W. de Regt H. (2009) - The Epistemic Value of Understanding
W. de Regt H. (2009) - The Epistemic Value of Understanding
W. de Regt H. (2009) - The Epistemic Value of Understanding
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
The University of Chicago Press, Philosophy of Science Association are collaborating with
JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy of Science
This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 20:05:00 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Epistemic Value of Understanding
Henk W. de Regt†‡
This article analyzes the epistemic value of understanding and offers an account of
the role of understanding in science. First, I discuss the objectivist view of the relation
between explanation and understanding, defended by Carl Hempel and J. D. Trout. I
challenge this view by arguing that pragmatic aspects of explanation are crucial for
achieving the epistemic aims of science. Subsequently, I present an analysis of these
pragmatic aspects in terms of ‘intelligibility’ and a contextual account of scientific
understanding based on this notion.
†To contact the author, please write to: Faculty of Philosophy, VU University Amsterdam,
De Boelelaan 1105, 1081 HV Amsterdam, The Netherlands; e-mail: [email protected].
‡I thank Hans Radder for comments on an earlier version of this article.
Philosophy of Science, 76 (December 2009) pp. 585–597. 0031-8248/2009/7605-0008$10.00
Copyright 2009 by the Philosophy of Science Association. All rights reserved.
585
This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 20:05:00 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
586 HENK W. DE REGT
This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 20:05:00 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
EPISTEMIC VALUE OF UNDERSTANDING 587
This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 20:05:00 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
588 HENK W. DE REGT
This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 20:05:00 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
EPISTEMIC VALUE OF UNDERSTANDING 589
This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 20:05:00 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
590 HENK W. DE REGT
Second, the fact that particular skills of the scientist are crucial for
constructing and evaluating explanations and for achieving understanding
entails that explanation has a pragmatic dimension that is epistemically
relevant. Many philosophers of science hold that the pragmatic and the
epistemic dimension of science can and should be kept separate. Thus,
Hempel (1965, 426) argues that scientific laws, theories, and explanations
are “objective in the sense that their empirical implications and their
evidential support are independent of what particular individuals happen
to test or to apply them” and that philosophers of science should therefore
construct “a nonpragmatic concept of scientific explanation” that “does
not require relativization with respect to questioning individuals.” In a
similar vein, Bas van Fraassen (1980, 4, 88) explicitly contrasts an epi-
stemic and a pragmatic dimension of theory acceptance. The epistemic
dimension contains the relevant beliefs concerning the relation between
a theory and the world, while the pragmatic dimension contains reasons
scientists may have for accepting a theory independently of their beliefs
about its relation to the world; these reasons typically pertain to the use
and usefulness of the theory. In contrast to Hempel, van Fraassen (1980,
Chapter 5) argues that explanation is not an epistemic aim of science but
rather belongs to the pragmatic dimension of theory acceptance. Both
Hempel and van Fraassen see the epistemic and the pragmatic as sharply
distinguished domains. On their view, the pragmatic dimension pertains
to the relation between the theory and its users, that is, to the dimension
that seems to be excluded from the epistemic dimension by definition.
The thesis that the epistemic and the pragmatic can and should be kept
separate presupposes that the epistemic status of a theory exclusively
depends on a direct evidential relation with the phenomena it purports
to describe or explain. On this presupposition, pragmatic elements—for
example, virtues of a theory that facilitate its use by scientists—are indeed
epistemically irrelevant: they do not carry any additional justificatory
weight. However, as the previous discussion of the role of skills in de-
ductive reasoning has made clear, this presupposition is false. Skills and
judgment are required for the establishing and evaluating relations be-
tween theories and phenomena (e.g., deductive-nomological explana-
tions). It follows that, although it is possible and useful to distinguish
analytically between the epistemic and the pragmatic, the two are inex-
tricably intertwined in scientific practice: epistemic activities and evalu-
ations (production and assessment of knowledge claims) are possible only
if particular pragmatic conditions are fulfilled.
Thus, the pragmatic dimension of explanation is epistemically relevant.
This is the case for deductive-nomological explanations but even more so
for scientific explanations that do not conform to the deductive-nomo-
logical ideal. And the latter are the rule rather than the exception in
This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 20:05:00 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
EPISTEMIC VALUE OF UNDERSTANDING 591
1. Note, however, that there are widely different accounts of representation, and that the
target systems of models may be real, fictional, or ideal (Knuuttila 2005).
This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 20:05:00 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
592 HENK W. DE REGT
2. These virtues are called ‘values’ by Kuhn, Longino, and Lacey. I use the term ‘virtues’
in order to avoid confusion: the virtue is a property of the theory, which may be valued
by scientists.
This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 20:05:00 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
EPISTEMIC VALUE OF UNDERSTANDING 593
3. It often happens that a theory can be represented in different ways (think of the various
formulations of classical mechanics), and each of these representations may have its own
specific virtues, which may be relevant to the intelligibility of the theory.
4. It may be the case that there is a discrepancy between scientists’ perception of the
fruitfulness of a theory and its actual fruitfulness for these scientists. Such errors of
judgment will hamper their work. I assume that they are the exception rather than the
rule.
This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 20:05:00 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
594 HENK W. DE REGT
5. To be sure, these requirements are included in the list of theoretical virtues that are
subject to valuation by scientists. Accordingly, there may be some variation in the way
they are valued and applied in specific cases. However, they are clearly generally accepted
among scientists, and explanations that completely fail to meet them will generally be
rejected as unscientific.
This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 20:05:00 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
EPISTEMIC VALUE OF UNDERSTANDING 595
This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 20:05:00 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
596 HENK W. DE REGT
REFERENCES
This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 20:05:00 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
EPISTEMIC VALUE OF UNDERSTANDING 597
Shanks, David R. (2005), “Implicit Learning”, in Koen Lamberts and Robert Goldstone
(eds.), Handbook of Cognition. London: Sage, 202–220.
Trout, J. D. (2002), “Scientific Explanation and the Sense of Understanding”, Philosophy
of Science 69: 212–233.
——— (2007), “The Psychology of Explanation”, Philosophy Compass 2: 564–596.
van Fraassen, Bas C. (1980), The Scientific Image. Oxford: Clarendon.
This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 20:05:00 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms