Hazout 1991 Thèse

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 454

VERBAL NOUNS: THETA THEORETIC STUDIES IN

HEBREW AND ARABIC

A Dissertation Presented

by

ILAN HAZOUT

Submitted to the Graduate School of the


University of Massachusetts in partial fulfillment
of the requirements for the degree of i

DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY

May 1991

Department of Linguistics

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Copyright by Ilan Hazout 1991
All Rights Reserved

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
VERBAL NOUNS: THETA THEORETIC STUDIES IN

HEBREW AND ARABIC

A Dissertation Presented

by

ILAN HAZOUT

Approved as to style and content by:

Elizabeth Selkirk, Chair

F. Higgins Member

Shmuel Bolozky, Member

Barbara H. Partee, Department Head


Department of Linguistics

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
This Dissertation is dedicated

to the memory of

NURIT HAZOUT

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

I would like to thank the members of my dissertation


committee, Shmuel Bolozky, Roger Higgins and Lisa

Selkirk. Roger and Lisa read earlier drafts of this


dissertation and made many helpful comments. In
particular, Roger's comments on two earlier drafts were

extremely detailed and helpful and led to many

substantial improvements.

Thanks to Edwin Williams under whose direction most


of this work was written. The influence of his work can

be recocnized throughout this dissertation. The elegance


of Edwin’s work and his teaching style won my admiration

from the very beginning. His sympathy and encouragement

were important for the development of this work.


I have had some interaction with my fellow students
at the Umass linguistics department over the last four
years. This has always been an enjoyable experience and
I should therefore be thankful to Rose-Marie Dechaine,

Gingi Fu, Greg Lamontaigne, Reine Pinsonneault ,


Bernadette Plunkette, Roger Schwarzshild, Tim Sherer,
Karina Wilkinson and Sandro Zucchi.
I would have hoped that the completion of this

dissertation would bring some joy into my sister,


Nurit's, life. Sadly, she didn't live to see this

moment. This dissertation is dedicated to her memory.

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
ABSTRACT

VERBAL NOUNS: THETA THEORETIC STUDIES IN

HEBREW AND ARABIC

MAY 1991

ILAN HAZOUT, LICENCE, UNIVERSITE DE PARIS VIII

MAITRISE, UNIVERSITE DE PARIS VIII

Ph.d. UNIVERSITY OF MASSACHUSETTS

Directed by: Professor Elizabeth Selkirk

This dissertation is a study of a variety of

constructions in Modern Hebrew and Standard Arabic which

involve nominalization processes. Such constructions

manifest a certain mixture of verbal and nominal

properties and are analyzed as involving a verbal

subconstituent, a VP, governed by an underlying nominal

head, a nominalizer . The surface form of the deverbal

head of such constructions is . the output of a head

movement operation adjoining a verb to the nominalizer

which governs it. The properties and the differences

between the different types of nominalization

constructions are explained on the basis of ceratin

assumptions about the thematic properties, the argument

structure, of the different nominalizers that are

postulated. The heads of nominalization constructions

are morphological as well as thematic nominalizers in

that they provide, in addition to a particular •-

vi

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
morphological shape, an argument structure particular to
nouns. In this approach to verbal nouns, the mixed

properties of these costructions are derived from the


properties of underlying verbs and nouns occurring within

a particular configuration.

This approach to nominalizations is embedded within


a particular approach to thematic relations and argument

structure combined with theoretical techniques developed

in recent work within the Government and Binding theory,


in particular, the operation known as head movement.

Chapter 1 presents the main theoretical assumptions


and includes some proposals concerning the structure of
infinitival clauses and the phenomenon of obligatory

control. Chapter 2 is a comprehensive study of genitive

constructions in Hebrew and Arabic. Chapter 3 is a study


of Action Nominalization constructions and includes a

detailed argumentation in a favour of a non-lexicalist


approach. Chapter 4 investigates and compares the
properties of two types of infinitival constructions,

standard infinitives and the verbal gerund, a

construction which is particular to Modern Hebrew.


Chapter 5 studies the Agent Nominalization construction
and the Benoni relative, a construction which is analyzed
as involving a definite article functioning as a thematic
nominalizer and an abstract adjectival morpheme which

functions as a morphological nominalizer.

vii

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
TABLE OF CONTENTS

Page
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS ........................................... V

ABSTRACT .................................................. vi

CHAPTER

I INTRODUCTION ......................................... 1

1.1 Head Movement, Morphology


and Syntax .................................. 11
1.2 Principles of Theta Theory ................. 23

1.2.1 Argument Structure, Theta


Roles and Theta Structure ............. 23
1.2.2 Types of Thematic Relatedness ........ 28
1.2.3 Infinitival Clauses
and Control............................ 32

1.3 Levels of Representation ................... 43

Footnotes to Chapter I................. 47

II THE SYNTAX OF GENITIVE CONSTRUCTIONS ......... ..49

2.1 Bound Genitives (The Construct State) ..... 51

2.1.1 The Data............................... 51


2.1.2 The Complement Approach
to Bound Genitives .................... 60
2.1.3 A Specifier Approach to Bound
Genitives: The Head Movement
Analysis ............................... 78

2.2 The Interpretation of Genitive


Constructions: Identification and
Classification .............................. 92
2.3 Sei Phrases and Double Genitives ......... 103

Footnotes to Chapter II ........................ 123

viii

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Ill THE SYNTAX Of ACTION NOMINALIZATIONS 129

3.1 Introduction .......................... .129

3.1.1 Nominal Properties of Action


Nominalizations .................. .130

3.1.2 Verbal Properties of Action


Nominalizations .................. .134
3.1.3 Binding and Control.............. ..138

3.2 Active Action Nominalizations ........ ..141

3.2.1 The Head Movement Analysis ...... ..141

3 . 2 . 1 .1 More About the Facts ........ ,.141


3. 2. 1.2 The Syntactic Derivation
of Active Action
Nominalizations .............. ..148

3.2.2 Syntactic vs. Lexicalist


Approaches to Action
Nominalizations .................. ..163

3. 2. 2.1 A lexicalist Analysis:


First Version................ ,.164
3. 2. 2. 2 A Lexicalist Analysis:
Second Version............... ,.172

3. 2. 2. 2.1 The Distribution of


Adverbs and Adjective... ..174
3. 2. 2. 2. 2 Free Genitive Variants.. ..175
3. 2. 2. 2. 3 Subjectless Action
Nominalizations and
Control.................. ..181
3. 2. 2. 3 The Interpretation of Action
Nominalizations .............. . .186
3. 2. 2. 4 Causative Constructions
in Arabic.................... . .296

3.3 Subjectless Action Nominalizations... . .222

3.3.1 Introduction ..................... . .222


3.3.2 Arguments Against a
Passivization Analysis .......... . .232

Verbs Which Don't Passivize... . .234


Verbs Which Do Passivize ...... . .237
Anaphors ....................... . .241
Control Structures in Arabic.. . .241

ix

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
3.3.3 Burzio's Generalization? ............. 243
3.3.4 The Structure of Subjectless
Action Nominalizations ....... ....... 248

3. 3. 4.1 Bound Forms and Genitive


Case Assignment .................. 248
3. 3. 4. 2 Control .......................... 259

Footnotes to Chapter 3......................... 266

IV INFINITIVES AND GERUNDS ........................ 277

4.1 Introduction ............................... 277


4.2 Verbal Gerunds............................. 284

4.2.1 The Structure of


Infinitival Clauses .................. 284
4.2.2 The Structure of Verbal Gerunds ..... 289

4. 2. 2.1 A Sentential Analysis of


Verbal Gerunds (I).............. 289
4. 2. 2. 2 A Non-Sentential Analysis of
Verbal Gerunds .................. 295
4. 2. 2. 3 A Sentential Analysis of
Verbal Gerunds (II)............. 299

4.2.3 The General Analysis of Infinitives:


Some Implications .................... 319

4.3 Nominal Gerunds 329

4.3.1 Introduction ......................... 329


4.3.2 Nominal Properties of
Nominal Gerunds ...................... 332
4.3.3 Verbal Properties of
Nominal Gerunds ...................... 334
4.3.4 The Structure of Nominal Gerunds .... 338

Footnotes to Chapter IV .......................... 348

V THE SYNTAX OF PARTICIPIAL CONSTRUCTIONS ......... 352

5.1 Introduction ................................. 352

5.1.1 An Overview............................. 352


5.1.2 Participles As Verbs................... 358

5.2 Agent Nominalizations ....................... 363


5.3 Benoni (participial) Relatives .............. 393

Footnotes to Chapter V........................... 419

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
APPENDICES

APPENDIX TO CHAPTER II: ADJECTIVAL BOUND


GENITIVES
............................................ 421
APPENDIX TO CHAPTER III: THE PARTICLE "ET" AND
ACCUSATIVE CASE MARKING............................. 429

REFERENCES.......................................... 435

xi

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
CHAPTER I

INTRODUCTION

One of the major linguistic distinctions, a

distinction which has been made by both linguists and

philosophers since the time of antiquity, is the one

between verbs and nouns. Thus, Aristotle (De

Interpretations, Chapters 2-3) distinguishes between

nouns, which he characterizes as significant sounds which

have no reference to time and verbs which he

characterizes as "that which, in addition to its proper

meaning, carries with it the notion of time".

The almost unquestionable status of the distinction

between verbs and nouns is certainly justified in view of

its attestability throughout the languages of the world.

Thus, in a recent typological study, Schachter (1985)

observes that "the distinction between nouns and verbs is

one of the few apparently universal part-of-speech

distinctions". As Schachter notes, although the

universality of this distinction has sometimes been

questioned, "it now seems that the counterexamples have

been based on incomplete data, and that there are no

languages that cannot be said to show a verb-noun

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
distinction when all relevant facts are taken into
account" (underlining is mine [I.H.]).

Notwithstanding the fairly well established status


of the noun-verb distinction, the criteria to be employed
for part-of-speech classification and the verb-noun
distinction are somewhat less clear. The intuitively
most immediate criteria for defining verbs and nouns are
the familiar semantic, or notional, part-of-speech
definitions. Thus, the notional definition of noun would
be as a name of a person, place or thing whereas verbs
would be defined as words that express actions, processes
and the like. Clearly, the idea of time has always been
central to the notional noun-verb dichotomy, as can be
observed in Aristotle's definition of this distinction
cited above. However, as claimed by Schachter (1985), it
has been amply demonstrated in the linguistic literature

that the familiar notional definitions fail to provide an


adequate basis for part- of-speech classification since

there are many cases in which their applicability or

inapplicability is unclear.
Other criteria for part-of-speech classification

which seem to be fairly well established are grammatical


criteria. Grammatical criteria have to do with the

distribution of a word and the range of its syntactic


functions as well as the morphological and syntactic

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
categories for which it may be specified. Thus, we may
observe that in a sentence such as the following,

1- detectives chase criminals

the words detectives and chase can be shown to differ in


their distribution.

*2- chase detectives criminals

detectives and chase also differ in their functional


range. Thus, detectives but not chase can function as
the subject of a sentence. Morphologically, detectives
is specified for number but not for tense, whereas chase

is specified for both number and tense. These two words


are therefore assigned to two distinct part-of-speech

classes .
On the other hand, the words detectives and
criminals have highly similar distribution and functional
range ,

3- criminals chase detectives

and can be morphologically specified for the same type of


feature distinctions. They are therefore assigned to the
same part-of-speech class.

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Clearly, the criteria employed for the assignment of
a certain word to a particular part-of-speech class are
often language particular rather than universal.

However, as noted by Schachter (1985) , the

characterization of a set of words as belonging to a


certain part-of-speech class mostly reflects universal
and crosslinguistically valid semantic considerations.
The distinction between nominal and verbal is also
standardly applied to the immediate syntactic environment
in which verbs and nouns occur. Thus, a Noun Phrase, a
collocation of words which is typically characterized as
nominal, may be said to inherit certain typically nominal
properties, or feature specifications (number, gender
etc.) from one of its members (its head noun) and to obey
certain collocation restrictions characteristic of noun
phrases. Equally, a Verb Phrase, a constituent "headed”
by a verb, may be said to inherit some of the properties
of its head (e.g. its external theta-role) and to obey

certain internal collocation restrictions which


distinguish it from a Noun Phrase.

To enumerate just a few of the more typical and


crosslinguistically observable collocation restrictions,
nouns may be typically accompanied by adjectives which
may be said to function as the modifiers of such nouns.
The occurrence of quantifier expressions and definite
articles is also typical NP internally. A noun, the head

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
of an NP, may also be accompanied by another NP which
would be marked with Genitive Case, or else governed by a
preposition, rather than being "directly" related to the
head noun. Verbs, on the other hand, may be accompanied
by a modifying adverbial expression. A verb may also be

accompanied by an NP which need not necessarily be


preceded (or followed, in some languages) by a
preposition. In such a case the NP may be said to be
directly related to (governed, or licensed by) the verb
and may, in languages such as Hebrew and Arabic, be
morphologically marked in a different way from a genitive
NP, namely, it may be marked with Accusative Case. Thus,

the characterization as nominal or verbal applies to


single lexical elements as well as to complex syntactic

constituents and may be fairly safely established on the


basis of certain crosslinguistically observed

regularities.

Verbal Nouns, a class of constructions with which


this dissertation is concerned, are of mixed nature in
that they manifest properties typical of verbs and VP's
as well as properties typical of nouns and NP’s. They,
thus, disturb the otherwise fairly clear cut distinction
between nominal and verbal constituents and for this
reason represent a major challenge to linguistic theory.
The main concern of this dissertation will be a class
of constructions, to be referred to as Nominalization

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Constructions, of which the following are typical
examples (the designations H and A are short for Hebrew
and Arabic respectively and will be used throughout this

dissertation)

4- (H) Action Nominalization:

axilat Dan et ha-tapuax bi-mhirut


eating Dan OM the apple quickly
"Dan's eating of the apple quickly"
5- (H) Nominal Gerund:

cet-o ha-maftia Sei ha-nasi im alot

depart-his the surprising Sei the president with break


ha-Saxar
the dawn

"The president's surprising departure with the break


of dawn"
6- (A) Agent Nominalization:

muSarrib -u l-?awlaad-i 1-Haliib-a

make-drink-er-Nom the kids -Gen the milk -Acc


"The one who makes the kids drink the milk"

Let us briefly point out what the mixed nature of these

constructions consists of. First, all three

constructions above are NP's, as far as their sentence


internal distribution is concerned, that is, they relate
to their syntactic environment just like any other NP.

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Their mixed nature relates therefore mainly to their
internal structure. Typical to all these constructions
is that the head noun, the noun which determines the

gender and number specification of the construction as a


whole (underlined in 4-6) , is morphologically related to

a certain verb. Moreover, just like a verb, the head of


such constructions may be accompanied by a direct object

marked with Accusative Case (examples 4,6) as well as by


other constituents which would normally be taken to be
the arguments of the corresponding verb. We may say that
the noun heading such a construction inherits the

argument structure of a verb. As examples 4,5 above


show, Nominalization constructions clearly allow the

occurrence of adverbs, a typical verbal property.


As to their internal nominal properties, let us just
note that the nouns heading these constructions are
always accompanied by an NP, an argument of the related

verb, to which they may be said to be related in a

genitive type of relation. This clearly shows on the

Case marking of the NP, or its head. Finally, as shown


in 5, the head of a nominalization construction may be
modified by an adjective, again, a typical nominal
property.

This mixture of properties is problematic to the


extent that the verb/noun distinction, as noted earlier,

is based mainly on the observation that a certain cluster

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
of properties is, in the general case, associated with a

certain class of elements to the exclusion of others.

However, in view of the mixed properties of verbal

nouns, it becomes, a t least, unclear to what extent our

view of the basic inventory of lexical elements in the

languages under consideration, as well as generally, can

be maintained or is in need of revision.

Thus, the main question facing us is how to explain,

or derive, this mixed nature of verbal houns. Here two

main approaches come to mind, the first would be to admit

that, besides verbs and nouns, the languages in question

also have a class of lexical elements that are of a mixed

nature, that is, elements which share properties with

both verbs and nouns and the constituents of which they

may be said to be the heads sh re some of the syntactic

properties of both NP's and VP’s. A second approach

would deny the possibility that there exist such things

as lexical elements of mixed catégorial nature. Rather,

the basic underlying inventory of lexical elements would

include, on thi” approach, only "strict" nouns and verbs.

Elements and constituents of mti.xed, verbo-nominal , nature

would, on such an approach, be derived rather than basic.

That is, they would only be the product of certain

processes to which verbs and nouns may serve as input.

Thus, we might say that in this, second, approach the

properties of verbal nouns are reduced to the properties

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
of verbs and nouns. We may therefore refer to this

approach as the reductionist approach and to the other,


opposing, approach as the non-reductionist approach.
The considerations in favour or against ope of these
two approaches may be of two main kinds . They can 1 be

general, theoretical or metatheoretical in character,


that is, they may involve considerations that would have
to do with a certain overall picture of the theory of
grammar and would involve notions such as simplicity,

elegance and the like. Thus, in making such i


considerations one might wish to claim that, given
certain notions of simplicity or elegance, a reductionist

approach is to be preferred as simpler or more elegant.

It is clear, however, that any discussion of tl is issue


must take into consideration mainly the empiriqal |

advantages of each of the approaches described above.


That is, given a certain set of basic assumptiqns

concerning the form of underlying representations and the


kinds of elements that may figure in such

representations , and given also the grammatical


mechanisms that may be assumed to be available for the
derivation of surface representations, the empirical
question would be how many of the known empiriqal facts
may be accounted for on the basis of each of ttyese two

main (the reductionist and the non-reductionist)


approaches .

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
This dissertation takes a rather clear position on
these issues. Chapters 3, 4 and 5 will present a

detailed argumentation in favour of a reductionist

approach to the analysis of each of the verbo-nominal

constructions to be considered. Moreover, the


argumentation in favour of this position will be strictly

empirical in character. Global considerations of


metatheoretical character will play no role.

As just stated, in a reductionist approach such as


the one defended in this dissertation only verbs and
nouns are assumed to exist and therefore only verbs and

nouns may be assumed to figure in syntactic deep

structures. It follows that the main task of the


analysis to be developed will be to show how the surface
manifestations of such constructions, in particular,

their mixed verbo-nominal properties are to be derived,

or explained. In developing such an analysis we will


make use of some recent theoretical developments. In
particular, we will make crucial use of recent proposals
concerning the interaction between syntax and word
formation. The centerpiece of these recent developments
is the transformational process known as head to head

movement. The elaboration and development of this

mechanism is due mainly to the work of Travis (1984) and,


most prominently, Baker (1985,1988). A second set of

theoretical assumptions we will adopt will include much

10

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
of the recent theoretical developments dealing with the

nature and distribution of theta roles and the

implications of a certain particular conception of theta

roles known as Theta-Theory, with respect to other

modules of the grammar. These recent developments are

due mainly to the work of E. Williams (e.g. Williams

1987a, 1987b, 1989) . The following sections present the

theoretical assumptions which will be the foundation on

which the analyses developed in the next four chapters

will be based.

1.1 Head Movement, Morphology and Syntax

This dissertation adopts and defends the view that

words may be the product of syntactic processes. Much

recent work in syntactic theory has been devoted to the

development of this idea. The work of Baker (1985,1988)

has been particularly influential in this respect.

The syntactic process of incorporation, applying to

two, or more, morphemes to create a morphologically

complex word, becomes possible if it is assumed that the

general transformation move- Alpha may also apply when

the bar level of the element to be affected by i t is

zero. This particular case of move-alpha is now

generally known as head movement.

11

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Head movement is subject to generally assumed
constraints. Travis (1984) suggests a locality condition
on head movement in the form of the following constraint.

7- The Head Movement Constraint (HMC)


An X° may only move into the Y°
which properly governs it.

This constraint imposes a restriction on head movement in


terms of the configuration existing prior to its

application. Baker (1988) shows that the HMC can be


derived from the ECP, a condition which applies to the
output of a movement operation and imposes certain

constraints on the structure created by a movement. The


ECP is formulated as follows.

8- Traces must be properly governed

8 makes use of the notion of proper government which is

defined as follows.

9- A properly governs B iff A governs B and A and B are


coindexed

9, in turn, presupposes the notion of government which is


defined as follows,

12

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
10- A governs B iff A c-commands B and there is no

category C such that C is a barrier between A and B.

Note that government is only one part of the requirement


of proper government. The other part, namely, the

requirement of coindexation may be satisfied in two ways.


First, a proper governor may theta-mark a trace, in which
case the trace and its theta-marker are coindexed.
Otherwise a coindexation between a trace and its governor
may arise if the two elements are related to each other
by movement, in which case they are coindexed. It is
this second type of coindexation relation which is most

relevant for head movement and the relation between a


moved head and its trace. This relation is constrained
by the structural conditions which are specified by the

definition of government in 10, namely c-command and


barrierhood. I will follow Baker (1988) on these two
points. First, as Baker shows, the c-command definition
relevant for head movement is the one of Aoun and
Sportiche (1983) which is formulated in terms of maximal
projections as follows.

11- A c-commands B iff A does not dominate B and for any


maximal projection C, if C dominates A then C
dominates B.

13

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
To illustrate, in a configuration like the following, it
must be YP and not Y* which counts as the relevant node

for c-command.

12- YP

/ \
Y* XP

/ \ / \
Xi Y X ZP

I
ti

Clearly, it must be assumed that Y* does not count in

order for some sort of head movement to be possible at


all.

The second requirement in the definition of


government in 10 is that there be no barrier between a
governor and a governee. Baker's (1988) definition of
barrier goes as follows.

14

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
13 - Let D be the s m a l l e s t maximal projection containing

A . Then C is a barrier between A and B if and only

if C is a maximal projection that contains B and

excludes A and either

i) C is not selected

ii) The head of C is distinct from the head of D

and selects some WP equal t o or containing B.

To illustrate, consider the two following configurations.

14- a) XP b) XP

/ \ / \

X' X'

/ \ / \

X° YP X° ** * YP

/ \ \ / \ \

Yi X° Y' Zi X° Y*

/ \ / \

Y Y° '~~ * ZP

ti Z*

ti

15

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
In 14a Yi c-commands its trace inside YP, but YP is not

selected by X, therefore it constitutes a barrier and 14a


is ruled out by the ECP given clause (i) of 13. YP in

14a may be taken to exemplify the case of adjunct

clauses .
13ii, in Bakers's words, is a "minimality condition

expressing the fact that an intervening theta assigner


breaks a government path". Thus, in 14b ZP is selected
by Y° but since YP does not contain X, YP is a barrier to

government of the trace of Z by Z. This definition of


Barrierhood makes use of the notion of selection. Let us

consider first Baker's definition of this notion and then


motivate a certain deviation from it. Baker (1988)

defines selection as follows.

15 - A selects B if and only if:

i) A assigns a theta role to B


ii) A is of category C and B is its IP
iii) A is of category I and B is its VP

15 seems to be unsatisfactory in some respects.

Considering first 15i, to the extent that 15 as the

definition of selection makes part of the definition of


barrierhood and therefore, indirectly, of the general
definition of the relation of government, 15i seems to
cover a larger territory than necessary since the subject

16

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
of a sentence is assigned a theta role by a verb (or by
VP, or by I') but is not governed by it (or by VP, or by
I'). As to 15ii and 15iii, these clauses do not really
provide a definition of selection but simply stipulate
that the relation between an element of category C and IP

and the relation between an element of category I and VP

is one of selection.

In general , there are two ways in which lexical

requirements holding between a head and a constituent


governed by it are encoded in lexical representations,
namely, theta-role assignment and subcategorization

specifications. Now, as just observed, theta-role

assignment holds not only between a governor and its

complement but also between a verb (or VP) and its


subject. On the other hand, it is largely assumed that

subcategorization requirements hold only between a head


and its complement. Thus, within the domain dominated by
an X' node, subcategorization features are specified with

respect to any lexically required complement. It follows

that every complement which is assigned a theta-role is


also subcategorized for. Note, however, that the

opposite does not hold. That is, not every


subcategorized element is assigned a theta-role. This

is, presumably, the case with the relation between a


complementizer and IP as well as the relation between

INFL and VP. This dissertation is concerned with a

17

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
family of constructions which may be analyzed as

involving an underlying nominal bound morpheme which


stands to a VP in exactly the same kind of relation,

namely, it subcategorizes for a VP but does not assign a

theta-role to it. Thus, if this way to view things is


correct then selection can be reduced to

subcategorization. We can therefore simplify 15 to the


following statement.

16- A selects B if B satisfies subcategorization

requirements for which A is lexically specified.

Note now that an output configuration such as 14b would

still be possible even if all the constraints introduced


so far are assumed. This would be possible if Z in 14b

underwent a successive cyclic movement, adjoining first


to Y and then to X. This would yield the following

configuration.

18

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
17 - XP

/ \
X'

/ \
X YP

/ \ / \
Zi X Y*

/ \
Y ZP

/ \ / \
ti Y Z'

/ \
Z

I
ti

However, as Baker (1988) argues, this may be excluded if


one assumes that the rule of move-alpha may not move a
part of a word. The following filter may capture this

principle.

18 - *[x° ti ]

Given 18 the only possible successive cyclic application


of head movement to 14b is the one which results in 19.

19

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
19- XP

/ \
X’

/ \
X YP

/ \ / \
Y X Y'

/ \ / \
Z Y Y ZP

I / \
ti Z*

/ \
Z

I
ti

The output of an application of head movement , such as

[y Z Y ] in 19 above, may be an actual morphologically


complex word. But it can also be an abstract object

which is still to undergo a process of morphological


"interpretation" or "spelling out".

Most of the constructions to be studied in this

dissertation are cases for which some sort of further


morphological interpretation needs to be assumed. To be
more concrete, chapters 3, 4 and 5 will study

constructions of a general structure as the following.

20

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
20- a) NP b) NP

/ \ / \
N' =======> N*

/ \ / \
N VP N VP

1 / \ / \ / \
X V YP Vi XV YP

ti

In 2 0 a a nominal bound morpheme (X) s u b c a t e g o r i z e s for a


VP . The verb heading VP i s adjoined to X by the

application o f h ead movement a s shown in 2 0 b . For


reasons to b e d i s c u s s e d in chapter 3 (section 3. 2. 1.2) it
is necessary to assume that X in 2 0 a , b i s an a b s t r a c t

element rathe r than an actual morpheme w i t h a c o n c r e t e

morphological and phonological shape. Thus, X is an


element w hich combines with a verb to produce a unique
nominal form which i s lexically listed for the p a r t i c u l a r

verb in q u e s t i o n . This is not an i m p l a u s i b l e assumption


if one as su mes that the derived nominal form o f a

pa r t i c ular verb is pa r t of its lexical entry. It is

therefore available for "spelling out" at the n e c e s s a r y


point in the d e r i v a t i o n .

A configuration such a s 2 0 a in which a bound morpheme


(X) , a " n o m i n a l i z e r " , heads an NP and governs a VP w i l l

21

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
be referred to as a Nominalization Construction. The

application of head movement adjoining V to X as in 20b,


of which the output is an abstract deverbal head, will be

referred to as a syntactic process of Nominalization.


The following chapters will study a number of such

constructions. The differences between the different


Nominalization constructions will be shown to follow from
the properties of the particular nominal heads (the X of

20) to be postulated, in particular, their thematic, or

argument, structure. This will presuppose an overall

conception of the nature and distribution of theta roles,


in particular, a certain set of principles to be

referred to as theta theory. The following section is

devoted to these matters.

22

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
1.2 Principles of Theta Theory

The set of assumptions and principles presented in this

section are mostly adopted from the work of E. Williams, in

particular, Williams (1987a) , (1987b) and (1989) as well as

Di Sciullo and Williams (1987). However, Some of the ideas

suggested here, in particular, the ideas concerning the

structure of infinitival clauses and obligatory control

(section 1.2.3) are novel and were developed in an attempt to

deal with certain issues that are particular to

Nominalization constructions in Hebrew and Arabic. I should

therefore assume full responsibility for these ideas as well

as for the rest.

1.2.1 - Argument Structure, Theta Roles and Theta Structure

The basis for thematic relations is the argument

structure of predicates. The argument structure of a

predicate is a list of its theta roles (Agent, Theme, Goal

etc. ) with one of the theta roles distinguished as the

external theta role. The other theta roles are thus

internal. Nouns, just like verbs and adjectives, also have

an argument structure. In particular, nouns have an external

theta role designated as R (for

23

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Reference) . When an NP is used predicatively this role is

assigned to the subject as in,

21- George is a president

Internal theta roles are assigned to NP's internal to the


first projection of the predicate of which they are lexically
specified as arguments. The external theta role may be

thought of as the head of the argument structure. It is

therefore passed up the X-bar projection and assigned to, or

becomes associated with, the maximal projection. We may say


that the external theta role of the head becomes the external

theta role of its maximal projection. The external theta


role is, thus, assigned "vertically". This is illustrated
below for VP's (22a) and NP’s (22b). We will adopt the
standard practice of marking an external argument by

underlining.

22- a) VPi b) NPi

/ \ I
V N’i

(Ai , B) I
Ni

(Ri ,. . . )

When an NP is used in a referential position, as an

24

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
argument, its external theta role, that is, the external R-
theta role of N which was vertically assigned to NP, is

coindexed with the particular theta role of the predicate


which is said to be assigned to it. Thus, theta role

assignment is a coindexation of two theta roles. This is


illustrated as follows.

23- VP

/ \
V NPi

A, Bi I
N’t

I
Ni
see a president

(Rt )

The coindexation is here expressed by the identical index (i)


associated with the internal theta role of the verb (B) and
the R role of its NP complement. This is to be interpreted
as expressing the idea that the reference of the verbal

theta-role is determined by the NP it is coindexed with, that


is, by the information provided by this NP. In this respect

the relation between a theta role of a predicate and an NP

(or its external, referential, theta role) is not symmetric.

Rather, it may be thought of as a relation between an anaphor

25

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
and its antecedent. We may say that a theta role "looks for"
reference which is provided by an NP which has reference
independently. Thus, instead of thinking of theta-role
assignment as a symmetric relation of coindexation, we will
follow Williams (1989) in viewing it as an asymmetric

relation of linking which may be

given expression by the use of arrows as in 24 below. We will


say that in such a state of affairs a theta role is

satisfied.

24- VP

/ \
V NP

(Aj,Bi) (Ri )

This conception of theta-role assignment may be taken


advantage of for an account of binding relationships (cf. in

particular Williams (1989) for a development of this idea) .

This dissertation, however, will be very little concerned

with issues of binding and therefore no detailed presentation


of a theta-theoretic binding theory will be undertaken here.

In general, except for vertical assignment (or "vertical

binding") , theta role assignment is subject to a severe


configurational restriction, namely, the "assigner" and the
"assignee" must stand in a relationship of sisterhood. This

may be claimed to hold for both internal and external theta

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
roles except that in the case of an external theta role the

relationship of sisterhood holds between a higher projection

and an argument NP, rather than between an NP and a governing


head. We can make this idea clear by illustrating what may
be referred to as the theta structure of a simple clause.

25- IP

/ \
NPi I 'i

1 / \
N 'i I VPi

1 / \
Ni V NPj

John (Ai , Thj ) 1


(Ri ) saw N'j

Nj
Mary

(Rj )

In 25 the theme role of see is assigned to Mary in observance


of the strict sisterhood restriction. The external (Agent)

theta role of the verb is vertically assigned to VP and then


to I’. It thus becomes the external theta role of I' and may
be assigned to John in accordance with the strict sisterhood
1
restriction .

27

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
As is clear from the structure illustrated above, we do

not assume, as has become common in much recent work in

syntax, a VP structure in which a subject is base generated

as specifier of VP. Rather, we adhere throughout this

dissertation to the assumption that a subject is external to

VP a t all levels of representation. This assumption will be

crucial for our analysis of nominalization constructions in

chapters 3 , 4 and 5.

1.2.2 Types of Thematic Relatedness

So far we have seen three types of thematic relations.

The core case of thematic relatedness is the relation between

a verb and an NP governed by it, that is, its internal

argument. This is, as was claimed, a relation between two

theta roles. Another type of thematic relation is the one

between a subject NP and its sister node (as in 25) . This

relation is similar to the first in that this also is a

relation between two theta roles except that in this case the

theta role assigner is not a head but, rather, a higher

projection. This relation is mediated, partly, by another

type of thematic relation, namely, vertical assignment (or

binding) of an external theta role from a head to its maximal

projection. This is the relation between the verb and VP in

25. This relation is natural given standard assumptions about

28

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
the relation between heads and their projections. Note,

however, that this is not exactly the case with respect to

the vertical assignment of the external theta role from VP to

I* in 25. I' is not a higher projection of VP in the X’-


theoretic sense of "being a projection of". Rather, the
relation between I' and VP in 25 follows from the relation

between I, the head of I', and VP. In this case I selects


VP, in the sense of the notion of selection as formulated in
16 above. However, given that I has no external theta role

of its own I ' has no external theta role either and the

external theta role of VP is free to be vertically assigned


to I* and become its external theta role. The external

theta-role is, thus, being "passed on" up to a point at which


it can be assigned to a sister.

Consider next the relation between the complementizer


that and the IP governed by it as in,

26- That John hit the ball

that in this case is not related to IP in the same way as I


to VP in 25 above. For one thing, that could never inherit

the external theta role of a lower constituent in such a way

that that external theta role would become its own external

theta role. This is because that has its own external theta
role. It is by virtue of this property that the sentential

constituent headed by that can function as an argument as in,

‘ 29

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
27- That John hit the ball is a surprise

However, that and I are similar in that none of them assigns


a theta-role to its complement. It follows that that is

incapable of "inheriting'* an external theta-role from the IP

governed by it and therefore the subject position of IP in


such a case must be occupied by an element which is capable
of being assigned a theta-role.

The nominalization constructions to be studied in

chapters 3, 4 and 5 will provide examples of the same type of


relation. In those constructions an abstract nominal
morpheme (the X of 20 above) selects a VP. Given, however,

that such nominal morphemes, like all nominal heads, have an


external theta role, the external theta-role of VP cannot be
vertically assigned to N’ to become its external theta role
but must find its satisfaction by a different strategy. We
will see soon how this may be done. Let us conclude this

section with a demonstration of the analysis of raising

constructions made possible within this framework. The main


assumption on which this analysis rests has to do with the
thematic properties of raising predicates. These are

identical to those assumed for I, namely, a raising predicate


has neither an external nor an internal theta-role. The

theta-structure of a standard raising construction would be

the following.

30

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
28- IP 2

/ \
NPl 1*2 1

I / \
John I VP2i

/ \
V IP11

I /. \
seems NP I *11

I / \
ei I VPi1

I / \
to Vi Adv.

work hard

In this configuration the external theta role of the verb

work is vertically assigned to VPi and then to I’i. At this

stage it is assigned to the NP trace in the subject position


of IPi . However, an NP trace, by definition, cannot satisfy

a theta role and, thus, the theta role is assigned to IPi in

its quest for satisfaction. It is subsequently assigned to


VP2 which is headed by seem, a raising predicate which has no

external theta role of its own, and ends up being assigned to


the subject John after being vertically assigned first to

1*2. A crucial feature of this analysis of raising is the

31

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
assumption concerning the nature of NP trace. The defining

properties of NP trace in the present framework are theta

theoretic rather than "binding theoretic". In the present

approach an NP trace is characterized as an element which

must be assigned a theta role but cannot satisfy it. The

distributional properties of NP trace, in particular,

certain locality restrictions applying to the relation

between an NP trace and its antecedent follow from its

assumed definitional properties combined with general

assumptions concerning the nature and distribution of theta

roles. This, in most cases, gives the same result as in a

standard, binding theoretic, approach to NP trace. But this

is not always the case. In particular, this view of NP trace

makes the prediction that i t should be possible for cases to

arise in which an NP trace has no antecedent occupying a

syntactic position. This is the case in infinitival clauses

headed by COMP, a matter to which we turn in the following

section.

1.2.3 Infinitival Clauses and Control

This section will present a brief discussion of

infinitival clauses and the phenomenon of obligatory control.

The analysis of obligatory control suggested here takes its

inspiration mainly from the work of Finer (1985) and Borer

32

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
(1989) and may be viewed as a theta theoretic implementation
of the insights of Borer (1989) . This section, however, is
only intended as a preliminary sketch. A detailed discussion
of control would go much beyond the intended scope of this

introduction.
We will follow Borer (1989) in assuming the non-existence
of the element PRO. However, unlike Borer (1989) who assumes
that it is small pro which figures in the subject position of

infinitives, we will assume that it is an NP trace which


occupies this position. The crucial feature of our approach
to infinitives will have to do with the complementizer

position and the particular element occupying this position


in (some) infinitives. We are concerned now with infinitival
clauses such as the sentential subject of 29a and the

complement of try in 29b.

