Erika Fischer Lichte

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 14
At a glance
Powered by AI
The document discusses the interplay between the semiotic (sign-based) and performative dimensions of theatre. It explores how semiotics provided tools to analyze performances despite their ephemeral nature.

The document discusses the application of semiotic analysis to theatre performances and the search for possible meanings in performances.

Semiotic methods and analyzing performances as coherent structures of signs such as gestures, movements, language, etc. are mentioned as ways to analyze performances.

Spring 2008

69

Sense and Sensation: Exploring the Interplay Between the


Semiotic and Performative Dimensions of Theatre
Erika Fischer-Lichte
The Semiotic and the Performative
In the 1970s, when the so-called linguistic, or semiotic, turn took place in the
humanities, it opened up new possibilities for theatre research. Up to then, its main
self-understanding had been that of a historical discipline analogous to art history
and the history of literature. But whereas these disciplines regarded the analysis
and interpretation of works of art from past epochs as their main task, a comparable
approach was not open to theatre studies. Performances of the past are no longer
accessible; they are gone and lost forever. The ephemeral and transitory nature of
performance, which the German playwright and theoretician Gotthold Ephraim
Lessing referred to as early as the 18th century as theatres unique peculiarity,
does not allow the analysis or interpretation of a past performance. It is possible
to examine documents on a performance as well as the material traces left behind,
such as the theatre building, stage sets, costumes, props, the text of a play, a score,
reports or reviews on the performance, etc., but not the performance itself.
On the other hand, a performance, which was accessible, i.e. contemporary
theatre, was not considered a suitable object of research. For while the literary
scholar or the art historian is able to take recourse to the object of his study whenever
it is needed and become absorbed in its details, contemplating it as long as he feels
necessary, the performance is not at the theatre scholars disposal in a comparable
way. Because of its eeting nature, any attempt to analyze it seems doomed to
failure. Therefore, dealing with contemporary performances was left to theatre
critics, while the scholars object of interest was taken from theatre history.
By the 1970s, when theatre scholars began to question this distribution of labor
and tried to develop methods of analyzing a performance despite its ephemeral
nature, semiotics provided them with a set of tools. Semiotically speaking, a
performance can be dened as a structured coherence of theatrical signs such as
Erika Fischer-Lichte is professor of theatre research and director of the newly founded Institute
of Advanced Studies on Interweaving Theatre Cultures at the Freie Universitaet Berlin. She is
past president of the International Federation for Theatre Research and a member of the Academia
Europaea, the Academy of Sciences at Goettingen and the Berlin-Brandenburg Academy of Sciences.
Her publications include The Semiotics of Theatre (German 1983, English 1992), History of European
Drama and Theatre (German 1990, English 2002), Kurze Geschichte des deutschen Theaters (1993),
The Show and the Gaze of Theatre (1997), Das eigene und das fremde Theater (1999), Aesthetische
Erfahrung. Das Semiotische und das Performative (2001), Theatre, Sacrice, Ritual: Exploring Forms
of Political Theatre (2005), and The Transformative Power of Performance: A New Aesthetics (2008,
German 2004 as Aesthetik des Performativen).

