Recovering Risk Aversion From Option Prices and Realized Returns
Recovering Risk Aversion From Option Prices and Realized Returns
Recovering Risk Aversion From Option Prices and Realized Returns
Abstract
A relationship exists between aggregate risk-neutral and subjective probability distributions
and risk aversion functions. We empirically derive risk aversion functions implied by option prices
and realized returns on the S&P500 index simultaneously. These risk aversion functions
dramatically change shapes around the 1987 crash: Precrash, they are positive and decreasing in
wealth and largely consistent with standard assumptions made in economic theory. Postcrash, they
are partially negative and partially increasing and irreconcilable with those assumptions.
Mispricing in the option market is the most likely cause. Simulated trading strategies exploiting
this mispricing shows excess returns even after accounting for the possibility of further crashes,
transaction costs, and hedges against the downside risk.
For helpful discussions I would like to thank Kerry Back (the editor), Ian Cooper, Julian Franks, Nils Hakansson,
Hayne Leland, Anthony Neuberger, Mark Rubinstein, two anonymous referees, and seminar participants at
Berkeley, Michigan, McGill, Yale, Harvard, London Business School, Long Term Capital Management (London),
University of Southern California, Inquire (UK) at Newcastle, Davis, City University London, Warwick, Bank of
England (London), the Computational Finance Conference at London, and the European Financial Management
Conference at Lisbon.
Recovering Risk Aversion from Option Prices and Realized Returns
The risk-neutral probability is the price, multiplied by the riskfree return, that an investor
would pay for receiving one dollar in that state. We need to multiply by the riskfree return in order
to have a proper probability distribution that sums to one. The subjective probability is simply the
assessment of an investor of how likely a state is to occur. These two probabilities would be
identical if the investor were indifferent to risk. However, the investor might value a dollar more
highly in certain states namely ones where wealth is low. The risk aversion adjustment indicates
these preferences of the investor. Once we know both risk-neutral and subjective probability
distributions, we can derive those preferences empirically.
While the theoretical relationship is well known, this paper is the first to recover risk
aversion empirically from the two distributions. This methodology is also used in Aït-Sahalia and
Lo (2000). Other, less closely related, studies are Rosenberg and Engle (1997) and Derman et al.
(1997). In our study, the risk-neutral distributions are recovered from option prices by a variation
of the method of Jackwerth and Rubinstein (1996).1 For the subjective distributions, we assume
that they are approximated by the actual (historical) return distribution of a broad index such as the
S&P500.
At this point, we are confronted with a potential puzzle which is depicted in the following
two figures. During the precrash period both the risk-neutral and the actual distributions look about
lognormal. Figure 1 depicts the distributions on October 22, 1986, and is typical of the precrash
period. The actual distribution is located slightly to the right due to the risk-premium. We know
that in this case a power utility function of moderate risk aversion is likely to provide a reasonable
risk aversion adjustment for translating one distribution into the other.
Figure 1
Figure 2
Next, we turn to the postcrash period where the actual distribution looks about lognormal
again. However, Jackwerth and Rubinstein (1996) document that the risk-neutral distribution is
now left-skewed and leptokurtic (more peaked). Figure 2 depicts the distributions on April 15,
1992, and is typical of the postcrash period. If we conclude that the risk-neutral distributions
changed in shape around the crash and that the actual distributions (which proxy for the subjective
distributions) did not, then we could conclude that the third component (risk aversion functions)
changed, too, around the crash. This paper sets out to empirically investigate this possibility.
We find indeed that implied risk aversion functions dramatically change shapes around the
1987 crash and thereafter exhibit negative and increasing risk aversion across parts of the wealth
dimension. These findings are remarkably stable with respect to changes of almost all model
parameters. Moreover, a number of potential criticisms of our methodology are discussed and
rejected. One potential explanation is that some options are mispriced during the postcrash period.
2
A simulated trading strategy exploiting this mispricing mean-variance dominates holding the
market. This result would not surprise us since the trading strategies involve selling put options
and there were no more significant crashes between 1988 and 1995. However, we simulate
crashes as well and still find strategies that strictly mean-variance dominate holding the market
even in the presence of transaction costs. A final concern is that the trading strategies can bankrupt
the investor. Nonetheless, we are able to hedge the downside risk and still achieve excess returns.
Section 1 presents the model for obtaining the implied risk aversion functions. Section 2
describes the data and procedures used for the empirical work. Section 3 presents and analyzes the
empirical results. Section 4 concludes.