29- a) to read this book is boring


b) John tried to read this book

The structure of the underlined part of 29a, b is the


following,

33

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
30- CP

/ \
c

/ \
COMP IP

/ \
NP Ii'

I / \
et I VPi

I / \
to Vi NP

I I
read this book

1» j

In 30 the external theta role of VP is vertically assigned to


I’ and from I’ to an NP trace in the subject position of IP.
Given the non-existence of PRO, an NP trace is the only
element that may occupy this position. In particular, empty
pronominal elements such as pro and expletive pro are
excluded from this position, pro is excluded from this
position since it requires to be "identified" by inflectional
morphology which is absent in this case (or else, pro is
simply not available in English) and expletive pro is
excluded due to the lack of Case to this position, an issue

which will be discussed in more detail in chapter 4.

34

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Clearly, the lack of Case to this position is also what
excludes the occurrence of a lexical NP in it. Note that we
are here following standard assumptions with respect to the
clausal (as opposed to VP) structure of infinitives. This
view is standard within the Government and Binding framework

but otherwise far from being universally accepted. The


discussion in chapter 4 will provide what seems to be fairly
strong evidence in favour of this view.
Note now that our analysis of 30 is not yet complete
since, given that an NP trace can not satisfy a theta role,
it is not yet clear how the external theta role of VP is
satisfied in this structure. The crucial assumption here has
to do with the properties of COMP, in particular, its
argument structure. This may be represented as follows.

31- Argument Structure of COMP: (Ri , Rj )

Note that the element COMP in 31 is a particular, abstract,


lexical element and the assumptions about its thematic
properties are limited to this element alone. In particular,
COMP is different from that which selects a finite INFL (and,
therefore, IP) and, presumably, lacks an internal R role.

The element COMP which, by assumption, selects an infinitival


INFL (or IP) has an external theta-role R which makes it
possible for the CP of which it is the head to occupy
argument positions. It is in this sense that COMP may be

35

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
said to be a "nominalizer" . In addition, COMP also has an

internal R role which makes it possible for a "lower" theta-


role to be linked to it and in this way to be "satisfied".
Thus, a fuller picture of the theta-structure of infinitival
clauses such as in 29a, b would look as follows.

32- CPi

/ \
C’i

/ \
COMP IPj

Ri , Rj / \

NP I'j

I / \
ej I VPj

I / \
to Vj NP

I I
read this book

i, . .

In this structure the external theta role of read is assigned


to the NP trace but, being unable to be satisfied by it, it
is assigned to IP and ends up being linked to the internal

argument of COMP. At this stage, the formal operation of


theta role assignment has been accomplished so that the

36

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
external theta-role of the verb may be said to be satisfied.
If no other grammatical mechanisms or lexical requirements
are at work the external theta-role is construed as

arbitrary, or generic, in reference. This is the case in


29a. 29b, on the other hand, exemplifies the phenomenon of
obligatory control, another mechanism by which the reference

of the external theta-role of VP in a configuration such as


32 may be determined.
Obligatory control of an infinitival clause is a
lexically established relationship between an argument of a

governing control verb and the argument structure of COMP.


The lexical entry of the verb try would look as follows,

33- try; Agi , Xj

< COMF1 >

This lexical representation encodes a requirement that a

thematic index associated with COMP be coindexed, that is,


interpreted as coref erential with an argument of the

governing verb. I assume that no particular difficulties


arise from a lexical specification which makes reference to a

zero level element (COMP) rather than to its maximal


projection. A governing verb has access to the head of a

governed constituent and dependency relationships can


therefore exist between the two heads. Obviously, in the

37

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
actual structure COMP is the head of the maximal projection

CP, but that follows from X'- theory. The notation in 33 is

adopted, with some modifications, from Zubizarreta (1985).

In particular, unlike the notation suggested in Zubizarreta

(1985) , 3 3 mentions the types of theta-roles assigned.

Crucially, I will adopt one particular feature of this

notational device which relates to the external/internal

distinction. In a notation such as in 33 only internal

arguments, unlike external arguments, are associated with a

syntactic frame. Thus, the internal/external distinction is


2
encoded in lexical structure in terms of subcategorization .

This also makes it possible to establish unambiguously a

control relationship between COMP and any of the arguments of

the verb governing i t since each of the arguments may be

uniquely identified. Note that if this format of lexical

representations is strictly observed, in particular, the

asymmetry between external and internal arguments, then the

possibility of control of an infinitival clause occupying a

subject position is excluded since a lexical representation

of the form in 3 3 can not "look inside" an external argument.

Thus, a controlled constituent can only be a lexically

designated complement of a verb (or another lexical head) .


3
This seems largely to be true .

Now, as just mentioned, the notation in 33 is to be

interpreted as expressing the requirement that one (not

necessarily the external) of the arguments of COMP be

38

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
coindexed with the controlling argument of the higher verb.
However, COMP is associated with two thematic indices,
namely, its external theta-role and its internal theta-role

which happens to be coindexed with the external theta-role of


VP. Thus, the main task of the present account is to avoid
ambiguity in the control relationship. It is only the
internal, and not the external, theta-role of COMP which is
understood as being controlled. This, however, can be

established in a rather simple fashion. Looking at the


following structure in which the subject of the matrix verb
is the lexically designated controller,
I

34- IP

/ \
NPj VP

/ \
V CPi

i, i / \
COMP IPk

Ri ,Rk / \
ek I'k

I \
I VPk

suppose that the subject is construed with the external


argument of COMP, so that j=i. However, the external

39

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
argument of COMP is also the external argument of CP. Now,

CP being a lexically required complement of the verb, i t is

coindexed with the verb's internal argument. The result is

therefore that CP is coindexed with the subject NP. But this

is a simple violation of principle C of the binding theory.

Thus, CP may be thought of as referential in some sense and,

indeed, this is the way CP is viewed within the present

framework. But CP is certainly not anaphoric. It follows

that only a coindexation with the internal argument of COMP

can satisfy the control requirement while avoiding such a

violation, that i s , only a situation in which j=k is

possible .

Given this analysis, some of the well known properties

of obligatory control ( t o be distinguished from non-

obligatory control) seem to follow in a rather natural

fashion. The literature on obligatory control (e.g. Williams

(1980), Chierchia (1984)) usually enumerates a certain number

of properties taken to be distinctive of this relation. In

the following I will go through some of these properties in

an attempt to show how the present analysis might provide an

account for them.

First, the relationship between a controlling NP and a

controlled infinitive is strictly local. In particular, it

can never cross an IP boundary.

*35- Mary believes that John tried to kill herself

40

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Within the present approach a controller of COMP can only be
a lexically designated argument of the control verb governing
COMP. That is, the controller and the controlled CP must be

coarguments of the same verb. Therefore, cases like 35 in


which the intended controller is not such an argument are
strictly excluded.

Second, a lexical NP cannot appear in the position of the


controlled subject (PRO in the standard theory of control)

36- *a) John tried Mary to leave


*b) John promised Mary John to leave

This, again, follows from the present analysis since a

control relation is a relation between the internal argument


of COMP and an argument of the governing verb. However, the

internal R argument of COMP must be satisfied, that is, it


must be assigned a theta role. This holds as an
independently motivated requirement. Namely, an R role, just

like an argument NP, must be thematically licensed, that is,


it has to be assigned a theta role. Now, the theta role

assigned to the internal R-role of COMP can only be the

external the external theta role of the lower verb. It


follows that the only element that can occupy the lower
subject position is an NP trace since this is the only

element which does not satisfy a theta role and, therefore,

makes possible its further upward propagation and assignment

41

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
to R. Any other nominal element will require this theta role

for itself and in this way block its upward propagation and
assignment to COMP.

Third, the controlling NP is uniquely determined.

*37- John promised Mary to wash herself

Given the notational device suggested here, the controlling

argument is lexically designated. In the case of promise


above, the subject (or Agent) is lexically specified as the
controlling element. Therefore, the anaphor in the
infinitival clause in this example couldn't be construed with
Mary as antecedent. A lexical entry for a control verb
couldn't specify two, or more, controlling arguments at one

and the same time since that will result in a lexical entry
in which both arguments will be specified as coreferential

and this is, simply, never the case.

Finally, Williams (1980) takes the requirement of c-

command between a controller and a controlled element to be

characteristic of obligatory control (his 0C3) . Thus, in 38a


below the preferred reading for the infinitival subject seems
to be with John as controlling its subject. But, as 38b

shows, an arbitrary reading is certainly possible for an

infinitival subject.

42

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
38- a) To leave would be John's pleasure

b) To leave would be a pleasure

Again, the c-command restriction follows naturally from the

present account. Under this account, the only position in

which a controlled infinitive wouldn't be c-commanded by its

antecedent is the subject position. But, as noted earlier,

the proposed format for encoding control relationships (cf.

33) is such that it excludes, in principle, control of a

sentential subject. This follows from the convention that

only internal arguments are associated in lexical entries

with subcategorization frames.

1 .3 Levels of Representation

An essential part of the view of the structure of

language within the generative tradition has always been the

distinction between different levels of representation. The

assumption of different levels of representation has been

originally motivated by the claim that certain linguistic

phenomena may be explained if one assumes that certain

elements in a sentence "belong", in some sense, to a

different position than the one at which they appear in the

actual spoken expression. It was therefore suggested that

such explanations could be achieved if one assumed the

43

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
existence of an underlying level of representation, a level
of "deep structure", from which a level of "surface
structure" could be derived by the application of various
movement operations. Standard work within the Government and
Binding framework (e.g. Chomsky (1981)) makes a distinction
between, at least, two levels of representation, namely, D-
structure and S-structure. The level of D-structure is
thought of as more basic in that it is this level which is
directly generated by the base in accordance with the general
principles of phrase structure (X' -theory). The mapping from
D-structure to S-structure is achieved by a transformational
component which consists of the general rule "Move-Alpha".

In particular, under the standard view, the mapping from D-


structure to S-structure includes both what is known as NP-
movement as well as A’-movement. NP-movement is movement
into argument (or A-) positions, that is, positions which can
bear grammatical functions and to which, in principle, a
theta-role may be assigned. A typical instance of this type
of movement is the transformation known as "raising".

A ’-movement, of which the most typical case is WH-movement,


moves an element to a non-argument position.

Van-Riemsdijk and Williams (1981) argue for the


existence of an additional, intermediate, level of

representation between D-structure and S-structure, a level


to which they refer as NP-Structure . In their model, NP-

44

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
movement maps D-structure to NP-structure and A'-movement

derives S-structure from NP-structure.


Williams (1986) goes one step further by claiming that

D-structure can be dispensed with if NP-structure is taken

to be the level at which A/A (as opposed to A/A') relations


are regulated. In the previous section it was shown how this

can be done if one adopts a certain set of principles which


characterize the nature of thematic relations and regulate

the distribution of theta-roles and NP-traces. Within such

an approach the distribution of NP-traces is governed by the


principles of theta-theory which apply at NP-structure. I

will adopt Williams' approach to the distinction between NP-


4
structure and S-structure . The term "underlying structure"

which will be often used in this dissertation is to be


understood as referring to NP-structure in the sense of

Williams (1986) . S-structure is derived from NP-structure by

the application of various movement processes such as WH-


movement, topicalization etc. all of which are instances of
A'-movement in the usual sense. Thus, the model suggested by
Williams (1986) does not get rid of all types of movement but

only of NP-movement.
This dissertation makes crucial use of the
transformational mechanism known as head movement which was

discussed in section 1.1 above. Clearly, head movement does

not put in relation two, or more, argument positions and in


this respect it may be viewed as another instance of A'-

45

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
movement. One might, therefore, say that head movement is a
surface phenomenon since it does not affect thematic
relations but, rather, applies to a level at which such
relations have already been established. We may therefore

consider head movement to be part of the inventory of


movement operations including WH-movement, topicalization

etc. by which S-structure is derived from NP-structure. As

will be seen, S-structure configurations may also be derived


by movement of NP 's . In such cases , however , movement is

purely motivated by the need to satisfy Case requirements and


the landing site of such movement is arguably a non-argument

position.

46

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Footnotes to Chapter I
1
The reader may have noticed that the term predication is
being avoided here. Originally (e.g. Williams (1980)), the
predication relation has been assumed to hold between a maximal
projection (VP, AP, etc. ) and a subject NP. Note that, since I’
is not a maximal projection, the relation of theta-role
assignment between an I' node and a subject NP is not entirely in
accordance with the strict formulation of the rule of predication
in Williams (1980) . In recent work Williams (1990) suggests that
the relation between a subject NP and I’ may be thought of as the
relation between two heads in a doubly headed structure. Thus,
for instance, the sequence from Alabama to Louisiana in (i)a is a
doubly headed structure which may be represented as in (i)b (both
taken from Williams (1990) ).

(i) a) John played the banjo from Alabama to Louisiana


b) PP
/ \
PP PP
/ \ / \
P NP P NP
The idea is that a sentence is a doubly headed structure
([Nominative, Tense] P) of which one head is a phrase marked as
Nominative and the other is a phrase marked for tense. In such a
case both heads count as maximal.

(ii) [Nominative, T]P


I \
[N+Nom] P [V+Tense]P
This, however, leaves open the question concerning the relation
between a predicate and its subject in an infinitival clause. It
might be (as suggested to me by E. Williams (personal
communication)) that the same holds for infinitives with the two
heads differently marked. I will simply leave this issue open
and assume the mechanism of theta-role assignment by upward
propagation without making reference to the notion of
predication.
2
I am using two types of notation for lexical entries, the
"fuller" type such as in 33 which includes subcategorization
frames, and the "reduced" type without subcategorization frames
in which an external theta-role is marked by underlining. As far
as I can see, there is no conflict between these two types of
notation. In this work, the argument structure of lexical items
will be mostly represented by the reduced type. The fuller type
will only
be used for the discussion of control of Action Nominalizations
in Chapter 3 .
47

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
3
One does find cases in which a non-finite constituent in
subject position seems to be in some sort of control relation
with an element which is embedded inside the predicate ((i)a was
suggested to me by R. Higgins) .

(i) a) To perjure himself would ruin Edward


b) Killing herself will be Mary's end

It seems reasonable to assume that these are not cases of


obligatory control, that is, a control relationship which is the
result of a requirement by a certain verb and which must be
satisfied. Thus, in analogy to (i)a above, consider the
following examples.
(ii) a) Perjuring himself would ruin Edward
b) Raising taxes would ruin this country
c) Raising taxes would ruin this president
It seems that, for some reason, Edward in (ii)a must be
construed as a controller of the gerundive NP in subject
position. In (ii)b, however, such a construal is highly
unlikely. As to (ii)c, it seems to be ambiguous between a
control and a ”non-control" construal. Thus, it is possible,
and more likely, to interpret (ii)c with the president as the
one who raises taxes, but an interpretation in which some other
authority, say, the senate, raises taxes is not impossible. This
kind of freedom in control relationships is not attested in the
core cases of obligatory control and therefore we may assume that
examples such as (i) and (ii) above involve some other type of
mechanism.
4
Williams (1986) suggests also that the level of LF be
dissolved and its functions be reassigned to the two remaining
levels of NP-structure and S-structure. In this work, the level
of LF will be assumed, at least at one point, but not crucially.
Otherwise, questions related to LF will play no role with respect
to the main issues with which this dissertation is concerned and
therefore it will have nothing to contribute on these issues.

48

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
CHAPTER II

THE SYNTAX OF GENITIVE CONSTRUCTIONS

The main theoretical interest and most challenging

aspect of verbo-nominal constructions derives from the

mixed array of properties manifested by these

constructions. Most important among the nominal

characteristics of verbal-nouns is their internal NP-like

syntax, in particular, the possibility for elements

within the construction to be related to each other as

terms in a genitive construction and be subject to the

regularities characteristic of the syntax of any noun

phrase. ' Therefore, a reasonably adequate account of the

syntax of genitive constructions is, in my view,

indispensable for the understanding of the syntax of

verbal nouns .

Genitive constructions in Hebrew and Arabic appear

in three variants, of which the most widely discussed has

been the construct state ( henceforth the Bound

Genitive ) exemplified in 1 below. The example in 2 is

of a Free Genitive, a construction in which a head noun

is followed by Sei (of) NP . The NP in the Sei phrase

is interpreted as the "possessor" . The example in 3

shows a Double Genitive, a construction in which a clitic

pronoun is attached to the head noun, the first term in

49

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
the construction. The clitic pronoun obligatorily
"doubles" the NP in the Sel-phrase, that is, it must
match in features and be interpreted as coreferential

with the NP.

1- a) (H) mazkir ha-miflaga

secretary the party


"the secretary of the party"
b) (A) ra?iisu 1- Hizb-i
head the party

"the head of the party"


2- (H) ha-xaverim Sei ha-miflaga

the members Sei the party

"the members of the party"


3- (H) xavere-ha Sei ha-miflaga

members-her Sei the party


"the members of the party"

The bulk of this chapter, section 2.1, will be

devoted to a discussion of the bound genitive. Section


2.2 will present a discussion of some issues concerning
the interpretation of genitive constructions. Free
genitives and double genitives will be discussed in

section 2.3.

50

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
2.1 Bound Genitives (the Construct State)

The bound genitive construction has enjoyed a

considerable amount of attention in recent years and is

still the subject of much dispute. In the following I

will first present the basic data and then go into a

discussion of the different approaches in an attempt to

defend my own analysis.

2.1.1 The Data

The bound genitive is a construction which relates

two terms, namely, a head noun and an NP following it, in

a genitive type of relationship. Semantically, the

content of this relationship may be construed in many

different ways such as possessed-possessor, action-theme

or any kind of pragmatically or semantically conceivable

kind of relation.

4- a) (H) beyt ha-more

house the teacher

"the house of the teacher"

b) ( A ) bayt-u l-mu9allim-i

house • the teacher-Gen

"the house of the teacher"

51

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
5- a) (H) harisat ha-ir

destruction the city


"the destruction of the city"
b) (A) qatlu 1- waziir-i

killing the minister-Gen

"the killing of the minister"


6- a) (H) xoxmat ha-el

wisdom the god


"the wisdom of god"
b) (A) S’afaa? l-ma?-i
purity the water
"the purity of the water"

The main facts about this construction are of two


types. The first has to do with the syntactic

restrictions to which it is subject and the second with


restrictions on its interpretation.

To begin with the syntactic restrictions, those are

first, the impossibility of any intervening material


between the two members of the construction. Thus, in 7
an intervening adjective renders the structure

ungrammatical (compare with 1) .

7- *a) (H) xaverim ne?emanim ha-miflaga

members loyal the party

52

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
*b) (A) ra?iis kabiir ddawla

head great the state

An adjective may only appear following the second term in


the construction.

8- a) (H) xavre ha-miflaga ha-ne?emanim


members the party the loyal

"the loyal members of the party"

b) (A) ra?iis ddawlat-i al-kabiir


head the state-Gen the great

"the great head of the state"

In 8 the adjective modifies the initial (head) noun


but it may also modify the following NP or be ambiguous
between the two. The same fact may be illustrated with
relative clauses as in the following examples.

9- *a) (H) mazkir Se nivxar emeS

secretary that was elected yesterday


ha-miflaga
the party
*b) (A) ra?iis allad'i ?untuxiba ?amsi

head who was elected yesterday

ddawla
the state

53

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
10- a) (H) mazkir ha-miflaga Se nivxar

secretary the party that was elected


emeS

yesterday
"The secretary of the party who was elected

yesterday"
b) (A) ra?iisu ddawlat-i allad'i ?untuxiba
head the state who was elected
?amsi

yesterday
"The head of the state who was elected yesterday"

Likewise, a clitic pronoun attached to the first noun

counts as intervening material and renders the structure

bad.

11- *a) (H) beyt-o ha-mazkir

house-his the secretary


*b) (A) baytu-hu rra?iis

house-his the president

A second syntactic restriction applies to the

occurrence of definite articles in bound genitives,


namely, a definite article may not be attached to the
initial (head) noun but may only appear in the following
NP.

54

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
12- *a) (H) ha-mazkir ha-miflaga

the secretary the party


*b) (A) rra?iis ddawla

the head the state

As to semantic interpretation, the most striking and

often discussed fact about the bound genitive has to do


with the definite/non-def inite distinction. If the NP
following the head noun is definite then the structure as
a whole is interpreted as definite. Thus, in la,b

(repeated here as 13a, b) the NP's are interpreted as

denoting to the (unique) head/secretary of the party and

not to a head/secretary of the party (that is, one of

the heads/secretaries of the party) .

13- a) (H) mazkir ha-miflaga

secretary the party


"the secretary of the party"
b) (A) raîiisu 1- Hizb-i

head the party-Gen


"the head of the party"

That the NP's in 13 are indeed definite can be

demonstrated by indicating the way they interact with

syntactic processes that are sensitive to the


definite/non-definite distinction.

55

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Thus, in Hebrew an NP figuring as direct object must
be preceded by the object marker (OM) et if and only if
it is definite. The contrast in 14 shows that the NP
mazkir ha-miflaqa (the secretary of the party) as a whole

is perceived as definite. The situation in 15 is exactly


the opposite.

14- a) (H) rait-i et mazkir ha-miflaga

saw I OM secretary the party

"I saw the secretary of the party"


*b) (H) rait-i mazkir ha-miflaga
saw I secretary the party

15- a) (H) rait-i mazkir miflaga


saw I a secretary party

"I saw a secretary of a party"


*b) (H) rait-i et mazkir miflaga

saw I OM secretary party

One grammatical process in Arabic which is sensitive


to definiteness is Relative Clause formation. A relative

pronoun must occur as the head of a relative clause if


the NP modified by it is definite (16) . Otherwise, a
relative pronoun is absent as in 17 below.

56

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
16- a) (A) ra?ayt-u ra?iis-a 1- Hizb-i llad'i

saw I head ACC the party-Gen who

?untuxiba ?amsi
was elected yesterday
"I saw the head of the party who was elected

yesterday”
*b) (A) ra?ayt-u ra?iis-a 1- Hizb-i ?untuxiba

saw I head ACC the party-Gen was elected


?amsi
yesterday
17- *a) (A) ra?ayt-u ra?iis-a Hizb-en llad'i

saw I head Acc party Gen who

Tuntuxiba ?amsi

was elected yesterday


b) (A) ra?ayt-u ra?iis-a Hizb-en ?untuxiba

saw I head Acc party-Gen was elected


?amsi

yesterday
"I saw a head of a party who was elected yesterday"

In 16 it is "the head of the party" who was elected

yesterday and not just "the head" or "the party". The NP


as a whole is perceived as definite and thus dictates the

particular form of the relative clause. In 17, on the

other hand, it is an indefinite bound genitive

57

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
construction which is being modified and therefore a
relative pronoun must not appear.
Another relevant fact concerns modification of the
head noun by an adjective. An adjective functioning as a
modifier (as opposed to a predicate) must agree with the
modified head on definiteness as well as on number and
gender. An adjective modifying the head noun of a bound
genitive must be marked as definite if the head noun is

followed by a definite NP.

18- a) (H) mazkir ha-miflaga ha-zaken


secretary the party the old
"the old secretary of the party”
*b) (H) mazkir ha-miflaga zaken
secretary the party old
19- a) (A) mudiir-u 1-madrasat-i ttawiil-u

director-Nom the school -Gen the tall-Nom


"the tall director of the school"

*b) (A) mudiir-u 1-madrasat-i tawiil-u

director-Nom the school -Gen tall -Norn

In both 18 and 19 the NP’s "the party" and "the school"


are feminine. Therefore, the following adjectives must
be interpreted as modifying the head noun, which is
masculine. As the contrast between the a and the b

58

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
examples shows, the adjective must be preceded by a

definite article.

These are the main facts which any adequate account

of the bound genitive must provide an account for. The

analyses of the bound genitive which have been proposed

in the literature in recent years may be classified into

two main approaches, the complement approach and the

specifier approach. The complement approach, represented

mainly by the work of H. Borer (1984,1988), views the

relationship between the members in a bound genitive

construction as one between a head and its complement.

Under this approach the head and its complement are base

generated in their surface order and no movement

operations are needed to map the one into the other.

Under the specifier approach, on the other hand, the NP

(the second member of the construction) is base generated

as a specifier to the head. However, in order to derive

the surface word order some sort of movement operation

must be invoked. This may be achieved in several

different ways, a point on which different versions of

the specifier approach diverge. To the best of my

knowledge, a version of the specifier approach has been

available in the literature since a t least as early as

Aoun (1978) . More recent proposals within the specifier

approach make use of the DP analysis of NP structure put

forth by Abney (1986,1987). This particular treatment of

59

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
bound genitives is due mainly to Ritter (1986) . Slightly

different versions of it are presented in Fassi-Fehri

(1988) and Mohammad (1989) .

In the following discussion I will first review the

complement approach of Borer (1984,1988) and present my

arguments against it (section 2.1.2). I will then

proceed to a presentation of my own analysis, a variant

of the DP analysis (section 2.1.3).

2.1.2 The Complement Approach to Bound Genitives

Borer (1984) proposes that 20a, b have the structure

in 20c.

20- a ) ( H ) mazkir ha-miflaga

secretary the party

"the secretary of the party"

b) (A) za9iimu 1- Hizb-i

leader the party-Gen

"the leader of the party"

c) N*

/ \

N NP

leader the party

secretary

60

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
It is suggested that 20c is the configuration for the

assignment of genitive Case. In this configuration the


first node dominating the head noun dominates also the

complement NP. Thus, the complement NP may be said to be

governed, government being the condition for Case


assignment. Ungrammatical cases in which some material

intervenes between the head and its complement are

straightforwardly accounted for in this approach.

*21- N'

/ \
N' NP

/ \
N (AP/RCI

Thus, 21, with an intervening adjective (cf. examples


7,8) or a relative clause (cf. examples 9,10), is ruled

out as a violation of an assumed strict c-command

restriction on the government of the complement by the


head. Cases in which a clitic pronoun is attached to the
head (cf. example 11) may be explained as having either

of the structures in 22.

61

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
22- *a) N' *b) N'

/ \ / \
N' NP N-cl NP
/ \
N-cl pro

22a incorporates an assumption that a clitic is always

associated with an empty pronominal category which it may


be said to "identify" (assign features ,content etc. ).

22a is thus ruled out on the same grounds as 21. In 22b


no pro is present and therefore no configurational

explanation may be invoked for its ungrammaticality. It

is however possible, within the framework assumed by

Borer, that a clitic must be assigned Case. If this is


so then the clitic in 22b may be said to absorb the Case
feature assigned by the head and thus deprive the

complement NP of Genitive Case. The structure is thus


ruled out as a violation of the Case filter.

Before proceeding into a discussion of the empirical

difficulties faced by the complement approach, it is

important to note a difficulty raised by it which is more

conceptual than empirical in character. The notion of


complement is generally used to refer to a syntactic
constituent standing in some privileged relationship to a

lexical head. Such a constituent, if present, is said to


satisfy requirements for which the head is lexically

62

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
specified. The syntactic realization of such a
relationship is assumed to be the configuration of
government. That is, a configuration which obeys severe
restrictions including, at least, sisterhood and possibly
linear adjacency. However, none of this holds with
respect to the core cases of the bound genitive

construction. In general, any noun can stand in a


genitive relationship to another noun and any noun can
simply stand on its own. No lexical restrictions are at
work in this respect. Moreover, the relationship of

being "the complement of" is not necessarily a one to one


relationship. Thus, a lexical head may be associated

with more then one constituent which may be said to be

its complement as, for example, in 23.

23- (A) sallama 1-waziir -u naa?ib-a -hu

handed the-minister-Nom aide -Acc-his


rrisaalat -a

the letter-Acc
"The minister handed his aide the letter"

However, only one NP may ever stand in a bound genitive


relationship to a head noun.

63

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
24- a) (A) tasliim 1-waziir -i naa?ib-a-hu

handing the minister—Gen aide -Acc-his


rrisaalat -a

the letter-Acc

"The minister's handing his aide the letter"


b) (A) tasliim naa?ib-i-hu rrisaalat-a

handing aide-Gen-his the letter-Acc


"The handing of the letter to his aide"
*c) (A) tasliim 1- waziir-i naa?ib-i-hu

handing the minister-Gen aide -Gen-his

rrisaalat-a
the letter-Acc

Note also that the kind of semantic relationship


that can be entertained by two terms in a bound genitive

may vary from the different kinds of argument-type

relationships to adjective-noun-like modification


relationship. Such a variation in the mode of semantic
construal is completely absent when it comes to the core
cases of constructions involving the head/complement

relationship such as, for example, verbal

complementation. Thus, the relations of "being a


complement of”, on the one hand, and the relation of

"being the second member in a bound genitive


construction" seem to belong to two fundamentally
different categories. It seems to me that this point

64

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
alone casts serious doubts on the complement approach.
However, in the rest of this section I will concentrate
on its empirical inadequacies.

Coming back now to the empirical issues, the


complement approach runs into serious problems when it
comes to explaining the ungrammaticality of cases in

which a bound genitive is preceded by a definite article


(cf.12). A configuration such as the one in 25 (proposed
in Borer (1984)) would, in fact, count as a violation of

the assumed conditions on the assignment of genitive


Case, but there is no motivation for the assumption of

such a structure.

25- N'

/ \
N*

/ \
Det N

25 implies the existence of a phrase structure rule such

as: N' --- > Det N , but such a rule seems to have no

motivation, neither on general theoretical grounds, since


it implies that Determiners may be base generated under
N' rather than as specifiers of NP immediately dominated

by the maximal projection, nor is it justified on

language specific grounds since Hebrew and Arabic are

65

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
both assumed to be, and in fact are, head initial
languages .
Another attempt to deal with this problem, still
within the complement approach, is a suggestion made by
Shlonsky (1987) to the effect that Hebrew (and Arabic)
NP's simply lack a specifier position. Following this
view the examples under consideration would have the
structures as follows.

26- a) NP b) NP

I I
N' N’

/ \ / \
N NP N NP
leader party leader the party

Note that, given this view, the definite article in


the NP complement of 26b couldn't possibly occupy a

specifier position in that NP since such a position, by


assumption, simply does not exist. It therefore must be
assumed that this definite article is the realization of
a definiteness feature specified, say, as [+Def ] , which
is present in the underlying feature composition of the
noun in question, together with other features such as

number, gender and so forth.


As a fact which seems to support such a view,

66

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Shlonsky notes that elements such as quantifiers and

numerals, which typically figure as specifiers of NP in


languages such as English, seem to figure as nominal
heads in Hebrew.

27- a) (H) SloSet ha-yeladim

three the children


"the three children"
b) (H) SloSt-am

Three-them
"the three of them"
28- (H) ha-kol
the all

"everything"

In 27a the numeral "SloSa" (three) seems to function as a


head of a bound genitive since it undergoes the

phonological modification associated with this

construction. In 27b a clitic pronoun is attached to the


numeral "SloSa" and in 28 a definite marker "ha"

precedes the quantifier "koi" (all) . These facts are

brought in support of the claim that there is no need to

postulate a specifier position for Hebrew NP's. Rather,


these quantifier expressions would occupy the head

position of an NP.

67

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
An obvious objection that may immediately be raised
concerns the, by now familiar, examples repeated below.

29- *a) (H) ha-mazkir ha-miflaga


the secretary the party
*b) (H) ha-mazkir miflaga

the secretary party

Shlonsky's suggestion fails to account for the


ungrammaticality of the examples above. By assuming that
the definite marker occupies no syntactic position this
analysis makes the claim that 29 a,b have exactly the
same structure as the grammatical 26 a,b above. That is,
definiteness being a feature, and just a feature, there
is no reason why the head noun wouldn't be specified as

[+Def] as well. Next, observe the two following


examples.

30- a) (H) mazkir ha-miflaga


secretary the party
"the secretary of the party"
b) (H) mazkir Sei ha-miflaga
secretary Sei the party
"a secretary of the party"

According to the view under consideration, 30b is assumed

68

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
to be the result of the application of an optional rule
of Sei insertion to the underlying structure 26b, which
is the structure of 30a (this is so given standard

assumptions about Sel» my assumptions are, however,


different, as will become clear later). However, 30a and
30b differ clearly in their interpretations, the one
I
(30a) being definite and the other (30b) indefinite. The

element Sei being a "dummy" Case marker, it is hard to


see how it could contribute to this difference in
I
meaning. Rather, one may consider the possibility that

30a and 30b are associated with two different underlying

structures, but these are not available under this

analysis. In fact, this objection holds regardless of


whether Sei is assumed to be base generated or, rather,
inserted at a later stage of the derivation for the
purpose of Case assignment. In either case it would be
I
implausible to assume that the difference in

interpretation between 30a and b derives from the


particular semantic contribution made by Sei. Thus ,
since, except for the presence or the absence of Sei , the

structures are identical, this difference in meaning

remains unexplained.

A third and last remark concerns the need to

postulate a specifier position in Hebrew NF's. There are

quantifier expressions that clearly fail to act like head

69

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
nouns. Thus, "harbe" (many) and ”kama" (some) cannot, for
example, have clitics attached to them.

31- a) (H) harbe

many
*b) (H) harbe-hem

many -them
32- a) (H) kama
some
*b) (H) kama -hem

some-them

In 33 a,b "harbe" (many) and "kama" (some) function as


regular quantifier expressions. Not being nominal heads
(as shown in 31, 32) , the most natural assumption would

be that they occupy a specifier position.

33- a) (H) harbe yeladim


many children

b) (H) kama yeladim


some children

A numeral like "SloSa" (three) , as already mentioned,


does have the possibility of having a clitic attached to
it. Note also that one finds constructions in which

70

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
numerals do not undergo the phonological modification

characteristic of heads of bound genitives (compare 27a) .

34- SloSa yeladim

three children

Now, "harbe" (many) , "kama" (some) and "SloSa” (three)

are in complementary distribution with the definite

marker "ha" .

35- *a) (H) harbe ha-yeladim

many the children

*b) (H) kama ha-yeladim

some the children

*c) ( H ) SloSa ha-yeladim

three the children

Moreover, exactly like the definite marker "ha", "harbe"

(many) , "kama" (some) and "SloSa" (three) cannot precede

the head of a bound genitive. Compare the following

examples with those in 29.

36- *a) ( H ) harbe yalde ha-kita

many children the class

*b) (H) kama yalde ha-kita

some children the class

71

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
*c) (H) SloSa yalde ha-kita

three children the class

It is therefore fairly plausible to assume, first, that


Hebrew (and for that matter Arabic) NP’s do have a

specifier position of the kind that it would be necessary

to postulate for 33,34, and, second, that the definite

marker "ha" occupies this very position, as would be

necessary in order to explain the facts in 35. Thus, the


analysis of bound genitives, in particular, a unified
account of the facts in 29 and 36, must have something to
1
do with this position .

Note that the proposal made by Shlonsky (1987) ,


along with its syntactic problems, still does not provide
(and, I assume, does not claim to provide) an account of

the interpretation facts. That is, the fact that, if the


"complement" NP is definite then the NP as a whole is
interpreted as definite. Borer (1988) presents an

attempt to provide an account for this fact making use of

the idea that definiteness may be viewed as a feature and


a special percolation mechanism by which the feature

[+Def] may percolate up and mark the NP, as a whole, as

definite. There is no need here to go into the details


of Borer's (1988) account which is embedded within a
general approach to morphology and the interaction

between morphology and Syntax and is designed to provide

72

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
support for such an approach. This general issue is

beyond the scope of the present discussion. The main

ideas of that account are the following. First, word

formation operations are possible both before D-structure


as well as after D-structure (that is, "in the syntax") .
A word formation operation applying to a certain domain

defines that domain as a word and thus makes it possible


for certain processes, such as feature percolation

processes which are characteristically word internal, to


take place. To make it possible for definiteness to mark
the NP as a whole the only additional assumption needed

is that definiteness in Hebrew is a feature. This

assumption is justified on the ground that Hebrew has

definiteness agreement. As has already been observed, a


head noun and a modifying adjective agree in

definiteness.

37- a) (H) ha-bayit ha-gadol/*gadol neheras


the house the big big was destroyed
"The big house was destroyed"

b) (H) bayit gadol /*ha-gadol neheras


house big the big was destroyed

"A big house was destroyed"

Thus, agreement processes are assumed to be processes

which involve features. Therefore, if definiteness is

73

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
subject to such processes then i t must be viewed as a

feature. Generally, the most typical type of information

that is assumed to b e encoded by the device of features

is "things" such as number and gender and, indeed, a head

noun and an adjective must agree in number and gender as

well .

38- *a) ( A ) al-bayt-u al-kabiirat-u

the house (ms) the big (fm.)

*b) (H) ha-bayit ha-gdol-im

the house (sg) the big -pl

Borer's percolation mechanism may be illustrated as

follows .

39- NP NP/ Def

NP/ Def

NP NP/ Def

Def Def

Thus, the configuration in 39 is defined as a domain in

which word formation operations are possible and this

allows the definiteness feature to percolate up.

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
The immediate question that comes to mind at this

point is what happens to other features . This question


is entirely justified since this whole approach is based
on the analogy between definiteness and other features.
Obviously, it is only definiteness which is ever allowed
to percolate up. Thus, it seems as though the
transparency to feature percolation which is achieved by
allowing for word formation rules to apply in the syntax
is rather selective, allowing certain types of
information in and filtering other types of information
out. The picture becomes even more suspicious once we
note that exactly the same phenomenon, that is, the
difference in behaviour between definiteness on the one
hand and other features on the other, may also be
observed in a language like English. Consider the

following examples (English makes no gender distinction


so only definiteness and number are relevant here) .