70

Journal of Dramatic Theory and Criticism

scenic space, the bodily appearance of the actors, gestures, movements, language,
sounds, music, and so on, and in this sense as a textwhich does not mean the
literary text of a play but a text made up of heterogeneous signs. Thus, semiotic
methods could be applied to a performance.1
The central purpose of semiotic analysis was to search for possible meanings. It
stemmed from the assumption that an unequivocal meaning can never be accorded to
a performanceas it cannot to lyrics or a painting. It is ambiguous and polyvalent.
Accordingly, it is open to most diverse processes of meaning generation. It is never
the meaning of a gesture, action, scene, or the whole performance, but only one
possible meaning from a generally large number of meanings generated with regard
to the element in question. A semiotic analysis never strives to discover a unied
meaning of performance or any one element of it. Even if one particular meaning
is generated, this does not mean that all others are to be excluded. Rather, a choice
is made with a view to the particular problem, question, hypothesis, or perspective
under which the analysis is undertaken, for there is no such thing as a complete
analysis. An analysis will always neglect elements of the performance which do not
seem relevant in terms of the leading question of the analysis or which were simply
not perceived at all, rst and foremost because an analysis is a dynamic process of
relating elements of the performance to each other as well as to all kinds of elements
to which the analyst may refer. Theoretically, this process can never come to an end.
Instead, the end, created by the analyst, is somewhat arbitrary. Although theatre
semiotics is sometimes blamed for being static, reducing the full range of possible
meanings to one meaning only, for demanding clarity and not allowing ambiguity
or even contradiction, for demanding a unied meaning, all such reproaches are
pointless. If such a result has occurred, it has not followed from any restrictions in
the semiotic approach per se, but from an inadequate application of it.
Another reproach is that theatre semiotics ignores the particular materiality
of theatrical signs. This does not hold true either, for a semiotic analysis always
proceeds from the very materiality of the sign. However, it must be conceded that
it is only considered with regard to its potential to serve as a signto produce
meaning. This can, in fact, be seen as a certain limitation.
While the linguistic turn of the 1970s resulted in an understanding not only
of theatre but quite generally of culture as a text made up of signs that have to be
deciphered, the so-called performative turn of the 1990s brought forth another
metaphor which, in some ways, is opposed to that of culture as textthe
metaphor of culture as performance. In theatre studies, this resulted in a shift
of focus from the semioticity of a performance to its performativity. This shift
promised to overcome the limitations of theatre semiotics. From the perspective
of performativity the interest is less in what the acts, actions, and movements of
the performers mean than in how they are perceived and experienced, how they
affect the spectators, and what kind of impact they have on them. Therefore, the

Spring 2008

71

focus on performativity often requires another kind of approach, which considers


these particular qualities of a performance as, for instance, a phenomenological
approach might.
Whereas a semiotic approach concerns itself with the conditions under which
meanings in a performance may emerge out of its performative processes and with the
meanings that are conceivable and possible, a phenomenological approach focuses
on the performative processes as such. While the semiotic approach asks, What
do the performative processes mean, the performative approach instead raises
the question, What do they do? Therefore a semiotic analysis of a performance
considers what is happening on stage as a text made up of theatrical signs that
are to be interpreted. Analyses concerned with its performativity proceed from
the eventness of a performance and highlight those performative processes which
result in something happening between actors and spectatorsthat the spectators
become colored, even affected and moved by what the actors/performers do. Hence
it follows that the semiotic and the performative dimensions of a performance are
different, although inextricably intertwined. They offer two different perspectives
on the same object, the performance, which, ultimately cannot be separated from
each other, and if so, only temporarily for heuristic reasons. I shall substantiate
my argument by referring to Frank Castorfs production of Trainspotting in the
Volksbuehne am Rosa-Luxemburg-Platz Berlin in 1997.
Trainspotting
The production was a theatrical adaptation of Irvine Welshs rst and highly
successful novel, Trainspotting, and its adaptation in 1996 for a lm by Danny
Boyle. Although it was presented in the Volksbuehne, a theatre building with a
stage and an auditorium, it was not the given spatial arrangement that dened the
relationship between actors/performers and spectators, for the auditorium was not
used at all. Instead the performance took place on the stage, and the spectators were
seated on scaffolding at the back of the stage. To take their seats, they had to cross
the stage, where some lighting equipment was laid out. Those spectators who had
already taken their seats watched later arrivals stumble across the stage, sometimes
destroying parts of the set though the ushers at the Volksbuehne had asked the
spectators to watch their step when walking over the lighting equipment. Here,
the spatial arrangement was used in order to redene the roles of the spectators
obviously, the roles of spectator and actor were being played with. Whether they
wanted to or not, the arriving spectators took on the roles of actors before the gaze
of the spectators already seated. At the same time, the performance toyed with the
conventions that mark the beginning of the performance. Did it start as soon as the
rst spectator had reached the scaffolding and started to watch others arriving, or
when the rst actor from the Volksbuehne entered the stage?
Right from the very beginning, the spectators were somewhat irritated about