In this section, we introduce a model of the economy within which we derive implied risk
aversion functions across wealth. We consider a complete market economy, which implies the
existence of a representative investor (Constantinides (1982)). The representative investor has an
endowed wealth of 1 unit and a fixed time-horizon t. The problem is to maximize utility across
future wealth subject to the budget constraint:
1
Max
W
∫ Q(W )U(W)dW − λ ( r ∫ P (W )WdW − 1)
t
(1)
By differentiating with respect to wealth, we find the first order conditions which have to
hold in equilibrium. In equilibrium we know that the aggregate investor has to hold the market
portfolio. Thus, if S is the return (cum dividends) on the market portfolio across states then the
following relation has to hold in equilibrium:
λ P (S)
U' ( S) = (2)
r t Q( S)
The approach to find the implied utility functions by using Equation (2) directly suffers from
the fact that we cannot measure the value of the shadow price λ accurately. Its formula involves
the probability in the tails of the subjective distribution where we have little confidence in our
estimates. However, there exists an interesting way around this problem. We can find a simple
expression for the absolute risk aversion, which can be expressed in terms of the subjective and
risk-neutral distributions after differentiating Equation (2) with respect to S once more:
3
λ P ' ( S )Q ( S ) − P ( S )Q ' ( S )
U' ' ( S ) = (3)
rt Q 2 (S)
In our economy, we would like to assure that utility functions are increasing (U′ > 0) and
concave (U'' < 0). U′ is guaranteed to be positive since all terms on the right-hand side of
Equation (2) are positive. However, the concavity of the utility function is not guaranteed by
Equation (3), and we will check for violations in the empirical section. Finally, we can write an
expression for the absolute risk aversion in terms of the subjective and risk-neutral distributions
(Leland (1980)):
The expression for the risk aversion functions does no longer depend on the shadow price
λ and is thus much more tractable. In particular, with Equation (4) we are able to obtain the risk
aversion for any state by using only local information. Thus, we can concentrate our attention on the
center states with the highest probability of occurring and neglect the tails of the distributions. In
particular, relative errors around the probability distributions are lower in the center than in the
tails.
For our economy with a representative investor, we would like to use a broad index
resembling the market in our empirical work. Thus, the empirical research in this paper is based
on a database which contains minute by minute trades and quotes covering S&P500 European index
options, S&P500 index futures, and S&P500 index levels from April 2, 1986, through December
29, 1995 (Jackwerth and Rubinstein (1996)). Moreover, we use daily closing prices and
dividends on the S&P500 from January 2, 1928, through December 29, 1995. Quotes with
excessive spreads (200 cents for options and 20 cents for futures) are eliminated. Option quotes
violating general no-arbitrage conditions are eliminated. Option quotes violating no-arbitrage
conditions in vertical or butterfly spreads were tentatively dropped and then reintroduced in such a
way as to keep as many quotes as possible.
We assume that the future dividends can be approximated by a dividend yield, which is
based on the actual payments throughout the life of the option. Thereby, we ignore the lumpiness of
the dividend payments; but, since we are dealing with European index options, this matters little as
we are only interested in the total dividend paid over the life of the option.
For the index level, we do not use the observed index itself but a futures-based index. The
reasons are that the index can be stale due to infrequent trading and that traders use the futures
contract for hedging rather than the underlying. In order to obtain the futures-based index, we
calculate the implied interest rates between all futures quotes and trades and the corresponding
index level. Next, we compute the median daily interest rates for all available maturities and
deflate all futures quotes and trades by these implied repo-rates. For each minute, the median of all
deflated quotes and trades is calculated and used as the futures-based index for that minute. As we
4
are interested in working with representative daily sets of options, we use for the daily index level
the median of the intraday levels of the futures-based index.
For the interest rate, we calculate the put-call parity implied borrowing and lending rates
for all feasible pairs of options of the same maturity on a given day where we use the futures-based
index. We then compute the median daily borrowing and lending rates. Finally, we use the
average rate as our daily interest rate for that maturity.
We are now ready to look at the representative daily set of options. As further safeguards,
we omit the first and last 30 minutes of quotes each day and all quotes with bids of 1/16 or less.
Also, we only consider options with strike price / index level (moneyness) ratios between 0.84 and
1.12. This procedure eliminates far-away-from-the-money observations, which are potentially
unreliable due to their low volume and low sensitivity to volatility. The remaining bid and ask
quotes are translated into their Black-Scholes implied volatilities2, and we use the midpoint
(average) implied volatilities thereafter. For every strike price we obtain the mean daily implied
midpoint volatility. If there are fewer than 20 quotes for a strike price during the day then we omit
these quotes from the data. Finally, using the daily futures-based index level, we translate the
implied midpoint volatilities back into option prices. This is our representative daily set of option
prices.
Every 31 days from April 1986 through December 1995, we estimate the subjective and
risk-neutral distributions for the 31-day index return and infer from these the absolute risk aversion
functions for a representative investor with a one-month investment horizon. Out of our total
sample, we are left with 114 days for which we have non-overlapping 31-day risk aversion
functions.