40- a) the man 1 s book [+Def, -Pl]


b) the man's books [+Def, +P1]
41- a) the men ’s book [+Def, -Pl]
b) the men's books [+Def, +P1]
42- a) a book [-Def, -Pl]
b) some books [-Def, +P1]

As the feature indications above show the specification

75

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
of the NP as a whole with respect to definiteness is

always determined by the material occupying its specifier


position. On the other hand only the head noun seems to

be relevant with respect to the overall number


specification of these NP’s. Thus, the NP's "the man"
and "the men" are [+Def, -Pl] and [+Def, +P1]

respectively and perceived as such by the syntactic


processes sensitive to these distinctions (number

agreement, definiteness effect, etc.). However, in the

cases above it is only the [+Def] feature of these NP’s

which seems to "percolate up". In this, English NP's


occupying the specifier position are rather strikingly

reminiscent of the Hebrew NP's assumed to be complements


in Borer's analysis of the bound genitive. It seems
rather obvious that something more general is here at
work than the, rather ad hoc, percolation mechanism
2
proposed by Borer .
Note that the difficulties pointed out so far for

the complement approach are all internal in character,

that is, they concern the syntax of bound genitives

considered in isolation from any other aspects of a given

construction in which it may occur. However, as already

stated, the main interest in the syntax of bound

genitives in the present context derives from the fact


that it constitutes one, important, aspect of the syntax
of verbo-nominal constructions. Therefore, any

76

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
satisfactory analysis of bound genitives must be

compatible with the general analysis of verbo-nominal


constructions such as Action Nominalizations (cf. chapter
3), nominal gerunds (cf. chapter 4) and Agent

Nominalizations (cf. chapter 5). A careful examination


of these constructions will reveal that the complement

approach to bound genitives is, quite clearly,


incompatible with any reasonable analysis of Action

Nominalization constructions, let alone the Nominal


Gerund and Agent Nominalizations. If this is indeed so,
then it constitutes another, fairly compelling, argument
against the complement approach. For a detailed

discussion of this particular issue with respect to


Action Nominalizations see footnote 4 to chapter 3.

77

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
2.1.3 A Specifier Approach to Bound Genitives:

The Head Movement Analysis

The analysis of bound genitives outlined in this

section makes use of an idea, due mainly to Abney

(1986,1987), as well as Fukui and Speas (1986) and

others, according to which constituents that have

traditionally been taken to be NP's should be viewed as

being headed not by a noun but rather by a functional

head, D( eterminer) , which takes an NP as its complement

in the same way that COMP is assumed to be the head of

CP and to have IP as its complement and INFL is assumed

to be the head of IP and have a VP as its complement.

The application of this approach to the analysis of

bound genitives is due mainly to Ritter (1986) . Variants

of Ritter's original analysis are developed in Fassi-

Fehri (1988) , Muhammad (1989) and Cohen (1990) . In the

following I will follow Ritter's proposal in most of its

details, deviating from it only as seems necessary in


3
order to overcome some of its main problems . In

developing this analysis I benefitted considerably from a

suggestion of Ur Shlonsky (personal communication) .

Under the present proposal, the underlying structure

of 43a, b is the one illustrated in 43c.

78

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
43- a) (H) mazkir miflaga

secretary party
"a secretary of a party"
b) (A) ra?iis Hizb-en
head party-Gen
"a head of a party"

c) DP

/ \
D'

/ \
D NP

! / \
POSS DP N'

/ \ I
D’ N

/ \ I
NP secretary
! head
N*

1
N

I
party

In the configuration above secretary/head is the head of

79

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
an NP embedded in a DP and party is a DP occupying the

specifier position of that NP. The head position of the

matrix DP is occupied by the abstract morpheme POSS.


POSS may be specified as [Def] . A DP headed by a [Def]

POSS is definite and a DP headed by a POSS unmarked for

definiteness is simply non-definite. In the

configuration above, the head (D) position of the DP


party is empty. In particular, there is no definite

article occupying this position. The position is


therefore indefinite by default and therefore also the

lower DP as a whole.
POSS is also a Case assigner. That is, the source of

genitive Case in a bound genitive is POSS rather than the


head noun and, crucially, this feature must be
discharged. It is also assumed that the relation of

genitive Case assignment is just like the relation of


nominative Case assignment, which holds between INFL and

a subject NP, in that this relation too holds under

agreement or, to use Chomsky’s (1986) expression, feature

sharing. The difference is that in this case the only

feature relevant for agreement is [Def]. However,

agreement being a process which applies between heads and

their specifiers, the assignment of genitive Case cannot

apply directly between POSS and party in their underlying


4
positions, as shown in 43c . There is, however, a way
out of this situation which consists of a head movement

80

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
adjoining the head noun to POSS and (following a
suggestion of Ur Shlonsky (personal communication) ) a
certain process of reanalysis as illustrated below.

44- DP

[Gen] Di NP

Ni [Gen] D DP N'

secretary [Gen] POSS NP N


head

N' ei

party

In 44 the head noun secretary/head moves and adjoins to


the element occupying the governing D position, leaving a
trace at the head position of NP. I will assume a
process of reanalysis by which the D node which dominates
the complex head N+POSS inherits the index of N. The

result of this process is a complex head which inherits


the features originating from POSS, that is, genitive
Case and, possibly, a definiteness feature (in case that

81

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
POSS is specified as [Def]) , and carries an index which
is identical to the one carried by the trace of N. It

follows that the complex head may now be construed as


antecedent of the trace of N and, since antecedence
implies the inheritance of features of the antecedent by
its trace, it also follows that the trace of N in 44

inherits the feature content of Di . In particular, the


trace of N inherits a genitive Case feature and a,
possible, specification for definiteness. Thus, it is
the trace of N in 44 which governs and assigns Case to
the DP in its specifier position. Since neither the
trace nor DP are definite in this case, the requirement
of agreement is satisfied and the DP party is licensed by
the Case filter.
As to the surface realization of such a
configuration, the sequence N+POSS is realized at the
surface as the bound form. The difference between the

bound and free forms is most visible with the plural and
feminine forms of nouns. 45 and 46 below demonstrate the
alternation /im/ — >/e/ for plural in Hebrew and /a/ —

>/at/ for feminine in Arabic (as well as in Hebrew)


respectively .

45- a) (H) mazkire miflagot


secretaries parties
"secretaries of parties"

82

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
*b) (H) mazkirim mifl ago t

secretaries parties
46- a) (A) ra?iis-at-u Hizb-en

head -Fm-Nom party-Gen

"a head of a party"


*b) (A) ra?iis-a Hizb-en

head -Fm party-Gen

The derivation of the definite variant of 43a, b is


identical except for the presence of a definite article
in the lower DP.

47- a) (H) mazkir ha-miflaga

secretary the party


"the secretary of the party"
b) (A) ra?iis-u 1 - Hizb-i
head -Norn the party-Gen

"the head of the party"

83

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
c) DP DP

/ \ / \
D NP ====> Di [Def] NP

1 / \ / \ / \
POSS DP[Def] N* Nt D DP [Def] N*
[Def] / \ î 1 1 / \ 1
D NP N secretary POSS D NP N

1 1 1 head [Def] 1 I |

ha/al N' secretary ha/al N' et


1 head 1
N N

1
party party

The definite article ha/al and the morpheme POSS are, in

this analysis, two separate, independently existing,

elements. In particular, the definite article is not


assumed to be the surface realization of an underlying

feature [Def]. The definite article ha/al and POSS, both


being heads of category D, are in complementary

distribution with respect to the head position of DP.


Obviously, the definite article is definite, that is, it

is marked as [Def] and the DP of which it is the head is

marked as [Def] as well. Thus, in 47c, the trace of N


inherits Case and definiteness specifications from the

complex head Di and, given that the DP it governs is also

84

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
definite, Case assignment may apply. Thus, Case

assignment to a definite DP is possible only if POSS is


specified as [Def] , that is, if the matrix DP is
specified and interpreted as definite.

Some of the observations made earlier with respect

to ungrammatical cases of bound genitives which involve

material intervening between the head noun and the

following NP receive a natural explanation in this


analysis. Thus, an adjective modifying the moved head
would be simply left behind and could never intervene

between the two head nouns. An interesting implication


of this analysis is that it should be possible for two

adjectives to occur, one modifying the head noun and the


other modifying the noun in Spec. Such cases are

somewhat marginal in Hebrew but seem to be perfectly


natural and acceptable in Arabic. The structure and

derivation of 48a, b,c is illustrated in 49 below.

48- ?a) (H) menahelet beyt ha-sefer ha-xadaS

director (fm) the school the new


ha-mecuyenet

the excellent (fm)


"The excellent director of the new school"

85

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
b) (A) mudiir-u 1-madrasat-i 1-jadiidat-i
director— Nom the school -Gen the new -Gen
1-mumtaaz -u
the excellent-Nom
"The excellent director of the new school"
c) (A) za9iim-u 1-firqat-i ssaRiirat-i

leader-Nom the group -Gen the small-Gen


al Raniyy-u

the rich -Norn

"The rich leader of the small group"

49- DP DP

/ \ / \
D NP ====> Di NP
| / \ / \ / \
POSS DP N* Ni D DP N’

/ \ / \ 1 / \ / \
D NP N* AP POSS D NP N' AP
| / \ | 1 / \ \
ha/al N' N ha/al N* ei

/ \ / \
N* AP N* AP

N N

86

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Switching the order of adjectives in these examples
renders them completely unacceptable. Note that the
nouns in these examples are different in gender and

therefore there is no ambiguity about which adjective is


supposed to modify which noun.

50-*a) (H) menahelet beyt ha-sefer ha-mecuyenet

director (fm) the school (ms) the excellent(fm)


ha-xadaS
the new (ms)
*b)(A) mudiir-u 1- madrasat-i al-mumtaz -u
director-Nom the school-Gen the excellent-Nom
al-kabiirat-i
the big -Gen
*c)(A) za9iim-u 1-firqat-i 1-Raniyy-u

leader-Nom the group-Gen the rich -Norn


ssaRiirat-i
the small-Gen

Note that even though 48a is somewhat marginal, 50a is


completely impossible, a contrast which is accounted for

by this analysis.
The present account also allows for a
straightforward derivation of multiply embedded cases
such as the following,

87

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
51- a ) (H) roS kvucat ha-kiconiyim

head group the extremists

"the head of the group of the extremists"

b) ( A ) ra?iisu firqat-i 1-mutaTarif iin

head group -Gen the extremists-Gen

"the head of the group of the extremists"

The structure and derivation of 51a, b is as follows.

52- a) DPi b) DPi

/ \ / \

D NPi Di NPi

1 / \ / \ / \

POSS DPa n* Nt POSS DPa N'

[Def] / \ 1 1 [Def] / \ 1

D NPz N head D NP 2 ei

/ \ 1 / \

DPa N * head DPa N’

/ \ 1 / \ 1

D NPa N D NPa N

ha/al N' group ha/al N* group


i
1

N N

extremists extremist

88

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
52- c ) DPi

/ \

Di NPi

/ \ / \

Ni D dp2 \

1 1 / \ N’

head POSS Dj \ 1

[Def] / \ np2 ei

Nj D / \

1 | DPa N'

group POSS / \ 1

[Def] D NPa N

I I I
ha/al N* ej

extremists

As the structures above show, 51a, b are derived by two

simple applications of head movement of the type

illustrated earlier for the non-embedded structure. It

is interesting however to observe how the interpretation

with respect to the def inite/non-def inite distinction is

computed in these structures. As mentioned above, a

definite D P is one of which the head position is occupied

89

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
by a definite element. That can be either POSS specified
as [Def] or the definite article ha/al . In 52a DPi must
be headed by a [Def] POSS since only POSS can provide the

genitive Case feature necessary for DP2 . Now, the POSS

heading DPi and the element heading DPa must (indirectly)


agree on definiteness. Of the two conceivable elements
that could occupy the head position of DPa , only a
definite POSS could satisfy this requirement since only
POSS carries the genitive Case features necessary for the

licensing of DPa . Next, looking at 52c, could a [Def]


POSS occupy the head position of DPa in order to satisfy
the agreement requirement between ej and DPa ? The answer

is "No" since POSS must discharge its genitive Case


feature and there is no DP further down to which this
feature could be assigned. It follows that the head of

DPa must be a definite article since this is the only


element that can satisfy the agreement requirement if

Case is to be assigned to DPa . Thus, in a multiply


embedded bound genitive it is only the last noun that may
be preceded by a definite article. It also follows from
the above suggestions that it is impossible for a non
embedded DP to be definite without an overt definite
article occupying its D position (ignoring right now
inherently definite elements such as proper names and
pronouns). Such a situation could result if a D

90

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
position was occupied by a definite POSS instead of a
definite article as follows.
53- DP

/ \
D NP

I I
POSS N'
[Def] |

In 53 POSS has nowhere to discharge its genitive Case


feature and the structure is therefore ruled out. For

the same reason, an isolated occurrence of a noun in a


bound form is impossible. Such a form may be the result
of the following configuration.

54- DP

/ \
Di NP

/ \ I
Ni D N*

I I
POSS N

I
ei

54 is ruled out for the same reason as 53.

91

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
2.2 The Interpretation of Genitive Constructions:

Identification and Classification

In dealing with the syntax of genitive constructions

it seems useful to make a certain distinction between two

main types of semantic relationship that may hold between

two members of a genitive construction. The first is a

possessive type of relationship, where "possessive” must

be understood in a very large sense. This is the kind of

relationship that is understood to hold between the two

members in the following examples.

55- a ) ( H ) beyt ha-more

house the teacher

"the house of the teacher"

b) ( H ) manhig ha-miflaga

leader the party

"the leader of the party"

c ) (H) xalon ha-bayit

window the house

"the window of the house"

56- a ) ( A ) baytu ttilmiid* -i

house the student -Gen

"the house of the student"

92

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
b) (A) ra?iisu ddawlat -i

head the state-Gen

"the head of the state"


c) (A) muHarriku ssiyyaarat-i

engine the car -Gen


"the engine of the car"

In the a examples above, the entities referred to by the

two nouns are most naturally understood to be related to

each other in the relation of possession. In the b and ç


examples, on the other hand, a different relationship
seems to hold. However, common to all these cases is an

interpretation involving two entities that are related to


each other in some way. The kind of relationship
involved is mostly determined by pragmatic factors, such
as general knowledge of the world and the like. I will

follow traditional terminology in referring to this type


of semantic relationship as Identif icatory . In an

identificatory interpretation the "possessor" half of the


pair answers the question "which", that is, the reference
of the NP as a whole is determined through the reference

of the "possessor".

A second type of semantic construal is exemplified by

the following NP's.

93

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
57- a) (H) metos krav

aircraft battle
"a battle aircraft"
b) (H) saxkan hagana

player defence
"a defence player"

c) (H) eSet mehandes

wife engineer
"the wife of an engineer"
58- a) (A) ka?su Hamr-en

glass wine-Gen
"a glass of wine"

b) (A) kursu xaSb-en


chair wood-Gen

"a wooden chair"


c) (A) qit9atu laHm-en
piece meat-Gen
"a piece of meat"

In these examples no interpretation is available in which


two separate entities stand in a relationship to each

other. Rather, the only available interpretation is one


in which one term, the second, restricts the reference of
the other. It is the same kind of relation that holds

between an adjective and a head noun, that is, a relation


of modification. In contrast to the identif icatory

94

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
relationship, in this case the genitive noun specifies,
or provides an answer to a question relating to, the
kind of something. The semantic relationship between the

two elements is such that the denotation of the

construction as a whole is a subset of the denotation of


the head alone. We will again follow traditional

terminology in referring to this mode of construal as


Classificatory ♦

In general, and this may be said with respect to


both Hebrew and Arabic (cf. Cowell 1964) there is a very

strong tendency to impose a classif icatory interpretation


on bound genitives of which the second term is
indefinite, whereas definite bound genitives are freely
ambiguous between the two types, depending, of course, on
the plausibility of the interpretation. Here it is

important to note that the process by which


classificatory bound genitives are formed is extremely

general and new combinations may be formed quite freely.


The interpretation that such forms could receive would be
strictly compositional in the same way that the meaning
of a noun and the meaning of an adjective are

compositionally combined to produce an overall meaning.


It is therefore not necessary to assume that forms such
as in 57,58 are compounds that are generated in the

morphological component, just as no such assumption is

95

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
made with respect to adjectives. Indeed, it seems

desirable to maintain the same general analysis of bound


genitives suggested here for classif icatory genitives as
well and this for the following reasons.
First, classificatory bound genitives observe exactly
the same restrictions with respect to the occurrence of a

definite article as do identificatory bound genitives.

Compare the following ungrammatical examples with 57a and


58a respectively.

*59 - (H) ha-matos krav


the aircraft battle

*60 - (A) al-ka?s-u Hamr-en

the glass wine-Gen

To the extent that these restrictions seem to require an

explanation in terms of syntactic configuration and

derivation when dealing with identif icatory

constructions, it seems reasonable to assume that the


same should apply when dealing with classif icatory

constructions. Note also that, just like adjectives, it


is possible to conjoin genitive nouns which are

interpreted in the classificatory manner.

96

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
61- a ) (H) metos krav ve hafcaca

aircraft battle and bombing

"an aircraft for both battle and bombing"

b) (H) saxkan hatkafa ve hagana

player offence and defence

"a player of both offence and defence"

c ) (H) mivne zxuxit u varzel

construction glass and iron

"a construction made of glass and iron"

Finally, we may note that, in Hebrew, the classif icatory

mode of construal is possible not only with bound

genitives but also with Sel-phrases.

62- a) (H) bayit Sei ec

house Sei wood

"a house of wood" ( a house made of wood)

b) (H) moadon Sei studentim

a club Sei students

"a club of students" ( a students club)

Moreover, i t is also possible for an adjective to

intervene between the head and the Sel-phrase.

97

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
63- a) (H) bayit gadol Sel ec

house big Sel wood

"a big wooden house"

b) ( H ) moadon yaSan Sel studentim

club old Sel students

"an old students club"

In the following slection it will be suggested that Sel-

phrases are adjuncts and that, being adjuncts, they may

be adjoined to a syntactic structure a t any syntactic

level. In any case, whatever analysis of Sel-phrases one

adopts, it seems highly unlikely, in view of examples

62,63, to assume that a classif icatory construal in the

case of Sel-phrases is due to certain semantic

combinatorial mechanisms that are exclusively associated

with morphological, as opposed to syntactic,

configurations. That is, i t is unlikely to assume that

the classifica oryl construal is exclusively associated

with semantic interpretation procedures that accompany

structure building processes at a level "earlier" than

the syntax, namely, the morphology. Rather, the

classif icatory mode of construal must be assumed to be

able to apply at a stage higher than the word level.

Given this fundamental distinction between these two

types of interpretation, i t might be useful to wonder how


i
they might be reflected in syntactic representation. As

98

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
just observed, the fundamental difference between these
two modes of construal is that in one case the genitive
NP is construed as a term in a relationship, whereas in
the other case it is construed as a modifier. Now,

within the set of assumptions we have adopted concerning


the nature of thematic relationships, for an NP to be a

term in a relationship means for the external referential


role of that NP to be coindexed with a thematic index

available in the argument structure of a predicate. In


the case of genitive constructions, the type of thematic

relationship holding between the two terms is

indeterminate. It is mostly pragmatically inferred. I

would like, therefore, to propose the idea that nouns, or


at least those nouns which are capable of standing as
9
heads in an identificatory relation , have as part of

their argument structure, in addition to the usual

external theta-role R, an internal thematic index


unspecified for thematic content. The argument structure
of a noun would, thus, look as follows.

64- (Ri , j)

Thus, at the level of syntactic representation, for a


genitive NP to be incorporated into the overall structure

as a term in a thematic relationship, means for that NP

to be coindexed with the internal argument in the

99

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
argument structure of the head noun. The identificatory

relationship in a bound genitive such as 65a may be


represented as in 65b.

65- a) (H) beyt ha-ikar

house the farmer

"the house of the farmer"


b) House [The farmer]

Ri ,j Rj

Note that the relationship between the two elements in 65


is not symmetric. It seems that the best way to

characterize this relationship is as one between a head

noun X and a genitive NP dominated by the maximal


projection of X (at least at some point in the
derivation) . This is restrictive enough to establish the

asymmetry between the two elements and would in fact be

necessary for the case of genitive adjuncts (Sel-

phrases) . Semantically, the mode of combination

associated with the identificatory construal of genitive


constructions may be represented by the following

formula.

66- Xy X p THEx [P (x) & Q(y,x)]

Applied to 65b this gives the following representation

100

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
where Q is most naturally construed as the possession

relation.

67- THEx [House (x) & Q(The Farmer, x)]

The operation associating two elements in the


identificatory relationship, as in 65b, is not obligatory
and if it does not take place then the classif icatory
mode of relationship is construed. In a classif icatory
structure only the head noun is ’’strictly” referential

while the modifying noun is not. This point may be


easily appreciated when one considers definite
classif icatory structures such as the following.

68- a) (H) saxkan ha-hagana


player the defence
"The defence player"
b) (H) metos ha-krav

aircraft the battle


"The fighter aircraft"

Nothing in the interpretation of 68a involves reference


to a contextually unique "defence" and, likewise, nothing

in the interpretation of 68b involves reference to a


unique "battle". Rather, the NP’s in 68 refer to a
unique player of a certain kind and a unique aircraft of

101

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
a certain type respectively. Thus, an NP which has not
been incorporated as a term in an identificatory relation
may still be construed, in the manner of an adjective, as
an expression of type <e,t>. In a case where two terms
in a bound genitive construction are not construed in the

identificatory relationship the thematic index in the


argument structure of the head noun remains without a
referential value. Therefore, it is free for

coindexation (or rather, linking) with another NP. Such


a situation arises when a head noun is related to two

genitive NP's, one which is related to it as a bound


genitive and another in a Sei phrase.

69- (H) beyt ha-ikar Sei Dina

house the farmer Sei Dina

In this example, unless Dina and "the farmer" are

interpreted "genitively" ("the farmer of Dina"), the only

other interpretation available would be the one in which


"the farmer" is a "classif icator" (that is, "a farmer's
type of house") and Dina is a possessor .

102

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
2.3 Sel-Phrases and Double Genitives

Here we will start first by considering cases of

what was referred to earlier as the Free Genitive. Since

constructions involving Sei. or some equivalent of i t do

not occur in Arabic ( a t least not in Standard Arabic) ,

the discussion in this section will be limited to Hebrew.

70- (H) ha-mazkir Sei ha-miflaga

the secretary Sei the party

"the secretary of the party"

My assumption with respect to Sel-phrases is that they

are adjuncts. Here I am using the notion of adjunct in

the sense of Lebeaux (1988) . In that approach adjuncts

may be absent from the tree structure at the level of D-

structure and be adjoined to it at a later stage in the

derivation. As will be seen, this particular assumption

will prove essential for the analysis of nominalization

constructions .

Sei phrases show the "anti-reconstruction" effects

first observed by Van-Riemsdi jk and Williams (1981) and

analyzed by Lebeaux as cases of adjunction. Anti-

reconstruction effects may be exemplified by the contrast

between the grammatical pair 71a, b and the ungrammatical

pair 72a, b.

103

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
71- a) (H) eyze sefer Se Dina kanta hi haxi

which book that Dina bought she the most

ohevet
likes
"Which book that Dina bought does she like the most"
b) (H) eyze sefer Se Dan katav ata XoSev Se

which book that Dan wrote you think that


hu haxi ohev
he the most likes
"which book that John wrote do you think he likes
the most"

72- *a) (H) eyze sipur Se Dan haya be-amerika hu

which story that Dan was in america he


himci be-acmo

invented in himself

* "Which story that Dan was in america did he


invent himself"
*b( (H) eyze teana Se Dan bicea et ha-peSa
Which claim that Dan committed OM the crime
ata XoSev Se hu asuy lehkxiS

you think that he may deny


*"Which claim that Dan committed the crime do you

think that he may deny"

The contrast between 71 and 72 derives, under Lebeaux's

approach, from the fact that 71a, b involve relative

104

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
clauses which are taken to be adjuncts whereas 72

involves argument clauses. The contrast between 71 and

72 may be explained if one assumes that argument clauses

must be present at D-structure (NP-structure, in our


terms) whereas adjunct clauses may be adjoined to the
tree at a later stage in the derivation, crucially in
this case, after Wh-movement has taken place. Given the
additional assumption that principle C of the binding
theory applies at all levels of representation, including

D-structure, the ungrammaticality of 72 may be explained

as a violation of principle C under the intended

interpretation in which Dan is coreferential with hu

(he) . This is because the clause containing Dan must be


present at D-structure in a position in which Dan is c-
commanded by hu (he) , that is, the original complement

position. This effect is circumvented in 71a, b since in

these examples there is no level of representation in

which the relative clause occupies a position which would


give rise to a principle C violation.
We may now note that the same effect observed for

relative clauses in 71 and 72 may also be observed for


Sei phrases in the examples below, thus, providing

support for their treatment as adjuncts.

105

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
73- a ) ( H ) eyze sefer Sei Dina a t a xoSev Se hi haxi

which book Sei Dina you think that she most

ohevet

likes

"Which of Dina ' s books do you think she likes i the

most"

b ) ( H ) eyze sefer Sel Dan ata XoSev Se hu

which book Sel Dan you think that he

katav haxi maher

wrote the most fast

"Which of Dan's books do you think he wrote the

fastest"

Thus 70 will h a v e the following structure in which a Sel-


6
phrase is adjoined a t the N * -level .

106

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
74- DP

/ \
D NP

I / \
the N*

/ \
N* Sel-Ph

I / \
N Sel NP

I / \
secretary the party

An NP/DP in a Sel-Phrase may be integrated into the

overall meaning of the NP containing it just like an


NP/DP in a bound genitive, that is, it may be related to

the head noun in either of the two main modes of noun-to-


noun construal, identificatory and classificatory ,

observed in the previous section. The pairs of free and


bound genitives below are identical in meaning.

75- a) (H) ha-bayit Sei Dina (identif icatory)


the house Sei Dina

"Dina's house"
b) (H) beyt Dina (identificatory )
house Dina
"Dina's house"

107

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
76- a) (H) bayit Sel ec (classificatory)

house Sel wood


"a house made of wood"
b) (H) beyt ec (classificatory)
house wood
"a house made of wood"

It may, therefore, be concluded that Sei does not make


«
any semantic contribution in such cases and should be

analyzed as a "dummy" Case marker. This, however, should


not be interpreted as a claim that Sei (or, rather, a

phonetically identical variant of it) may not sometimes

function as a "semantic" preposition. It


is plausible to assume that Sel-phrases in predicate

position are of this kind.

77- (H) ha-bayit ha-ze Sei Dina

the house the this Sei Dina

"This house is of Dina"

("this house belongs to Dina")

In this example, it is not the external referential

theta-role of Dina which is assigned to the subject "this


house", but rather the external theta-role of the PP

"Sel-Dina", establishing a relationship of possession

between Dina and "the house".

108

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
As was mentioned earlier, in cases in which both a

bound genitive NP and a "Sel-NP" are present, only one of

the two may stand in an identif icatory relation to the

head, and, therefore, the classif icatory interpretation

must be imposed on the other. This is the cape in the

following example where the relations are indicatted by

the arrows.
classif icatory

78- (H) beyt ha-mora Sei Dina

identificatory
house the teacher Sei Dina

"Dina's teacher-house"

Of-course, it is possible for Sei Dina to be related as a

possessor argument of ha-mora (the teacher). Thiis is ,in

fact, the more likely construal of this example but is

not the relevant one a t this point. Cases such as 78

seem to be subject to a very strong semantic restriction

which is the following. The NP in the Sel-phpase must be

construed as an "identif icator" rather than as a

classificator (modifier) . More generally, thp |

restriction seems to be that in a classif icatory Irelation

the modified element may not be complex, that is, in our

case, consisting of more than a single noun. This is why

cases such as the following are unacceptable.

109

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
*79- (H) beyt Dina Sel ha-mora
house Dina Sel the teacher

In trying to assign 79 an interpretation, one way to go


would be to construe ha-mora (the teacher) as the
possessor argument of Dina, but this is unlikely for the
same reason that 80 is unlikely.

*80- (H) Dina Sei ha-mora

Dina Sei (of) the teacher

Another way to go would be to construe the teacher as a


possessor argument of the head bayit (house) and Dina as
a classif icator . But this is an unlikely interpretation
for a proper name. The remaining option is to construe
Dina as a possessor and "Sel-the teacher" as a
classificator , but this, again, seems to be unfeasible by
virtue of the above mentioned restriction, namely, that
in a classificatory relation the modified element may not

be complex. Note that this restriction applies even if


the "would be" classif icator is indefinite, indefinites

being most likely construed as classificators .

*81- (H) beyt Dina Sei mora


house Dina Sei (a) teacher

110

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Thus, to repeat, our explanation for the ungrammaticality
of 79 is the following: The only construal available for

the NP in the Sel-phrase is as an "identificator"


(possessor) with respect to the head noun. However, that
would force a classif icatory construal on Dina, which is

impossible, Dina being a proper name. In our terms, the


internal argument position in the argument structure of
the head noun is "taken" by Dina and there is no way to

assign an interpretation to Sel-the teacher.


Note now that exactly the same state of affairs as
in 79 holds in the following example where a pronoun
replaces Dina. Here, again, a pronoun could never be
construed as a classif icator and must, therefore, be

construed as standing in the identificatory relation to


the head.

82- (H) beyt -a Sei ha-mora


house-her Sei the teacher
"The teacher's house"

82 exemplifies the much discussed phenomenon of clitic-


doubling. Thus, the teacher and the pronoun which is
attached as a clitic to the head bayit (house) , must be
interpreted as coref erential. Obviously, that this is
the only interpretation that could ever be assigned to 82
is now clear, given our discussion of 79. The question

111

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
is, rather, what is the mechanism that makes it possible

for the Sel-phrase to be assigned an interpretation, that

is, to be "licensed**, given that the internal argument of

the head is "taken* 1 and, second, what is it that

distinguishes languages which have clitic-doubling from

those which don't.

We might, in fact, start from the second question by

suggesting that this variation among languages involves

the notion of "levels of representation". Here the idea

would be that, in a language that does not allow for

clitic doubling, the counterpart of a Sel-phrase in that

language must be "licensed" in the syntax.

Generally, an element is licensed if it can be

incorporated into a well formed representation given

general principles and mechanisms available in the

grammar. An overall conception of the grammar in which a

distinction between levels is assumed, makes i t possible

to provide explanations by attributing the applicability

of certain principles or the application of certain

mechanisms to particular levels of representation. Thus,

as was demonstrated in the discussion above, certain

observations about the syntax of adjuncts may be

accounted for by the assumption that adjunction

operations are free to apply at a certain "later" level

of representation rather than a t another "earlier" one.

The explanation proposed here for the phenomenon of

112

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
clitic doubling and the linguistic variation observed
with respect to this phenomenon relies on the distinction
between, on the one hand, the levels of representation in

which strictly syntactic processes are assumed to take


place (NP-Structure, S-Structure) and the level of

representation which provides the input to semantic


interpretation, namely LF, on the other. The claim made
here is that it can be shown that the mechanism which
makes clitic doubling possible is basically semantic in

nature. The idea would be that a language in which

clitic doubling is not attested is a language in which


the counterpart of a Sel-phrase must be licensed at the

level of S-structure or NP-structure, whereas a language


in which clitic doubling is attested is one in which the
counterpart of a Sel-phrase may be licensed at LF7 .

The question is then what does this mode of


licensing consist of. Here we may adopt an approach

similar to the one generally suggested for the treatment

of resumptive pronouns. In particular, I will follow


Chomsky's (1982) proposal with respect to resumptive
pronouns according to which resumptive pronouns are

construed as bound variables by a mechanism of

coindexation applying at the level of LF. Such a

mechanism, according to Chomsky, must be restricted to


the level of LF since NP's base generated in an A'
position do not have an index at S-structure.

113

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Allowing for free indexing at S-structure would lead to
base generation of violations of island constraints.
Following the spirit of this approach, we will assume an
LF mechanism by which an NP in a Sel-phrase is coindexed
with a pronoun within the NP immediately dominating it.

Being coindexed with a pronoun, a Sel-NP is properly


licensed as part of a well formed representation which
may serve as input to a process of semantic
interpretation to be described soon.
Following Lebeaux's (1988) treatment of relative
clauses, we may now introduce the following constraint
applying in English.

83- An Of-Phrase must be licensed at S-structure.

Given these assumptions, we may now propose an


explanation for the ungrammaticality of 84 below along
the following lines.

*84- her house of Mary

In this example, the only way for Mary in of Mary to be


licensed would be for it to have its referential theta-
role coindexed with the thematic index in the argument
structure of the head noun (a classificatory construal of

Mary being impossible. Compare, however, "her house of

114

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
snow", "my friend of many years"). However, the
classif icatory construal being impossible for pronouns,
that thematic index is taken by the pronoun for which
too this is the only available mode of licensing. Thus,
since an of-phrase in English must be licensed in S-
structure, prior to the availability of any LF
mechanisms, 84 is ruled out.
Hebrew, on the other hand, allows for a Sei-Phrase
to be licensed at a later stage, that is, at the level of
LF. Thus, a language like Hebrew can make use of the

kinds of mechanisms that are available at this level of


representation, in particular, the mechanism of
coindexing applying between a genitive Sel NP and a
possessive pronoun. The resulting LF representation is
then subject to generally available mechanisms of
interpretation.

One such typical semantic mechanism is lambda


abstraction, an operation which makes it possible to
transform a semantic expression of any kind into a
predicate and in this way to make it possible for a
certain element to be incorporated into the overall

interpretation as an argument to that predicate. An


obvious condition for the application of this mechanism
is the availability of a variable in the semantic
translation of the expression over which the operation of
lambda abstraction applies, that is, the availability of

115

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
an element inside that expression which is "translatable"
into a variable of the required type (the required type
being <e>, in this case). Thus, at the level of semantic

representation a clitic doubling configuration such as 82


may be represented roughly as follows.

85 - 7)x [ x's house ] (Dina)

In this expression Dina is interpreted (and semantically


"licensed") as the argument of a lambda-expression formed

by "lambda abstracting" over "her house". Thus, the


pronoun "her" enters the semantic interpretation as a

bound variable. Obviously, such an interpretation is


only available for a pronoun having the status of an

argument (in the sense of the identification/

classification distinction suggested in this chapter) ,

from which the impossibility of 81 is derived.


A rather striking confirmation for this analysis,

that is, the view that it is the logical representation


of the structures in question and, in particular, the
status of a pronoun in such a representation which is

responsible for the acceptability of clitic doubling


constructions comes from examples such as the following.

116

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
86- a) (H) bayit Sel ec
House Sel wood
"a house of wood" (a house made of wood)
b) (H) beyt ec

house wood
"a house of wood" (a house made of wood)
c) (H) beyt -o

house-his
"his house"
*d) (H) beyt -o Sei ha-ec

house-his Sei the-wood

In both 86 a and b "ec" (wood) is interpreted as a

classificator . Semantically, it is a predicate, that is,


an expression of type <e,t>. The mode of combination of
a construction such as 86c may be represented as follows.

87- Ap y THEx [P(x) & Q(x,y)]

The resulting representation after the filling in of the

specific lexical contents for the variables in 87 is as


follows, where the relation Q is most naturally construed

as the possession relation.

88- THEx [ Q(x,he) & House (x) ]

117

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
The pronoun in 88 is a term in a relation involving two

entities. It is semantically of type <e>. It is an


expression such as 88 which would be the input to the
semantic mechanism involved in clitic doubling. The
point at which the incorporation of the adjunct starts
may be roughly illustrated as in the following

representation (where i is a variable binding the


pronoun) which would be the logical structure of 86d.

89- 2\i [ THEx [ Q (x,hei ) & House (x) ]] (wood)

Note now that there is no way in which "ec" (wood) in 86d

could be incorporated into the overall interpretation as


represented in the above formula since, being an
expression of type <e,t>, it is of the wrong type to be
construed in this way with the bound variable in 89.
Therefore, 89 is ruled out as a case of type mismatch.
Thus, the possibility or impossibility of a clitic
doubling construction seems to be sensitive to the

semantic relation holding between the NP in the Sel-


phrase and the rest of the expression, the relevant

distinction being that between identification and


classification, a distinction which is basically semantic
in nature.
Further confirmation for this approach to clitic
doubling is provided when one observes the interaction of

118

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
such constructions with anaphoric relations. Consider
the following pairs.

90- a) (H) xaver Sei acmo

friend Sei himself


"a friend of himself"
*b) (H> xaver -o Sei acmo
friend-his Sei himself
91- a) (H) tmuna Sei acmo

picture Sei himself


"a picture of himself"
*b) (H) tmunat-o Sei acmo

picture-his Sei acmo

As the contrast between the a and the b examples above

makes clear, the reason for the ungrammaticality of the b


examples couldn't be that the thematic, or argument,
structure of the nouns xaver (friend) or tmuna (picture)
is such that they cannot provide the necessary antecedent
for the anaphor. Some kind of antecedent must be assumed

to be available in the a examples and therefore also in


the b examples. Under the present account of clitic

doubling, the anaphors in the b examples may only be

incorporated into a well formed representation at the


level of LF as A* binders of a bound variable.
Therefore, principle A of the binding theory to which

119

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
anaphors are subject is violated at all syntactic levels

of representation since at none of these levels is the


anaphor integrated as an argument into the overall
structure.

Thus, clitics in this approach are syntactically and


semantically just like any other pronoun and no special

stipulations need to be made. In particular, the

"clitichood" of the clitics in the constructions under

discussion is irrelevant to any of the syntactic or


semantic issues that seem to be involved and seems to be

relevant only to issues of morphology. Linguistic


variation with respect to clitic doubling is in this

approach reduced to a minimum, namely, the distinction


between licensing at different levels of representation,
a distinction of which the necessity has been

demonstrated elsewhere in any case. To conclude,


the structure of a clitic-doubling construction such as
in 82 would be the following.

120

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
92- DP

/ \

D'

/ \
D< NP

/ \ / \

Ni D DP N'

1 1 1 / \
house POSS NP N* Sei the teacher

N' N

1 1
N ei

her

As the above configuration demonstrates and given the


discussion so far, a clitic doubling construction is one
in which a pronoun stands as a second term in a bound
genitive construction with the head noun and with a Sel-
phrase adjoined to that construction. Given the thematic

structure of nouns as discussed above, the NP in the Sel-

phrase must be "parasitic" on the pronoun for its

licensing and interpretation. We may therefore say that


the so called double genitive is a construction which

involves the cooccurrence of the bound and the free

121

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
genitive. Thus, there are, in fact, only two basic types
of genitive constructions, the bound and the free
genitive, and a derived, or combined, one, namely, the

double genitive.

122

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Footnotes to Chapter II

1
Note that the discussion at this stage is neutral with
respect to the issue concerning a DP analysis of NP's as opposed
to the more traditional NP structure. The present arguments hold
regardless of this issue since what they show is that some
syntactic position to the left of the head of an NP must be
assumed.

2
Needless to say, Borer's analysis is not supplemented by any
explicit theory about percolation. Note that the percolation
mechanism as illustrated in 39 is a clear deviation from the
standard assumption that features, or a t least those features
which d o , percolate up a projection path rather than from a
complement of a head to a node which is a projection of that
head. To the best of my knowledge, there is no explicitly
elaborated theory of percolation within the GB framework. I
suppose that an eventual theory of percolation will have the form
of a set of principles which specify feature cooccurrence
restrictions in such a way as to regulate the distribution of
information in a tree structure, that is, a t least, the type of
information which is generally assumed to be encoded by means of
the device of features (such an explicit and detailed theory has
been developed within the GPSG framework, cf. Gazdar e t al.
(1985)). With respect to the present issue, one might only
wonder a t this point whether such a theory of percolation would
allow for the percolation of definiteness across verbal nodes as
well as nominal nodes. Thus, Borer (forthcoming) assumes the
following configuration to underlie an Action Nominalization
construction.

(i) NPi [+Def]


/ \
SPEC N'i [+Def]
I \
Ni VP [+Def]
/ \
NPa [+Def] VP
I / \
Na [+Def] V
/ \
V NPa

In the surface structure derived from the configuration above Ni


and NPa form a bound genitive. This is assumed by Borer to
involve movement of N 2 to Nt . Now, since all the observations
which apply to bound genitives elsewhere apply also to bound
genitives in Nominalization constructions, I suppose that in this
case too the percolation mechanism of Borer (1988) must be
assumed to apply, allowing for the feature [+Def] to percolate

123

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
from NP2 to NPi . This, as shown in <i), will create a sequence
of nodes along the path from NPa to NPi , including VP, that are
marked as [+Def ] . This seems somewhat problematic since, in
general, definiteness is a distinction which is relevant to the
nominal rather than to the verbal domain. But, obviously,
nothing can be concluded one way or the other in the absence of
any explicit theory of percolation.

3
In Ritter's (1986) analysis the underlying structure of a
bound genitive as in (i) would be the configuration in (ii).

(i) - a) (H) beyt ha-more


house the teacher
"the house of the teacher"

(ii) - DP
/ \
D NP
[+/-POSS] / \
[+/-Def] (DP) N'
I I
house N
I
teacher

In (ii) the head D is specified for the feature [+/-POSS] which,


if specified as [+] , can assign genitive Case, and for the
feature [+/-Def ] which, if specified as [+] , is realized as a
clitic. Moreover, if [Def] is specified as [+] then the DP is
interpreted as definite. (i) is derived by a cliticization of
[+def] to the DP in the Spec position of its NP complement,
followed by a head movement of the head noun teacher to D. The
movement of the head noun is assumed to be obligatory in order
for the feature [POSS] to be morphologically supported. This
analysis encounters some serious difficulties which relate mainly
to the issue of definiteness both at the level of surface
realization as well as on the level of interpretation.
As to surface realization, looking at the configuration in
(ii), we see that the specifier position of the complement NP is
occupied by DP. However, if this DP happens to be definite then
the cliticization of the higher [+Def] to it would result in a
sequence of two definite articles, clearly, an undesirable
result. Ritter (personal communication) suggests that this may
be avoided by assuming a filter which rules out such sequences,
but this would be an ad hoc move to make.
A more serious problem arises with respect to
interpretation. It is assumed by Ritter (1986) that a bound
genitive is interpreted as definite if its head D is specified as
[+Def] and as indefinite otherwise. However, the surface
realization of the definite article in an example like (i) could

124

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
originate either from the head D or from the DP in the specifier
of the complement NP. That is, (i) is predicted to be ambiguous
between the definite and the indefinite interpretations. This
prediction is obviously wrong.

« Given the theory of government adopted here (cf. Chapter 1)


and in particular the notion of Barrierhood employed in this
theory (see 13 in Chapter 1) , POSS in 43c certainly governs the
lower DP. I am, thus, deviating from the assumption made in
Hazout (1988) (and adopted by Shlonsky (1990)) that NP blocks
government in such a configuration.

0
Although the great majority of nouns manifest a syntactic
behavior which is in conformity with the proposal represented in
64, one does find some variation in this domain. Thus, pronouns
have no internal thematic index in their lexical representation
and the same is true (except for some marginal cases) of proper
names. The examples in (i) below are obviously possible and
those in (ii) are not.

(i) a) his house


b) Mary's house
(ii) *a) he of the house
*b) Mary of the house

6
The evidence above and the similarities with relative
clauses, as opposed to sentential complements, clearly support
this treatment of Sel-phrases. Note that there would arise some
difficulties for any treatment which takes Sel-phrases to be
complements. Under such a treatment Sel-phrases are assigned
genitive Case, of which Sei is the surface marking, by virtue of
being governed by a head noun. An analysis of this kind must
provide some special stipulations about the distribution of Sei.
I will explain what this means by looking at Shlonsky *s (1990)
analysis of bound and free genitives.
Shlonsky (1990) assumes that the free genitive involves a
complement DP whereas a bound genitive involves a DP in specifier
position. Thus, the free genitive in (i)a will have the
underlying structure in (i)b (ignoring irrelevant details).

(i) a) (H) ha-harisa Sei ha-maxanot


the destruction Sei the camps
"the destruction of the camps"

125

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
b) DPi
/ \
D NP
I / \
ha N*
/ \
N DP 2
I /
harisa D NP
I I
ha max a not

(i) b is taken by Shlonsky to be a configuration in which DP2 is


assigned genitive Case by the governing N (or its trace, if N
moves to D) . Genitive Case is realized by means of the
preposition Sei. On the other hand, the bound genitive in (ii)a
below is derived by an adjunction of N to NP as illustrated in
(ii) b.

(ii) a) (H) tmunat ha-yalda


picture the girl
"the picture of the girl"

b) DPi
/ \
NP
/ \
Ni NP
1 / \
tmuna DPz N'
/ \ 1
D NP N
1 1 1
ha N ei
1
yaldt1

The adjunction operation (which is adopted, with some


modifications, from Hazout (1988)) in (ii)b is motivated by the
assumption that the head N does not govern its specifier prior to
the application of movement and therefore must adjoin to NP, a
position from which it governs DPa and assigns Case to it. In
this case no "Sel-insertion" takes place.
One wonders at this point what it is about this analysis
that distinguishes between the two cases in such a way that makes
it possible to determine when the preposition Sei occurs and when
it doesn't. If the crucial factor is government of DP by N then
the prediction made by this analysis is that Sei should always
(or never) be "inserted". This is because both configurations
are configurations of government of DP by N with the same two
elements participating, namely, N and DP. After all, this is
the motivation for the adjunction operation, that is, to move N

126

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
to a governing position with respect to DP. Thus, to distinguish
between the two cases, the distinction must be made literally in
terms of complement and specifier.
Considering this possibility , note first that the
distinction between specifier and complement couldn't be
understood as a thematic distinction since one finds common
minimal pairs such as the following in which the two terms in the
construction seem to stand to each other in the same thematic
relation.

(iii) a) (H) beyt ha-mora


house the teacher
"the house of the teacher”
b) (H) ha-bayit Sei ha-mora
the house Sei the teacher
"the house of the teacher"
(iv) a) (H) harisat ha-ir
destruction the city
"the destruction of the city"
b) (H) ha-harisa Sei ha-ir
the destruction Sei the city
"the destruction of the city"

So the distinction between specifier and complement must be


configurational. Configurationally, a complement is a sister to
the head whereas a specifier, at least in a base generated
structure, is a sister to X* . In a structure resulting from
adjunction such as (ii)b the specifier is governed by the head
but is not a sister to it.
Now, the problem with this analysis is that i t makes one
clear prediction with respect to cases for which i t is possible
to show that the DP which is the second member in the genitive
relation couldn't possibly be a complement ( a sister to the head)
at any derivational stage. The prediction is that in such cases
only a bound genitive, rather than a free genitive, should be
possible. Cases of this sort are fairly common. The following
are typical examples.

( v ) a) (H) harisat ha-cava et ha-maxanot


destruction the army OM the camps
"the army's destruction of the camps"
b) (H) ha-harisa Sel ha-cava et ha-maxanot
the destruction Sei the army OM the camps
"the army's destruction of the camps”

The examples in ( v ) are instances of what we refer to here as the


Action Nominalization construction. Chapter 3 is dedicated to a
detailed discussion of this construction. One of the main
conclusions of that discussion is that the two NP's in such a
construction must be asymmetrically related to each other and
must also be differently situated with respect to the head.
This is necessary in order to establish an unambiguous mapping of

127

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Case markings to the two HP's (Genitive, Accusative) and also in
order to establish an asymmetry in anaphoric relationships
between them (see in particular the discussion in sections
3. 2. 2.1 and 3. 2. 2. 2 as well as footnote 4 to Chapter 3). It
follows from these considerations that the first, the genitive,
NP (ha-cava in these examples) couldn't be a complement at the
underlying structure of such examples. It couldn't also be a
complement in any derived structure since there is no movement
operation which would have as output a configuration in which the
"Spec-NP" is a sister to the moved head. The prediction is then
that in such cases Sei couldn't occur, that is, that an example
like (v)b should be impossible. But this is clearly false.
On the other hand, when it comes to cases such as (i)a above
in which the genitive NP is arguably, on the basis of thematic
considerations, a complement, the prediction is that only the
free genitive should occur. This prediction, again, is false.

(vi) harisat ha-maxanot


destruction the camps
"the destruction of the camps”

It is therefore clear that the specifier/complement distinction


has no relevance to the respective distribution of free and bound
genitives and, therefore, some other way must be found to
distinguish between the two construction types.

7
This type of explanation is suggested by Lebeaux (1988) for
the variation between languages which have correlatives and
languages that don't. A language with correlatives is, to use
Lebeaux's terminology, a language in which "a relative clause
linker need not be saturated at S-structure” . Semantic and
syntactic treatments of correlatives along the lines suggested
here for clitic doubling may be found in Bach and Cooper (1978)
and Srivasta (1988).
It also seems reasonable to assume that the same type of
mechanism is involved in the licensing of left-dislocated
elements as in i below. The well formed semantic representation
that would make i possible would be the one in ii.

i) John, I like him


ii) x [ I like x] (John)

128

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
CHAPTER III

THE SYNTAX OF ACTION NOMINALIZATIONS

3.1 Introduction

In this chapter I will propose an analysis of the

Action Nominalisation construction in Hebrew and Arabic.

From the point of view of the theoretical questions

raised by this construction a classification may be made

into two main types, namely, an Action Nominalisation

construction in which the full argument structure of an

"underlying" verb is lexically present (la) and one in

which the subject, or rather, the external argument of

the verb in question i s missing (lb). This view of the

facts will also dictate the overall organisation of this

chapter. Section 3.2 will be concerned with active

Action Nominalisations and section 3.3 with their

subjectless counterparts.

1- a ) (H) axilat Dan et ha-tapuax

eating Dan OM the apple

"Dan's eating the apple"

129

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
b) (A) aklu ttufaaHat-i

eating the apple-Gen

"the eating of the apple"

This section, however, will be devoted to a presentation

of the main facts for which the analysis described in the

following sections attempts to provide an account. The

main theoretical interest of Action Nominalizations, in

my view, derives from their "mixed" verbo-nominal nature.

This is to say that they manifest certain syntactic

characteristics some of which are normally considered

typical of both the external and the internal syntax of

NP's and some of which are normally taken to involve a

constituent headed by a verb. Our presentation will

start with facts concerning the first type of properties,

that is, the nominal.

3.1.1 Nominal Properties of Action Nominalizations

First among the nominal characteristics of Action

Nominalizations is their distribution. Action

Nominalization constructions have the regular

distribution of NP's. Thus, one finds Action

Nominalizations as subjects (2) , objects (3) and objects

of prepositions (4) .

130

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
2- a ) (H) harisat ha-cava et ha-ir hayta

destruction the army OM the city was


axzarit

cruel

"The army’s destruction of the city was cruel"

b) (A) dahaSa-ni iRtiyaal-u zaid-en

surprised me assassination-Nom zaid-Gen

al waziir -a

the minister-Acc

"Muhammeds assassination of the minisrter

surprised me”

3- a ) (H) ha-bamay hisrit et harisat ha-cava et

the director filmed OM destruction the army OM

ha-ir

the city

"The director filmed the army’s destruction of

the city"

b)(A) ra?ayt-u iRtiyaal-a zaid-en

saw -I assassination-Acc zaid-Gen

al waziir -a

the minister-Acc

"I saw zaid's assassination of the minister"

4- a ) (H) dibar-nu al harisat ha-cava et ha-ir

spoke-we about destruction the army OM the city

"We spoke about the army's destruction of the city”

131

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
b) (A) fuji?t -u bi- Rtiyaal -i zaid-en

surprised -I with-assassination-Dat zaid-Gen

al-waziir -a

the minister-Acc

"I was surprised by Zaid's assassination of the

minister"

Second, as can be seen in the arabic examples in 2-4, the

head of an Action Nominalization construction is a

typical noun in that it shows Case marking depending on

the position it occupies. Thus, the noun iRtiyaal

(assassination) is marked for Nominative, Accusative and

Dative in 2, 3 and 4 respectively.

A third type of facts characteristic of the internal

syntax of Action Nominalizations is the assignment of

genitive Case to an NP ("logical" Subject or Object) by

the head noun. The examples in 2-3 all have a subject

(agent) standing in the bound genitive construction to

the head. In modern Hebrew the head and the subject may

also appear in the free and double genitive

constructions as follows.

5- a) (H) Free Genitive:

ha-harisa Sel ha-cava et ha-ir

the destruction Sei the army OH the city

"The army's destruction of the city"

132

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
b) (H) Double Genitive:

harisat -o Sel ha-cava et ha-ir

destruction-his Sel the army OM the city

"The army's destruction of the city"

This "opening" of the structure in the free and double

genitives makes it possible for an adjective modifying

the head noun to intervene between the head and its

subject, again a typical nominal property.

7- a ) (H) ha-harisa ha-maftia Sel ha-cava et

the destruction the surprising Sei the army OM

ha-ir

the city

"The surprising destruction of the city by the army"

b) (H) harisat-o ha-maftia Sel ha-cava et

destruction-his the surprising Sei the army OM

ha-ir

the city

"The surprising destruction of the city by the army"

133

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
3.1.2 Verbal Properties of Action Nominalizations

First among the verbal properties of Action

Nominalizations is the occurrence of Accusative Case

marking on a direct object. Accusative Case marking is

typical, and is normally taken to involve the government

of an NP by a verb (see also Appendix to this chapter).

All the examples in 2-4 show the marking of accusative

Case on a constituent which would correspond to what is

standardly designated as a direct object in a sentence.

Thus, if one wishes to argue that the constructions in

question do not involve the syntactic presence of a verb

one would still have to account for the striking

similarity which holds between the way a verb in a

sentence is related to its arguments on the one hand and

the way a head noun is related to the corresponding

elements in an Action Nominalization construction. This

correlation holds, in fact, with respect to other

complement types that a verb might have. In general, a

nominalized head manifests the same argument structure as

its corresponding verb. Thus, in the following examples

an arbitrary requirement by a verb for a certain type of,

semantically empty, preposition is shown to be observed

by the corresponding nominal form.

134

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
9- a ) ( H ) Dan viter al ha-misra

Dan "gave up" on the position

"Dan gave up the position"

b) ( H ) vitur -o Sel Dan al ha-misra

"giving up" -his Sel Dan on the position

"Dan’s giving up of the position"

10- a ) (H) Dan histalek min ha-misra

Dan left from the position

"Dan resigned the position"

b) (H) histalkut-o Sei Dan min ha-misra

leaving -his Sei Dan from the position

"Dan’s resignation from the position”

In. Arabic, Action Nominalisations with nominal heads

that are related to double object verbs take the same

number of arguments and show the same dative alternation

characteristic of the corresponding verbs.

11- a ) (A) ?a9ta zaidun al-walad-a ttufaaHat-a

gave zaid-Nom the boy -Acc the apple-Acc

"Zaid gave the boy the apple"

b) ( A ) ?i9ta zaid-en al-walad-a ttufaaHat-a

giving zaid-Gen the boy -Acc the apple-Acc

"Zaid's giving the boy the apple"

135

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
12- a) ( A ) ?a9ta Zaid ttufaaHat-a li-1- walad-i

gave zaid the apple-Acc to the boy -Dat

"zaid gave the apple to the boy"

b) ( A ) ?i9ta zaid-en ttufaaHat-a li-1- walad-i

giving zaid-Gen the apple-Acc to the boy-Dat

"Zaid's giving of the apple to the boy"

The occurrence of adverbs is also characteristic of

verbal constituents. Again, Action Nominalization

constructions in both Hebrew and Arabic allow freely for

the occurrence of adverbs.

13- (A) ?akl zaid-en ttufaaHat-a bi-sur9a

eating zaid-Gen the apple-Acc quickly

"Zaid's eating of the apple quickly"

14- (H) harisat ha-cava et ha-kfar be-axzariyut

destruction the army OM the village cruelly

"The army's destruction of the village cruelly"

It seems that the occurrence of adverbs in these

constructions is not licensed simply by the action or

process type of interpretation associated with these

constructions, but is, rather, syntactically

conditioned. This may be evidenced by the fact that,

although the nouns in question may appear all by

themselves (15) , the occurrence of an adverb is not

136

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
allowed unless it is accompanied by the rest of the

complement system required by the corresponding verb.

15- a ) (H) ha-harisa nimSexa Saatayim

the destruction lasted two hours

b) (A) kaana 1- iRtiyaal-u waHSiyy-an

was the assassination-Nom barbaric-Acc

"the assassination was barbaric"

*16- *a) (H) ha-harisa be-axzariyut

the destruction cruelly

*b) (A) al-iRtiyaal bi-sur9a

the assassination quickly

These are then the main nominal and verbal

characteristics of Action Nominalization constructions,

obviously, the main question raised by this interesting

mixture of properties is what assumptions must be made

about its underlying syntactic structure and what

properties need to be attributed to the lexical items

involved in order to derive its surface manifestation.

This way of presenting the question already indicates the

two main strategies that come to mind. The first would

be to postulate a VP or sentence-like structure from

which the surface forms would be derived by the

application of certain syntactic operations. This

strategy would necessitate no (or almost no) additional

137

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
assumptions about the properties of the individual items

(verbs, nouns etc. ) involved. An alternative strategy

would make minimal assumptions with respect to syntactic

structure and derivation and would attempt to explain

some of the facts by attributing certain, exceptional,

properties to some lexical items, such as, for example,

the ability to assign Accusative Case attributed to a

certain class of nouns. We may refer to these two

approaches as the syntactic and the lexicalist approach

respectively. In this work the syntactic approach will be

argued for.

3.1 .3 Binding and Control

Less directly classifiable as either

characteristically nominal or verbal are the facts

concerning binding and control relations in Action

Nominalization constructions. To start with binding, the

relationship between an anaphor and its antecedent in an

Action Nominalization construction shows the same

asymmetries that are observed in a sentence between the

subject and the object position. Thus, a subject NP can

serve as the antecedent of an anaphor in the object

position but not the other way around.

138

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
17- a) (H) Dan ohev et acmo

Dan loves OM himself

"Dan loves himself"

*b) (H) acmo ohev et Dan

himself loves OM Dan

The contrast between the two examples in the following

pair is the same as the one above.

18- a) (H) ahavat Dan et acmo

love Dan OM himself

"Dan’s love of himself”

*b) (H) ahavat acmo et Dan

love himself OM Dan

As to control phenomena in Arabic, an Action

Nominalization construction may figure as the complement

of a control verb just like an infinitival clause in

English or in Hebrew. Obviously, in this case the

subject of the deverbal form is not overtly realized but

is understood as "controlled" by the governing verb.

19- (A) Haawala Zaid-un ?akl-a ttufaaHat-i

tried Zaid eating-Acc the apple-Gen

"Zaid tried to eat the apple”

139

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Example 19 also demonstrates an important £act concerning

Action Nominalisation constructions in which the subject

is missing, namely, in such cases an object must be

assigned genitive Case and not accusative Case as in the

fuller forms.

*20- (A) (al-) ?akl ttufaaHat-a

(the) eating the apple-Acc

By themselves, the facts concerning binding and

control are not readily interpretable. However, it would

certainly be desirable if one could show how they

correlate with or follow, if they do, from an analysis of

this construction that would be motivated by the rest of

the facts.

As mentioned at the beginning of this presentation,

there are two main variants of Action Nominalization

constructions, those in which a (logical) subject is

missing and those in which it is present. I will refer

throughout this work to the first type as the

" subjectless " and to the second as the "active" Action

Nominalization. The discussion in the next section will

be devoted to active Action Nominalizations .

140

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
3.2 Active Action Nominalizations

3.2.1 The Head Movement Analysis

3. 2.1 .1 More About the Facts

Before going into the actual discussion let us

elaborate a little more on the facts. The verbal

properties of active Action Nominalizations are basically

two, the assignment of accusative Case and the

admissibility of adverbs, both of which are exemplified

in 21.

21- (H) axilat Dan et ha-tapuax bi-mehirut

eating Dan OM the apple quickly

"Dan's eating of the apple quickly"

As to the first property, I will adopt the general

assumption (which will be amended later, cf. section

3.3.4) that accusative Case is assigned to an NP in the

context: [vp V ] , that is, accusative Case is assigned

by a verbal head within a particular configuration. As

later discussion will show, such an assumption must be

made and therefore the object NP in 21 must be assumed to

satisfy this structural requirement a t least at some

stage of the derivation.

141

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
As to the admissibility of adverbs, two points are

to be mentioned. The first concerns the kind of adverbs

which are admitted. In particular, while manner and time

adverbials may freely occur in these constructions,

sentential adverbs are strictly excluded. 22 below shows

sentences with sentential adverbs at different positions

in the sentence. The Action Nominalizations

corresponding to these sentences (23) are all bad.

22- a) (H) lelo safek Dan katav et ha-avoda

doubtlessly Dan wrote OM the work

b) (H) Dan karov le-vadai axai et ha-tapuax

Dan probably ate OM the apple

c) (H) ha-oyev behexlet haras et ha-ir

the enemy definitely destroyed OM the city

23-*a) (H) ktivat Dan et ha-avoda lelo safek

writing Dan OM the work doubtlessly

*b) (H) axilat Dan et ha-tapuax karov le-vadai

eating Dan OM the apple probably

*c) (H) harisat ba--oyev et ha-ir behexlet

destruction the enemy OM the city definitely

24 and 25 below are the corresponding paradigms for

manner and time adverbials. These types of adverbs are

perfectly admissible as demonstrated in 25.

142

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
24- a) (H) Dan katav et ha-avoda bi-mehirut

Dan wrote OM the work quickly

b) (H) Dan axai et ha-uga be-nimus

Dan ate OM the cake politely

c ) (H) ha-oyev haras et ha-ir emeS

the enemy destroyed OM the city last night

25- a) (H) ktivat Dan et ha-avoda bi-mehirut

writing Dan OM the work quickly

"Dan's writing of the work quickly"

b) (H) axilat Dan et ha-uga be-nimus

eating Dan OM the cake politely

"Dan's eating of the cake politely"

c ) (H) harisat ha-oyev et ha-ir emeS

destruction the enemy OM the city last night

"The enemy's destruction of the city last night"

Thus, if it is assumed (as it generally is) that

manner and time adverbials are attached to the tree

structure a t the VP level (or are at least internal to

VP) , whereas sentential adverbs are attached higher on

the tree structure, then the ungrammaticality of the

examples in 23 may be taken to indicate that an

underlying verbal constituent to be postulated goes up to

the VP level and no further. This obviously presupposes

that the required configuration is indeed available at an

underlying level of representation in order for such

143

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
distinctions as the one between the VP and the IP-level

to be possible.

The claim that the distribution of adverbs in Hebrew

Action Nominalizations is syntactic rather then semantic

in nature is further supported by the following facts.

As was already mentioned above, adjectives can follow the

head noun in free and double genitives. Thus, compare

the following paradigm with 25 above.

26- a )(H) ha-axila ha-menumeset Sel Dan et ha-uga

the eating the polite Sei Dan OM the cake

"Dan's polite eating of the cake"

b) (H) axilat-o ha-menumeset Sel Dan et ha-uga

eating-his the polite Sei Dan OM the cake

"Dan's polite eating of the cake"

Note, however, that in contrast to adjectives, it is

impossible for adverbs to follow the head noun in free

and double genitives. Thus, compare the following

paradigm with 25 above.

27-*a) (H) ha-ktiva bi-mehirut Sel Dan et ha-avoda

the writing Quickly Sei Dan OM the work

*b) (H) axilat-o be-nimus Sel Dan e t ha-uga

eating-his politely Sei Dan OM the cake

144

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
*c) (H) harisat-o emeS Sel ha-oyev et

destruction-his last night Sel the enemy OM

ha-ir

the city

To complete the picture, note that adjectives as opposed

to adverbs, are bad in final position. Compare the

following paradigm with 25 again.

28-*a) (H) ktivat Dan et ha-avoda ha-mehira

writing Dan OM the work the quick

*b) (H) axilat Dan et ha-uga ha-menumeset

eating Dan OM the cake the polite

*c) (H) harisat ha-oyev et ha-ir ha-axzarit

destruction the enemy OM the city the cruel

Thus, adverbs and adjectives are in complementary

distribution with respect to final position and the

position immediately following the head. This may also

be demonstrated by examples in which both an adjective

and an adverb occur as in the following. Switching the

order between adjective and adverb as in 29b below is

totally inconceivable.

145

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
29- a ) (H) harisate-nu ha-axzarit et ha-ir

destruction-our the cruel OM the city

in alot ha-Saxar

with break the dawn

"Our cruel destruction of the city with the break of

dawn"

*b (H) harisate-nu im alot ha-Saxar et

destruction-our with break the dawn OM

ha-ir ha-axzarit

the city the cruel

These distributional facts may be summarized as follows.

30- (Det) N (cl) (Adj) (Sei) NPi NP2 (Adv)

Note that, of the options available in 30, only a subset

occurs in Standard Arabic. That is, as far as Standard

Arabic is concerned, only the bound genitive form occurs

and therefore the possibility of an intervening adjective

as in the free and double forms in Hebrew is not

available. In 30, NPi and NP2 are the subject (agent)

and object (theme) respectively and the distribution of

adverbs and adjectives is as indicated. In this sequence

NP2 is assigned accusative Case while NPi is genitive.

Concerning the respective distribution of adverbs and

146

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
adjectives, the ungrammaticality of the examples in 27

(adverbs following the head) must be taken to show that

the admissibility of adverbs in Action Nominalizations is

not a fact that has simply to do with some kind of

semantic compatibility. Rather, it is a syntactic fact

that has to do with the principles that determine which

elements can be attached at which positions in the tree

structure. This is not to be interpreted as a claim that

the admissibility of adverbs has nothing to do with the

event type of interpretation associated with Action

Nominalizations. Indeed, some such correlation, or even

dependency, seems very likely. But it is clear that the

interpretation of Action Nominalizations as denoting an

event is simply not sufficient as an explanation of the

severe restrictions on the distribution of adverbs within

the construction.

Thus, all of the facts considered above point

clearly towards the necessity of assuming an underlying

configuration of which a substructure is a verbal

projection of a certain level (the VP level) . Such a

configuration will make possible a direct account of the

above observations concerning the distribution of adverbs

as well as the facts concerning Case marking.

147

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
3 . 2. 1 . 2 The Syntactic Derivation of Active Action

Nominalizations

Here we will be concerned first with the core cases

of Action Nominalizations, that is, cases in which the

head noun and the subject form a bound genitive as in 30

below. These cases are common to both Modern Hebrew and

standard Arabic. Free and double genitives which are

special to Hebrew will be examined later.

31- a ) (H) axilat ha-yeled et ha-tapuax bi-mehirut

eating the boy OM the apple quickly

"The boy's eating the apple quickly"

b) (A) aklu 1-walad-i ttufaaHat-a bi-sur9a

eating the boy-Gen the apple-Acc quickly

"The boy's eating the apple quickly"

Let us first present the actual derivation assumed here

and then go into further details. The underlying

configuration assumed for 31 a,b is the following.

148

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
32- DP

/ \
D NP

I / \
POSS NPi N*

I / \
the boy N VP

I / I \

NOM V NPa Adv

I I I
eat the quickly

apple

In 3 2 a nominal bound morpheme, NOM, figures as the head

and subcategorizes for a VP headed by a verb of which any

lexical requirements must be satisfied within the domain

of its government. The NP which is interpreted as the

logical subject of the underlying verb is base generated

in the specifier position of NP. The actual deverbal

form of the head noun is derived by a head movement of

the underlying verb to NOM. The result of this movement

is the following configuration.

149

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
33- DP

D NP

POSS NPi N

N® VP

N V NP 2 Adv

NOM

The circled subtree in the above configuration is the

derived head of the construction. The trace left by the

verb is assumed to inherit the properties of the verb, in

particular, its Case assigning features. The next step

in the derivation is the movement operation generally

assumed as part of the derivation of bound genitives (cf.

Ch. 2). The result of that process is the following.

150

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
34- DP

/ \

D NP

/ \ / \

N POSS NPi N'

/ \ 1 / \

V N the N VP

1 1 boy 1 / 1 \

eat NOM e V NPa Adv

the apple

The two main characteristics of this construction are

directly accounted for by this derivation. First,

accusative Case assignment is a manifestation of the

government of the direct object by the verb (or by its

trace). Second, adverbs are licensed in the

configurations 32-34 as subconstituents of VP. Given the

above configurations, it is only VP adverbs that may

occur, and this only in the position following the NP

object, if one assumes that linear adjacency is a

requirement on government and Case assignment.

As will be soon realized, this analysis relies on

properties attributed to the abstract nominal head NOM to

derive many of the properties of this construction.

However, before going into this issue, a word must be

151

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
said about the morphological realization of the derived

head in 33. As is well known, verbs in both Hebrew and

Arabic appear in a certain number (roughly, 7 or 8 in

Hebrew and 1 2 or more in Arabic) of different

morphological patterns known as Binyanim. Generally, a

certain pattern has a unique nominal i zed form.

Otherwise, if more than one nominal form is associated

with a verb form, each single verb in that particular

class will be associated with a unique nominal form. A

possible difficulty for the present analysis is that it

raises the possibility that one will have to postulate a

different NON morpheme depending on the verb form

appearing as head of VP in a configuration like 32.

Making such an assumption, however, would raise another

difficulty, namely, how to account for the dependency

between the form of the verb and the particular

morphological form of NOM, given that both are inserted

independently. However, no such difficulty arises if

one simply assumes NOM to be an abstract form rather than

an item having an actual morphological shape. Being an

abstract form, NOM may be thought of as some sort of

function which maps a verb onto a unique nominal form

which is lexically listed for that verb.

Some examples of Binyan patterns with the corresponding


1
verbal and nominal forms are the following .

152

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
35- Hebrew

Binyan pattern verb form nominal form

a) CaCaC SaVaR SViRa

break breaking

b) CiCeC DiBeR DiBuR

speak speaking

c) hi-CCiC hi-LBiS haLBaSa

dress (trans) dressing

d) ni-CCaC ni-SBaR hiSaVRut

be broken being broken

e) hit-CaCeC hit-KaTeV hitKaTVut

correspond correspondence

36- Arabic

Binyan pattern verb form nominal form

a) (Form I) CaCaCa NaQaLa NaQL

transport transportation

b) (Form II) CaCCaCa SaRRaBa taSRiiB

make drink making drink

c) (Form III) CaaCaCa QaaWaMa muQaaWaMa

resist resistance

d ) (Form IV) ?aCCaCa TaRSaLa 7iRSaaL

send sending

e) (Form V) ta-CaCCaCa ta-BaYYaNa taBaYYuN

become clear becoming clear

f) (Form X) ?ista-CCaCa 7ista9MaRa ?isti9MaaR

colonize colonization

153

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Having clarified the morphological issue, we may now

come back to the syntactic analysis. As stated earlier,

the role played by NOM is central and many of the

properties of the construction may be explained by making

certain assumptions about the nature of NOM. Aside from

being a bound morpheme taking a VP complement, NOM has

the properties of a nominal head. Given the fact that an

Action Nominalisation construction may occur as an

argument of a verb and refer to events processes and the

like, we may assume (following ideas of E. Williams) that

NOM has a referential theta-role R which is assigned up

("vertically") to the dominating NP node. We will also

assume that NOM has an additional referential theta role

R, which is necessarily an internal one. Thus, a lexical

representation of NOM may look roughly as follows, where

37b encodes its subcategorization frame.

37- a) Argument structure of NOM: (Ri , Rj )

b) Subcategorization frame of NOM: [ VP]

Note that NOM is always situated in a configuration i n

which it may be assigned the external theta role of VP.

NOM is the sister of the VP subcategorized by it. In

this case it is the internal R-role of NOM which enters

the relation of theta role assignment with VP. Now, just

as it is the case with any instance of theta role

154

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
assignment, here too the relation is not symmetric.

Rather, it is an asymmetric relation of linking. It is

the external theta role of VP which is dependant on Rj

for its referential content rather than the other way

around. Therefore the linking of both theta roles

results in a thematic structure such as illustrated

below.

38- N’i

/ \

Ni VPj

I / \

NOM V NPk

Ri > Rj

The syntactic process represented above is one of theta-

role assignment in the usual sense in which theta-role

assignment is understood in this work. Thus, as far as

the formal operation of theta role assignment is

concerned, the external theta role of VP is satisfied.

Moreover , the operation in 38 must apply since the

external theta-role of VP must be assigned and, most

importantly, it couldn't be vertically assigned to N* and

become its external theta-role since N* already has an

external theta-role, namely, the external theta-role of

NOM. Thus, the assignment of theta-roles as indicated in

155

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
38 is the only available option. This simple point will

turn out to be of crucial importance as our presentation

proceeds .

The only unusual aspect about the situation

illustrated in 38 is that the internal theta role of NOM

has no referential content. In the normal cases in which

an R-role figures as the external argument of a noun this

referential, or descriptive, content is provided by the

noun itself. Thus, the noun man associated with an

external theta role R corresponds to the expression "man

(x) '* in logical notation. Now, clearly, the referential

content of Rj in 38 does not remain unspecified since it

is the NP in specifier position which ends up being

interpreted as the subject. Thus, it remains to

establish the relationship between the internal argument

of NOM and the NP situated in the specifier position of

the NP of which NOM is the head (cf. 32). This, however,

may be achieved in the way that this is done in any

genitive construction in which the two members of the

construction are related in the identif icatory mode of

construal, as described in Chapter 2, section 2.2. That

is, the external theta-role R of the genitive NP is

coindexed with the internal thematic index of the head

noun, that is, the internal argument of NOM. We can,

therefore, say that the subject NP is assigned a theta-

role through the mediation of NOM. That is, the subject

156

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
theta-role which was assigned first to NOM nay be said to

have been passed on (although not externally, or,

vertically) rather than being "absorbed" by NOM. This

state of affairs may be represented as follows.