72

Journal of Dramatic Theory and Criticism

their own role in the performance. They were seated on the stagei.e., the place
reserved for the actors, and those arriving later, in fact, acted before the eyes of the
others. They were not free to decide on their own whether to become actors or to
remain spectatorsas in some sort of old-fashioned audience participationbut
rather in order to become spectators they rst had to act as performers. Stumbling
over a faintly lit stage and accidentally disconnecting lighting cables while sensing
the eyes of others staring at them, at least in some cases, resulted in a feeling of
insecurity and awkwardness. In this way, the very process of entering the stage
space in order to participate in a performance caused irritation. People who arrived
in order to act as spectators were suddenly forced into the role of actors, which
some apparently hated while others enjoyed the experience.
Moving over the stage in order to reach ones place stimulated some to try
and make sense of the whole procedure. What was the purpose of being made to
appear on stage? Was it meant to point to the permanent change between the role
of actor and performer we undergo in everyday life? Or did it hint at a particular
involvement of the spectators in the story to be acted out later on by the Volksbuehne
actorsperhaps in the sense of the old Tua res agitur? While for some the walk
over the stage might have been experienced as somewhat destabilizinghaving
their clumsiness exposed to the gaze of othersthe attempt to make sense of it
surely contributed to a re-stabilization.
However, during the course of the performance, the spectators quickly
recognized that having arrived at the scaffolding, taken their seats, and thus regained
the role of spectator, they were by no means in a safe position. The four actors
repeatedly provoked interaction with the spectators. One of the actors (Hendrik
Arnst), a man of massive physical proportions playing the part of Frank, went
up to one or another spectator from time to time, violently stamping the ground
in a terrifying way, attacking her/him with aggressive remarks, bodily posture,
or gestures. He abused a female spectator in the upper rows as fucking bitch
and bellowed at her to stop her idiotic gawping. The reactions of the spectators
were different at each performance. One spectator who was attacked obviously
felt threatened and moved back, terried; he seemed to make himself smaller and
in this way invisible, while the other spectators burst out laughing. This seemed
to be a welcome pretext for the actor to launch another attack on the audience
by shouting to them: Shut up when the lady is going to speak! whereupon the
actress Kathrin Angerer, who played the part of Alison, took up her scolding aria
on Frank, the swine, a second time. At another performance, the man addressed
by the actor tried to ignore the attack, and the audience did not laugh. This time,
the actor went back to the playing area, and the actress began her aria anew. On one
occasion, during the performance rst mentioned, two spectators wanted to leave
before the end and tried to sneak out unnoticed by the actors. One actor (Matthias
Matschke) managed to run up to them before they could leave and took them to

Spring 2008

73

task. He interrogated them as to why they did not like the performance and asked
them to rethink their decision. When they determinedly opened the door and left
without saying a word, he sent after them the rudest abusewhich the audience
cheered. In any case, whatever happened, the spectators had a hard time claiming
the position of distanced observers. The production did its utmost to make them part
of the performance. The spectators experienced themselves as being determined
by the course of the performance as it was not in their power to prevent the actors
from addressing them directly, thus turning them into actors of the play. At the
same time they experienced themselves as being able to co-determine the course
of the performance by their observable reactions. On the one hand, this provoked
a number of physiological, energetic, affective, or motor states in the spectators
concerned; on the other, it raised the question of how to make sense of this kind
of forced audience participation.
The bodily co-presence of actors and spectator
One possible meaning might have been created by making the spectators
experience and, as a consequence, recognize that a performance always comes
into existence through the bodily co-presence of actors and spectators who
assemble at a certain time and place in order to share a situation, a moment in time.
While those who actreal actors or spectators in the position of actorsdo
somethingmove through the space, perform gestures, manipulate objects, speak
and singthe spectators perceive them and react.
It may well be the case that such reactions are at least partly internal
imaginative and cognitivei.e., purely mental processes. However, most of the
reactions and responses can be perceived by the actors and the other spectators, e.g.,
giggling, laughing, shouting, yawning, snoring, sobbing, crying, eating, drinking,
commenting on what is happening, getting up, running out, and slamming the
doors. The perception of such responses, in its turn, results in further perceptible
reactions. Whatever the actors do, it has an effect on the spectators; and whatever
the spectators do, it has an effect on the actors and other spectators. It can be
concluded from this situation that a performance only comes into being through
the interactions between actors and spectators. Hence it follows that its course
cannot be completely planned or predicted and is, in fact, different each night. It
is kind of an autopoietic process, which is characterized by differing degrees of
contingency. Anything that occurs in the course of a performance cannot be entirely
foreseen at its beginning. Many elements emerge in the course of a performance
as a consequence of certain interactions.
Of course, the actors on stageand the director behind themset the decisive
preconditions for the progression of the performancepreconditions that are xed
by the process of mise-en-scne. As director, Castorf decided on the place of the
performancethe stageand the special kind of opening ceremony that turned