In order to find the 31-day risk-neutral probability distribution, Jackwerth and Rubinstein
(1996) propose a method where they search for the smoothest risk-neutral distribution, which at the
same time explains the option prices. The trade-off between the two contradicting goals is
exogenously specified. Three problems arise with this approach which leads us to deviate slightly
from the Jackwerth-Rubinstein method. First, matching the option prices by minimizing the squared
error puts more weight on in-the-money compared to out-of-the-money options. Instead, we match
implied volatilities, which are of the same order of magnitude across striking prices. Second, the
Jackwerth-Rubinstein method does not account for the fact that at-the-money option prices vary less
throughout the day than away-from-the-money options. Therefore, we measure the standard
deviation of the implied volatilities during the day for each strike price. This information is then
used to force a tighter fit around at-the-money options (where standard deviations are lower) and to
allow for a looser fit for away-from-the-money options. Third, the Jackwerth-Rubinstein method
uses as a measure of smoothness the integral of squared curvature of the probability distribution.
Due to the general bell-shape of probability distributions there will always be some curvature
present. Here, we minimize the curvature of the implied volatilities (volatility smile) which in a
Black-Scholes economy would be flat. In the limiting case, where we observe only one option, the
method coincides with the Black-Scholes model and backs out a lognormal risk-neutral
distribution.
Our new method thus achieves a similar objective as the Jackwerth-Rubinstein method,
namely finding a smooth risk-neutral distribution, which at the same time explains the option prices,
but avoids the above problems. In order to implement the method, we discretize the future index
5
value such that the spacing coincides with the strike prices and the mid-points between the strike
prices:
Sj = S0 + j ∆, j = 0, ... , 99 (5)
2
σ − σi
( )
99
MIN (1 − p )∑ σ ′′j + p∑ i
2
(6)
i STD i
σj
j= 0
Alternatively, we could employ the related method of kernel regression (Härdle (1990))
which yields very similar volatility functions. Once we have solved Equation (6) for the optimal
implied volatility function, we calculate the Black-Scholes option prices across strike prices and
differentiate twice with respect to the strike price. After multiplying by the riskfree return (rt), we
write down the risk-neutral probability distribution directly:
6
r − t n( d 2 j ) d1 j d 2 j
P(S j ) = r t
[1 + 2 S j t d 1 j σ ′j ] + sd − t t n( d 1 j )[σ ′′j + ( σ ′j ) 2 ] (7)
S j σ j t σj
e− 2 x
1 2
1
where: n(x) = standard normal density function = 2π
sd − t
ln
S j r −t
d1j = + 12 σ j t
σj t
d2j = d1j − σ j t
d = 1 + dividend yield
s = index value today
σ j′ = first derivative of implied volatility with respect to strike prices,
σ j +1 − σ j − 1
numerically approximated by: σ ′j =
2∆
Our approach nests the Black-Scholes economy with its lognormal risk-neutral distribution
as a limiting case when the trade-off parameter (p) goes to zero. Empirically, we set the trade-off
parameter to 7 × 10-12. This choice assures that all risk-neutral probability distributions are non-
negative and thus arbitrage-free. Only a few options are priced outside their empirical bid/ask
spreads, and those tend to be options with extreme moneyness.
In order to estimate the subjective distribution, we use the historical time series of the
index. The length of the sample is an issue, and we select 4-year time frames. This particular
choice and a number of parameter choices below can be criticized as somewhat arbitrary.
However, we show that varying these initial choices does not change the basic findings.
We calculate 31-day, non-overlapping returns from our 4-year sample and derive the kernel
density with a Gaussian kernel and bandwidth: 3
1.8σ
h= 5
(8)
n
7
know that the historical mean is very difficult to estimate. Merton (1980) argues that one should
explicitly model positive risk-premia and, thus, we de-mean the actual distribution and then reset
the mean to the riskfree interest rate + 8% per year for the risk premium. So far, we made a few
modeling choices to obtain our risk aversion functions. However, we will show shortly that our
empirical results are not sensitive to reasonable changes in any of these choices.
3. Empirical Results
We are now in the position to calculate the risk aversion functions across wealth. The
empirically observed risk aversion functions are unfortunately not nearly as well behaved as
standard assumptions made in economic theory suggest, namely, that risk aversion functions should
be positive and monotonically downwards-sloping. Figure 3 shows our empirical results, which
are aggregated but still indicative of the respective periods covered. We also report the empirical
standard deviations by showing the mean risk aversion levels across wealth ± 0.5 times their
standard deviations.4
Figure 3
Precrash, the risk aversion function is largely consistent with standard assumptions made in
economic theory: it is positive and decreasing across wealth except that it increases again for
wealth levels greater than 1.03 which corresponds to an increase in wealth of 43% over the year.
However, in the postcrash period two disconcerting features arise and become progressively
worse as we move through time. First, the postcrash risk aversion functions are negative around
the center. Second, the risk aversion functions rise for wealth levels greater than about 0.99.
Before we analyze these features in detail, we want to address the potential concern that our
particular modeling choices caused them.
