
51 Raz, Nihayat al- uqul wa-dirayat al-usul, Istanbul Ayasofya ms 2376, fols 22r9v24.
[viz., al-As ar] mutlaqan wa-l-Hukama f l-wagib); but note I.1.4.1 (F annaha
[viz., alwugub, al-imkan, al-qidam and al-hudut] umur aqliyya la wuguda laha f l-harig). Al (F anna l-wugud mustarak); I.1.1.3 (F anna lQazwn al-Katib, Hikmat al- ayn I.1.1.2
wugud za id ala mahiyyat al-mumkinat) and I.1.1.2 (F anna l-wugud nafs haqqat al tarakun
wagib al-wugud). Al-Abhar, Kasf al-haqa iq 1 (F kawnihi [viz., al-wugud] mus
bayna l-mawgudat) and 2 (F anna wugud al-mumkinat za id ala mahiyyatiha); but note
his opposite view in Muntaha l-afkar f ibanat al-afkar I.1.1.1 (al-mashur anna l-wugud
amr mustarik min gam al-mawgudat wa-l-kull da f ) and I.1.1.2 (al-mashur anna
wugud al-mumkinat f l-a yan za id ala mahiyyatiha wa-huwa da f ). For a brief
Bereitgestelltvon|DeGruyter/TCS(DeGruyter/TCS)
Angemeldet|172.16.1.226
Heruntergeladenam|02.03.1209:57
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
48
only difference between Suhraward and Averroes is that Averroes assigns this
position to Avicenna himself, while Suhraward associates it to unspecified
followers of the Peripatetics. The Magrib philosophical mystic Ibn Arab (d.
638/1240) similarly condemns construing existence as something superadded;
although to be precise, what Ibn Arab denies is that existence is superadded to
the existent, not that existence is superadded to the essence.54
It remains an open question whether any of the critics of what I have labeled
Avicennian ontology felt that Avicennas own theory of existence could be
salvaged if it had been interpreted in a different way. However fertile they
doubtless were to subsequent Muslim thinkers, Avicennas various articulations
of the essence-existence distinction, and his attempts to press that distinction
into the service of his distinction between the necessary of existence in itself and
the necessary of existence through another, were perhaps so tentative and
inconsistent that they resisted systematization. Suhrawards creation of a new
metaphysics of light might have partly resulted from his frustration with the
flaws that emerged from recent and ongoing attempts to systematize Avicennian
ontology.
Bibliography
abbar, al-Mugn f abwab at-tawhd wa-l- adl, eds M.M. Hilm et al., Cairo: alAbd al-G
f.
Mu assasa al-Mis. riyya al- Amma, 1958
A. Alami, Lontologie modale: "tude de la th#orie des modes dAbu Hashim al-Jubba , Paris:
Vrin, 2001.
ayat al-maram f ilm al-kalam, ed. A.F. al-Mazd, Beirut: Dar al-Kutub alal-Amid, G
Ilmiyya, 2004.
, Abkar al-afkar f usul ad-dn, vol. II, ed. A.F. al-Mazd, Beirut, 2004.
al-As ar, Maqalat al-islamiyyn, I-II, ed. H. Ritter, Istanbul: Devlet, 1929 30.
al-Bayhaq, Tatimmat siwan al-hikma, ed. M. Saf , Lahore: L. Ishwar Das, Registrar,
uwayn
, Luma f qawa id ahl as-Sunna wa-l-gama a, in al-G
M. Allard, Le probl!me
des attributes divins dans la doctrine dal-Ash ar et de ses premiers
grands disciples, Beirut: Imprimerie Catholique, 1965.
54 fa- lam anna l-wuguda wa-l- adama laysa bi-say in za idin ala l-mawgudi wa-l-ma dumi
lakinna huwa nafsu l-mawgudi wa-l-ma dumi lakinna l-wahma yatahayyalu anna l Arab, Kitab
wuguda wa-l- adama sifatani ragi atani ila l-mawgudi wa-l-ma dumi, Ibn
17.