74

Journal of Dramatic Theory and Criticism

most spectators into actors. And it was the actor Hendrik Arnst, for example, who
decided when, how, and which of the spectators to address directly. Nonetheless,
neither was in a position to control the course of the performance entirely. In the
end, it is all participants together who generate the performance.
Therefore, the performance opens up the possibility for all participants to
experience themselves in its course as subjects that are able to co-determine the
actions and behavior of others, and whose own actions and behavior, in the same
way, are determined by others. The individual participantswhether actor or
spectatorexperience themselves as subjects neither fully autonomous nor fully
determined by others, subjects who accept responsibility for a situation which they
take part in but have not created. This demonstrates that a theatre performance is
also to be regarded as a social process in which different individuals and groups
encounter, negotiate, and regulate their relationships in different ways.
This interpretation is backed up at the end of the performance. The actors tried
hard to draw as much applause from the audience as possible in order to extend the
performance. Moreover, they not only jumped and smiled and stretched out their
arms, they also stopped spectators who tried to steal away in order to ask why they
were leaving so soon, whether they did not like the performance, or to scold them
for being so stingy with applause. They mingled with the spectators, shakingor,
in the case of female spectators, kissingtheir hands, and said, Thank you. In
other words, they fraternized with the spectators and tried all means to prevent
them from leaving, extending the play into a clearly social situation and thus
prolonging the performance. At the end, the spectators decided on the conclusion
of the performance: it was only over when the last spectator left. This kind of
ending unmistakably stressed that the performance had come into being through
the encounter of actors and spectators.
By playing with and exploiting some of the possibilities that are given with the
bodily co-presence of actors and spectators, the interplay between the performative
and the semiotic dimension was also highlighted. It was the bodily experience
of such co-presence which led to transformations of the physiological, affective,
energetic, and motor states of the spectators and, following from that, to the semiotic
processes by which spectators tried to make sense of such an experience.
The materiality of the performance
This interplay was also decisive with regard to the materiality of the
performance as will be shown with regard to spatiality and corporeality.
The space
The playing area on the stage was formed by an almost empty space. In the
back, where the curtain usually hangs, and at the right side, there were screens on
which lm clips were shown as, for instance, pictures of a landscape in spring, lmed
from the window of a moving train, or a documentary on Nico Icon, the singer of