We find that the general shape of the functions in Figure 3 is remarkably stable with respect
to different modeling choices. Using a different length for the historical sample of 2 or 10 years
instead of 4 years does not change Figure 3 significantly. Also, some option traders are concerned
that the hedging of out-of-the-money put options has become more difficult after the crash as they
became aware of the possibility of large jumps. We therefore investigate the impact of option
prices with low strike prices (moneyness between 0.84 and 0.89) on our empirical findings by
omitting them from our calculations. Only the lower left tails of the risk-neutral probability
distributions are somewhat affected and Figure 3 does not change significantly altogether.
Small changes in the risk premium in the interval where most financial economists would
expect it to lie over the long run (5 to 10% per year) do not change Figure 3 other than through
slight shifts (downward and upward, respectively). However, very large risk premia cause all risk
aversion functions to shift upward while the shape of the functions is preserved. A risk premium of
more than 40% per year would finally cause all functions to be non-negative throughout.
Also, we changed the bandwidth for the kernel density from 0.5 to 2 times its value in
Equation (8). Small bandwidths lead to spurious multi-modalities, which cause all risk aversion
functions to fluctuate more. However, the basic features of Figure 3 are still preserved in that the
precrash risk aversion function is mostly positive and the postcrash ones are mainly negative.
8
Next, we use the actual distributions straight with their means as calculated from the
historical data. Figure 3 does not change significantly except that the precrash risk aversion
function is now even higher and the postcrash ones are even lower.
Finally, we change the time-to-maturity to 15 and 64 days and, again, Figure 3 is unaffected.
We cannot investigate longer horizons since the number of non-overlapping returns in our historical
sample dwindles dramatically, and we would like to observe at least 25 return observations
(corresponding to at most 64-day returns in a 4-year sample) for the kernel density estimation.
Aït-Sahalia and Lo (2000) and Rosenberg and Engle (1997) also have studied empirical
risk aversion functions. Less closely related, Derman et al. (1997) ask if option prices are “fair”
given the actual distribution. Most of the above studies find positive and rather “well-behaved”
risk aversion functions in the postcrash period. There are a number of possible reasons why their
results might differ from ours.
Aït-Sahalia and Lo (2000) present a positive risk aversion function in their Figure 4, but the
risk aversion function associated with the marginal utility in their Figure 3 is partially negative. A
number of possible reasons could explain their result. First, the sign of the risk aversion function
changes according to the bandwidth they use for their kernel estimation; and the sign is evidently
rather sensitive to their particular methodology. Second, the study provides only one snap-shot in
time (based on option prices during the year 1993) where the distributions and the risk aversion
function are estimated and not, as we do, a time series of the risk aversion functions over 10 years.
We know that we can observe “well-behaved” risk aversion functions on individual days postcrash
and that the pattern of partially negative risk aversion functions only emerges as we check many
dates over a longer time series. Third, Aït-Sahalia and Lo (2000) use overlapping returns to
estimate the actual distribution. We recalculated their actual distributions with and without
overlapping returns, and the two distributions look rather different. Since they only show one risk
aversion function, the shape of that function can be affected by the choice of overlapping versus
non-overlapping returns.
Rosenberg and Engle (1997) only present results on marginal utilities, but the associated
risk aversion functions are all positive. The reason appears to be the particular way in which the
risk-neutral distributions are estimated. Their “sigma-shape” polynomial, which is related to
implied volatilities, seems to be a rather rigid and inflexible function. As a result, the empirical
option prices may not be very well matched as the implied risk-neutral distribution is surprisingly
close to a lognormal distribution. In particular, the risk-neutral distribution is only slightly left-
skewed and less peaked then the lognormal distribution. One interpretation is that the positive risk
aversion functions could be a result of their estimation technique.
Derman et al. (1997) implicitly assess the risk aversion function even if they do not estimate
it formally. They observe that on one particular date the actual distribution of over-lapping returns
is left-skewed and thus similar to the risk-neutral distribution. They interpret this observation as
being consistent with a “well-behaved” risk aversion function. Two possible reasons could
explain their observation, which we have discussed already in relation to Aït-Sahalia and Lo
(2000). First, their study provides only one snapshot in time and not a time series. Second,
Derman et al. (1997) use overlapping returns, too. We recalculated their actual distributions with
and without overlapping returns and, again, the two distributions look rather different. Their
observation is thus sensitive to the way the actual distribution is estimated.
9
3.3 Discussion of the Empirical Risk Aversion Functions
In our discussion of Figure 3 we want to point out that the results for the precrash period are
rather encouraging. The implied risk aversion function is positive throughout; and both absolute
and relative risk aversion functions are decreasing with increasing wealth until wealth levels of
about 1.03 as one might deem reasonable behavior for the economy.
The problems occur postcrash where risk aversion functions are now negative throughout
wealth levels from about 0.96 through 1.01. Moreover, risk aversion is increasing for wealth
levels greater than about 0.99, that is for ending up wealthier at the end of 31 days than at the
beginning of those 31 days.