39- NPt k

/ \

NPa N'k

R t / \

N VPi

1 / \

NOM V NPa j

Rk ,Ri i,j

Note that in a case where an NP is present in specifier

position the operation (coindexation) illustrated in 39

nust take place since this is the only way for this NP to

be thematically licensed. If no NP is present in this

position then no ungranunaticality results and the

internal argument of NOM is construed as arbitrary in

reference. An additional mechanism by which the internal

R-role of NOM may be assigned referential content is the

one of obligatory control to be described later in this

chapter .

This is then the analysis of the core cases of

Action Nominalization constructions involving the bound

157

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
genitive. Given this approach, the analysis of the free

and double genitive variants which are special to Hebrew

is a straightforward natter. Note that just as is the

general case in genitive constructions, here too, a Sel-

phrase may be adjoined to the tree structure at a later

stage in the derivation. This is in line with Lebeaux's

(1988) general approach to adjuncts adopted in this work

and applied to the treatment of Sel-phrases. The Sel-NP

is construed in the identif icatory relation with the head

noun NOM by having its external R theta-role coindexed

with the internal theta role available in the argument

structure of NOM, which is at this point assigned

(coindexed with) the external theta-role of VP. The

result is the free genitive variant of 39, of which the

two relevant derivational stages are illustrated in 40

b,c.

40- a ) (H) ha-axila Sel Dan et ha-tapuax

the eating Sei Dan OM the apple

"Dan's eating of the apple"

158

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
b) NP-structure

NPk

/ \

Det N* k

1 / \

the Nk VPi

1 / \

NOM V NPj

Rk , Ri 1

eat i , j

c) S-structure DP

/ \

D - NP

1 / \

the N'

/ \

N' VPi

/ \ / \

N Sei V NPj

/ 1 Dan? 1 1

V N Ri e the apple

1 1

eat NOM

Rk , Ri

159

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
The structure of the corresponding double genitive

construction is a combination of the free and the bound

form. Here it is the pronoun in the Spec-of-NP position

which is thematically linked with NOM and it is to this

underlying structure that a Sel-phrase is adjoined. 41b

is the configuration resulting from this adjunction prior

to the head movement of V to NOM and of the movement of

the resulting head noun to D.

41- a) ( H ) axilat-o Sei Dan et ha-tapuax

eating-his Sei Dan OM the apple

"Dan's eating <of the apple"

b) DP

/ \

D NP

1 / \

POSS NP N•

1 / \

hei N' \

/ \ VPi

NOM Sei- Dan / \

Rk ,R1 V NPj

i,j

The relationship between "Dan" and the doubling clitic

pronoun in this structure follows from the general

160

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
analysis of clitic doubling proposed in Chapter 2

(section 2.3). The pronoun is coindexed with the

internal argument of NOM in the same way as this is

achieved with a "full" NP in the bound genitive variant.

The Sel-phrase is incorporated into the overall

interpretation by the proposed LF mechanism.

Binding relationships between NP2 and NPa ,

coarguments of the underlying verb in the configuration

in 39, are directly accounted for. NP2 , being assigned

the external theta-role of VP, stands to NPa , an internal

argument, in the same asymmetric relationship that would

exist between a subject and an object in a sentence. The

contrast in 42 is thus explained.

42- a ) (H) reiyat Dan et acmo

seeing Dan OM himself

"Dan's seeing of himself"

*b) (H) reiyat acmo et Dan

seeing himself OM Dan

In this respect there is no difference to be expected

between the three different variants of genitive

constructions. The following examples confirm this

expectation.

161

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
43- Free Genitive

a) (H) ha-reiya Sei Dan et acmo

the seeing Sei Dan OM himself

"Dan's seeing of himself"

*b) ( H ) ha-reiya Sei acmo et Dan

the seeing Sei himself OM Dan

44- Double Genitive

a ) (H) reiyat-o Sei Dan et acmo

seeing-his Sei Dan OM himself

"Dan's seeing of himself"

*b) (H) reiyat-o Sel acmo et Dan

seeing-his Sei himself OM Dan

162

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
3.2.2 Syntactic vs. Lexicalist Approaches to

Action Nominalizations

The account outlined in the previous section may be

referred to as syntactic since it assumes a syntactic

process by which the noun head of an Action

Nominalization construction is derived, the head being a

single word as far as morphological and phonological

criteria are concerned. Taking this line, we were able

to derive many of the properties of the construction,

some of which are “configurationally sensitive" (for

example, binding and the distribution of adverbs) and

some of which have to do with the properties that may be

attributed to lexical items by virtue of being members of

certain word classes (for example, Acc. Case assignment

by a verb). The burden of providing an explanation is

put in the syntactic approach mainly on the properties of

the configuration and the syntactic operations that it

makes possible. However, as mentioned at the beginning

of this chapter, this is not the only conceivable

approach. Another way to go might be to attempt to

derive the facts by attributing certain properties to

lexical items. For example, the property of being able

to assign accusative Case may be attributed to a certain

class of nouns. Such an approach might be desirable from

the point of view of a certain general theoretical

163

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
conception which wishes to exclude the possibility of any

word formation processes in the syntax. I n this section

I will examine two possible versions of a lexicalist

approach to Action Nominalizations, in an attempt to

demonstrate their inadequacies (sections 3. 2. 2.1 and

3. 2. 2. 2). In sections 3.2.2. 3 and 3. 2. 2. 4 I will

present what seem to be two fairly compelling arguments

in favour of the syntactic analysis outlined in the

previous section. These arguments will be based on

certain facts concerning the interpretation of Hebrew

Action Nominalisation constructions and on an analysis of

causative constructions in Arabic respectively.

3. 2 . 2 . 1 A Lexicalist Analysis ~ First Version

A first possible version of a lexicalist analysis of

Action Nominalizations would be represented by the

structure in 45b which is assigned by this analysis to

45a below.

45- a ) (H) harisat ha-oyev et ha-ir

destruction the enemy ON the city

"the enemy's destruction of the city"

164

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
b) N*

/ \

N NP NP

1 1 1

destruction the the

enemy city

The particular analysis represented by the tree structure

above is proposed in Doron (1989) . The discussion in

this section will concentrate on general issues

concerning the validity of this approach. Some problems

that are internal to Doron* s particular proposal are

discussed in footnote 3. A slight variant of this

approach due to Borer (1984) is discussed and rejected in

footnote 4 to this chapter.

In 45b the two arguments of the head noun are .

strictly. c-commanded and thus governed and assigned Case

by it. It is assumed by Doron that nouns such as the one

figuring as head of 45b have the special, lexically

specified, property of being able to assign accusative

Case. Such nouns are referred to in Doron (1989) as

"strong" nouns.

One might say that the set of assumptions

represented by the configuration in 45b is the minimal

and the most simplistic one to make and, as I will show,

its inadequacies are rather striking. Nevertheless, I

165

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
assume that it still deserves to be examined even if only

for the purpose of illustrating the nature and the

complexity of the problems involved.

The central assumption in this analysis is the one

about the existence of what are referred to as "strong"

nouns. This assumption makes it possible to derive the

fact of the assignment of accusative Case to the

(logical) object without being forced to assume a more

elaborate sentence or VP-like structure. Obviously,

this is a legitimate assumption to make and the

comparison between this analysis and a syntactic analysis

should center mainly on the explanatory gains made by

each one. That is, how many of the facts associated with

the Action Nominalization construction may be explained

on the basis of this assumption.

Taking this line of reasoning, the most striking

property of the configuration in 45b is that both

arguments are situated in the same structural

relationship to the head (immediate dominance by the

first branching node) and are, thus, also symmetrically

related to each other.

As to the empirical facts, we may start with those

concerning the order of constituents in the construction.

Thus, one might raise the legitimate question as to why

the two arguments, the genitive NP and the accusative NP,

16 6

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
appear in the order as in 45 (Genitive-Accusative) rather

then in the reverse order as follows.

*46- (H) (ha-) harisa et ha-ir ha-oyev

(the) destruction OM the city the enemy

Here an obvious answer suggests itself, namely, it is

fairly plausible to assume that an NP standing in a bound

genitive relation to a head noun must be adjacent to it

whereas such a requirement need not, presumably, be

observed by a direct object which is assigned accusative

Case. Note that by proposing this answer we are ignoring

a range of facts concerning the syntax of bound genitives

for which the structure in 45b can provide no account.

These include the well known restriction on the

occurrence of an initial definite article in a bound

genitive. But this problem may be ignored at the moment

for the sake of the argument. Note also that by implying

that no adjacency requirements hold with respect to the

relationship between the head and the (logical) object

one raises the expectation that other types of material

may intervene between the two, say, adverbs. In this

case, again, the following contrast remains unaccounted

for.

167

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
47- a) (H) harisat ha-oyev et ha-ir be-axzariyut

destruction the enemy OM the city cruelly

"The enemy's cruel destruction of the city"

*b) (H) harisat ha-oyev be-axzariyut et ha-ir

destruction the enemy cruelly OM the city

We may ignore this problem as well for the sake of the

discussion and come back to the issue of word order.

Note now that the answer suggested above, namely, that a

genitive NP must be adjacent to the head noun does not

yet solve the problem but simply sets the stage for

another, more fundamental, question, namely, why it is

that the (logical) object, or theme, may only be marked

with accusative Case and the (logical) subject, or agent,

may only be marked with genitive Case (in case, of

course, that both arguments are present), that is, why

the following example is impossible with an

interpretation identical to that of 45a ("The enemy's

destruction of the city").

*48- (H) harisat ha-ir et ha-oyev

destruction the city OM the enemy

The problem is that there is nothing about the structure

in 45b that makes it possible to establish a unique

configurational relationship between the head and each

168

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
one of the arguments and in this way to explain the

difference in Case marking between the two arguments as a

manifestation of two different configurational

relationships. Now, if such an unambiguous mapping from

logical (Subject , Object) or thematic (agent , theme) roles

to Case marking is impossible on the basis of

configurational relationships, some other kind of

mechanism must be invoked. It seems that the only

alternative left is a direct, one-to-one, mapping from

logical, or thematic, roles (taken as primitive notions)

to case marking in the way that such mechanisms are

assumed to exist in so called "non-configurational"

languages. Thus, we will have to assume that, at least

as far as the syntax of NP's is concerned, Hebrew and

Arabic are "non-configurational". A mapping from logical

or thematic roles to case marking for the two languages

might look as follows.

49- Logical/Thematic role Case marking

Subject/Agent --------> Genitive

Object/Theme --------> Accusative

Is it, however, the case that such a, one to one, mapping

really exists ? Going from left to right in 49, a

(logical) object is indeed assigned accusative Case, but

169

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
only if the (logical) subject is present. Otherwise, it

is assigned genitive Case and is still, to be sure,

interpreted as the theme. Going from right to left,

genitive Case is assigned to the (logical) subject, but

if the subject is missing then it must be assigned to the

object. We see then that there is no unambiguous,

unique, mapping from logical, or thematic, roles to Case

marking, and there is no way in this approach to exclude

48. If 48 cannot be ruled out on the basis of some non-

conf igurational mechanism, it becomes necessary to assume

a configuration in which each of the arguments stands in


2
a unique structural relationship to the head .

Obviously, 45b couldn't be that configuration.

The same type of problem arises with respect to

anaphoric relationships in these constructions. In 45b

the two NP's are in a relationship of mutual c-command.

Therefore, given a standard version of the binding

theory, no account is available on this approach for the

following contrast.

50- a ) (H) harisat ha-enoSut et acma

destruction the humanity OM herself

"The destruction of humanity by itself"

*b) (H) harisat acma et ha-enoSut

destruction herself OM the humanity

170

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Rather, given condition C of the binding theory, both 50a
3
and 50b are predicted to be ungrammatical . It is

therefore obvious that this version of a lexicalist

approach suffers from serious inadequacies at the most

elementary level. Indeed, it accounts for none of the

relevant facts, including the assignment of accusative

Case to the object. This fact is not explained on the

basis of any generally known facts or principles but is

simply derived from a certain stipulation about the


4
properties of "strong" nouns .

The important lesson to be drawn from this

discussion is the following. Accusative Case assignment

is not a property that may simply be attributed to a

lexical head of a certain kind. It is the property of a

lexical head within a particular syntactic configuration

and in this sense it may be said to be configurational.

Therefore, any syntactic analysis of a construction

involving Accusative Case marking must provide the

required configuration.

171

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
3. 2. 2. 2 A Lexicalist Analysis - Second Version

One might think of another, more elaborated analysis

within a lexicalist approach. Such an analysis may be

represented roughly as in the following configuration.

51- DP

/ \

D NP

/ \

NP N*

I / \

the enemy N NP

I I

destruction the city

In the configuration above each of the arguments stands

in a unique structural relation to the head and in this

way this analysis, at least, establishes a certain

asymmetry between the two NP's. The surface structure

corresponding to 51 would be derived by the movement

operation assumed to apply generally in the derivation of

bound genitive constructions. The output of this

operation would be the following.

172

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
52- DP

/ \

D NP

/ \ / \

Nt D NP N'

1 1 1 / \

destruction POSS the N NP

enemy 1 1

et the city

It may also be said in favour of this analysis that the

asymmetry it establishes between the two NP positions

makes it possible to account for binding relationships in

this construction.

Note that, in fact, at least within the theta

theoretic framework assumed here, this analysis does not

yet solve the problem. This is for the following reason.

Given the framework assumed here, the head noun in 51

would have three arguments, an external R role and two

internal roles, say. Agent and Theme. However, this

theory makes only a binary distinction between external

and internal roles. It follows that the two internal

roles are of an equal status so there is still no way to

ensure that the Agent role will be mapped onto the Spec-

of-NP position and that the Theme will be assigned to the

complement position. This is, however, a highly theory

173

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
internal argument and is therefore far from being

sufficient to settle the issue.

In the following I will present several other

arguments against this analysis, some of which may be

considered more conclusive and some of which less.

However, there do seem to be two fairly conclusive

arguments against it, or any other lexicalist analysis,

which will be presented in the next two sections.

3 . 2. 2 . 2.1 The Distribution of Adverbs and Adjectives

It is generally assumed that the distribution of

adverbs is conditioned by syntactic factors such as the .

availability in the tree structure of a VP node (at least

for time and manner adverbials) and possibly other

factors. If these assumptions are accepted, then it can

be claimed that a configuration as in 50,51 does not

provide the right environment for an adverb to occur.

Otherwise it would become necessary to argue that the

distribution of adverbs is conditioned by semantic rather

then syntactic factors. This, however, was argued

against in section 3. 2. 1.1 in which evidence was provided

showing that the distribution of adverbs, in particular,

the respective distribution of adverbs and adjectives in

174

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Action Nominal izat ion constructions, is due, most

likely, to syntactic rather then semantic factors.

3. 2 .2. 2. 2 Free Genitive Variants

Cases in which the subject NP appears in a Sel-

phrase in the free genitive construction as in the

following example raise some serious difficulties for

this version of lexicalist analysis.

53-* (H) ha-hafcaca Sel ha-cava et ha-ir

the bombardment Sei the army OM the city

"The army's bombardment of the city"

The problem with 53 is that the approach under

consideration incorporates the assumption that the

assignment of theta-roles is achieved unambiguously by

mapping the "theme” onto the complement position and the

"agent" onto the specifier position. However,

since in this case the specifier position of NP is

occupied by the subject as in 52 above the only way to

derive the surface order in 53 is by an operation of head

movement adjoining the head noun to D. This raises at

least two serious problems as follows.

Starting with the, possibly, less serious one, the

175

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
head position of DP may be occupied by a definite

article. It is therefore not clear whether such a

movement would still be possible. Shlonsky (1990)

suggests that such a movement is not only possible but

also necessary. In particular, Shlonsky (1990) assumes

that the definite article "ha-" is an affix which needs

to be supported. For this requirement to be satisfied

the head noun must move to D and adjoin to "ha-". The

structure of 53 would thus be the following in which the

definite article is an affix attached to the head noun.

54- DP

/ \

D NP

/ \ / \

D N NP N’

ha 1 1 / \

the bombar- Sei N NP

dment the 1 1

army e the city

It seems that there is some data which makes this

analysis highly implausible. Thus, it is possible to

have numerals instead of the definite article in examples

corresponding to 53.

176

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
55- a ) (H) SaloS hafcacot Sel ha-cava et ha-ir

three bombardments Sel the army OM the city

"Three bombardments o£ the city by the army”

a ) (H) arbaa nifnufim Sel Dan et ha-yad

four wavings Sei Dan OM the hand

"Four hand wavings of Dan”

It is questionable whether the numerals in the examples

above may be viewed as affixes rather than free forms and

whether the sequences Numeral+N in these examples can be

taken to be derived words rather than units of a higher

level. Note that the numerals in these examples are in

their free rather than bound forms (SaloS as opposed to

SloSa and arbaa as opposed to arbaat). It seems

reasonable to assume that in general numerals and the

definite article occupy the same position since they are

in complementary distribution as demonstrated by the

following pairs.

56- a ) (H) SaloS mexoniyot

three cars

* b) (H> SaloS ha-mexoniyot

three the cars

57- a ) (H) arbaa sfarim

four books

177

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
b ) (H) arbaa ha-sfarim

four the books

A more serious problem to this analysis relates to such

examples as the following i n which the head is modified

by an adjective.

58- (H) ha-hafcaca ha-maftia Sel ha-cava et

the bombardment the surprising Sei the army OM

ha-ir

the city

"The army's surprising bombardment of the city**

The problem is that the present analysis simply can't

generate such cases. This is because the operation which

moves the noun up to D applies to the head alone and must

therefore leave a modifying adjective behind as

illustrated below.

178

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
59- DP

/ \

D NP

/ \ / \

(ha) Nt NP N*

/ \

N* NP

/ \

N AP

et

Thus, the best that the present analysis can do is

generate ungrammatical sequences such as the following

(compare with 58).

*60- (H) ha-hafcaca Sel ha-cava ha-maftia et

the bombardment Sei the army the surprising OM

ha-ir

the city

Within the analysis proposed in this work, in particular,

the approach to adjuncts adopted here (due t o Lebeaux

(1988)), cases such as 58 pose no problem. Thus, it may

be assumed that Sel-phrases are adjoined to the tree

179

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
structure at a later stage in the derivation, say, S-

structure, as follows.

61 - NP-structure S-structure

DP DP

/ \ / \

D NP -----> D NP

1 / \ 1 / \

the N' the N’

/ \ / \

N' NP N' NP

/ \ 1 / \ 1

N AP the city N' Sei the

1 / \ the city

bombardment N AE’ army

bombardment

Now, it couldn’t be the Sel-phrase which is (directly)

assigned the subject theta role in this construction

since its configurational positioning does not observe

the requirement of asymmetry between subject and object.

So it must be some other element. This issue is handled

within the approach advocated here by making certain

assumptions about the role played by NOM as a "receiver"

180

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
of a theta-role, but this makes a non-lexicalist approach

necessary.

3. 2. 2. 2. 3 - Subjectless Action Nominalizations

and Control

An analysis such as the one represented in 51 , 5 2

runs into serious problems when it comes to subjectless

Action Nominalizations. Here we are referring to cases

such as the following.

62- a ) (H) haxzarat ha-taSlumim bi-mehirut

return the payments quickly

"the return of the payments quickly"

b) (A) ?aklu ttufaaHat-i bi-sur9a

eating the apple-Gen quickly

"the eating of the apple quickly"

I n these examples the object stands in the bound genitive

construction to the head noun and therefore must be

assumed to occupy the specifier position of NP. In this

state of affairs no other structural position is

available for an additional argument. However, that the

existence of such an additional argument must be assumed

may be demonstrated by the fact that subjectless Action

181

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Nominalizations allow for the occurrence of an anaphor

and therefore must be assumed, at least under a standard

approach to binding, to provide a position for an

antecedent .

63- (H) reiyat acmo ba -mar?a

seeing himself in the mirror

The facts concerning control of subjectless Action

Nominalizations in Arabic point in the same direction.

64-a) (A) yuriidu zaid-un naql-a 1-kitaab-i

wants zaid-Nom transportation the book -Gen

?ila bayruut

to beirut

"zaid wants to transport the book to Beirut"

b) (A) yuriidu zaid-un al-intiqaal -a ?ila

wants zaid-Nom the transportation-Acc to

bayruut

beirut

"Zaid wants to be transported to beirut"

As the facts in 64 show, control of subjectless Action

Nominalizations in Arabic is just like control of

Infinitives in Hebrew or English. That is, it is

insensitive to the type of theta-role assigned to the

182

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
controlled element. Rather, it is a control of a

position. Presumably, under a standard approach, the

controlled element would be an empty NP, PRO, situated

somewhere i n the configuration. However, it would have

to be situated in such a position as to be able to serve

as the antecedent of an anaphor as in the following

example.

65- (A) yuriidu zaid-un qatl-a nafs-i -hi

wants zaid-Nom killing-Acc self-Gen-him

"Zaid wants to kill himself"

These structural requirements cannot be met by the

configuration in 51,52 if the anaphor in 6 5 is assumed to

occupy the specifier position of NP.

There is still another possibility to be considered

with respect to the control phenomenon, namely, one which

assumes a theta theoretic approach to control, rather

than a standard, "structuralist" approach. Under such an

approach, the control relation would hold not between a

controlling NP and a controlled element occupying a

specific structural position, but rather a relation

between a controller and a uniquely identified thematic

role. It is my contention that such an unambiguous

relationship cannot be established within the approach

183

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
under consideration. This can be demonstrated with the

following example.

66- ( A ) Sajja9 -tu zaid-an 9ala l-?akl -i

encouraged-I zaid-Acc on the eating-Dat

"I encouraged zaid to eat"

In this example it is unambiguously the agent of "eating"

which is controlled, although the verb "eat" is lexically

specified for both an "agent" and a "theme". To

establish an unambiguous relationship between a

controller and a theta-role, one of the theta-roles would

have to be assigned a unique status. Here, the only kind

of distinction available is the external/internal

distinction since notions such as "agent" or "theme" are,

as demonstrated above, irrelevant. However, given that

the noun ?akl (eating) has, like any other noun, an

external referential role R, the two remaining "agent"

and "theme" roles are both internal and there is no other

way to single out one of them for the purpose of control.

In section 3. 3. 4. 3 below it will be demonstrated how the

non-lexicalist analysis developed so far can handle the

control phenomenon. This will be done by relying,

crucially, on the thematic properties, the argument

structure, of NOM and the way it interacts with the

overall configuration. But this necessitates the

184

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
assumption of such an element as NOM and such an

assumption implies a non-lexicalist analysis.

As may be concluded from this discussion, this

second version of a lexicalist analysis of Action

Nominalizations faces a number of serious problems, most

of which have to do with the fact that the structure

assumed by this version does not provide enough

"configurational space" so as to make possible an account

of a certain number of facts. However, the main

characteristic of a lexicalist analysis, the one to which

it would owe its name, is the assumption that the head

noun in an Action Nominalization construction is not the

product of a syntactic process but is rather lexically

inserted at the base generated structure in its final

surface form. In section 3. 2. 2. 4 I will outline what

seems to be a rather strong argument against this

assumption based on the analysis of causative

constructions in Arabic. Before going into this issue,

however, I will present in the next section an argument

in favour of the syntactic approach based on the

interpretation of Action Nominalization constructions in

Hebrew.

185

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
3. 2. 2. 3 The Interpretation of Action Nominalizations

Here we will be concerned with pairs such as the

following

67- a) (H) harisat ha-romaim et ha-ir

destruction the romans OM the city

"The romans* destruction of the city"

b) (H) harisat ha-ir Sei ha-romaim

destruction the city Sei the romans

"The romans' destruction of the city"

Under any version of a lexicalist approach to Action

Nominalizations both examples above would be assumed to

involve a lexically derived head noun, with the only

difference between the two variants being the different

positioning and Case marking of the NP's related to it.

This is the approach taken by both Dor on (1989) and Borer

(1984) . For the sake of the discussion I will

concentrate in what follows on the particular details of

Doron's analysis of the pair in 67. But, as will become

clear, the argument presented in this section undermines

the validity of any lexicalist analysis regardless of its

particular details and provides strong support in favour

of the syntactic analysis proposed in this work.

186

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Doron (1989) assigns the a and b examples in 67 the

structures in 68 a and b respectively.

68- a) N*

/ I \
N NP NP

I I I
destruction the the city

enemy

b) NP

/ \
N' NP

/ \ I
N NP Sei the enemy

I I
destruction the city

In Doron's words, 68a is claimed to be "a process NP with

an internalized argument" whereas 6 8 b is "a process NP

with an external argument". Thus, both NP's are taken to

be process NP's with the only difference being that the

agent theta-role is assigned internally in one case and

externally in the other. 68 a,b are, on this view, what

one may refer to as "transformational variants". That

is, in both cases it is, allegedly, the same array of

187

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
theta-roles which is lexically available, the only

difference being the structural position onto which the

agent theta-role is "mapped" in each one of these

variants. This alleged difference between the two

variants would be similar to the difference which is

assumed to exist between, say, an active sentence and its

passive counterpart. That is, both sentences tell

basically the same story with some slight differences of

emphasis. The main argument of this section is that

this view of the difference between 67a and 67b is

totally erroneous. Rather, 67a and 67b are different in

both interpretation and structure and an explanation of

the difference between the two involves, necessarily, the

distinction between syntactic (67a) and lexical (67b)

nominalizations. Thus, if the argument to be presented

is valid then a syntactic process of nominalization of

the kind advocated here must be assumed as part of the

analysis of 67a.

There is a subtle, but still visible, difference of

interpretation between 67a and 67b. 67a denotes a

specific, temporally defined, event in which the Romans

destroyed the city. 67b, on the other hand, is most

felicitous in a context in which the destruction of the

city by the Romans is compared or contrasted with the

destruction of the city by somebody else, say, the

crusaders. Here the NP is interpreted as referring to

188

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
the manner in which the d e s t r u c t i o n was executed rather

than to the event i t s e l f . Corresponding differences may

be observed with pairs such as the f o l l o w i n g .

69- a) (H) reiyat Dan et Dina

seeing Dan OM Dina

"Dan 's seeing <


of D i n a "

b) (H) reiyat Dina Sei Dan

seeing Dina Sei Dan

"Dan's seeing of Dina"

The most likely interpretation o f 69a is one in which i t

r e f e r s to the event of Dan's seeing Dina. 69b , on the

other h a n d , i f i t i s assigned any interpretation a t a l l ,

i s more l i k e l y to be assigned a g e n e r i c type o f

i n t e r p r e t a t i o n in which reference is made t o D a n ' s way o f

viewing Dina in g e n e r a l .

A d m i t t e d l y , these contrasts are rather subtle and

may not be agreed upon by some s p e a k e r s . It would

therefore be advisable t o concentrate on p a i r s in which

the contrasts are c l e a r and undeniable. The f o l l o w i n g i s

such a pair.

70- a ) <H> harisat pikasso et yeruSalayim

destruction picasso OM Jerusalem

" P i c a s s o ' s destruction o f Jerusalem"

189

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further


Reproduced reproduction prohibited
Further reproduction permission..
without permission
prohibited without
b) (H) harisat yeruSalayim Sel pikasso

destruction Jerusalem Sel picasso

"Picasso's destruction of Jerusalem"

70a can only have the event interpretation by which it

refers to the event of the destruction of Jerusalem by

picasso (say, a roman emperor) . For 70b, on the other

hand, the most likely interpretation is radically

different. In a pragmatic context in which picasso is

widely known as a famous painter it is most likely

construed as referring to a picture depicting the

destruction of Jerusalem which was painted by picasso.

We may refer to this as the authorship interpretation.

Note that in an imaginary context in which "picasso" is

the name of a roman emperor an interpretation of 70b in

which picasso is the destroyer of Jerusalem, although

very unlikely, is not completely excluded. To make such

an interpretation more likely we may replace "picasso" in

70b by the name of the real destroyer of Jerusalem.

71- (H) harisat yeruSalayim Sei titus

destruction Jerusalem Sei titus

"Titus* destruction of Jerusalem"

Here an agent (destroyer) reading of "titus" is indeed

more likely. Thus, pragmatic factors such as background

190

Reproduced
Reproduce Further reproductio
d with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without
n prohibited permission..
without permission
knowledge and the like seem to play an important role in

the interpretation of 70b, 71 and similar examples,

giving rise to widely varying interpretations. Note now

that, as has often been observed, such a variation is

typical of the interpretation of constructions which

involve "noun to noun" relationships. Thus, in the

following example

72- John's book

John may be understood as standing in any of a wide range

of possible relationships with respect to the book such

as ownership, authorship and so forth. The only

limitations in this respect are pragmatic in nature.

Similar observations were also made by Williams (1982)

with respect to english derived nominal constructions

such as the following which may have, among others, the

interpretation indicated below.

73- Your destruction of Rome =* Your account of the

destruction of Rome.

Returning now to the pair in 70, note that for 70a,

unlike 70b, the "authorship" interpretation is completely

excluded. Rather, "picasso" in this example may only be

understood as the agent of "destruction". Pragmatic

191

prohibited without permission.


reproduction prohibited
Further reproduction
Repro duced with permis
Reproduced permission the copyright
sion of the owner.. Further
copyright owner without permission.
factors such as background knowledge and the like are

strictly excluded from influencing the interpretation of

such examples. Thus, in observing the difference

between 70 a and b, a clear generalization seems to

emerge which may be formulated as follows:

Whenever the "object" is marked Accusative the

"subject" must be interpreted as the agent (or

whatever type of theta-role happens to be the

external theta-role of the corresponding verb)

It is clear that any approach to the analysis of these

constructions which allows only for the possibility that

the head noun in both variants in 70 is a lexically

(rather then syntactically) given element is completely

incapable of making sense of such a generalization.

Generally, if destruction and picasso in 70 a and b are

lexically given nouns then one would expect the freedom

of interpretation typical of noun-to-noun constructions

to be attested in both variants. Obviously, this

semantic difference couldn’t be attributed to a

contribution of the Case markers which happen to be

different in each one of these variants.

If 70 a and b had the structures in 6 8 a and b

respectively, with the distribution of theta roles as

claimed by Doron, then the attested difference in

192

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without
reproduction prohibited permission.
without permission.
interpretation is, again, totally mysterious. Thus, on

Doron's account, "picasso” would have to be interpreted

as the agent of "destruction" in both variants and this

is clearly false.

These facts and the observation stated above receive

a straightforward explanation within the analysis of

Action Nominalisations and the general view of genitive

constructions advocated in this thesis. Thus, 70b is a

typical instance of a construction in which two nouns

("destruction" and "picasso") are construed in an

identification relation (with Jerusalem being construed

as a classificator) . The interpretation of such a

construction is typically open to pragmatic influences.

70a, on the other hand, is the output of a syntactic

process of nominalization and has the following

underlying structure.

193

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
prohibited without permission.
74- DP

/ \
D NP

I / \
POSS NP N’

I / \
Picasso N VP

I / \
NOM V NP

I I
destroy the city

The obligatory agent interpretation of "picasso" in this

case derives from the obligatoriness of the assignment of

the external theta role of VP first to NOM and then from

NOM to the NP in SPEC. Thus, the interpretation of the

subject in this case is strictly determined by syntactic

factors to the exclusion of any pragmatic factors.

Clearly, in this configuration the object NP

("the city") may only be assigned accusative Case. In

this way the correlation between the interpretation of

the "subject" and the Case marking of the object receives

a fairly simple account which is clearly impossible under

any version of a lexicalist approach.

The difference between the two structures in 67 is

clearly reflected in other syntactic properties. Here

194

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
the most striking difference between the two has to do

with the phenomenon of clitic doubling. Thus, in a

structure such as 67b, if the object (theme) NP is a

pronoun then it must be coreferential with the NP in the

Sel-phrase.

75-*a) (H) harisat-a Sei ha-romaim

destruction-her Sei the romans

b) (H) harisat-am Sei ha-romaim

destruction-their Sei the romans

"The destruction of the romans"

Obviously, clitic doubling is completely out of question

for 67a

*76- (H) harisat-ai et ha-iri

destruction-hen OM the cityi

An analysis such of the type suggested in Doron (1989)

has nothing to offer on this point. On the contrary,

given the assumption that the two NP's are independently

assigned a theta role in both variants, the observed

facts come rather as a surprise. Of-course, it is

possible for a pronoun to be coreferential with an NP

which is configurationally placed in a certain way with

respect to it but, on this account, one sees no reason

195

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
why it should be obligatory in one case while strictly

excluded in the other.

3. 2 . 2 . 3 Causative Constructions in Arabic

The discussion in this section will be concerned

with data from both Standard literary Arabic (A) and what

is largely designated as Syrian Arabic (SA). Marking for


0
each of the examples will be given correspondingly •

Note that dialectal variation is irrelevant for the main

point that this section is intended to make and therefore

no difficulties arise from our use of data from

Standard Arabic and Syrian Arabic alternately in the

following discussion.

Typical examples of causative constructions are

pairs such as the following.

77- a ) (A) 9allama zaid-un al- qasm-a haad'a

teach zaid-Nom the class-Acc this

1-kitaab-a

the book -Acc

"Zaid taught the class this book"

196

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
b) (A) 9allama zaid-un haad'a 1-kitaab-a

teach zaid-NOM this the book -Acc

li- 1- kasm-i

to the class-Dat

"Zaid taught this book to the class'*

78- a ) (A) Sarraba zaid-un al- awlaad-a al-

make-drink zaid-Nom the children-Acc the

Haliib-a

milk -Acc

"Zaid made the children drink the milk"

b) (A) Sarraba zaid-un al-Haliib-a li- 1-

make drink zaid-Nom the milk-Acc to the

?awlaad-i

children-Dat

"Zaid made the children drink the milk"

As the translations show, in the a examples above the

verb is followed by two accusative marked NP’s whereas in

the b examples the order of the two NP's is reversed, the

first of which is marked accusative and the second is

governed by the dative preposition li. I will refer

throughout the discussion to the first type (examples a )

as the "double accusative" and to the second type

(examples b) as the "dative" (or "dative causative").

Mushaweh (1986) and Hoyt (1989) enumerate a certain

number of facts which suggest a complex hierarchical

197

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
structure for the double accusative and illustrate some

striking differences between the two variants. We may

start with some facts concerning binding.

In a double accusative construction only the first

accusative NP may be anaphorically related to the subject

of the sentence.

79- a) (SA) samma9-na ba9da-na 1-Ranaani

make hear-we selves-our the songs

"we made ourselves hear the songs"

*b) (SA) samma9-na al-awlaad ba9da-na

make hear-we the children selves-our

*”we made the children hear ourselves"

Equally, the first accusative NP may be an antecedent to

the second accusative NP, but the reverse does not hold.

80- a) (SA) Hanna 9addad aHmadi Haalui

John made count ahmed himself

"John made Ahmed count himself"

*b) (SA) Hanna 9addad Haalui Ahmadi

John made count himself Ahmed

In the dative construction, on the other hand, the

accusative NP, which corresponds to the second accusative

198

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
NP in the double accusative variant, may be anaphorically

related to the subject.

81- (SA) Hannai 9 add ad Haalui la-aHmad

John made count himself to Ahmed

"Johm made Ahmed count himselfi "

We may summarize the binding facts as follows,

82- a ) Double Accusative: NPi V NP2 NPa

b) Dative : NPi V NPa P NP2

In 82a NPi can be the antecedent of NPa and NPa can be

the antecedent of NPa . NPi and NPa may not be

anaphorically related. In 82b NPi can be the antecedent

of NPa .

Another set of facts concerns the possibilities of

cliticization in double accusative and in the dative.

Using the patterns in 82, we may say that in a double

accusative, if NPa is a pronoun then it can (in fact,

must) be cliticized on the verb (82b) but this is

impossible for NPa (82c).

83- a ) (SA) fahham aHmad hind ddars

made understand ahmed hind the lesson

"Ahmed made hind understand the lesson"

199

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
b) (SA) fahham-a aHmad ddars

made understand-her aHmed the lesson

"Ahmed made her understand the lesson"

*c) (SA) £ahham-o aHmad hind

made understand-it ahmed hind

In 83a NP2 and NPa are two "full fledged" non-pronominal

(feminine and masculine respectively) NP's.

In the corresponding dative, however, it is

perfectly possible for NPa to be cliticized on the verb.

84- (SA) fahham-o aHmad la-hind

made understand-it ahmed to hind

"Ahmed explained it to hind"

One more set of facts may be provided before we proceed

to present an analysis. As observed by Hoyt (1989),

double accusative sentences with a modifying adverb are

ambiguous between two possible construals of the adverb,

as indicated in the following examples.

200

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
8 5- (SA) Hanna massak xaalid 1-Sunta bi-beit 1-

John made hold khalid the suitcase in house the

jiraan

neighbors

"John made khalid hold the suitcase in the

neighbors house"

i ) John caused the following: khalid held the

suitcase in the neighbors house.

ii) It was in the neighbors house that John made

khalid hold the suitcase.

86- (SA) Hanna ?akkal xaalid 1-sanduiS bi-tariqa

John made eat khalid the sandwich in manner

biSaa9

rude

"John made khalid eat the sandwich in a rude

manner"

i ) khalid *s actions were rude

ii) John's actions were rude

Hoyt (1989) also notes a rather interesting contrast

between double accusative sentences and semantically

equivalent sentences of which the main verb is not a

morphological causative. In the following example with

the causative verb "cause to die" the same ambiguity is

observed with respect to an accompanying adverb as in

85-86.