Spring 2008

75

Velvet Underground. Music was played not only during the lm and video clips, but
also in all parts of the performance. It included recordings by Velvet Underground,
Iggy Pop, and Lou Reed, as well as Karel Gott (a Czech-German pop-singer born
in 1939, who mostly performs easy listening music with folksy tunes and themes),
and Arnold Schoenberg. There were only a few objects on stage: an iron bed where
Alison was positioned during the whole performance, a baby doll, a toilet bowl, a
Union Jack, and, on the oor, the lighting equipment mentioned above, laid out as
it is used on construction sites. With the exception of the lights on the oor, none
of the objects were in the playing area as the spectators made their entrance but
were pushed on or brought in later by the three male actors.
The atmosphere which dominated the space changed several times during the
course of the performance. Right from the start the spectators sensed a particular
atmosphere, which was brought about by the huge dimension of the whole stage
space with the naked wall behind only faintly lit. This, and the lighting equipment
on the oor at the front and center stage, was reminiscent of a construction site,
an atmosphere that was felt to be unpleasant. The atmosphere changed when the
actors made their entrance, when the bed was pushed in, or when the toilet bowl
was brought on stage. It also changed when the lm and video recordings were
presented or when music lled the space. However the atmosphere changed, it was
always felt to be something one could not escape.
As the philosopher Gernot Boehme has shown, atmosphere, although not
bound to a particular place, pours into the space. It is not tied to the objectsor
peoplefrom which it seems to emanate or to those who enter the space and
sense it physically. Usually, atmosphere is the rst thing that spectators perceive,
tingeing them and thus allowing for a very specic experience of the space. An
experience such as this cannot be explained by taking recourse to the single elements
in spaceits extension, particular objects, sounds, smells, or anything else. For it is
not these individual elements that create the atmosphere but the interplay between
all of them which, in theatre productions, is usually carefully calculated. Boehme
denes atmosphere as spaces, in that they are tinged by the presence of objects,
of human beings or environmental constellations. They are themselves spheres of
the presence of something, its reality in space.2 The phrase spheres of presence
describes a particular mode in which objects are perceived. Boehme explains the
mode in which a thing appears in a particular way as present, as an ecstasy of the
object. Not only its colors, smells, or sounds are conceptualized as ecstasiesi.e.,
the so-called secondary qualities of a thingbut also its primary qualities such
as extension and form. The ecstasy of things inuences their environment; they
attract, even demand attentionas do the iron bed or the toilet bowland they
appear to those who perceive them as present in a particularly intense way. They
force themselves into their eld of attention.
Atmosphere contributes considerably to the creation of spatiality. Through

76

Journal of Dramatic Theory and Criticism

the atmosphere, which seems to permeate the space and the things, the things and
the space appear to the subject who enters or who is present while it changes, as
present in a highly emphatic sense. Not only do they present themselves in their
so-called primary and secondary qualities; moreover, in the atmosphere, they even
invade the body of the perceiving subjectwhich is mostly experienced through
light, smells, and sound. For the spectator is not confronted with an atmosphere,
is not distanced from it; rather, s/he is surrounded by it, s/he is permeated by it. In
this sense, atmosphere is something which is physically sensed.
On the other hand, an atmosphere is able to work on the perceiving subject
in a particular way because for the subject it connects with particular meanings
which contribute to the feelings of, for example, uneasiness, awkwardness, or
threat. As a result, the subject will accord various meanings to the atmosphere
which it senses. It may well be that the particular shade of the atmosphere sensed
deviates from any that have already been experienced in one respect or other. Thus
the subject is challenged to nd a new meaning which will inform the experience
of the atmosphere at a later date, when it is sensed again. Therefore, atmosphere
appears as a kind of phenomenon in which the performative and the semiotic
dimensions are intertwined in a way that it is hard to separate themand possible
only for heuristic reasons.
The actors body
Because of the bodily co-presence of actors and spectators, corporeality plays
an essential role in performances. In Trainspotting this was not only effective
when one of the actors went up to a spectator and addressed him or her directly,
intimidating by his mere physical presence. It dominated the performance right
from the very rst entrance of the actors. The three male actors/junkies sat down
side by side and ung their words out in a way that what they said was almost not
intelligible. Instead, how they uttered it had an immediate effect on the spectators.
The rhythm of their choric speech, the volume, the particular quality of the
voices, the harmony or disharmony of their voices, and most of all the energy of
the speakers had a physiological, affective, and energetic effect on the spectators.
It seemed as if a stream of energy emanated from the actors, transferred onto the
spectators, and energized them in their turn. In a particular way and with a particular
intensity the actors were experienced as PRESENT.
What was sensed here was the phenomenal body of the actors, not their semiotic
bodies that represented the junkies. While up to now the semiotic body representing
dramatic gures in performances has attracted and received much attention, the
phenomenal body of actors and spectators, i.e., their bodily being-in-the-world, has
only seldom come into view. This is all the more surprising since the phenomenal
body and the semiotic body are inextricably bound to each other; it is possible to
think of the phenomenal body without referring to the semiotic body but not the
other way round. It seems productive to relate them to one another via the concept