Inspection of Equation (4) yields insight into this behavior. The risk aversion function is
the vertical distance of two downward sloping functions (Q' / Q and P' / P). The respective
intersections with the wealth axis occur at the modes (that is the maxima) of the probability
distributions. In the precrash period, depicted in Figure 1, with about lognormal distributions for
the subjective and risk-neutral probabilities, the mean, median, and mode of each distribution tend
to lie rather close together compared to the risk premium. This changes in the postcrash period,
depicted in Figure 2, where the risk-neutral distribution suddenly exhibits a mode to the right of the
mean. The mode of the risk-neutral distribution often appears even to the right of the mean (and
mode) of the subjective distribution, causing negative risk aversion functions. The steep drop in
probability to the right of the mode of the risk-neutral distribution causes the P' / P function to fall
rapidly after intersecting the wealth axis. This leads to increasing absolute risk aversion for wealth
levels greater than about 0.99.
One way to interpret Figure 3 would simply be to believe what it suggests, namely that the
risk aversion functions changed dramatically around the crash. If all the assumptions for the
representative investor model hold true, then concavity in the utility functions implies all positive
risk aversion functions. In turn, since we observe negative risk aversion functions, we would now
have to believe that the utility functions are convex. This would lead to corner solutions where the
representative investor with a convex utility function would avoid returns in all states of the world
where the utility function is convex and would seek returns in the adjacent states where the utility
function is concave. This cannot be the case since the representative investor has to hold the
market. If we are not willing to accept the implications of Figure 3, then we might suspect that one
or more of the assumptions are violated. Here we are faced with the two usual concerns that the
S&P500 index might not be a good proxy for the market as a whole (Roll’s critique) and that the
assumptions needed for the existence of a representative investor, namely a complete market and a
state-independent utility function, might be violated. Both these questions arise in numerous studies
and have been investigated in the literature. However, advancing our understanding of these
questions takes us beyond the scope of the present paper and we will not spend time on addressing
them here.
More closely related to the present study are concerns that we might omit volatility
clustering when we compute the actual distribution. Or, the subjective distribution might not be
well approximated by the actual distribution. Specifically, investors could make mistakes in
deriving their subjective distributions from the actual distribution, which could then lead to options
being mispriced. We will now look into each of these explanations in turn.
So far, we estimated the actual distribution non-parametrically as a kernel density.
Alternatively, in order to capture volatility clustering, we also estimated the index return process
as a GARCH(1,1) model, and we simulated 10,000 31-day returns (22 trading days). The resulting
10
simulated distributions are very close to lognormal distributions, and the implied risk aversion
functions exhibit the same patterns as in Figure 3, only more pronounced.
A further explanation for the empirical findings might be that the subjective distribution is
not well approximated by the actual distribution due to the so-called peso problem. In that case,
the investor could observe a historical sample of returns, without a crash, which looks about
lognormal. However, in determining the subjective distribution the investor might well incorporate
the possibility of a crash. The investor could then arrive at a subjective distribution, which is much
more similar in shape to the risk-neutral distribution than the actual distribution would suggest.
However, the 4-year period after the crash of 1987 allows us to rule out a peso-problem: during
those 4 years, all historical samples include the crash. Therefore, the subjective distributions
reflect a crash of about 20% with a chance of one in every 4 years. Nonetheless, the risk aversion
function in Panel B of Figure 3 during the 4 years right after the crash (October 1988 - March 1991)
is u-shaped and negative around the center and thus incompatible with standard assumptions made
in economic theory. In addition, we also used historical samples spanning 2 and 10 instead of 4
years. These samples weigh the crash differently in the subjective distributions, but the risk
aversion functions are still u-shaped and negative around the center during the 2 (10) years after the
crash. We conclude that a peso problem cannot explain the empirical risk aversion functions.
However, the discussion of the peso problem leaves one more unpalatable possibility open:
investors might be overly concerned with the possibility of further crashes and therefore could have
updated their subjective beliefs about the distribution of market returns too much. The resulting
subjective distribution would in this case be left-skewed which, given any well-behaved risk
aversion function (Rubinstein (1994)), results in a similarly left-skewed risk-neutral distribution,
just as we observe empirically. The options based on this distribution would then exhibit too steep
of a volatility smile and out-of-the-money puts would be priced too high. If we now try to extract
the empirical risk aversion function from the option prices (which are affected by the mistakes of
investors) and the realized returns (which are unaffected by the mistakes) then it is to little surprise
that the risk aversion functions exhibit perverse shapes. In order to investigate this possibility
further, we note that we should be able to make money from this mispricing, and we employ the
following methodology.