201

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
87- (SA) Hanna mawwat xaalid bi- bila9 1-

John caused to die khalid with swallowing the

mikrofilm

microfilm

"John made khalid die by swallowing the microfilm"

i) Khalid swallowed the microfilm

ii) John swallowed the microfilm

However, in the following example, with the non-causative

verb "kill", only one construal is possible for the

adverb, namely, the one in which it is related to the

subject.

88- (SA) Hanna qatal xaalid bi-bila9 1-

John killed khalid with swallowing the

mikrofilm

microfilm

"John killed khalid by swallowing the microfilm"

i ) John swallowed the microfilm

I will present first the analysis I propose for the

double accusative and show how it accounts for the facts

enumerated above. The underlying structure of the double

accusative in this analysis is the following.

202

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
89- IP

NPi VP

NP2 VP
0

NPa

In this structure the abstract verbal element CAUSE

subcategorizes for a VP and an NP object to which it

assigns a theta role. The surface structure

corresponding to 89 is derived by a single application of

head movement adjoining the lower verb to the morpheme

CAUSE.

90- IP

/ \

NPi VP

/ I \

V NPa VP

/ \ / \

Vi CAUSE V NPa

et

203

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
In the configuration above, both NPa and NPa are

governed, either by a lexical verb or by the trace of a

verb and are, in this way, assigned accusative Case.

Within the binding theory assumed here

(cf. Williams (1987a, 1989) ) the binding facts with

respect to 89 are directly accounted for. The basic

principle guiding this approach to binding may be roughly

stated as follows:

Two elements X and Y may be anaphorically related if

they are coarguments (or coarguments of

coarguments) .

In 89 NPi and NPa are coa rguments


c of the verb CAUSE and

may, therefore, be anaphorically related. The same holds

with respect to NPa and NPa as indicated by the arrows in

89. Since NPi and NPa are not coarguments they may not

be anaphorically related. Note that the two verbs in 89

constitute two separate thematic (argument-) complexes

and therefore no ungrammaticality results from the fact

that NPa is assigned a theta-role by both verbs a t the

same time. This is a standard case of what are known as

structures of secondary predication exemplified in

English by the following sentences.

91- a) John considers himself sick

b) John considers Mary crazy about herself

*c) John considers Mary crazy about himself

204

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
These examples have the following structure,

92- IP

/ \

NPi VP

/ I \

V NPa AP

I / \

consider A (NPa )

In 91c NPi cannot be the antecedent of NPa just as in the

Arabic double accusatives above. The other options for

anaphoric construal (NPi -NP2 , NPa -NPa ) are possible as in

91 a,b.

The cliticization facts are also directly accounted

for. Thus, as far as cliticization phenomena in Hebrew

and Arabic are concerned, a pronoun may only be

cliticized onto a lexical head (V,P,N) directly governing

it. In the configuration in question (89,90) only NPa is

governed by the verb CAUSE-V. Obviously, NPa has no

governing lexical verb to be attached to. The contrast

between 83 b and ç is, thus, explained. As pointed out

to me by Lisa Selkirk, it is interesting to note that

this explanation of cliticization possibilities in

causative constructions fits nicely with the general view

of cliticization advocated in this work. Cliticization,

205

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
at least in the constructions under investigation, is a

"late" process which belongs, most probably, to the

morphology. Thus, the head movement operation assumed

here as part of the derivation of causatives provides the

input, the necessary lexical head, which must be

available for cliticization to take place.

The facts about the ambiguity in the interpretation

of adverbs are also directly accounted for. An adverb

may be attached a t each one of the VP nodes as follows,

each construal corresponding to one of the possible

interpretations .

93- IP

/ \

NPt VP

/ I Adv

V NPa VP

I / \*'"'"''Xdv

CAUSE V NPa

Clearly, as the pair of examples below shows, a reversal

of order of the two accusative NP*s is completely out of

question (under the same interpretation) . This fact is

naturally accounted for given the hierarchical

configuration assigned to this construction under the

present analysis. In this configuration each of the two

206

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
NP's is governed by a different verbal head, the two

verbal heads being strictly linearly ordered with respect

to each other.

94- a ) (A) Sarraba zaid-un l-?awlaad-a 1-

made-drink Zaid-Nom the kids -Acc the-

Haliib-a

milk -Acc

"Zaid made the kids drink the milk”

*b) (A) Sarraba zaid-un 1-Haliib-a

made-drink Zaid-Nom the milk -Acc

1- ?awlaad-a

the kids -Acc

Thus, the analysis of the double accusative is rather

straightforward and simple. It relies crucially,

however, on the assumption of a "double-VP"

configuration, the two VP*s being headed by the morpheme

CAUSE and a verbal form respectively. The surface

causative verb must be, on this analysis, the output of a

syntactic derivation. If this assumption is made, then

all of the observed facts are explained.

We may turn now to the dative causative. Here a

rather striking observation has been made by a number of

authors with respect to a certain semantic difference

between the double

207

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
accusative and the dative. Thus, Cowell (1964) reports

as follows:

"In some cases.... the first object of the causative

may be replaced by a la-phrase and put after the

remaining object: Sawwaf jeruHak le-ddaktoor "show

your wounds to the doctor” samme9 darsak la-?abuuk

"recite your lesson to your father”. The use of a

prepositional complement with the causative in lieu

of a first object generally implies a certain

idiomatic specialization with respect to the

underlying simple verb: samma9 meaning "to recite”,

kattab meaning "to dictate" etc." (Pg. 241)

Similar facts are observed by Mushaweh (1986) for

standard Arabic as well as Syrian Arabic. Thus, while

the interpretation associated with the double accusative

is strictly compositional and can be paraphrased as

"make, or force, someone to do something”, a dative

construction may receive idiomatic and derived meanings.

On the basis of this observation Mushaweh concludes that

the two variants of causative constructions couldn't be

transformationally related, that is, they couldn't be

derived from the same underlying structure. This seems

to be the right conclusion. However, there is no need to

assume that the two variants are completely unrelated.

They are visibly related, in fact identical, as far as

208

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
the morphology of the main verb is concerned, and they

are certainly related also in interpretation. As Mushaweh

(1986) notes, a dative causative may also have the

strictly compositional interpretation in addition to the

idiomatic and derived interpretation.

One might say that the ability to undergo semantic

drift is the property "par excellence" of lexical items.

If this is so then one couldn't avoid the conclusion that

the causative verbs occurring in dative constructions are

single lexical items inserted, as they are, at the level

of NP-structure. But this seems to be a fairly natural

possibility. That is, if the morpheme CAUSE and the

whole array of verbal forms are available in the lexicon

anyway, then there is no reason to expect that the option

for them to be combined in the lexicon, rather then in


6
the syntax, shouldn't be open . If this is indeed the

case then new lexical items are formed which may freely

assume derived and idiomatic meanings. Thus, the

resulting picture seems to be that in Arabic both options


7
are available . This implies that the dative causative

construction involves a single verbal head and a single

VP.

As to the effect of the lexical operation by which a

causative verb is derived, this may be described as

consisting of the two following components: i ) addition

of an external agent theta-role, ii) internalization of

209

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
the external theta-role of the verbal form. The

resulting verb has only one Accusative Case feature to

assign and therefore, in order to allow an additional

object to occur, a special mechanism is invoked by which

a "dummy" Case marker li is inserted. Similar facts seem

to hold crosslinguistically. (for similar observations

see a discussion of Romance causatives in Zubizarreta

(1985)).

The structure of a dative causative construction may

therefore look as follows,

95- IP

/ \

NPi VP

/ I \

CAUSE-V NPa li-NPa

The facts observed at the beginning of this discussion

with respect to the dative construction may now be

directly accounted for. Thus, NPi and NPa can be

anaphorically related simply by virtue of being

coarguments. As to the cliticization facts, NPa in the

configuration above is governed by the lexical head

CAUSE-V and can be cliticized onto it (cf. 69).

Note that any analysis which derives both variants

of causative constructions from an underlying structure

210

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
involving a bi-clausal (or "bi-VP") configuration can

provide no explanation for the differences between the

two. Such an analysis is in fact proposed in Hoyt

(1989), based on ideas of Larson (1988) for the analysis

of the double object construction in English. The

following are the D and S-structures proposed by hoyt

(1989) for the two causative variants.

96- a) Double Accusative: D-structure

IP

/ \

I'

/ \

I VPi

/ \

NPi V

/ \

V VP2

I / \

CAUSE NPa V’

/ \

V NPa

C-C-C

(verbal root)

211

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
96- b) Double accusative: S-Structure

IP

/ \

NPi » I'

/ \

I VPi

1 / \

CAUSE-V ei V'

/ \

V VP2

1 / \

e NP2 v

/ \

V NPa

212

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
9 7 - a ) Dative Causative: D-Structure

IP

/ \
I’

/ \
I VP

/ \
NPi V

/ \
V VP

I / \
CAUSE V

/ \
V NPa

/ \
V NPa

I
C-C-C

213

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
97- b) Dative Causative: S-Structure

IP

/ \

NPi i I’

/ \

I VPi

I / \

CAUSE-V ei V’

/ \

V VP2

1 / \

e NPa j V'

/ \

V1 PP

/ \ / \

V NP P np2
1 1 1

e ej la

There is no need to go into the derivational

complexities of this analysis. In any case, it is hard

to see how the different underlying and surface

structures attributed to the two variants under this

analysis could correspond to the differences in

214

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
interpretation observed earlier, in particular, the

difference between a compositional and an idiomatic

interpretation observed by Cowell (1964). On Hoyt's

analysis, the difference between the two causative

variants would correspond to the difference between the

two corresponding variants involving a dative shift verb

in Arabic or in English ("give Mary a book" vs. "give a

book to Mary") . However, if there is any difference in

meaning between two such variants, it certainly does not

correspond to the idiomatic vs. compositional difference

observed above. In any case, on Hoyt's (1989) approach

one would expect to find at least a certain regularity in

the meaning difference between the two variants, a

regularity which would be due, on this approach, to a

possible semantic contribution of the preposition la

(to). Such a regularity, however, is non-existent.

Thus, at least in this respect, the analysis

proposed here is to be preferred. Hoyt's analysis makes

also the claim that the two causative variants have the

same hierarchical structure, namely, both variants have a

bi-clausal structure and therefore it should be expected

that some of the empirical facts that may be explained

on the basis of this structural property will be observed

for both variants. The main relevant fact here is the

one concerning adverbial modification. The ambiguities

observed by Hoyt (1989) (cf. examples 85-87) certainly

215

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
support a bi-clausal (or "bi-VP") analysis, but these

ambiguities, as Hoyt fails to note, are observed only for

the double accusative and not for the dative

construction. Thus, the following dative causative

example allows only for the interpretation in which Hanna

is using a knife to make khalid eat the sandwich (compare

with 85) . An interpretation in which khalid is using

the knife is not available.

98- (SA) Hanna ?akkal 1-sandwiS la-xaalid bi-

John made eat the sandwich to khalid with-

ssikiini

the knife

"John made khalid eat the sandwich with the knife"

The analysis proposed here makes the right prediction and

is, again, to be preferred.

The main conclusion of the discussion so far seems

to be the following. In the double accusative

construction the causative verb is the output of a

syntactic process whereas in the dative causative the

main verb is the output of a lexical process. This

distinction between processes at the lexical as opposed

to the syntactic level was shown to be crucial for an

explanation of the difference between the two variants as

well as the properties internal to each one.

216

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
The implications of this conclusion with respect to

the analysis of Action Nominalisation constructions may

now become clear. Here too, both causative variants are

attested as in the following double accusative/dative

pairs .

99- a) (A) ta91iim zaid-en al- qasm-a haad'a 1-

teaching zaid-Gen the class-ACC this the

kittab-a

book -Acc

"Zaid's teaching of this book to the class"

b) (A) ta91iim zaid-en haad'a 1-kittab-a li-1-

teaching zaid-Gen this the book-Acc to the

qasm-i

class-Dat

"Zaid's teaching of this book to the class"

100- a ) (A) taSriib hind-en al- ?awlaad-a al-

making-drink hind-Gen the children-Acc the

Haliib-a

milk -Acc

"Hind's making of the children drink the milk"

b) (A) taSriib hind-en al-Haliib-a li- 1-

making-drink hind-Gen the milk-Acc to the

?awlaad-i

children-Dat

"Hind's making of the children drink the milk"

217

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
It follows from the analysis argued for above that at

least the double accusative variants (the a examples) in

99,100 must involve a syntactic derivation of which the

head noun is an output. The head nouns in 99,100 may be

viewed as the combination of the three morphemes NOM,

CAUSE, and V. However, at least for the case of double

accusatives, the combination CAUSE-V must be viewed as

syntactically derived, that is, it must have at least the

sub-structure 101a and therefore may only be assumed to

have the underlying structure 101b.

101-a) VP b) NP

/ 1 \ / \

V NP 2 VP NPi N*

1 / \ / \

CAUSE V NP 3 N VP

1 / 1 \

NOM V NP2 VP

1 / \

CA USE V NPa

It 1nay therefore be concluded that, since causative

constructions of the double accusative variant occur in

Action Nominalizations , the option of a syntactic

derivation for Action Nominalization constructions must

be assumed to be open in principle and therefore there is

218

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
good reason to assume that this is, indeed, the actual

derivation of active Action Nominalizations in general,

given the empirical advantages of such an assumption.

Some of the more basic facts about Action

Nominalizations involving the double accusative receive a

straightforward account given an underlying structure

such as 101b, whereas such facts would remain unexplained

under any lexicalist approach to these constructions.

One such fact concerns the order of the two accusative

NP's in 101b. A reversal of order of NPa and NPa in this

configuration is strictly ungrammatical (under the same

interpretation) as in the following pair corresponding to

the grammatical 100a and 101a respectively.

102-*a) ( A ) taOliim zayd-en haad'a 1-kitaab-a

teaching zaid-Gen this the book -Acc

al- qasm-a

the class-Acc

*b) ( A ) taSriib hind-en al-Haliib-a al-

making-drink hind-Gen the milk -Acc the

?awlaad-a

children-Acc

A reversal of order of NPa and NPa is possible only if

the dative option is taken. These word order facts are

identical to the facts attested in the corresponding

219

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
sentential structures (compare with 94) and receive a

natural explanation if the same underlying configuration

is assumed. A lexicalist analysis of 99a and 100a might

assign them something like the following configuration

and would have nothing to say about the respective order

of NPa and NPa .

103- NP

/ \

NPi N*

/ I \

N NPa NPa

Another basic fact which follows naturally from the

present analysis concerns the subjectless variants of 99a

and 100a. Generally, in the absence of a subject no

accusative Case may be assigned to the object, which

therefore must surface in a bound genitive construction

with the head noun. Note now, that in the case of double

accusative Action Nominalizations only NPa may be

affected by this process, that is, only NPa may appear as

a genitive NP in the absence of a subject.

104- a ) (A) ta91iim al-qasm -i haad'a 1-kitaab-a

teaching the class-Gen this the book -Acc

"teaching the class this book"

220

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
*b) (A) ta91iim haad'a 1-kitaab-i al-qasm -a

teaching this the book -Gen the class-Acc

105- a ) (A) taSriib al-?awlaad -i al-Haliib-a

making-drink the children-Gen the milk -Acc

"making the kids drink the milk”

*b) (A) taSriib al-Haliib-i al-?awlaad -a

making-drink the milk -Gen the children-Acc

A detailed discussion of the phenomenon by which the

absence of a subject results in the impossibility of

assigning accusative Case will be undertaken in section

3.3.4. It is sufficient for the present argument to note

that a lexicalist type of configuration such as the one

in 103 can provide no explanation as to why only NPz

should be affected by the absence of a subject. In that

configuration no distinction can be made between NPz and

NPa (Note that this issue is clearly different from that

concerning the configurational distinction between

subject and object which was discussed earlier). On the

other hand, in a configuration such as 101b NPz and NPa

are governed by two different verbal heads and there is a

clear asymmetry in their configurational positioning

with respect to each other. This makes it possible for

whatever principles are involved in the process in

question to distinguish between the two NP's and to

affect NPa while "ignoring” NPa .

221

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
3.3 Subjectless Action Nominalizations

3.3.1 Introduction

Subjectless Action Nominalizations are those

constructions in which the (logical) subject, or the

external argument of the corresponding active verb, is

missing as in the following examples.

106- a ) (H) ktivat ha-avoda

writing the work

"the writing of the work”

b) (A) ?aklu ttufaaHat-i

eating the apple-Gen

"the eating of the apple"

In this introductory section I will first review some of

the data which seems to point towards a mixed verbo-

nominal nature and, therefore, motivate a syntactic

analysis corresponding to the one suggested for active

Action Nominalizations in the previous section.

The first relevant fact has to do with the

occurrence of adverbs.

222

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
107- a ) (H) ktivat ha-avoda leat

writing the work slowly

b ) (A) ?aklu ttufaaHat-i bi-sur9a

eating the apple-Gen quickly

Thus, both the Hebrew and the Arabic variants allow

for the occurrence of adverbs. In this respect we may

also observe the following data from Hebrew,

108- a ) (H) bniyat ha-binyan tox Svuayim

construction the building within two weeks

"The construction of the building in two weeks”

b ) (H) harigat ha-nasi be-ofen pitomi

killing the president in manner sudden

"Killing the president suddenly"

c ) (H) harisat ha-ir be-ofen axzari

destruction the city in manner cruel

"Destroying the city cruelly"

These examples should be contrasted with the "bare"

nominals in the pairs below.

109- a ) (H) ha-bniya

the construction

*b) (H) ha-bniya tox Svuayim

the construction within two weeks

223

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
110- a ) (H) ha-hariga

the killing

*b) (H) ha-hariga be-ofen pitomi

the killing in manner sudden

111- a ) (H) ha-harisa

the destruction

*b) (H) ha-harisa be-o£en axzari

the destruction in cruel manner

The carefully chosen verbs corresponding to the nouns in

108-111 are all strictly transitive. Obviously, like any

other verb they may have the corresponding de verbal nouns

which appear in 109a-llla. These nouns, however, may not

cooccur with an adverb alone (109b-lllb) , simply because

of a general restriction on the distribution of adverbs,

and they obviously do not require an object like their

corresponding verb. Thus, the grammaticality of 108 a-c

could only be explained by invoking a more complex

syntactic structure in which a VP node makes it possible

for an adverb to occur. Conversely, the ungrammaticality

of 109b-lllb could also be explained as involving

structures in which the lexical requirements of an

underlying verb for an object is not satisfied as it is

in 108 . Thus, nouns derived from non-transitive verbs

or optionally transitive verbs admit adverbs, without

"asking for" an object, as in the following examples.

224

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
112- a) (H) ha-halixa leat nimSexet z m a n rav

the walking slowly " t a k e s a long time"

"walking slowly t a k e s a long time"

b) (H) ha-axila bi-mehirut goremet keeve

the eating quickly causes aches

beten

stomach

" E a t i n g quickly causes stomach a c h e s "

Another verbal c h a r a c t e r i s t i c of Hebrew subjectless

Action Nominalizations r e l a t e s to the d i s t r i b u t i o n o f by-

phrases. Unlike E n g l i s h , by-phrases in Hebrew cannot

occur in what we may r e f e r to as " p u r e " nouns. T h u s , the

Hebrew counterparts of 1 1 3 are s t r i c t l y excluded.

1 1 3 - a ) a f i l m by Felini

b ) a play by Shakespeare

114-*a) ( H ) seret al-yede felini

film by Felini

* b ) ( H ) maxaze5 al-yede Shakespeare

Play by Shakespeare

By-phrases do occur in p a s s i v e sentences (115) and

s u b j e c t l e s s Action N o m i n a l i z a t i o n s (116).

225

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
115- (H) ha-uga ne ex la al-yede Dan

the cake was eaten by Dan

116- (H) axilat ha-uga al-yede Dan

eating the cake by Dan

"The eating of the cake by Dan"

Thus, in this respect subjectless Nominalizations pattern

with sentences and differ from pure nouns.

The probably most compelling argument in favour of a

syntactic analysis of subjectless Action Nominalizations,

along the same lines suggested earlier for their active

counterparts, comes from the interaction between these

constructions and the syntax of Arabic causative

constructions. As was observed in the last section

( 3 .2. 2. 4), causative constructions do occur in

subjectless Action Nominalizations in both the double

accusative and the dative variants. I will repeat here

the relevant examples for convenience.

117- a) (A) ta91iim 1-qasm -i haad'a 1-kitaab-a

teaching the class-Gen this the book -Acc

"The teaching of this book to the class"

b) (A) ta91iim haad'a 1-kitaab-i li- 1- qasm-i

teaching this the book -Gen to the class-Dat

"The teaching of this book to the class"

226

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
* c ) (A) ta91iim haad'a 1-kitaab-i 1- qasm-a

teaching this the book -Gen the class-Acc

118- a ) (A) taSriib l-?awlaad-i 1-Haliib-a

making-drink the kids -Gen the milk-Acc

"Making the kids drink the milk"

b) (A) taSriib 1-Haliib-i li- l-?awlaad-i

making-drink the milk-Gen to the kids -Dat

"Making the kids drink the milk"

* c ) (A) taSriib 1-Haliib-i l-?awlaad-a

making-drink the milk-Gen the kids -Acc

looking simply at the surface of things, if Accusative

Case marking is taken to be an indication of government

by a verbal element (the a examples), then we are led,

again, to the assumption that some such element is

under lyingly available. But this implies that a

syntactic derivation must be postulated by which the

actual nominal form of the head is derived. Such an

assumption receives further support from the ç examples

above which show that a simple reversal of order of the

two NP's is impossible. The same restriction was shown

to apply in the corresponding sentential structures. A

reversal of order is possible only in the dative variant

(the b examples). It would therefore seem necessary to

assume the same type of causative substructure for these

constructions as the one suggested earlier for causative

227

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
constructions occurring in sentences and in active Action

Nominalisations. This will make possible a unified

account of the same phenomenon across all construction

types, certainly a desirable result.

I assume that it is justified, on the basis of the

above considerations, to assunie an analysis of

subjectless Action Nominalisations which postulates the

same underlying structure as the one suggested for active

Action Nominalisations in section | 3.2. Obviously, the

analysis will have to prove capable of accounting for

further facts. Among these f ctsi an extremely

intriguing one relates to the phenomenon of control in

subjectless Action Nominalisations in Arabic already

alluded to in this chapter. Typical examples of control

structures in Arabic are the following.

119- a) (A) Haawala zaid-un | naql -a 1-

tried zaid-Nom trànsportation-Acc the

kitaab-a ?ila bayruut

book -Acc to beirut

"Zaid tried to transport the book to beirut”


1
b) (A) Haawala said-un al- ?intiqaal-a ?ila

tried said-Nom the transportation-Acc to

bayruut

beirut

"Zaid tried to be transported to beirut”

228

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
As the translations of these examples suggest, the

control relationship established between the higher

subject Zaid and the unexpressed subject of the Action

Nominalizations is not sensitive to thematic role

distinctions. Here we might make use of a distinction

between two types of control relations discussed i n

Williams (1985) , namely, the distinction between control

of a theta-role and control of a position. Control of a

theta-role is exemplified in English by pairs such as the

following (from Williams (1987)).

120- a) John underwent an operation

b) John performed an operation

In 120a the verb "undergo" dictates a control by "John"

of the theme of "operation" whereas in 120b the verb

"perform" dictates a control of the agent of "operation"

by "John".

Standard cases of obligatory control of infinitival

complements lack this kind of sensitivity as in the

following pair.

121- a) John wants to see the movie

b) John wants t o be seen

121 a,b are, thus, cases of control of a position. The

229

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Arabie examples in 119 are cases of control of a position

too. Standard syntactic approaches to control assume it

to involve some sort of anaphoric relationship between

the controlling NP and an empty NP (mostly PRO, sometimes

pro) occupying the subject position of an infinitival

clause. It is hard to see how such an approach may be

applied to the Arabic construction given the assumed

distributional properties of PRO and what we know about

the syntax of Action Nominalizations . The main

difficulty here has to do with the assignment of Case in

these constructions, in particular, the fact the object

in such a construction is in the bound genitive

configuration with the head. It therefore must be

assumed to be situated in the specifier position and

would therefore leave no place for an empty NP, either

PRO or pro, to occur. Moreover, any treatment of the

control issue should provide an explanation for the

observed difference between Hebrew and Arabic. Thus,

given that control of Action Nominalizations is possible

in Arabic but not in Hebrew and the apparent identity in

syntactic structure of Action Nominalization

constructions in the two languages, it is plausible to

assume that this difference between the two languages

couldn't be explained on the basis of structural

distinctions, or distinctions having to do the

distribution of elements which occupy structural

230

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
positions but rather, as will be suggested here, on the

basis of distinctions made at the lexical level. The

relevant lexical distinctions are, to be sure, reflected

in the syntactic configuration but this while observing

the assumed structural similarity. Such an outcome would

be natural, given that the phenomenon of obligatory

control is typically associated with the properties of

individual verbs. This issue will be addressed in

section 3. 3. 4. 3.

Another fact concerning subjectless Action

Nominalizations has to do with the, already mentioned,

possibilities of Case marking in these constructions,

namely, the fact that in the absence of a subject only

genitive Case may be assigned to the remaining NP (or

NPa in the corresponding subjectless double accusative

Action Nominalization) . This raises the natural

assumption that something like a process of passivization

may be involved in the derivation of subjectless Action

Nominalizations. The following section provides some

evidence against such an assumption.

231

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
3.3.2 Argumenta Against a Passivization Analysis

This section is concerned with contrasts as in the

following pairs in which the a examples show accusative

Case marking on the (logical) object NP whereas in the b

examples it is in a bound genitive construction with the

head noun.

122- *a) (H) ha-harisa et ha-ir

the destruction OM the city

b) (H) harisat ha-ir

destruction the city

"The destruction of the city"

123- *a) (A) ?aklu ttufaaHat-a

eating the apple-Acc

b) (A) ?aklu ttufaaHat-i

eating the apple-Gen

"the eating of the apple"

Given the analysis proposed in section 3.2, in

particular, the assumption that the underlying structure

of Action Nominalization constructions contains a VP

headed by the related verb, an obvious possible

explanation for this contrast comes to mind, namely, that

the underlying verb in these constructions has undergone

a lexical process of passivization and is therefore

232

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
deprived of its ability to assign accusative Case to its

object. Under such a view, the relevant steps in the

derivation of 122b 123b would be roughly as follows.

124- a) DP b) DP

/ \ / \

D NP D NP

1 / \ 1 / \

POSS N’ ====> POSS NPi N*

/ \ ! \
N VP N VP

1 / \ 1 / \

NOM Vr NPi NOM V ei

In 124a no Case is available for NPi . Therefore, the

only way for it to be assigned case iss by moving to the

specifier position in which it can be assigned Case by

the morpheme POSS at the head-* of- DP position in the

manner usual for bound genitives. This is then the

passivization analysis. In the following subsections I

will present four different arguments against this

suggestion, three of which rely on data from Hebrew and

one on data from Arabic.

233

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
3. 3. 2.1 Verbs Which Don't Passivize

There are verbs in Hebrew which may figure as

transitive verbs in active sentences but cannot be

passivized. The two following pairs show the verbs calax

(cross) and hitxil (begin,start) respectively. 125a and

126a are the active sentences and their b counterparts

are the ungrammatical ]passives.

125- a) (H) ha-cava calax et ha-teala

the army crossed OM the canal

*b) (H) ha-teala niclexa al-yede ha-tsava

the canal was crossed by the army

126- a ) (H) ha-saxkan hitxil et ha-hacaga

the actor started OM the play

*b) (H) ha-hacaga hutxela al yede ha-saxkan

the play was started by the actor

Naturally, one would like to know why these verbs resist

passivization. It is hard to see any morphological or

phonological reason for it. Thus, for example, the verbs

Salax (shalakh) (send) and salax (pardon) each form a

phonologically minimal pair with calax (cross) and are

identical to it in their morphological pattern. Both

verbs, however, appear in the passive forms niSlax (was

sent) and nislax (was pardoned) respectively. Neither

234

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
can one find any semantic explanation for this fact.

Thus, a verb like hifsik (stop), which belongs to the

same semantic class of verbs as hitxil (begin, start)

(aspectuals) and manifests the same variety of uses

(transitive, raising constructions etc. ) and has also

the same morphology, can be passivized as in the

following pair of examples.

127- a) (H) ha-saxkan hifsik et ha-hacaga

the actor stopped OM the play

b) (H) ha-hacaga hufseka al-yede ha-saxkan

the play was stopped by the actor

It is hard to see in what sense two verbs like calax

(cross) and hitxil (begin, start) could be claimed to

belong to the same class, except in the sense of not

being able to undergo passivization. It seems,

therefore, that this is an arbitrary lexical property, as

lexical properties happen to be, a fact which might be

expressed by simply attributing to the lexical entries of

these verbs the feature [-PASSIVE] . Assuming the

analysis proposed above for "passive" Action

Nominalisations, it is these lexical items that would be

lexically inserted in tree structures such as 124a.

Having the feature [-PASSIVE] , the "passive" Action

Nominalizations of these verbs are predicted to be bad in

235

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
the same way that the passive sentences 125b and 126b

are. The following pair of examples shows this

prediction to be wrong. Crucially, the a and the b

examples allow the occurrence of an adverb and a by-

phrase, respectively, and therefore, by the logic of the

argument so far, must be syntactically derived.

128- a) (H) clixat ha-teala bi-zehirut

crossing the canal carefully

"The crossing of the canal carefully"

b) (H) hatxalat ha-hacaga al-yede ha-lahaka

starting the play by the group

"The starting of the play by the group"

At this point it might be argued that even if the feature

[-PASSIVE] is admitted to figure in the lexical

representation of these verbs, it only relates to their

morphology. If this is so, it should be possible for the

lexical items in question to undergo all the operations

involved in passivization except for the morphological

one and, in this way, for the forms in 128 to be

derived. This, however, leads to the prediction that, at

least for these verbs, it would be possible to derive

sentences with the active morphology on the verb but with

passive interpretation. This is clearly wrong.

236

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
129- *a) (H) ha-teala calxa

the canal crossed

b) (H) ha-hacaga hitxila

the play started

129a, of which the intended meaning would be: "The canal

was crossed", is completely impossible. 129b can only

mean: " The play started" and not: "The play was started

by someone".

3. 3 . 2. 2 Verbs Which Do Passivize

A converse argument can be made as follows. As

observed by Berman (1978), one finds i n Hebrew verbs

which take a prepositional complement, an example of

which is the verb hiSpia (influence) .

130- (H) Dan hiSpia al Dina

Dan influenced on Dina


It
"Dan influenced Dina

Interestingly, the verb in 130 can be passivized and the

complement of the preposition al (on) become its derived

subject.

237

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
131- (H) Dina huSpea al-yede Dan

Dina was influenced by Dan

If a passive verb like the one in 131 was the input to

the nominalization process proposed here, one would

wrongly predict the NP in 132 to be grammatical .

*132- haSpaat Dina al-yede Dan

influence Dina by Dan

Here it is important to note that the pair of examples

130-131 which shows the disappearance of a preposition in

the passive variant is far from being an isolated case.

Rather, it seems to be an instance of a general

phenomenon by which a preposition may be dropped as part

of the general process of passive formation. It is

likely that the possibility for a preposition to be

dropped has to do with its semantic contribution. That

is, a preposition can only be dropped if i t has no

semantic import and its presence is arbitrarily required

by a certain verb. The following is a list of some

verbs which show the same behavior as hiSpia (influence) .

238

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
133- a) verbs taking the preposition be (in) :

tipel be (take care o£,deal with) , bagad be

(betray) , baat be (kick) , tamax be (support) .

b) verbs taking the preposition al (on) :

diveax al (report) , hexlit al (decide)

hixriz al (declare) , himlic al (recommend) .

c) verbs taking the preposition le (to) :

hirSa le (allow, permit) , azar le (help, support)

kara le (call) .

The following sets of examples show the same contrasts

illustrated above for hiSpia (influence) . 134 shows the

verb tipel (deal with) with the preposition be (in) and

135 shows the verb kara (call) which takes the

preposition le (to) . '

134- a) (H) Dan tipel ba- inyan

Dan dealt with in the matter

"Dan dealt with the matter"

b) (H) ha-inyan tupal (al-yede Dan)

the matter was dealt with (by Dan)

c ) (H) ha-tipul ba -inyan

the dealing with in the matter

"The dealing with the matter"

239

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
*d) (H) tipul ha-inyan

dealing with the matter

133- a ) (H) ha-memSala kar?a la -cibur

the government called for to the public

lehoSit ezra

to hand help

"The government called the public for help"

b) (H) ha-cibur nikra lehoSit ezra

the public was called for to hand help

"The public was called for help"

c ) (H) ha-kria la- cibur lehoSit ezra

the call to the public to hand help

"The call to the public for help"

*d) (H) kri'at ha-cibur lehoSit ezra

call the public to hand help

The b examples above show passive sentences in which the

prepositions be and l e respectively are dropped. The ç

examples are the corresponding Action Nominalizations in

which the preposition is retained while in the

ungrammatical d examples it is missing.

240

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
3. 3. 2. 3 Anaphora

The passivization analysis faces a serious problem

with structures involving anaphors.

136 -*a) (H) acmo nira

himself was seen

b) (H) reiyat acmo be-ofen barur

seeing himself in manner clear

"Seeing himself clearly"

Assuming the analysis in 124, in particular, the fact

that it contains a VP, we would rather expect 136b to be

bad, in the same way that a passive sentence with an

anaphor in subject position (136a) is. This is, however,

wrong, as the above pair shows.

3. 3 . 2 . 4 Control Structures in Arabic

The already mentioned phenomenon of control of

Arabic Action Nominalizations raises another serious

problem for a passivization analysis. The argument here

is strikingly simple. Consider the following example.

241

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
137- (A) yuriidu zaid-un ?akl-a ttufaaHat-i

wants zaid-Nom eating-Acc the apple-Gen

"Zaid wants to eat the apple"

In this example the object "the apple" is assigned, and

can only be assigned, genitive Case. However, 137 can

only mean that "Zaid wants to eat the apple". It is hard

to imagine what would be the paraphrase of a passive

construal of this sentence. It certainly doesn't have

the interpretation: "Zaid wants the apple to be eaten"

(in which, in any case, zaid is not a controller) . In

this, 137 is identical to the corresponding English

infinitive in which an indisputably active form of the

verb eat occurs.

138- John wants to eat the apple

It is therefore hard to see what it would mean to say

that the embedded subjectless Action Nominalization in

137 is the output of a passivization process. In fact,

to the extent that passivization means the non-assignment

of the external theta role of a verb, it is possible to

develop a detailed argument showing that this is not

what happens in subjectless Action Nominalizations . To

this extent, the argument in the next section should be

viewed as completing the argument of this section.

242

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
3.3.3 Burzio* s Generalization ?

The impossibility of accusative Case marking in the

absence of a lexical subject is strongly reminiscent of a

general phenomenon observed among others by Burzio (1981)

and formulated by him as the following generalization.

139 - Burzio* s Generalization

If a verb does not assign an external theta role

then it does not assign accusative Case.

Although the statement in 139 was originally put forth as

a simple observation about the individual properties of

lexical items, it has been suggested by a number of

authors (e.g. Larson (1988)) to assign it the status of

an active principle of the grammar which may be taken to

participate in different grammatical processes (e.g.

passivization, dative shift). The issue of Hebrew (and,

therefore, Arabic as well) Action Nominalizations did not

remain unaffected by this trend. Thus, generalizing

Burzio *s generalization to both verbs and nouns, the

suggestion has been made by Ritter (1986) , and adopted by

Doron (1989) , that it is exactly this generalization

which is at work in the Action Nominalization

constructions under consideration, making it impossible

for the head noun to assign accusative Case in the

243

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
absence of a subject. It is the purpose of this section

to show that this view is wrong.

Note first that it is not just the absence of a

lexically realized subject which is here at stake.

Obviously, the absence of a lexical subject in a standard

infinitive is not sufficient to trigger the application

of Burzio’s generalization.

140- a ) (H) Dan roce leexol et ha-tapuax

Dan wants to eat OM the apple

*b) (H) Dan roce leexol ha-tapuax

Dan wants to eat the apple

Rather , it is the non assignment of an external theta-

role which would trigger the application of the

generalization regardless of whether the theta-role would

be assigned to a lexically overt or non overt NP. Thus,

an argument intended to show that burzio's

generalization is not at work in subjectless Action

Nominalizations would have to proceed in two steps as

follows. First, to show that the theta-role which would

normally be the external theta-role of the verb or noun

in question is assigned. Second, to show that it is

assigned as an external theta-role (having the status of

an external theta-role) and, therefore, externally.

Here, again, the control phenomenon associated with

244

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Arabie subjectless Action Nominalisations proves to be

extremely helpful. We may, again, observe the following

standard example.

141- (A) yuriidu zaid-un ?akl-a ttufaaHat-i

wants zaid-Nom eating-Acc the apple-Gen

"Zaid wants to eat the apple"

It seems that the agent theta-role of ?akl (eating) in

this example is assigned. That is, it is syntactically

available for participation in the control relation and

therefore must be assumed to be present in some form or

another. Moreover, the controlled agent theta-role is

also syntactically present for the purposes of binding,

serving as an antecedent to an anaphor as in the

following example.