Spring 2008

77

of embodiment.3 By embodiment I do not mean the process of lending ones own


body temporarily to something mental (an idea, a concept, a meaning, or even a
bodiless spirit), which needs a body to articulate itself and gain presence. Rather,
the term embodiment aims at the bodily processes by which the phenomenal
body generates itself as a particular body and at the same time generates specic
meanings. Thus, the actor brings forth and presents his phenomenal body in a very
specic way through a process of embodiment which is sometimes experienced as
PRESENCE. At the same time, he produces a dramatic gure, for example, Frank.
In the performance, PRESENCE and the dramatic gure do not exist outside the
particular process of embodiment by which the actor brings them into existence;
rather, they are brought forth by them.
Perception and Production of Meaning
As already indicated, this interplay of the semiotic and the performative
dimensions has consequences for the processes of perception and meaning
generation which the spectators perform. To perceive the body, the things, and the
space in their specic presence does not mean to perceive them as meaningless.
Instead, all of these phenomena are perceived as something. We are not dealing
with a non-specic stimulus here, mere sensorial data, but with a perception of
something as something. In my perception, the objects appear in their particular
phenomenalitythe iron bed as an iron bed or the toilet bowl as a toilet bowl. These
objects signify that which they appear to be. Their self-referentiality, accordingly,
is not to be described as the mediation of a given meaning or as a desemantization
of a sign but as a process of a very particular kind of production of meaning. This
process is performed as the perception of a phenomenon in its particular materiality,
in its phenomenal being. Perceiving and the generation of meaning, in this case,
are performed in and by the very same act. Meaning is brought forth by and in the
act of perceiving. In other words, in this case we do not perceive something rst
and thenin an act of interpretationattribute the meaning of something else to
it. Rather, the act of perceiving something as something is performed at the same
time as the process of producing its meaning as this particular phenomenal being.
I call this kind of perception the order of presence.
From this, I distinguish quite another kind of perception and production of
meaning, namely, the order of representation. To perceive the actors physicality
in its bodily being-in-the-world lays the foundation for the order of presence. To
perceive it as a sign for a dramatic gure or another symbolic order establishes the
order of representation. When Kathrin Angerer takes the baby doll in her arms and
rocks it, the doll is perceived as a sign for Alisons baby. When the cloth on the
oor is identied by the spectator as the Union Jack, it is perceived as a symbol
of the United Kingdom. And when the actors take it from the oor and stuff it into
the toilet bowl, the spectators will perceive this as a sign process to which different