During the 7 years starting in October 1988 and ending in December 1995, we select 86
trading dates one month apart. The sample is extended from an earlier version of this paper. The
additional data for 1995 provides for a true out-of-sample test, which fully supports all our
findings. Each trading period, we start out with $100 to invest, and we can invest into the riskfree
asset or into the S&P500 or we can select one of two option strategies. These involve lending
$100 and simultaneously selling puts with moneyness of either 0.95 or 1.00. The number of puts
sold is chosen such that the betas of the options strategies are about 1. We can now directly
compare the option strategies against holding the market which otherwise would be difficult as
excess returns depend on the riskiness (beta) of the strategies. Also, we insure that the margin
requirements for index options of the Chicago Board Options Exchange are always maintained.
All positions are closed out one month later, and we earn the riskfree return on our lending.
For each of the 86 one-month periods we bootstrap 1,000 sample returns from the historical
monthly index returns throughout the whole 7 year sample. Our sample does not include the crash,
but we suspect that the options are priced to reflect that possibility. We therefore compute 5
different runs where we introduce artificial crashes with a probability of one crash every 4, 8, 16,
11
and 32 years and one run without any crashes. With a crash every 4 years, we lose about 5% risk
premium per year due to crashes. Therefore, we did not model more frequent crashes since the
security market line would then slope downward. A crash is created by replacing one monthly
return during the specified period with that return times 0.8. We finally regress the returns for each
strategy against the market returns. We show in Figure 4 the expected, annualized excess returns
(alphas) across betas.
Figure 4
We find excess returns for both option trading strategies as long as the probability of a
crash does not exceed one in 8 years, and even a 20% crash every 8 years seems to be a rather
pessimistic outlook. For the strategy where we sell puts with moneyness of 1.00, we would even
come out ahead with crashes as frequent as one every four years. Above, we noticed that the
perverse shape of the risk aversion functions is not affected much by the deep-out-of-the-money
puts. Here we find the result supported in that the most profitable strategy involves selling at-the-
money puts. Also, if the same analysis is conducted for longer term options (say 180 days-to-
expiration), then the option trading strategies are generally more profitable. The reason for this
finding is that, over the next half year, it is more likely for the market to recover from a crash than
over the next month only.
A number of objections can be made. Namely, we ignore transaction costs, employ a
bootstrap method for the index returns, and use a mean-variance framework to assess the option
trading strategies. We will now address each objection in turn.
We recalculated Figure 4 with transaction costs, and the expected excess returns per year
are only 4% (2%) lower for the trading strategy involving puts of moneyness 0.95 (1.00). With
transaction costs, all positions are entered at the current bid prices observed on the trading date and
charged a 2% commission. The commission is mainly relevant for the initial sale since the puts are
often not exercised, and we therefore normally do not pay commission at expiry.
Another objection might be that the bootstrap approach changes the original sequence of
returns. We therefore use the above analysis, including the artificial crashes, in combination with
the observed returns in their historical sequence for each trading period. Figure 4 changes only
insignificantly.
Finally, in the above analysis we do not properly adjust for the risk of higher order
moments beyond mean and variance such as the negative skewness which is created by selling puts.
Recent work by Leland (1999), based on Rubinstein (1976), allows us to remedy this problem. If
the market exhibits lognormal returns (which approximately holds true for the actual returns), then
the usual beta measure should be replaced with an adjusted beta measure. Next, we can replace the
usual alpha measure with an adjusted alpha to measure the adjusted expected excess return.
However, Figure 4 does not change much when we use the adjusted measure.
The above strategies of selling puts can lose all the money invested if there are a sufficient
number of crashes and the margin is exhausted. But there are two interesting hedging strategies
available. For one, we can limit the downside risk by setting up a vertical bull spread: in addition
to every one put sold in our above positions, we buy one out-of-the-money put with moneyness of
0.90. We thereby cap our maximum losses at 5% (10%) of the index value for each put with
moneyness of 0.95 (1.00) sold. Given the number of puts typically sold, this amounts to a maximum
loss of about $25 on our initial investment of $100. We show the results of the hedged trading
strategies in Figure 5. The excess returns turn out to be similar to the excess returns of the
unhedged strategies, but the hedged strategies are significantly less sensitive to crashes.
12
Figure 5
Finally, Toft and Prucyk (1997) report that individual stock option smiles are significantly
flatter than the index option smiles in the postcrash period. Another potential hedging strategy is
therefore to sell puts on the index and to buy puts on (only a few) individual stocks. The hedge will
perform the better the more we need it since in the case of a crash, correlations across different
stocks (and the index) tend to go up (Kelly (1994)). Further research will investigate the economic
causes of negative skewness as the smile for index options is very steep compared to the smiles for
individual stock options.
4. Conclusion
The present paper models a representative investor economy in which we can empirically
determine implied risk aversion functions through simple expressions of risk aversion across
wealth in terms of the subjective and risk-neutral probability distributions, only.
The resulting risk aversion functions are largely consistent with standard assumptions made
in economic theory during the precrash period, but we find partially negative and partially
increasing risk aversion functions during the postcrash period. These findings are remarkably
stable with respect to varying input parameters. Changes in the empirical methodology do not seem
to affect the results.