142- (A) yuriidu zaid-un qatl-a nafs-i -hi

wants zaid-Nom killing-Acc self-Gen-his

"Zaid wants to kill himself"

For a theory which views control as a relationship

between a controlling NP and a PRO subject, the agent

theta-role would have to be assigned to an ungoverned PRO

and, therefore, necessarily, structurally external.

For a , possible, theta-theoretic analysis of control

245

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
in which a control relationship is established between a

controlling NP and a thematic role, a minimal

requirement, in order to avoid ambiguity in the control

relation, would be for the controlled theta-role to be

assigned a special status, that is, to be distinguished

from other theta-roles for which the noun or verb in

question is lexically specified. Within such an

approach, the only available distinction between theta-i

roles is the external/ internal distinction (note that, lin

any case, it is in terms of this distinction that

Burzio's generalization is formulated) and, for a theta-

role to be unique in status, it would have to be external

since there can, in principle, be more than one internal

theta-role but only one external. Clearly, the control

relationship observed in arabic Action Nominalizations is

unambiguous and, as demonstrated by the following pair,I

insensitive to thematic distinctions but only to I

"position" .

143- a ) (A) Sajja9t-u zaid-an 9ala 1- ?akl -i

encouraged-I zaid-Acc on the eating-Dati

"I encouraged Zaid to eat"

246

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
b) ( A ) yuriidu zaid-un al- intiqaal-a ?ila

wants zaid-Nom the transportation-Acc to

bayruut

Beirut

"Zaid wants to be transported to beirut"

In 143a none of the two thematic arguments of ?akl

(eating) is lexically realized. However, no ambiguity

results from this situation. 143a is identical in

meaning to its English infinitival counterpart: "I

encouraged John to eat". Our argument is that for this

to be possible, the controlled theta role must have been

singled out as the external theta role. Thus, It must

be the case that the agent theta-role in this case is

assigned the status "external” and is therefore

externally assigned, given the rest of the analysis

developed so far ( a syntactic configuration involving a

VP which functions as a predicate etc. ) , and

uncontrovertial assumptions about the obligatory

assignment of (at least, external) theta-roles. Thus,

it may be safely concluded that the subject theta-role in

the control structures in question is assigned and that

it is assigned externally. Given this conclusion, the

fact remains that no accusative Case can be assigned to

the object NP in these cases and, therefore, given that

the verbs in question are, in principle, capable of

247

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
assigning accusative Case, it couldn't be the case that

Burzio's generalization is here at work. We must,

therefore, look for another explanation.

3.3.4 The Structure of Subjectless Action

Nominalizations

3. 3. 4 . 1 Bound Forms and Genitive Case Assignment

we consider first standard cases such as the

following.

144- a) (H) axilat ha-tapuax

eating the apple

"the eating of the apple"

b) (A) ?aklu ttufaaHat-i

eating the apple-Gen

"the eating of the apple"

The underlying structure of 144a, b is the following.

248

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
145- DP

/ \

D NP

I / \

POSS N*

/ \

N VP

I / \

NOM V NP

I I
eat the apple

Our assumptions about the properties of the nominal bound

morpheme NOM were presented in section 3. 2. 1.2. We may

repeat them here briefly.

146- a) Argument structure of NOM: (Ri , Rj )

b) Subcategorization frame of NOM: [ VP]

In the active Action Nominalization constructions

considered in section 3. 2. 1.2 NOM acted as a mediator for

the purposes of theta-role assignment. In those cases

the external theta role of VP was assigned (linked) to

the internal R-role of NOM which was further linked to

the external R role of the subject NP. In such cases the

relation between the internal R-role of NOM and the R-

249

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
role of the subject NP is like the one which holds

between an NP used predicatively and the NP subject of a

sentence. However, we assume that in the absence of a

subject NP, NOM may simply retain the external theta-role

of VP. This is the most crucial property of NOM. The

reference of this theta-role may either be construed as

arbitrary, or generic, or else it may enter the control

relationship as will be discussed later. Thus, in cases

in which no overt subject is present, the external theta-

role of VP is "inherited" by NOM. In such a state of

affairs NOM may be said to be an argument, that is, i t

fulfills the function of a missing NP. I would like now

to propose the following definition of a "nominal" bound

morpheme .

147- A bound morpheme is nominal if and only if

i t is an argument.

As was just seen, NOM has the ability to change status in

this respect depending on whether a subject NP is present

or not. If a subject NP is absent then NOM functions as

an argument and is therefore "nominal". This is the

situation in 145 in which the distribution of theta-roles

may be illustrated as follows.

250

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
148“ NP k

/ \

N’k

/ \

N k VPi

I / \

NOM V NPj

R k ,Ri i, j

My suggestion is that, if the configuration in 148 can be

characterized in these terms, then it becomes possible to

view some of its properties, in particular, the

impossibility of accusative Case assignment, as part of a

wider phenomenon having to do with the general nature of

accusative Case assignment.

Larson (1988) suggests the following assumption

about structural objective Case.

149- V Assigns objective Case in the configuration

[in fl INFL [vp V.... ]]

If it is assumed that only structural objective


s
(accusative) Case is available in general , then it is

clear that 149, as it is, does not exhaust all instances

of structural Objective Case assignment. To begin with,

it certainly does not apply to accusative Case assignment

251

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
in active Action Nominalizat ions . But note also that,

given the analysis of causative constructions of the

double accusative variant outlined in section 3. 2. 2. 3, an

analysis which seems to be fairly well motivated, then

the Case marking of the second accusative NP remains

uncovered by 149.

150- IP

/ \

NPi I'

/ \

I VP

/ I \

V NP 2 VP

I / \

CAUSE V NPa

Thus, in 150 only the verbal morpheme CAUSE may be viewed

as satisfying the condition in 149 and the assignment of

accusative Case to NPa remains unaccounted for. Thus, if

149 is to have any validity, it should be reformulated in


9
a more general fashion . Given the three cases

mentioned above, it may be assumed that there exists a

class of elements having the capacity to license

accusative Case marking of an object by a governing verb.

It is, of course, an interesting question what property

252

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
it is which is shared by all these elements and by virtue

of which they may be taken to form a class. As a first

approximation we may suggest that the most typical of

this class are elements occupying the INFL node such as

the cluster of inflectional features which constitute

the content of a finite INFL and, probably, the element

occupying the INFL node in an infinitival clause, namely,

the preposition le (to) in Hebrew and to in English. At

this preliminary stage it is at least clear that all of

the elements which may be reasonably argued to fulfil

such function are elements which belong to what may be

referred to as the A* system, that is, elements of which

the distribution is limited to what are standardly known

as A* positions. Here we are making use of the well

established distinction between A positions (argument

positions) and A* positions (nonargument positions). A

positions are positions which bear a grammatical function

such as subject of, object of etc. and it is to elements

occupying such positions that Case features and thematic

roles are assigned. Note now that at least this minimal

condition is satisfied by both NOM and CAUSE and as will

be argued in chapter 4, some elements occupying the head

of CP position may also be assumed to fulfil the same

function. In what follows I will assume that these

elements share the abstract feature +F and that it is

253

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
by virtue of this feature that an element can license

the assignment of accusative Case.

It must now be clarified what structural

relationship must hold between a +F element and a verb

(or a VP) in order for the assignment of Accusative Case

to be possible. For this purpose, let us first define

the relation of being in the domain of as follows,

151- For a maximal projection and a head

o/ is in the domain of iff p c-commands

and there is no head such that 0 is in

the domain of ft and c-commands TT

151 may be relativized to +F elements as follows ,

152- For a maximal projection and a +F head

is in the domain of (3 iff p c-commands

and there is no +F head V such that is i n

the domain of X and J? c-commands *fl* .

Next we may reformulate Larson's (1988) suggestion as

follows ,

153- V assigns Accusative Case in the configuration

[x • X [vp V.... ]]

Where X is +F and VP is in the domain of X.

254

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
153 seems to take care of the three cases considered if

INFL, NOM and CAUSE are assumed to be +F elements.

However, configurations such as 148 are an exception to

153 since the structural condition it specifies is

satisfied and the verb in question may be capable of

assigning Case as well. Note now that, given the

discussion of 148 above, there is one obvious way in

which it constitutes an exception, namely, NOM in 148 has

the status of an argument. Given the definition of a

"nominal** bound morpheme in 147, we may reformulate 153

as follows.

153- V assigns accusative Case in the configuration

[x« X [vp V.... ]] Iff.

i) X is +F

ii) VP is in the domain of X.

iii) X is non-"nominal"

As can now be seen, 148, a subjectless Action

Nominalization configuration, is a case in which the

assignment of accusative Case is not allowed. This seems

to be a natural result since, as just observed, the most

fundamental characteristic of +F elements is their

function as A* elements. Therefore, by assuming the

function of an argument NOM clearly loses the main

255

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
property by virtue o f which i t forms part of this class
of elements.
Thus, in the configuration 1 4 8 the o b j e c t NP cannot
be assigned accusative C a se and therefore some other
strategy o f Case assignment must be invoked. The only

other strategy available is for NP to move to the


specifier position and be assigned Case by the head noun
in a bound genitive configuration.
This is then the account proposed here for the
"Burzio's generalization effect" observed in s u b j e c t l e s s
Action Nominalizations. Obviously, it remains to be seen

whether this explanation has any general applicability.


As will be shown in chapter 5 , the same explanation may
be invoked for the occurrence of the same phenomenon in
Agent Nominalizations. The surface structure

corresponding to 1 4 8 , that is, the structure of 144 a,b


would be the following.
155- DP

/ \
D NP

/ \ / \
Nj D NPi N*

I II / \
eating POSS the N VP
apple I / \
ej V et

25 6

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Note, in light of the above discussion, that the

relation between the moved NP and its trace in 155

couldn't be an A/A relation. This is because the

specifier position in this particular case is not an

argument position. This status is now assumed by NOM.

Therefore, this relation may be viewed as an A* /A

relation. In particular, the relation between the moved

NP and its trace in this case is different from the one

holding between a derived NP subject and its trace in,

say, Raising constructions. In such constructions the

derived subject is assigned a theta-role by the upward

propagation of a thematic index from a trace in a lower

position to its sister node as illustrated in Chapter 1.

Such a thematic relation would be impossible in 155.

Rather, the NP occupies the VP internal position at NP-

structure and moves to the specifier position only in

order to satisfy Case requirements.

The binding facts in the subjectless bound genitive

variant ( c f . section 3. 3. 2. 3) are also accounted for by

this analysis.

156- a) (H) reiyat acmo

seeing himself

b) (H) qatlu nafs- i -hi

killing self-Gen-him

"killing himself"

257

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
In these cases the external theta role assigned to NOM

and the internal theta role assigned to the anaphor are

coarguments. The binding relation here is the same as

the one which holds between a subject and an object in an

active finite sentence with the same asymmetries.

The structure of the corresponding double genitive

in Hebrew is identical in all relevant respects except,

of course, for the Sel-phrase which I assume to be

adjoined as in the following configuration. Otherwise,

the only difference between the bound and the double

genitive is the usual one, namely, that in the second the

object NP is a pronoun rather than a full NP.

157- A subjectless double genitive

DP

/ \

D NP

/ \ / \

Ni D NPj N*

II / \

POSS pron. N’ VP

/ \ / \

ei Sel-NP V ej

258

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
3. 3. 4 . 2 Control

Given our assumptions concerning obligatory control

as presented in chapter 1, the implications with respect

to control of Action Nominalizations i n Arabic may now

become clear. As has already been observed in this

chapter, control of subjectless Action Nominalization

constructions in Arabic is control of a "position".

Typical pairs which demonstrate this property are the

following .

158-a) (A) Haawala Zaid-un ?ixraag-a l-?awlaad-i

tried Zaid-Nom taking out-Acc the kids-Gen

miin 1- bayt-i

from the house-Dat

"Zaid tried to take the kids out of the house"

b ) (A) Haawwala Zaid-un al-xuruug miin 1-

tried Zaid-Nom the going out from the

bayt -i

house-Dat

"Zaid tried to go out of the house"

259

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
159-a) (A) yuriidu Zaid-un naql-a 1-

wants Zaid-Nom transportation-Acc the

kitaab-i ?ila bayruut

book -Dat to beirut

"Zaid wants to transport the book to beirut"

b) (A) yuriidu Zaid-un al-?intiqaal-a ?ila

want Zaid-Nom the transportation to

bayruut

beirut

"Zaid wants to be transported to beirut”

Whereas in the a examples above it is an agent theta role

which is controlled, in the b examples it is a theme,

even though it is the same verb which governs the

controlled constituent in both examples. This relation

is thus insensitive to thematic role distinctions and is

clearly an instance of the general phenomenon of

obligatory control. In this case, however, unlike the

case in controlled infinitives, the lexically established

control relationship holds between an argument of the

governing verb and the argument structure of NOM. Thus,

the lexical entry of the control verb "Haawala" (try)

would look roughly as follows.

260

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
160- Haawala (try) : Agi , Xj

< NOMi >

As is the case with the element COMP in lexical entries

which encode the control relation with infinitival

complements (see Chap. 1) , the lexical representation

above encodes a requirement that a thematic index

associated with NOM be coindexed with an argument of the

governing verb (the external argument in this case) . I

assume that no difficulties arise from a lexical

specification which makes reference to the lexical head

NOM rather than to its maximal projection DP. The

overall DP structure of the constituent in question

follows, presumably, from general principles of phrase

structure.

- In many of the control structures attested in Arabic

the controlled constituent is governed by a lexically

specified and, most likely, semantically empty

preposition. This does not raise any difficulty for the

present analysis since these prepositions do not disturb

the direct relationship between the governing verb and

NOM and may be straightforwardly accommodated into

lexical representations as shown by the examples below.

(A, B , C , etc. in the lexical entries below stand for

thematic role names such as "Agent" "Theme" etc.)

261

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
161- a) Tamara (order): Aj , Bi , Ck

I I

< NP> < bi NOMi >

b) ( A ) Tamarat hind-un zaid-an bi- 1 -xuruuj-i

ordered hind-Nom zaid-Acc with the leaving-Dat

"Hind ordered zaid to leave”

162- a) ? arRama (force): Aj , Bi , Ck

I I

< NP> < 9ala NOMi >

b) (A) ? ar Ram a zaid-un hind-an 9ala tark-i

forced zaid-Nom hind-Acc on leaving-Dat

1- bilaad -i

the country-Dat

"Zaid forced hind to leave the country”

163- a) tamakkana (be able): Ai , Bj

< min NOMi >

b) (A) lam yatamakkan zaid-un min qiraa?at-i

not be able (jus) zaid-Nom from reading -Dat

jjariidat -i

the newspaper-Gen

"Zaid was not able to read the newspaper”

262

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
As is the case with control of infinitives, the

requirement encoded by a lexical entry such as the one in

160 can only be satisfied if it is the internal argument

of NOM which is coindex d with the controlling NP. A

coindexing of the external argument of NOM with the

controlling NP will result in the following

configuration .

.164- IP

/ \

NPi i I•

/ \

VP

/ \

V NPa 1

try / \

N*i

/ \

Ni VPj

I / \

NOM Vj NPa k

Ri , Rj eat

l,k

However, with NPi and NPa coindexed, 164 is ruled out as

a simple violation of principle C of the binding theory.

263

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Only coindexation with the internal theta role of NOM can

avoid such a situation and therefore no ambiguity in this

respect can ever arise.

On this view of control the variation between Hebrew

and Arabic derives from the fact that Hebrew does not

have lexical entries in which control relations are

specified in terms of NOM but, rather, only in terms of

COMP. Presumably, this variation involves a parametric

choice in such a way that one option is taken to the

exclusion of the other. That is, we should not expect to

find mixed cases of a language which has both control of

COMP and control of NOM. Viewed in this perspective,

Hebrew is an interesting case since it has structures

involving both COMP and NOM but has obligatory control


10
only with COMP .

Finally, as one would expect, given the general

analysis of Action Nominalizations advocated here,

nominalized control verbs should maintain control

properties since in the underlying structure of such

cases it would be the control verb itself which occurs.

We should therefore expect to find cases of a controlled

nominalization which is embedded under a nominalized

control verb. The following example with the nominalized

form of the control verb Haawala (try) confirms this


1 1
expectation .

264

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
165- (A) 9ind muHaawalat- i -him 1-faraar-a ?ila

with attempt Dat their the £light-Acc to

1-Rarb

the west

"upon their attempt to flee to the west"

265

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Footnotes to Chapter III
1
This conception of NOM as an abstract rather than a
concrete morphological object having an actual
morphological form is designed to avoid possible
conflicts which may arise between the material in VP and
the nominalizing morpheme. It seems that the analysis of
Action Nominalization constructions suggested in Borer
(forthcoming) commits exactly this error. Thus, adopting
(with some modifications) the proposals of Hazout (1988) ,
an earlier version of the present analysis, Borer
(forthcoming) proposes the following configuration for an
Action Nominalization construction.

NPi
/ \
N'i
/ \
N VP
I / \
haCCaCat NPa VP
I /
the army (SPEC)
\
NPa
I
the city

Concentrating just on the morphological issue, the


element figuring as head of the NP in i is the actual
morphological form of a noun, haCCaCa. The particular
phonological shape of the C(onsonant) positions in this
word is to be filled in by a movement of a verb stem as
indicated by the arrow. Note that the form figuring as
head in i is a form particular to a certain Binyan
pattern, the hiCCiC pattern. However, not every verb has
(either a verbal or nominal) hiCCiC form. Thus, the verb
haras (destroy) has a CaCaC form, of which the
corresponding derived nominal form is C (a) CiCa, and lacks
a form in the hi-CCiC binyan. Now, if the verb stem of
haras (destroy) is to be inserted in an underlying
structure such as i a mismatch between the two elements,
the head of the construction and the verb is going to
arise.
The same problem of a possible conflict arises with
respect to argument structure and the deployment of
arguments in a tree structure such as i. This may be
illustrated with causative verbs in Arabic (see section
3. 2. 2. 4 for the analysis of Arabic causative
constructions). Thus, a causative verb, or its nominal
counterpart, cooccurs with a subject and two accusative
objects as in the following examples.

266

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
ii) (A) Sarraba zaid-un l-?awlaad-a 1-Haliib-a
made drink Zaid-Nom the | kids -Acc the milk-Acc
"Zaid made the kids drink the milk"

iii) (A) taSriib zaid-en l-?awlaad-a 1-Haliib-a


making-drink Zaid-Gen the kids -Acc the milk-Acc
"Zaid's making the kids < rink the milk"

Note now that under Borer's suggestion there is nothing


to avoid a situation in which the head of the
construction is a causative form| but where the VP
governed by it contains only a subject and a single
object, that is, the argument structure corresponding to
a simple transitive verb such aS| Saraba (drink).

iv) NPi
/ \
N'i
/ \
N VP
1 / \
taCCiiC NP2 VP
1 / 1 \
Zaid (SPEC) 1 V
I \
V NPa
I I
drink the milk

In fact, an underlying structure such as (iv) does not


necessarily result in an ill-formed Surface form.
Indeed, (iv) may give rise to the following perfectly
well formed sequence.

(v) (A) taSriib Zaid-en aH-Haliib-a


making-drink Zaid-Gen the| milk -Acc
"making Zaid drink the milk"

The problem is that an analysis like| (iv) makes the claim


that in this structure only two theta roles are assigned,
namely, the agent and theme of drink . The agent of
CAUSE, the "causer", is in this structure non-existent.
It is, however, a simple matter {to show that the "causer"
is there and must be there. Thus, if (v) is embedded
under a control verb as in (vi) below, it is necessarily
the "causer" which is understood) to be controlled.

267

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
(vi) (A) Haawala muHammad taSriib -a zaid-en
tried muhammed making-drink-Acc Zaid-Gen
al-Haliib-a
the milk -Acc
"Muhammed tried to make Zaid drink the milk"

Thus, an analysis like the one proposed by Borer


(forthcoming) allows for the occurrence of mismatch
between argument structure and surface morphology.
Argument structure is a function of verb root and a
Binyan pattern combined, rather than of the verb root
alone. A structure such as (i) above makes it impossible
to ensure a correlation between the morphological form of
the verb (and the corresponding noun) and the argument
structure as it is realized within VP. The present
analysis, as well as the original one in Hazout (1988),
provides a simple way out of this problem.

2
In fact, one may think of one more, rather trivial,
possible way to establish a relationship between the head
and its arguments, namely, by linear adjacency. But,
obviously, here too no one to one mapping is possible.
Thus, in an active form the subject must be adjacent to
the head. But, in the absence of a subject, the NP
adjacent to the head is interpreted as an object and not
as a subject.

3
The same problem arises for Doron's analysis if one
assumes a "theta-theoretic" version of the binding
theory. This is because both arguments in 44 a,b are
considered by Doron to be internal and therefore, again,
symmetrically related.
With respect to this assumption we might point out
another, rather striking, inconsistency in Doron's
analysis. It is assumed in that work that Burzio's
generalization is an active principle of the grammar
"which could be interpreted to state that any lexical
item assigning accusative Case must link its external
argument” (Pg. 12) . This principle is invoked as an
explanation for the ungrammaticality of the following
example in which a subject is missing.

*i) ha-harisa et ha-ir


the destruction OM the city

One might wonder at this point what explains the


grammaticality of 44a. Given Doron's assumption that
both arguments in that example are internal, one might
expect it to be impossible for accusative Case to be

268

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
assigned. However, in that example, accusative Case not
only can be assigned but, in fact, must be assigned.

*ii) harisat ha-oyev ha-ir


destruction the enemy the city

The same kind of inconsistency arises in Doron’s analysis


of the following example.

iii) harisat ha-ir Sei ha-oyev


destruction the city Sei the enemy
"The enemy's destruction of the city"

This example is assigned the following structure in which


"the enemy" in the Sel-phrase is said to be an external
argument (see section 3. 2. 2. 3 on the analysis of these
cases) .

iv) N"
/ \
N' NP
/ \ Sei the enemy
N NP
destruction the city

Given, again, Burzio's generalization, one might expect


it at least to be possible for accusative Case to be
assigned since the external theta-role is, in this case,
linked and the "strong" head noun harisa (destruction) is
certainly capable of assigning accusative Case to its
object. Obviously, none of this is the case. The
following example in which the object NP is preceded by
the object marker et is completely impossible.

*v) ha-harisa et ha-ir Sei ha-oyev


the destruction OM the city Sei the enemy .

4
The account presented in Borer (1984) (Pg. 80-88) is
a variant of the analysis criticized and rejected in this
section. In her account Borer gives the following
paradigm and assigns
ia the structure in ii below.

i) a) (H) ktivat Dan et ha-maamar


writing Dan OM the article
"Dan's writing of the article"
b) (H) ktivat ha-maamar Sei Dan
writing the article Sei Dan
"Dan's writing of the article"

269

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
c) (H) ktivat Dan Sel ha-maamar
writing Dan Sel the article
"Dan's writing of the article"

ii) N ’'i
I \
N"i N"2
/ / \
N'i et N"a
I \ I
Ni N* *3 the article
I I
writing Dan

In this configuration Dan , the (logical) subject, is the


genitive complement of the deverbal head noun "writing".
It is assumed that, since in this state of affairs no
genitive Case can be assigned to the (logical) object
"the article", "the accusative dummy Case marker" et is
inserted to assign Case to NPa . The same situation is
assumed to hold in ib with a reversal of positions
between (logical) subject and (logical) object. Here it
is the "dummy" Case marker Sei which is inserted. Thus,
Borer assumes ib to have the following structure.

iii) N"i
I \
N"i N”a
/ / \
N’i Sei N"a
/ \ I
Ni N**3 Dan
I I
writing the articles

Note first that, given the discussion in section 3. 2. 2. 3 ,


it is clear that ia and ib involve two different
configurations. Therefore, either ii or iii or both
must be the wrong structure. Next, it is assumed by
Borer that the particles Sei and et, being "dummy" Case
markers, are required to be present only for the needs of
Case marking. This implies that the Object Marker et is
a Case assigner rather then the manifestation of Case
assignment by something else, say, a verb. I assume that
this is simply wrong, that is, et is the manifestation of
government by a verb and not a Case assigner itself.
There is no need to go here into a detailed discussion of
this point. It suffices to note that the corresponding
Arabic construction, identical to the Hebrew construction
in all relevant respects, shows morphological accusative
Case marking of the object, the same Case marking that

270

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
would appear on the object of a verb in a regular
sentence .

iv) a) ( A ) ?akala muHammad-un ttufaaHat-a


ate muhammed-Nom the apple-Acc
“Muhammed ate the apple"
b) ( A ) ?aklu muHammad-en ttufaaHat-a
eating muhammed-Gen the apple-Acc
"Muhammed's eating of the apple"

Coming now to the more fundamental issue, note that from


the paradigm in i one important member is missing,
namely, the following, in which the intended reading is
one in which Dan is the agent of "writing" and "the
article" is the theme.

*v) (H) ktivat ha-maamar et Dan


writing the article OM Dan

Thus, the discussion in Borer (1984) implies that the


subject and the object in this construction may freely
change positions with Case markers blindly inserted to
satisfy Case requirements. From this perspective, of the
four logically possible combinations y is the missing
variant .
What is then wrong with y ? Intuitively, et is an
object marker and therefore should not precede a
"logical" subject (or agent) as it does in y. The
crucial difficulty however is the following: What counts
as an object in the configurations ii and iii ? That
is, given configurations ii and iii, in what sense is
"the article” in ia an object and Dan in y not. It is
hard to see in what sense of the notion "object" can the
NP "the article" in ii be said to be an object. It is
obviously not an object in the configurational sense,
that is, an NP governed by a verb and immediately
dominated by VP ( [NP,VP] ) which is the standard
definition of this notion in the government and binding
framework, and, in any case, at least in Borer's account,
the subject NP in ib (configuration iii) occupies exactly
the same position. Thus, in mapping a Case marker onto a
certain NP, it couldn't be any configurational
sensitivities which would avoid the case marker et from
being inserted in the way it is inserted in y. Besides,
it is far from being clear what kind of position the
(logical) object in ii occupies. Is it a complement (of
what?) or an adjunct?
We are forced then, again, to the assumption that
the insertion of et must be sensitive to logical
("subject", "object" taken as primitive notions) or
thematic distinctions rather then to configurational
ones. Here, however, we run into the same problems

271

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
indicated above for Doron's analysis, namely, there is
no unique, unambiguous mapping from logical or thematic
roles to Case markings. The only restriction is that
accusative Case may not be assigned in the absence of the
subject, but this is not the situation in y. Thus, a
claim that accusative Case marking is mapped onto a theme
or a (logical) object would raise the expectation that
the NP identified as such in, say, ib could be preceded
by et. This is however false.

*vi) (H) ha-ktiva et ha-maamar Sei Dan


the writng OM the article Sei Dan

At least under Borer's approach, the only difference


between ib and vi on the one hand and ia on the other is
one of order of constituents, that is, of surface
structure and not of logical and thematic structure and
therefore vi would be expected to be grammatical.
We see then that the analyses of both Borer (1984)
and Doron (1989) fail to see the crucial point that the
occurrence of et is the outcome of a certain
configurational relationship between an NP and a
governing head rather then some other type of
relationship. Neither the analysis proposed by Borer nor
the one suggested by Doron provide a configuration in
which one NP can be unambiguously singled out as an
"object” .
Given this basic shortcoming certain other facts
remain unexplained under Borer's (1984) lexicalist
approach. First, as noticed by Borer, clitic doubling is
possible only with Sei (figure iii) and impossible with
et.

vii) a) (H) ktivat -oi Sei ha-maamar i


writing-his Sei the article
"the writing of the article"
*b) (H) ktivat -oi et ha-maamari
writing-his OM the article

Given the identity of structure assigned to the a and b


examples above, there is no explanation for this contrast
in grammaticality. Obviously, it couldn't have anything
to do with the "dummy" Case markers Sei and et. This
contrast is naturally accounted for within the approach
suggested in this thesis.
Another major shortcoming of Borer's analysis has to
do with the issue of anaphoric relationships in these
constructions. Here the relevant examples are the
following.

272

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
viii) a) (H) reiyat a cm a Sel ha-mora
seeing herself Sel the teacher
"The teacher's seeing of herself"
*b) (H) reiyat acma et ha-mora
seeing herself OM the teacher

According to Borer, Sei has the option of being inserted


in the phonological component of the grammar. Thus, a t
the relevant level of representation (viii) a is a flat
structure which makes it possible for "the teacher" to c-
command and be the antecedent of "herself". On the other
hand, et, the object marker, is present at all levels of
representation and therefore makes it impossible for an
NP governed by it to be the antecedent of an NP outside
its own phrase. However, as noted by Borer herself (Pg.
150) , examples in which an object governed by e t serves
as an antecedent are rather common.

ix) (H) Dan hera et Dina le acma


Dan showed OM Dina to herself

Thus, again, the contrast between (viii)b and (ix)


remains unexplained in Borer's approach. It does have,
however, a fairly simple explanation under the present
approach, namely, (viii)b is an instance of the asymmetry
between a subject and a (VP internal) object, (viii) a
being a different construction. In (ix) , on the other
hand, both "Dina" and "herself" are internal arguments
and can therefore be anaphorically related with "Dina"
as antecedent. Obviously, et plays no role in this
relationship.
Thus, to conclude, Borer's analysis faces much of
the same problems faced by Doron's analysis, namely, the
distinction between a subject and an object in these
constructions must be configurational. Both analyses,
however, simply do not provide the right configuration
for this distinction to be made possible.
It should be noted a t this point that much of the
problems faced by Borer's analysis result from her
assumption of the complement approach to bound genitives.
Looking back at configuration (ii) , we may observe that,
since in this structure Dan, the subject, is assumed to
be a complement, the object "the article" must be
relegated to an adjoined position of unclear status. In
the same way, the same configuration (iii) must be
assumed for (i)b with the subject Dan in an adjoined
position. The difficulties pointed out above are thus a
direct result of this set of assumptions.
Is the complement approach to bound genitives
compatible with any variant of a syntactic approach to
Action Nominalizations? Most probably not. In a
syntactic analysis of (i)a the only element that must

273

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
clearly be the complement of anything is the object Dan,
which is assumed here to be the complement of a verb and
dominated by VP. Now, obviously, a VP in these
constructions must be assumed to be governed by a
nominal bound morpheme functioning as head of the
construction. Thus, in the resulting configuration there
is nowhere in which the subject could fit as the
complement of anything. It may therefore be concluded
that a complement approach to bound genitives is
incompatible with a syntactic analysis of Action
Nominalizations . In view of the striking inadequacies of
lexical approaches to Action Nominalizations and the
clear advantages of a syntactic approach, it may be
concluded that a complement approach to bound genitives
is most probably wrong.

* The account provided here relies heavily on the data


and discussion of Arabic causatives in Mushaweh (1986)
and Hoyt (1989). The analysis proposed here is, however,
radically different from those suggested in these two
works. The data provided in Cowell (1964) has also been
of great importance.

6
Note that this analysis of causative constructions,
in particular, the assumed difference of structure
between the double accusative and the dative variants is
in sharp contrast to recent well known and quite
influential treatments of causative constructions. Here
I have in mind mainly Baker's (1985,1988) work on
causatives. Baker's work clearly, and explicitly,
excludes the possibility of the two morphemes CAUSE and V
being combined in the lexicon. This position is forced
upon Baker by his assumption of UTAH, a principle from
which it follows that NP's which are assigned the same
theta-role in both structures should be hierarchically
related to each other in the same way in the underlying
configurations of both structures. However, the
evidence from Arabic concerning the differences between
the two causative variants speaks clearly against Baker’s
general approach to causatives as well as against UTAH.
For a detailed argumentation, see below my discussion of
Hoyt (1989) which is an attempt to analyze Arabic
causative constructions in the spirit of Baker's and
Larson's recent proposals.

274

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
7
By making here the distinction between processes at
the syntactic as opposed to the lexical level, I do not
wish to imply that the two options are freely available.
Thus, Hebrew has causatives as well but these seem to be
lexically rather then syntactically derived. Causative
verbs in Hebrew are mostly of the hi-CCiC form, examples
of which are: hi-XTiV (dictate), hi-LBiS (dress
someone) , he-?eXiL (feed) hi-STiK (make quite) , and
rather rarely of the CiCeC form as in LiMeD (teach) .
These causative verbs are clearly lexical given two main
criteria. First, it is mostly impossible to have a
causative verb followed by two accusative NP's.

*i) Dina hilbiSa et Dan et ha-sveder


Dina dressed OM Dan OM the sweater
??ii) Dina heexila et Dan et ha-tapuax
Dina fed OM Dan OM the apple

Glinert (1989) (Pg. 163) enumerates only three verbs that


may be followed by two accusative NP's, limed (teach) ,
Saal (ask a question) and heevir (take.... across...).
Second, Hebrew causative verbs may freely assume
derived and idiomatic meanings. For example, hilbiS
("dress somebody" as opposed to "make someone put
something on"), he' exil (feed), hixtiv (dictate), etc.

8
Larson (1988) assumes, in fact, that in any instance
of government of a direct object by a verb two accusative
Case markings are assigned, structural and inherent. For
the ideas suggested here to hold it must be assumed that
this is not so, but rather, only structural accusative
Case is assigned. Note that the assumption of two types
of accusative case forces Larson to the conclusion that
in Passivization the two Cases are suppressed whereas in
Dative-shift only the inherent Case is suppressed. On
the other hand, no evidence is brought by Larson to show
that the assumption of two types of accusative Case is
necessary for constructions other then Dative-shift.

8
There seems to be growing cross linguistic evidence
in favour of the idea that accusative Case assignment in
sentential constructions is a process which takes place
in a configuration involving both VP and I and which
depends, most likely, on the particular specification of
I. Emonds (1989) proposes an account along these lines

275

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
for the phenomenon o£ nominative objects in finnish, old
russian and languages of the baltic group (lithuanian and
latvian) . The phenomenon is that under certain
conditions the morphological nominative instead of
accusative marking is used for direct objects as well as
cognate objects and certain adverbial NPs. Relying on
work by Timberlake, Emonds notes that a necessary
condition for the application of this process in all the
languages examined is that the verb be non-finite. Thus,
the assignment of accusative Case to the object seems to
be directly dependent on distinctions such as
finite/non-f inite which are specified on I. In Emonds
words, a non-finite I is "too weak" to allow for
accusative Case to be assigned. In this case Nominative
is assigned as the "default Case".

10
Interestingly, one finds cases of "control" of an
Action Nominalisation in subject position in Hebrew.

i) reiyat acmo ba-mara xaSuva le- Dan


seeing himself in the mirror is important for Dan

In such cases "Dan" must be interpreted as the antecedent


of "acmo" (himself) in the sub jet. However, given that
Hebrew, unlike Arabic, does not have obligatory control
of Action Nominalisations figuring as complements, there
are good reasons to suspect that the two control
phenomena are of a different nature.

11
Taken from Al-Hayaat October 3 1990.

276

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
CHAPTER IV

INFINITIVES AND GERUNDS

4.1 Introduction

This chapter will be concerned mainly with two

construction types known within the terminology currently

used in the literature on Hebrew grammar as the Verbal

Gerund and the Nominal Gerund. It will also include some

discussion of standard infinitival clauses which seem to

be closely related to the verbal gerund. Since gerundive

and infinitival constructions of the type discussed here

are non existent in Arabic, this chapter will be

exclusively concerned with Hebrew. 1 a,b below are

typical examples of the verbal and the nominal gerund

respectively .

1- a) bi- reot Dan et Dina

with seeing Dan OM Dina

"With Dan seeing Dina"

b) Suv ha-poalim me- ha-avoda

return the workers from the work

"The return of the workers from work"

277

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Introducing the verbal gerund, let us take a brief look

at some of its main characteristics. First, verbal

gerunds are most typically used as temporal adverbs as in

2.

2- bi-reot Dan et Dina hi yac?a me- ha-xeder

with seeing Dan OM Dina she left from the room

"With Dan seeing Dina she left the room"

Thus, a verbal gerundive clause may never figure as an

argument (subject, object etc.). With respect to the

elements occurring in its surface form, the initial

element in a verbal gerund is always a preposition,

interpreted temporally (before, after, "at the same time"

etc.). Immediately following the initial preposition is

an infinitival verb form, morphologically identical to

the verb form which appears in a standard infinitive

(except, of course, to the initial preposition which is

different for infinitives) . Immediately following and

adjacent to the verb is a subject ("Dan" in la) . The

subject, in turn, may be followed by any complement which

happens to be required by the verb. Thus, the surface

sequence of elements in a verbal gerund is as follows,

where XP is any complement (possibly more then one) which

is lexically required by the verb.

278

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
3- Verbal Gerund: P - V i m - NP - (XP)

Going next to the nominal gerund, forms such as in lb are

NP's and have the regular distribution of NP's. Thus,

the NP in lb may occur in the following sentence.