78

Journal of Dramatic Theory and Criticism

meanings may be attributedwhether as something the dramatic gures want to use


for cleaning the toilet bowl or to express an act of contempt for what the ag stands
for, or whether the director wanted to take a stance in political theatre or something
else again. While the rst order produces meanings regarding the phenomenal being
of the perceived, the second order brings forth meanings which, in their sum total,
strive to constitute the dramatic gure or another symbolic order.
During the performance of Trainspottingas is usual in a performancethe
spectators perception oscillated between both orders of perception. For instance, as
long as Hendrik Arnst communicated with the other actors, he was mainly perceived
as Frank, although his very peculiar physicality drew the attention of the spectator
to his phenomenal body from time to time, to his particular bodily being-in-theworld. When he went up to the scaffolding and addressed a spectator with abuse or
threats, it was rather his bodily being-in-the-world that was perceived. In this way,
the spectators perception was forced to shift from perceiving the semiotic body to
perceiving the phenomenal body and vice versa. The moment the shift took place,
a rupture occurred, a discontinuity manifested itself. A state of instability came
into being that placed the perceiving subjects between the two orders, transferred
them into a state of inbetweenness, of liminality.4
Each shift, each instability, that comes up in the course of a performance causes
the dynamics of the process of perception to take another turn. The more often a
shift happens, the more often the perceiving subjects begin to wander between two
worlds, between two orders of perception. They increasingly become aware of their
inability to cause, steer, and control the shifts. They may consciously try to adjust
their perception anewto the order of presence or to the order of representation.
Very soon, however, they will become aware that the shift takes place even if they
do not intend it, that it simply happens, befalls them, that they are moved between
the two orders without wanting or being able to prevent it. At that moment, the
spectators experience their own perception as emergent, as withdrawn from their
will and control, and yet as an action performed consciously. That is to say that
the shift draws the attention of the perceiving subject to the process of perception
itself as well as to its particular dynamics. At the moment of shift, the process of
perception itself becomes conspicuous, thereby self-conscious, and in itself the
object of perception. The perceiving subject begins to perceive itself as perceiving
subject. That is a performative as well as semiotic process in itself and produces
new meanings which, in turn, generate other meanings and so forth. In this way,
the process of perception continuously takes another turn. What is perceived and
what meanings are produced become less and less predictable. The perceiving
subjects become aware that the meanings are not conveyed to them but that it is they
themselves who produce them and that they could have generated quite a different
set of meanings if the shift from one order to the other would have happened earlier,
later, or less frequently.

Spring 2008

79

The performance as eventaesthetic experience as liminal experience


From these different kinds of interplay between the performative and the
semiotic in performance it can be concluded that a performance cannot be considered
a work of art but an art event. Since a performance comes into being by way of the
interaction between actors and spectators, since it brings forth itself in and through
an autopoietic process, it is impossible to label it a work. For when the autopoietic
process comes to an end, the performance does not remain as its result; rather, the
performance has come to an end, too. It is over and therefore irretrievably lost. It
exists only as and in the process of its performance; it exists only as event.
The performance as eventcontrary to the mise-en-scneis unique and
cannot be repeated. It is impossible for exactly the same constellation between
actors and spectators to occur another time. As has been shown with reference to
Trainspotting, the response of the spectators and their effect on the actors and other
spectators will be different with each and every performance. A performance is also
to be understood as an event in the sense that no one participant can completely
control it, that it simply happens to themparticularly to the spectators. This holds
true not only with respect to the consequences of the bodily co-presence of actors
and spectators, but also regarding the particular presentness of the phenomena as
well as the emergence of meaning. As explained above concerning the shift of
perception, it also befalls the perceiving subjects and transfers them into a state of
betwixt and between, into a state of liminality.
Moreover, the particular eventness of performance is characterized by a strange
collapse of oppositions. The participants in a performance experience themselves
as subjects who co-determine its course and, at the same time, are determined by it.
They live through the performance as an aesthetic as well as a social process in the
course of which relationships are negotiated, power struggles fought, communities
established and dissolved. Through embodiment, the actors bring forth the body
as phenomenal as well as semiotic, and produce presence as well as meaning. The
spectators perception follows the order of presence as well as that of representation.
This is to say that what is traditionally held to be an opposition in Western cultures,
which is grasped by pairs of dichotomous conceptssuch as autonomous subject
vs. subject determined by others, art vs. social reality, presence vs. representation,
the performative vs. the semioticis not experienced in the mode of either-or but
in that of an as-well-as in performance. The so-called oppositions collapse, the
dichotomies dissolve.
The moment this happens, when one category can also be taken for another, our
attention is attracted by the passage from one state to the other, by the instability,
which, in its turn, is experienced as an event. In the space between these opposites,
an interval opens up. The betwixt and between which Turner stresses with regard
to ritual,5 thus becomes a privileged category for the aesthetics of performance. It