Thus, we are left with either believing that risk aversion functions did indeed change
dramatically around the crash or questioning the assumptions of the model in order to explain their
radical shapes or concluding that the market misprices some options. The most likely explanation
is mispricing of options in the market since negative risk aversion functions are irreconcilable with
a representative investor and since we can defend most other assumptions of the model rather well.
A simulated trading strategy exploiting such mispricing yields risk-adjusted expected excess
returns during the postcrash period. These excess returns persist even when we account for
transaction costs and hedge the downside risk.
13
References
Aït-Sahalia, Y. and A. W. Lo, 1998, “Nonparametric Estimation of State-Price Densities Implicit
in Financial Asset Prices,” Journal of Finance, 53, 499-547.
Aït-Sahalia, Y. and A. W. Lo, 2000, “Nonparametric Risk Management and Implied Risk
Aversion,” Journal of Econometrics, 94, 9-51.
Banz, R. and M. Miller, 1978, “Prices for State-Contingent Claims: Some Estimates and
Applications,” Journal of Business, 51, 653-672.
Breeden, D. and R. Litzenberger, 1978, “Prices of State-Contingent Claims Implicit in Options
Prices,” Journal of Business, 51, 621-651.
Brown, G. and K. B. Toft, 1999, “Constructing Binomial Trees from Multiple Implied Probability
Distributions,” Journal of Derivatives, 7, 83-100.
Constantinides, G. M., 1982, “Intertemporal Asset Pricing with Heterogeneous Consumers and
without Demand Aggregation,” Journal of Business, 55, 253-267.
Derman, E., M. Kamal, I. Kani, and J. Zou, 1997, “Is the Volatility Skew Fair?,” Quantitative
Strategies Research Notes, Goldman Sachs, New York.
Härdle, W., 1990, Applied Nonparametric Regression, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Jackwerth, J. C. and M. Rubinstein, 1996, “Recovering Probability Distributions from Option
Prices,” Journal of Finance, 51, 1611-1631.
Kelly, M. A., 1994, “The U.S. Equity Market Has Become More Diversified,” J P Morgan Equity
Derivative Strategies, New York.
Leland, H., 1980, “Who Should Buy Portfolio Insurance?,” Journal of Finance, 35, 581-594.
Leland, H., 1999, “Beyond Mean-Variance: Risk and Performance Measurement in a
Nonsymmetrical World,” Financial Analyst Journal, 55, 27-36.
Melick, W. R. and C. P. Thomas, 1997, “Recovering an Asset’s Implied PDF from Option Prices:
An Application to Crude Oil During the Gulf Crisis,” Journal of Financial and Quantitative
Analysis, 32, 91-115.
Merton, R. C., 1980, “On Estimating the Expected Return on the Market: An Exploratory
Investigation,” Journal of Financial Economics, 8, 323-361.
Press, W. H., B. P. Flannery, S. A. Teukolsky, and W. T. Vetterling, 1992, Numerical Recipes in
C, (2d ed.), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Rosenberg, J. V. and R. F. Engle, 1997, “Option Hedging Using Empirical Pricing Kernels,”
working paper, New York University.
Ross, S., 1976, “Options and Efficiency,” Quarterly Journal of Economics, 90, 75-89.
Rubinstein, M., 1976, “The Valuation of Uncertain Income Streams and the Pricing of Options,”
Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science, 7, 407-425.
Rubinstein, M., 1994, “Implied Binomial Trees,” Journal of Finance, 49, 771-818.
Shimko, D., 1993, “Bounds on Probability,” RISK, 6, 33-37.
Silverman, B. W., 1986, Density Estimation for Statistics and Data Analysis, Chapman and Hall,
London.
Toft, K. B. and B. Prucyk, 1997, “Options on Leveraged Equity: Theory and Empirical Tests,”
Journal of Finance, 52, 1151-1180.
14
Figure 1. Precrash risk-neutral and actual distributions. The risk-neutral distribution is the 31-
day option implied distribution on October 22, 1986. The actual distribution is a kernel density of
the 31-day non-overlapping returns over the 4 years prior to October 22, 1986.
12
10
8
Probability
0
0.80 0.85 0.90 0.95 1.00 1.05 1.10 1.15 1.20
Wealth
15
Figure 2. Postcrash risk-neutral and actual distributions. The risk-neutral distribution is the 31-
day option implied distribution on April 15, 1992. The actual distribution is a kernel density of the
31-day non-overlapping returns over the 4 years prior to April 15, 1992.
12
10
8
Probability
0
0.80 0.85 0.90 0.95 1.00 1.05 1.10 1.15 1.20
Wealth
16
Figure 3. Risk aversion functions across wealth. For 114 days from April 2, 1986, through
December 29, 1995, we calculate the absolute risk aversion functions across wealth. A wealth
level of one corresponds to the forward price of the index where the forward contract has the same
maturity as the options used for obtaining the risk-neutral probability distribution. For each wealth
level we calculate the mean risk aversion across the periods 860402-871018 (Panel A), 881019-
910318 (Panel B), 910319-930818 (Panel C), and 930819-951229 (Panel D). In addition, we
calculate their empirical standard deviations and graph the means ± 0.5 times the standard
deviations.