Insa ad-dawa ir, p. 6,14
Bereitgestelltvon|DeGruyter/TCS(DeGruyter/TCS)
Angemeldet|172.16.1.226
Heruntergeladenam|02.03.1209:57
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
Robert Wisnovsky
49
al-Qusayr, Sarh asma Allah al-husna, eds T. A. Sa d and S.H.M. Al, Cairo: Dar al
t, 2001.
Haram li-t-Tura
al-Raz, al-Arba n f usul ad-dn, no ed., Hyderabad: Da irat al-Ma arif al- Utmaniyya,
1934 35.
, al-Mabahit al-masriqiyyah, vol. 1, ed. M.M. al-Bagdad, Beirut: Dar al-Kitab al
Arab, 1990.
, ar-Risalat al-kamaliyya f l-haqa iq al-ilahiyya, ed. A. Muhyuddn, Beirut: Dar al
Kutub al- Ilmiyya, 2002.
, Asas at-taqds, ed. A.H. Saqqa, Cairo: Maktabat al-Kulliyyat al-Azhariyya, 1986.
Atiyah, Cairo, 1936.
, Lubab al-isarat, ed. A.S.
2001.
as-Sahrastan and Ilaq, Guftgu-yi Sahrastan va-Ilaq, ed. M.T. Danispazhuh, Nama-yi
Astan-i Quds 3/9, 1348 H., pp. 97 104.
as-Sahrazur, Rasa il as-sagara al-ilahiyya, vol. III, ed. N. Habb, Tehran: Mu assasa-i
Tehran,
2008.
Ibn Arab, Kitab Insa ad-dawa ir, in Kleinere Schriften des Ibn al- Arab, ed. H. Nyberg,
Leiden: Brill, 1919.
Ibn Rusd, On Aristotles Metaphysics: An Annotated Translation of the So-called Epitome,
ed. R. Arnzen, Berlin: De Gruyter, 2010.
, Tafsr ma ba da t- tab a, ed. M. Bouyges, 3 vols, Beirut: Imprimerie Catholique,
1938 48.
, Tahafut at-Tahafut, ed. M. Bouyges, Beirut: Imprimerie Catholique, 1930.
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
Bereitgestelltvon|DeGruyter/TCS(DeGruyter/TCS)
Angemeldet|172.16.1.226
Heruntergeladenam|02.03.1209:57
50
Ibn Sna, al-Mabda wa-l-ma ad, ed. A. Nuran, Tehran: The Institute of Islamic
Studies, McGill University, Tehran Branch, 1984.
, al-Mubahatat, ed. M. Bdarfar, Qum: Intisarat Bdar, 1371 H.
, at-Ta lqat,ed. H.M. Al- Ubayd, Baghdad, 2002
, Kitab as-Sifa /Ilahiyyat (1), eds G. Anawat and S. Zayid, Cairo: al-Haya al-amma
li-suun al-matabi al-amriyya, 1960.
hiyyat (2), eds M.Y. Musa, S. Dunya and S. Zayid, Cairo: al-Haya
, Kitab as-Sifa /Ila
Ahwan, Cairo: al-Matbaa al-amriyya, 1952.
, Kitab as-Sifa /Mantiq (6): as-Safsata, ed. A.F. al-Ahwan, Cairo, 1958.
Avicennas De anima; Being the Psychological
, Kitab as-Sifa /Tabiyyat (6): an-Nafs.
Part of Kitab al-Sifa , ed. F. Rahman, London: Oxford University Press, 1959.
T. Izutsu, The Distinction between essentia and existentia, in The Fundamental Structure
of Sabzawaris Metaphysics, in (viz., the introduction to) Sabzawar, Sarh-i
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
Robert Wisnovsky
Bereitgestelltvon|DeGruyter/TCS(DeGruyter/TCS)
Angemeldet|172.16.1.226
Heruntergeladenam|02.03.1209:57