80

Journal of Dramatic Theory and Criticism

points to the threshold between the spaces, to the state of liminality into which the
performance transfers all those who participate in it.
Since such pairs of dichotomous concepts serve not only as tools for the
description and cognition of the world but also as regulators for our actions
and behavior, their destabilization not only upsets our perception of the world,
ourselves, and others but also shatters the rules and norms that guide our behavior.
Different frames can be deduced from the pairs of concepts, for instance, This
is theatre/art or This is a social or political situation. Such frames prescribe an
adequate behavior in the situation they encompass. By letting opposite or only
different frames collide, by thus allowing different, even completely opposite values
and claims to stand side by side so that they are all valid while at the same time
they annul each other, performances create liminal situations. They transport the
spectators between all these rules, norms, orderssometimes they even transfer
them into a crisis.
The performance transfers the spectators into a state, which alienates them
from their everyday life and from the norms and rules valid in it. Such a state can
be experienced as a pleasure as well as a torment. The transformations undergone
by the subjects can be most diverse. Mainly, they are temporary transformations,
which last only for a limited time span in the performance. These include changes in
the bodys physiological, affective, energetic, and motor states, a well as changes in
status such as those from the status of a spectator to that of an actor, or the building
up of a community between actors and spectators or only among the spectators.
Such changes take place during the performance and are perceptible; after the
performance has come to an end, however, they usually do not continue. This marks
the difference between liminal states in ritual and in artistic performance. While
in a ritual the transformation undergone is irreversible and the change of status
requires social acceptance, this is not the case in an artistic performance. From
this, it follows that although both ritual and aesthetic experience can be dened as
liminal experience, they are by no means the same. While in a ritual the state of
liminality is the path to gain a new status or identity, in an artistic performance it is
an end in itself. However, although aesthetic experience does not result in a socially
accepted change of status and identity, it may well cause a change in the perception
of reality, self, and others in individual participants which will also inuence this
individuals action and behavior. This applies not only to the artists involved but
also to the spectators. In this sense, the event may result in a transformation of the
participants, which can even outlast the end of the performance.
As has become evident, performances always have a performative and a
semiotic dimension. Both interact constantly, so that it is sometimes impossible
to distinguish one clearly from the other. However, in the mise-en-scne of a
performance as well as in the perception of individual spectators there may be a
tendency to privilege one over the other. For instance, particular staging strategies

Spring 2008

81

may be intended and applied that strive for privileging one dimension and for
guiding the spectators perception in such a way that either the performative mode
outweighs the semiotic one or vice versa. Nonetheless, such guidance does not often
prove successful, and spectators may respond in an unpredictable way. On the other
hand, there will always be spectators who tend to privilege one dimension, even if
the staging strategies privilege the other. Whatever they perceive, they will either
rst ask what it means or, on the contrary, try to get immersed in the atmosphere,
respond to the stream of energy which emanates from an actor and allows them to
be energized, and vibrate with rhythms set by the mise-en-scne, without asking
for meanings. In both cases, the rather neglected dimension will also always be
effective since, as we have seen, both are inextricably intertwined.
This has to be kept in mind when undertaking a performance analysis. It
depends on the leading question, the main problem, or the initial hypothesis as to
whether the analysis will consider both dimensions equally well or one more than
the other. In any case, it is wise to consider both even if to a different degree and
in differing depth. For we are never to forget that it is the particular interplay of the
performative and the semiotic dimension which constitutes performance.
Notes
1. Cf. Erika Fischer-Lichte, The Semiotics of Theatre, tr. Jeremy Gaines and Dores L. Jones
(Bloomington: Indiana U P, 1992).
2. Gernot Boehme, Atmosphaere. Essays zur neuen Aesthetik (Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp, 1995)
33.
3. Regarding this concept see Thomas J. Csordas, Embodiment and Experience. The Existential
Ground of Culture and Self (Cambridge: Cambridge U P, 1994) and Erika Fischer-Lichte, Embodiment
From Page to Stage: The Dramatic Figure, Assaph: Studies in Theatre No. 16 (2000): 65-75.
4. Regarding the concept of liminality cf. Arnold van Gennep, The Rites of Passage (Chicago:
Chicago U P, 1960, originally 1909) and Victor Turner, The Ritual Process: Structure and Anti-Structure
(Chicago: Aldine, 1969).
5. Turner 95.

82

Journal of Dramatic Theory and Criticism

You might also like