Panel A: 860402 – 871018 Panel B: 881019 - 910318
20 20
15 15
10 10
5 5
Abs. Risk Aversion
0 0
0.95 0.96 0.97 0.98 0.99 1 1.01 1.02 1.03 1.04 1.05 0.95 0.96 0.97 0.98 0.99 1 1.01 1.02 1.03 1.04 1.05
-5 -5
-10 -10
-15 -15
-20 -20
Wealth Wealth
20 20
15 15
10 10
5 5
Abs. Risk Aversion
0 0
0.95 0.96 0.97 0.98 0.99 1 1.01 1.02 1.03 1.04 1.05 0.95 0.96 0.97 0.98 0.99 1 1.01 1.02 1.03 1.04 1.05
-5 -5
-10 -10
-15 -15
-20 -20
Wealth Wealth
17
Figure 4. Risk-adjusted expected excess returns of selling puts. We depict the strategy of
investing $100 in the riskfree asset and in the S&P500. Returns are calculated for 86 31-day
periods starting in October 1988 until December 1995. The market return for each 31-day period
is bootstrapped from the complete 7-year sample. In four runs, artificial crashes of -20% during
one month are added every 4, 8, 16, and 32 years on average and in a fifth run, no crashes are
added. We report the average of the 86 expected excess returns (alphas) across betas. The
expected excess returns for the riskless asset and the market are zero with betas of 0 and 1
respectively. We also report two strategies of lending $100 and selling puts with moneyness levels
of 0.95 and 1.00. The number of puts sold is chosen such that the strategies have a beta of about 1
if there is a crash every 8 years.
0.25
16 8
market
0.1
riskfree
4 put 0.95
0.05 8 put 1.00
risk-free
market
0
0 0.5 1 1.5 2
-0.05 4
-0.1
beta
18
Figure 5. Risk-adjusted expected excess returns of hedged strategies. We depict the strategy
of investing $100 in the riskfree asset and in the S&P500. Returns are calculated for 86 31-day
periods starting in October 1988 until December 1995. The market return for each 31-day period
is bootstrapped from the complete 7-year sample. In four runs, artificial crashes of -20% during
one month are added every 4, 8, 16, and 32 years on average and in a fifth run, no crashes are
added. We report the average of the 86 expected excess returns (alphas) across betas. The
expected excess returns for the riskless asset and the market are zero with betas of 0 and 1
respectively. We also report two strategies of lending $100, buying a put with moneyness of 0.90,
and selling puts with moneyness levels of 0.95 and 1.00. The number of puts bought and sold is
chosen such that the strategies have a beta of about 1 if there is a crash every 8 years.
0.25
no crashes
0.2 32 no crashes
16 8
4
0.15
8
annualized alpha
market
0.1
4 riskfree
put 0.95
0.05 put 1.00
risk-free market
0
0 0.5 1 1.5 2
-0.05
-0.1
beta
19
Endnotes
1
For alternative methods see Rubinstein (1994), Shimko (1993), and the extensions in Brown and
Toft (1999) for polynomial interpolation of the smile. Melick and Thomas (1997) use lognormal
mixtures and Aït-Sahalia and Lo (1998) use kernels. Earlier, theoretical papers are Banz and
Miller (1978), Breeden and Litzenberger (1978), and Ross (1976).
2
The implied volatility (σ*) causes the Black-Scholes formula to accurately price the option in the
market: C = sd − t N ( x ) − Kr − t N ( x − σ * t ) , where s is the index level, d the dividend yield, t the
sd −t
ln −t
time, N(•) the cumulative normal distribution, x = Kr + 12 σ * t , and K the strike price.
σ t
*
3
See Silverman (1986), p. 15. This choice of a bandwidth leads to slight over-smoothing but
removes spurious multi-modalities. These multi-modalities are due to the small sample size of
only 48 returns over the past 4 years. Solving an optimization problem, which searches for the
smoothest distribution consistent with the actual returns gives very similar results but is
significantly slower.
4
We also investigate bootstrapped error bounds. They are very similar and only somewhat tighter
than the empirical bounds and, therefore, we do not graph them separately. For those error bounds,
we assume that the non-overlapping historical returns are independent and identically distributed;
and we then sample 100 times with replacement. Each new set of non-overlapping returns can be
viewed as another sample, and we recalculate the risk aversion functions. For each day, we
calculate the mean risk aversion levels across wealth and the mean levels ± 0.5 times their
standard deviations. For each of our periods, we finally calculate the means of the risk aversion
functions and their bounds. See Press et al. (1992), pp. 689, for a very clear introduction and
Härdle (1990), p. 105, for further details on the bootstrap method.
20