4- anaxnu mexakim le-Suv ha-poalim la- avoda

we waiting to return the workers to the work

"We are waiting for the return of the workers to

work"

Given its distributional as well as other properties

(e.g. modification by adjectives, interaction with

genitive constructions) , the initial element in lb seems

to be a noun. It is followed by an NP which may be said

to be the logical subject of the related verb and by

other, possible, prepositional complements of that verb.

Thus, the surface sequence of elements in the nominal

gerund is the following, where N stands for the

gerundive form of the verb.

5- Nominal Gerund: N - NP - (PP)

Unlike the verbal gerund in which almost any verb may

occur (the exceptions will be discussed and explained in

section 4.2), in the nominal gerund, it is only a small

279

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
subset of verbs of which the gerundive form may occur.

Morphologically, however, the form of the head of the

nominal gerund construction is identical to its

counterpart in the verbal gerund. In fact, and, again,

abstracting away from the initial preposition, it is the

same as the verb form appearing in a standard infinitive.

This is illustrated in the following table.

6- Infinitive Verbal Ger. Nominal Ger.

le-header be-header header

to-be absent with-being absent being absent

la-Suv im-Suv Suv

to-return with-return return

le-healem be-healem healem

to-disappear with-disappearance disappearance

1
Traditional grammarians grouped together the verbal

gerund and the infinitive under the term "Infinitive

Construct". I assume that the main motivation for this

classification has been the fact that in both cases the

infinitival verb form is "in construction" with a

preposition, this, in addition to a certain phonological

280

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
difference between this form and the absolute form, an

archaic biblical form which will not be discussed in this

work. More recent work (e.g. Berman (1978), Glinert

(1989)) tends to group the verbal and the nominal gerunds

together, while taking the infinitive to be a separate

form. This is obviously reflected in the terminology.

Whatever its theoretical motivations, it seems to me

that the traditional classification is basically correct.

As I will attempt to show, both the standard infinitive

and the verbal gerund involve a clausal structure. This

is, of course, the standard view of infinitives, at least

within the broad outlines of the Government and Binding

framework assumed here. It will therefore be the verbal

gerund which will enjoy more detailed attention in this

chapter. The discussion in section 4.2 will be devoted

to the verbal gerund. The nominal gerund, on the other

hand, does not involve a clausal structure. Rather, it

involves an underlying structure similar to the one

argued for in chapter 3 for Action Nominalisation

constructions and a syntactic process of nominalisation.

That is, a process of head movement applying to a verb

and attaching it to a nominal bound morpheme, GER, which

governs the verb and the VP of which it is the head. The

crucial properties of the nominal gerund may be explained

by making certain, rather minimal, assumptions about the

281

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
properties of GER as will become clear in the discussion

in section 4.3.

Notwithstanding my view of the correct

classification of these constructions, as just stated, I

will adhere throughout this chapter to modern terminology

which has now become standard in reference grammars

(Glinert (1989)) and descriptively oriented work (e.g.

Berman (1978)). It is obvious, however, that the issue

of correct classification derives mainly from the

(mostly) identical verbal (or deverbal) form appearing in


2
all three constructions . Thus, in all three

constructions it is the same combination of verb root and

vowel pattern which occurs. This raises the question of

whether a unified approach to all three constructions is

conceivable in which a verb form would combine with the

same underlying morpheme in all three cases. This,

however, is not necessary. Rather, what seems necessary,

and certainly plausible, is to assume that the derivation

of the nominal gerund involves a " nominal izat ion- type"

of process applying to a nominal bound morpheme and a

verb form, whereas the infinitive and the verbal gerund,

involve a clausal structure in which a verb form combines

with a non finite verbal INFL to produce an infinitival

verb form. Thus, we will assume that the morphological

entity which combines with a verb form to produce the

particular infinitival shape is doubly lexically listed

282

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
as either a noun or a verbal inflectional element. The

lexically listed nominal element GER may be attributed

certain properties related to its thematic, or argument

structure, properties which are generally typical of

nouns. As will be seen, a similar situation holds with

respect to participial constructions. In chapter 5,

which is devoted to participial constructions, a more

detailed discussion of this type of problem is

undertaken.

The situation just described is similar to the one

existing in English, where one finds a variety of forms

and constructions involving the morpheme -ING. While

some ING- forms are clearly nominal (7) ,

7- a) The killing of a prisoner of war is a crime

b) Loud singing disturbs John

other ING- forms/constructions are of intermediary

verbal /nominal nature (8) ,

8- a ) Their killing a prisoner of war was a crime

b) His singing loudly disturbs John

and others, such as the following progressive form, are

simply verbal.

283

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
9- Mary is running

It seems to me rather implausible to assume that a

unified analysis of all these constructions is possible

in which a unique -ING morpheme ( a nominal morpheme or

possibly, a realization olf INFL) combines with a verb to

produce all existing Verb+ING forms. Rather, it could

be that the same approach would be appropriate in this

case as the one suggested! here for Hebrew. The

discussion in this and the next chapter will attempt to

demonstrate the advantages of such an approach in dealing

with the Hebrew and Arabic data

4.2 Verbal Gerunds

4.2.1 The Structure of Infinitival Clauses

The main claim about the structure of the verbal

gerund has already been presented in the previous

section. The claim is, to repeat, that the verbal gerund

has a clausal structure just like a standard infinitive

In particular, just like lan infinitive, its verb form is

derived by a movement operation adjoining a verb to a

non-finite INFL. I will adopt here a standard view of

284

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
the finite/non-finite distinction. A finite INFL is one

which is specified as [+TENSE] . Such a specification of

INFL is made possible by assuming the following rule,

10- INFL -----> [ [+/- TENSE] , (AGR) ]

A non-finite INFL is thus an INFL node specified as [-

TENSE] . The claim is then that both an infinitive and a

verbal gerund involve a [-TENSE] INFL. Given the basic

assumption that both structures are clausal, the obvious

question to raise is where the differences between the

two constructions come from. The two main differences

between the two constructions are the following.

The first concerns their distribution. An

infinitival clause can function as an argument and occupy

any argument position in the sentence. Thus, it can be a

complement to a verb (11) , an adjective (12) or a

preposition (13) as well as function as the subject of a


3
sentence (14) .

11- Dan roce [le-sayem et ha-avoda]

Dan wants to finish OM the work

12- naim [li-hyot ba -xeder]

pleasant to be in the room

"It is pleasant to be in the room"

285

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
13- ze yoter xaSuv mi [li-lmod ivrit]

it (is) more important than to learn Hebrew

14- [li-lmod anglit] ze xaSuv

to learn English it important

"To learn English is important"

A verbal gerundive clause may never be an argument.

Rather, its most typical use, but, possibly, not the only

one, is as a time adverbial.

15- [im hikanes Dan la- xeder] hitpateax vikuax

with entering Dan to the room developed a dispute

"With Dan's entering the room a dispute developed"

A second major difference between the two constructions

concerns the occurrence of a subject. In an infinitival

clause no lexically realized subject may appear (16) ,

whereas in a verbal gerund exactly the opposite situation

obtains, namely, there must be a lexical subject (17) .

16- *a) Dan li-•r'ot et Dina

Dan to see OM Dina

*b) li-r'ot Dan et Dina

to see Dan OM Dina

*17- bi-r ' ot et Dina

with seeing OM Dina

286

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
In the account proposed in this chapter these differences

derive from one single factor, namely, the nature of the

element occupying the position of head of CP in each

case. In an infinitival clause it is the abstract

functional head COMP, whereas in the verbal gerund it is

a preposition, one out of a small class of prepositions.

Our assumptions about the structure of infinitival

clauses were presented in chapter 1. Here we will just

repeat them in their main outlines. The structure of an

infinitival clause is assumed to be as follows.

18- CP

/ \

/ \

COMP IPt

(Rj , Ri ) / \

NP I'i

I / \

e le-I VPi

In an infinitival clause, the external theta-role of VP

is vertically assigned first to I * . It is assumed that,

in general, in infinitival clauses, COMP, or rather, its

internal theta-role inherits the external theta-role of

VP. In structures involving obligatory control this

287

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
provides the input needed to satisfy the requirements of

a higher control verb, control being a relation between a

lexically designated argument of a control verb and a

governed COMP. Thus, the subject position of IP may

only be occupied by an NP-trace, an element which must be

assigned but cannot satisfy a theta role. Of the other

empty elements which may be seriously considered

(assuming the non-existence of PRO) , a small pro would

require to be identified by inflectional morphology which

is absent in this case, and an expletive pro, as will be

argued later in this chapter, must be assigned nominative

Case, which is not available to this position. Thus,

COMP inherits the external theta role of VP and has also

its own external referential theta-role R by virtue of

which it can figure in argument positions in the

sentence .

18 shows the preposition "le" (to) attached to INFL.

This preposition plays no role in the thematic structure

of the clause and it is absent from gerundive clauses.

Following a suggestion of R. Higgins I will adopt the

idea that the preposition le, situated in the INFL

position, fulfills the function of a non "nominal" +F

element in the sense of this notion suggested in section

3. 3. 4.1 of the previous chapter. Thus, it provides the

environment for the assignment of accusative Case. Its

presence is not required in the verbal gerund since in

288

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
this construction this function is fulfilled by a

prepositional element occupying the COMP position as will

become clear soon.

Thus, the two main facts illustrated in 11-16 are

explained for infinitives. Given its external theta-role

R , COMP and the CP that it heads can be the argument of a

predicate (11-14) . An NP in the subject position of an

infinitival clause can be assigned Case neither by INFL

nor by COMP (or a governor from outside the clause) and

is therefore ruled out.

4.2.2 The Structure of Verbal Gerunds

4 .2 . 2.1 A Sentential Analysis of Verbal

Gerunds (I )

The underlying structure of a verbal gerund, as in

example 19a, is represented in 19b,

19- a) be- exol Dan et ha-tapuax

with eating Dan OM the apple

"With Dan eating the apple”

289

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
b) CP

/ \
C

/ \
P IP

I / \
be NP I'

with 1 / \

Dan I VP

[-TENSE] / \

V NP

eat the apple

In this structure the specifier position of IP is

occupied by a lexical NP. The head of IP is a non-

finite INFL. As just suggested above, the absence of the

"dummy” preposition "le" (to) in verbal gerunds may be

explained as having to do with the fact that its function

in an infinitival clause as a licensing element for the

assignment of accusative Case is now fulfilled by the

preposition occupying the COMP position as head of the

entire construction. Given that no +F element occupies

the I position, VP in 19b above is in the domain of P , in

accordance with the definition of this notion in 150

(Chap 3) .

The surface structure of a verbal gerund is derived

290

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
by two successive head movement operations. First, the

verb moves and adjoins to I.

20- CP

/ \

/ \

P IP

/ \

NP I’

/ \

I VP

/ \ / \

I V V NP

Then, I moves and adjoins to P in the head position o£

CP.

291

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
21- CP

/ \
C*

/ \
P IP

/ \ / \
P I NP I'

/ \ / \
IV I VP

I / \
e V NP

The outcome o f these operations is a complex preposition


((P+I+V) 4 which i s in a position to govern and a s s i g n
Case to an NP in the subject position of I P .
Just l i k e any other NP governed and assigned Case by
a lexical head (N, V, P) , i f the su bj e c t NP in 2 1 happens
to be a pronoun i t is realized as a c l i t i c on the head
governing it.

22- a ) b i- reot -i et ha-seret


wit h seeing-me OM the fi lm
"Upon my seeing the film"

292

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
b) leaxar saym-o et ha-limudim

after f inishing-his OM the studies

"After his finishing the studies"

The facts about the distribution of the verbal gerund may

be explained as a direct outcome of the properties of the

prepositions that figure as the head of this

construction. Unlike the COMP of standard infinitives,

such prepositions do not have an external referential

theta-role and, therefore, the construction of which they

are the head may not be the argument of a verb. Rather,

they function just like any regular temporal PP. The

most typical function of such PP's is as time adverbials

as in the following example.

23- axare ha-bxirot tukam memSala

after the elections will be formed a government

"After the elections a government will be formed"

24 is the verbal gerundive paraphrase of 23.

24- leaxar hearex ha-bxirot tukam

after being held the elections will be formed a

memSala

government

"After elections are held a government will be formed”

293

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Note, however, that temporally interpreted PP's may also

figure as predicates. This is not a very common use of

such PP's but it is possible if the NP of which they are

predicated can be construed as referring to a certain

point or interval in time rather than to an object or a

non temporal entity.

25- a) ha-maaraxa ha-Sniya hay ta leaxar ha-hafsaka

the act the second was after the intermission

"The second act was after the intermission"

b) ha-mikre hay a axare ha-diyun

the incident was after the discussion

This predicative use is also available for verbal

gerundive clauses.

26- a) ha-maaraxa ha-Sniya hay ta miyad im

the act the second was immediately with

histayem ha-hafsaka

terminating the intermission

"The second act was immediately after the

termination of the intermission”

294

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
b) ha-mikre baya miyad im higamer

the incident was immediately with finishing

ha-diyun

the discussion

"The incident happened right after the discussion

ended"

4.2.2 .2 A Non-Sentential Analysis of Verbal Gerunds

Given the similarity in use and distribution between

verbal gerunds and simple temporal PP's, as just

demonstrated above, the possibility may be raised that

the structure of a verbal gerund is, in fact, not the one

suggested in the previous section but, rather, one

corresponding to the PP's in 25a, b. That is, a verbal

gerund, it may be suggested, is a PP which has the

structure P-NP, where the NP in this structure may have a

more complex "nominalization-like" structure and

derivation but in which the gerundive head is the head

noun. The arguments against such a possibility are

simple and straightforward as follows.

The first argument has to do with distribution. The

material following the initial preposition simply does

not have the distribution of an NP, that is, it cannot

appear independently of the preposition in regular NP

295

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
positions. The following examples show a verbal

gerundive as subject, direct object and object of a

preposition respectively. Such positions are perfectly

natural for Action Nominalization constructions

discussed in chapter 3.

27- *a) reot Dan et Dina haya maftia

seeing Dan OM Dina wasi surprising

*b) hiklat-nu et daber Dan el ha-kahal

recorded-we OM speaking Dan to the audience

*c) Sama-nu al reot Dan et Dina

heared-we about seeing Dan OM Dina

Next, a verbal gerundive head cannot be modified by an

adjective,

*28- be- haros ha-iriya ha-axzari et ha

with destruction the municipality the cruel OM the

bay it

house

Here, the intended interpretation would be one in which

the destruction (of the house) is described as cruel.

Note that the inacceptability of 28 may not be attributed

to the violation of some possible adjacency requirement

imposed on the relationship between an adjective and the

296

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
noun that i t modifies. Such a restriction simply does

not exist as the following example shows in which the

adjective may only be understood as modifying the non

adjacent head noun.

29- beyt ha-mora ha-gadol

house the teacher (fm) the big (ms)

“The big house of the teacher"

Thus, being unable to be modified by an adjective, it

would be implausible to assume that the verbal gerundive

head is a noun.

In an analysis in which the gerundive head is taken

to be a noun, the most natural, and the only available,

assumption with respect to the way it is related to the

subject following it would be that it assigns genitive

Case to it. On such an assumption, the head and the

subject would be related to each other as two terms in a

bound genitive construction. This, however, raises the

expectation that the free and the double genitive

variants would also be possible, but this is clearly not

the case.

30- *a) bi-reot Sel Dan et ha-seret

with seeing Sei Dan OM the film

297

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
*b) bi-reot -o Sel Dan et ha-seret

with seeing-his Sel Dan OM the film

This argument can actually be stated in a simpler way,

namely, if a gerundive head is a noun then i t should be

possible for i t to figure in genitive constructions of

all types, but this, again, is not the case.

A last argument against this proposal has to do with


0
the possibilities of coordination . In general, it is

perfectly possible for a preposition to govern two or

more coordinated NP’s,

31- a) axare aruxat ha-erev ve ha-seret ba-

after dinner and the film on

televizia

television

b) im Dan ve Dina

with Dan and Dina

If the alternative analysis considered in this section

was correct, we would expect to find two verbal gerundive

"NP's" coordinated under a single preposition. This can

be shown to be wrong.

298

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
*32- bi-Smoa Dan et ha-muzika ve

with hearing Dan OM the music and

reot Dina et ha-seret

seeing Dina OM the movie

These are, then, the arguments against the P-NP analysis

of verbal gerunds. In view of these arguments i t may be

concluded that this analysis is fairly implausible.

Since this is, however, the only conceivable alternative

to the clausal structure proposed in the previous

section, these arguments make the clausal analysis, or

some version of it, all the more plausible. We may turn

now to a further elaboration of that analysis.

4. 2.2.3 A Sentential Analysis of Verbal Gerunds (II)

As was suggested in section 4. 2. 2.1, the verbal

gerund has a sentential structure and may be viewed as a

type of infinitival clause in that its INFL head is

specified as [-TENSE] (and also does not carry agreement

features) . Its surface structure is derived by two

successive applications of head movement, first moving

the verb to INFL and then INFL+V to COMP. The resulting

tree structure is repeated below for convenience.

299

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
33- CP

/ \

/ \

P IP

/ \ / \

P I NP I'

/ \ / \

I V I VP

I / \

e V XP

Given this structure, all of the facts enumerated in the

previous section as arguments against the "P-NP" analysis

are directly accounted for. Beginning with the

distribution facts in 27, a substructure in which the

initial preposition is missing is simply not a

constituent and therefore it shouldn't be expected to be

able to appear independently. Moreover, if it is correct

to assume, as we do here, that the subject is assigned

Case by the initial preposition, then the underlined

sequences in 27, and therefore the sentences as a whole,

are also ruled out by the Case filter.

As to adjectival modification (example 28), given

300

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
the proposed structure, the gerundive head is not a noun

but, rather, a non-f ini te form of the verb and there is,

therefore, no reason to assume that it should be possible

for it to be modified by an adjective. The same

explanation holds with respect to the facts in 30. The

distribution of Sel-phrases is limited to NP's and

therefore they may not occur in a configuration like 32,

related as genitive arguments to the gerundive head.

Note, on the other hand, that adverbs are perfectly

admissible in verbal gerunds as is to be expected, given

the proposed analysis.

34- [ be-nos'e -nu leat ] garam-nu li-pkake tnua

with driving-we slowly caused-we to jams traffic

"By driving slowly we caused traffic jams"

Turning next to coordination possibilities in gerundive

clauses, an ungrammatical example such as 32 would have,

presumably, the following "pre- head movement" structure.

301

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
35- CP

/ \
C

/ \
p IP

1 / \

be IP IP

1 / \ / \

with NP I’ NP I'

1 / \ 1 / \

Dan I VP Dina I VP

/ \ /

V NP V NP

Il II
hear the music see the movie

I assume that 3 2 is ruled out simply because there is no

adjunction site for the verb in the second clause (see)

which would give rise to a surface word order such as the

one in 32, that is, one in which reot (see) follows the

first IP and precedes the second IP.

One does, however, find cases of conjunction which

may be attributed a configuration identical to the one in

35. One such example is 36a which I assume to have the

structure in 36b.

302

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
36- a ) be-hagia ha-banim be-Saa Seva ve- ha-

with-arriving the boys at hour seven and the

banot be-Saa Smone

girls at hour eight

"With the boys arriving at seven o’clock and the

girls at eight o'clock"

b) CP

/ \

P IP

/ \ / 1

p V IP and \

1 1 / \ IP

with arriv. NP I’ / \

1 / \ NP I*

the I VP the / \

boys 1 / \ girls I VP

e V Adv. 1 / \

1 1 e V Adv.

e at 7 1 1

e at 8

36 is an instance of an across-the-board movement. Given

the constituent structure and derivation suggested here

303

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
for verbal gerunds, such cases are naturally accounted

for. Note that the occurrence of a temporal adverb in

each one of the conjuncts serves as an indication that

there are in this structure two VP's and therefore two

sentential (IP) constituents (otherwise, the sequence

"The girls at 8 o'clock" would have to be taken for an

NP, which is rather implausible)

Further support for the clausal structure proposed

here is provided by the facts concerning binding

relationships in these constructions. Here the facts are

rather straightforward, namely, the same subject object

asymmetries that hold in a finite clause hold in a verbal

gerund. Thus, the contrast between the two following

examples is exactly what we expect.

37- a) bi-reot Dan et acmo

with seeing Dan OM himself

"With Dan seeing himself"

*b) bi-reot acmo et Dan

with seeing himself OM Dan

Equally, the passive variant of 37a is bad (38a) just

like its sentential counterpart (38b) .

38- *a) be- heraot acmo

with being seen himself

304

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
*b) acmo nira

himself was seen

On the basis of the analysis proposed here there is no

reason to expect 38a to be good. In this, verbal gerunds

stand in an interesting contrast to Action

Nominalizations such as in the following example

(discussed in chapter 3) .

39- reiyat acmo

seeing himself

"The seeing of himself"

We may turn now to some facts concerning the initial

preposition. As was claimed and argued for, the initial

preposition in a verbal gerund is not the head of a PP

but rather occupies the COMP position as the head of CP.

As was also mentioned earlier, it is only a small class

of prepositions that may appear as the initial element in

a verbal gerund. Thus, one does find prepositions for

which the most typical, or only, use is as temporal

prepositions but which may not occur in a verbal gerund.

40- a) me az ha-mahapexa

since the revolution

305

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
*b) meaz reot Dan et ha-seret

since seeing Dan OM the film

41- a) be-meSex ha-hafgana

during the demonstration

*b) be-meSex exol Dan et ha-tapuax

during eating Dan OM the apple

42- a) ad yom riSon

until Sunday

*b) ad Smoa Dan et ha-sipur

until hearing Dan OM the story

These facts, again, can be naturally accounted for on the

basis of the present analysis. A preposition may simply

be lexically specified as being able or not to figure as

the head of CP. We may assume that this is simply

achieved by assigning a preposition a certain feature,

say, [+COMP] . Conversely, one finds also instances of

prepositions that may appear in a verbal gerund and

receive a temporal interpretation but may not be used as

temporal prepositions when occurring as heads of a PP.

Consider the following examples.

306

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
43- a) lifne

before

b ) xaxare ha-teuna

after the accident

*c) im

with

*d) be

with

44- a ) lifne

before

b ) axare hitraxaSut ha-teuna

after occurrence the accident

??c) im "The occurrence of the accident”

with

*d) be

with

45- a ) lifne

before

b) axare hitraxeS ha-teuna

after occurring the accident

c ) im "the occurrence of the accident

with

d ) be

with

307

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
The UP ha-teuna (the accident) in 43 and the Action

Nominal izat ion the occurrence of the accident in 44 both

denote an event. Therefore, the most natural, or only,

way to interpret the governing preposition in 43-44 is as

a temporal preposition. This is, however, impossible for

the prepositions im and be. These two prepositions,

however, are perfectly fine with a verbal gerund (45) and

are, in fact, the most common and typical for this

construction. This, again, may be simply accounted for

by attributing the feature [+COMP] to these two

prepositions. Thus, a preposition specified as [+COMP]

may only occur as the head of CP. If this is so then we

must assume that the prepositions lifne (before) and

axare (after) have actually two separate variants, one

which is specified as [+COMP] and one which is not. Both

variants, however, will be semantically temporal. This

may be objected to at first glance as an unnecessary

complication but may be supported by the fact that the

same distinction needs to be made with respect to the

prepositions be and im. These two have an identical [-

COMP] counterpart which is, however, not semantically

temporal and may occur in PP's such as the following.

46- a) be amerika

in america

308

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
b) im Dina

with Dina

Thus, the distinction between prepositions which may

occur in a verbal gerund, as complementizers, and those

which don't must be made and given the present analysis

such a distinction may be achieved naturally by assuming

the existence of a certain, limited, class of

prepositions marked as [+COMP] of which the distribution

is strictly limited to the COMP position. Obviously,

such a distinction wouldn't be available on the basis of

a "P-NP" analysis of verbal gerunds. This distinction

turns out to be independently necessary for the two

identical variants of be and im which happen to differ

also in their meaning, the [+COMP] variants being

semantically temporal while the

[-COMP] ones are not.

This result is, in fact, desirable and is to be

expected given the theta-theoretic approach assumed in

this work. This is so for the following reason. In

regular PP's such as the ones in 46, the NP may be said

to be the argument of the preposition. It is assigned,

or satisfies, an internal theta-role of the preposition.

On the other hand, the theta-theoretic relation which

holds between a preposition situated in the COMP position

and the IP it governs must be different. This is because

309

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
IP in these constructions has no external theta-role and

is therefore incapable of being an argument. For this to

be the case, however, the governing preposition must be

one which has no internal argument. We are thus led,

again, to a distinction such as the one suggested above

between two separate classes of prepositions, the [-COMP]

(argument taking) ones and the [+COMP] (non argument-

taking) ones. The semantic difference between the

prepositions be and im which are marked [+COMP] and their

[-COMP] counterparts provides a certain amount of support

for this result since, given the reasoning above, they

must be lexically separate items on independent grounds.

In 4.2.1 two major differences between verbal

gerunds and infinitives were pointed out, the first

concerning distribution and the second concerning the

occurrence of a subject. It was claimed that both

differences are related to the occurrence of a

preposition in the COMP position of the verbal gerund and

its absence from the COMP position of infinitives. The

distribution facts were shown to follow naturally from

this assumption and it now remains to explain the fact

concerning the subject. The fact is, to repeat, that in

a verbal gerund a lexically realized subject must occur.

Given the clausal analysis of gerunds proposed here, a

rather natural explanation suggests itself if i t is

assumed that any sentential structure has a subject

310

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
position which must be occupied by some element. This,

it seems, is far from being a non-standard assumption.

Rather, it is an assumption which seems to have a fairly

general justification and the following discussion will

provide further support for it. The question as to the

obligatory presence of a lexical subject is then reduced

to the one concerning which elements are allowed to

occur in the subject position of this particular

sentential structure. In the case of the verbal gerund,

as I wish to argue, it is only a lexical NP which may

occur. In the following I will simply go through the

different possibilities in an attempt to show that a

lexical NP is the only one available, to the exclusion of

any other NP types.

Let us first repeat for convenience the proposed

configuration and note that its most important feature

for the present discussion is the fact that the COMP

position in this configuration is occupied by a complex

preposition derived by head movement.

311

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
47- CP

/ \

/ \

P IP

/ \ / \

P I NP I’

/ \ / \

I V I VP

I / \

e V XP

Given this characterization of the COMP position in the

configuration above, it follows that the subject position

in this configuration must be occupied by an element

capable of being assigned and satisfying a theta-role.

This would be part of the explanation for the following

contrast.

48- *a) bi-Smoa et ha-yedia

with hearing OM the message

b) bi-Smoa Dina et ha-yedia

with hearing Dina OM the message

"With Dina hearing the message"

312

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Thus, as was concluded in the above discussion and unlike

the abstract element COMP which occurs in standard

infinitives, the preposition which occupies this position

in the verbal gerund does not have the appropriate

argument structure and is, therefore, incapable of being

assigned the external theta-role of VP (which would

"percolate" first to IP) . Therefore an NP-trace is

excluded from the subject position of 48a * . Thus, from

the variety of empty elements available the only

remaining option which may seriously be considered is

"small" pro.

Considering first "theta-role-assigned" pro, to be

distinguished from "expletive" pro, this element is

generally assumed to be licensed by morphological

agreement features, available in a governing INFL, and

those are not available in the case of 48a. An

infinitival INFL (at least in Hebrew) lacks agreement

features and it is for this reason that it is also

incapable of assigning Nominative to a lexical NP

subject.

Note that if the subject NP in 47 happens to be a

pronoun then it is realized as a clitic attached to the

gerundive head, as in the following example.

313

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
49- be-yode -nu et ha-tSuva

with knowing-we OM the answer

"With us knowing the answer"

Under certain approaches, it would be assumed that in

such cases the subject position in 47 is, in tact,

occupied by pro which is said to be "identified" by the

cluster of morphological features which are the clitic.

Alternatively, and what seems to be a fairly reasonable

approach, cliticization may be viewed as a process which

belongs into the morphological component of the grammar

so that at the relevant syntactic level of representation

the subject position of 49 is simply occupied by a

pronoun. In any case, however, such constructions may be

said to have a subject and are, therefore, irrelevant.

Thus, in cases such as 48 a,b, in which the verb in

a verbal gerundive clause has an external theta-role to

assign, only a lexical NP may occur.

The only remaining cases for which the question

arises are those in which the main predicate is one which

does not assign an external theta-role. Such cases

involve, for example, predicates which take only an

internal sentential argument (50a) or impersonal passive

(50b) .

314

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
50- a) (haya) barur Se Dan xole

(was) clear that Dan sick

"It was clear that Dan is sick"

b) nimsar al ha-teuna

was reported about the accident

"It was reported about the accident"

I assume that the subject position of such sentences is

occupied by an expletive pro and that the condition for

the occurrence of an expletive pro is that it be assigned

nominative Case. Thus, I am assuming that identification

by inflectional morphology is not the relevant factor

here. This is supported by cases such as 50a in which

the main predicate is an adjective. Adjectives, and,

more generally, third person morphology, do not allow for

pro-drop in Hebrew, that is, the occurrence of pro in

subject position. Note now that the verbal gerunds

corresponding to 50a, b are ungrammatical.

51- *a) be-heyot barur Se Dan xole

with being clear that Dan (is) sick

*b) be-himaser al ha-teuna

with being reported about the accident

The claim is then that the requirement of nominative Case

assignment to an expletive element occupying the subject

315

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
position of these gerundive clauses is not met and

consequently that the only remaining option for a non-

lexical subject in a verbal gerund, namely, expletive

"pro", is also excluded.

That this explanation is on the right track, that

is, that the ungrammaticality of these cases (51a,b) must

have something to do with conditions imposed on an

element occupying the sentential subject position is

strongly supported by the following examples in which the

infinitival counterparts of 50a, b occur.

52-* a ) lihyot barur Se Dan xole ze acuv

to be clear that Dan (is) sick it (is) sad

*b) lehimaser al ha teuna ze lo

to be reported about the accident it (is) not

naim

pleasant

Note that the only difference between the grammatical 50

a , b and the ungrammatical 52 a,b is that the former are

finite whereas the latter are not. To narrow the issue

further down let us note that corresponding infinitival

clauses in which an external theta role is assigned to

the subject are perfectly fine.

316

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
53- a) liSmoa Se Dan xole ze acuv

to hear that Dan sick it sad

"to hear that Dan is sick is sad"

b) limsor al ha-teuna ze lo naim

to report about the accident it not pleasant

"to report about the accident is not pleasant"

Considering first the contrast between 53a, b and 52a, b we

may note that the only difference between these two cases

has to do with the thematic status of the subject

position, namely, in one case (53) it is assigned a theta

role and in the other (52) it is not. Looking next at

the contrast between 50a, b and 52a, b we note that here

the minimal difference is that the first are finite while

the latter are not. Thus, the ungrammatical cases are

only those in which no theta role is assigned to the

subject and INFL is specified as [-FINITE] . We may

therefore conclude that the ungrammaticality of 52a, b may

only be explained on the basis of some assumption about

the way an INFL node in these sentences is related to

something else in the construction. This "something

else", however, could only be the subject position since

this is the only position with which INFL may be

plausibly assumed to be related in a government

relationship and, otherwise, why would the availability

or non-availability of an external theta role make any

317

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
difference (Note that, in any case, no other NP is

present in the construction which could be affected by

the finite/non~finite distinction) . The explanation

suggested here is that the expletive pro occupying this

position is not in the environment of the nominative Case

assignment as would be necessary for its licensing. It

follows that the ungrammaticality of the gerundives 51

a,b has, most probably, something to do with restrictions

applying to the subject position too. The

ungrammaticality of the 51a, b is thus not an isolated

case but rather a particular instance of a general

phenomenon having to do with the general conditions that

are imposed on the subject position of a sentential

structure .

To conclude this section, it was argued that the

Hebrew verbal Gerund construction is a type of

infinitival clause. The most important detail in this

analysis is the assumption that the initial preposition

in this construction is a complementizer to which an

infinitival form of a verb is adjoined by head movement.

This assumption allowed us to explain the facts about the

distribution of the verbal Gerund as well as some

restrictions with respect to its subject position. The

obligatory occurrence of a subject in a verbal gerund was

explained on the basis of the general assumption that any

clause must have a subject. As was demonstrated above,

318

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
of the variety of NP elements that may come into

question, only a lexical NP is licensed in that position.

Obviously, such an explanation is only available if a

clausal structure is assumed. The parallelisms

demonstrated between the verbal gerund (51) , on the one

hand, and finite (50) and infinitival (52) clauses, on

the other, provide rather strong support for this


7
assumption .

4.2.3 The General Analysis of Infinitives:

Some Implications

It would be interesting at this point to briefly

consider some implications of the above discussion to the

general debate concerning the analysis of infinitival

constructions. As is well known, the assumption that

infinitives are clausal is standard within the Government

and Binding framework but is otherwise far from being

universally accepted. The relevance of the discussion

in the previous section derives from the fact that the

explanation of some of the data relies crucially on a

clausal analysis of both standard infinitives and verbal

gerunds. It would therefore be interesting to consider

to what extent nonsentential approaches to infinitives

can provide an account for these facts. Nonsentential

319

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
theories of infinitives are theories which take

infinitives to be VP's. For the sake of concreteness we

will consider here the particular semantic theory of

infinitives developed in Chierchia (1984). Chierchia's

approach may be briefly summarized as follows.

Generally, properties, the semantic value of VP's, have

two modes of being: as propositional functions and as

individual images of propositional functions. A finite

VP such as runs, as in John runs, is a propositional

function, an unsaturated structure that "looks for" an

argument to yield a proposition. Propositional

functions have individual correlates. The semantic

operation by which a propositional function such as runs

is mapped onto its individual correlate is achieved by

the nominalizing function ' '. The operation of

mapping a propositional function onto its individual

correlate is marked in the syntax by means of the

f inite/non-finite distinction. Thus, to run is an

expression referring to the individual projection of

runs . Being an individual projection of a propositional

function, to run cannot take an argument, from which

follows the ungrammaticality of,

*54- John to run

Concretely, the syntactic counterpart of the nominalizing

320

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
function • ' is assumed to be the infinitival morpheme

[-Agr]. That is, [-Agr] is semantically associated with

the nominalizing function * * and, in the same way that

’ ' operates on an entire VP meaning, so does [-Agr]

have an entire VP in its scope.

The contrasts that concern us now are the following,

55- a) nimsar al ha-teuna ba- radio

was reported about the accident on the radio

"It was reported about the accident on the radio”

*b) lehimaser al ha-teuna ba- radio ze

to be reported about the accident on the radio it

acuv

sad

c ) Dan masar al ha-teuna ba- radio

Dan reported about the accident on the radio

d ) limsor al ha-teuna ba- radio ze acuv

to report about the accident in the radio it sad

"To report about the accident on the radio is sad"

56- a) hitbarer Se Dan xole

became clear that Dan sick

"It became clear that Dan is sick"

*b) lehitbarer Se Dan xole ze acuv

to become clear that Dan sick i t sad

c) Dan hirer et ha-nose

Dan clarified OM the issue

321

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
d) levarer et ha-nose ze xaSuv

to clarify OM the issue it important

"To clarify the issue is important"

The b examples above show the ungrammatical infinitival

counterparts of the grammatical finite sentences in a.

The verb in the a and the b examples does not assign an

external theta role. The verb in the ç examples does

assign an external theta role and its infinitival

counterpart in the d examples is perfectly grammatical.

Thus, the availability or unavailability of an external

theta role seems to be the only factor in the contrast

between the b and the d examples. Now, a theory that

assumes infinitives to be VP's, rather than clauses, will

have to provide an explanation of this contrast only in

terms of the lexical properties of these verbs. An

explanation in terms of the sentential structure in which

such verbs may be embedded is not available for such a

theory. A theory like Chierchia's (1984) will have to

assume that for some reason the semantic operation of

"nominalizing” a VP does not apply in these cases.

Here, it seems, a fairly plausible hypothesis suggests

itself as follows. The VP's in 55a and 56a do not have

an external theta role. In Chierchia's terms, these VP's

are not 1-place propositional functions (They are

therefore not propositional functions a t all) and can

322

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
therefore serve as input neither to the nominal i zing

function * * nor to its syntactic correlate [-Agr] . We

would therefore not expect to find infinitival forms of

these verbs.

This, however, turns out to be a wrong prediction as

the following examples show (compare with 55b and 56b

respectively) .

57 -a) amur lehimaser al ha-teuna

supposed to be reported about the accident

ba- radio

on the radio

"It is supposed to be reported about the accident

on the radio"

b) alul lehitbarer Se Dan xole

may become clear that Dan sick

"It may become clear that Dan is sick"

In these examples the infinitival clauses of 55b and 56b

are embedded under the (modal) raising predicates amur

(supposed to) and alul (may) respectively. T at amur and

alul function as raising predicates is attested by the

ungrammaticality of the following examples.

323

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
58-*a) amur ledaber ba- radio

supposed to speak on the radio

*b) alul levarer et ha-nose

may clarify OM the issue

Here the verbs embedded under amur and alul have an

external theta role to assign but a subject NP is

missing. As the examples in 57 show the requirement for

a subject couldn *t originate from the predicates amur and

alul themselves.

Now, in view of the grammaticality of 57a, b the

syntactic/morphological operation performed by

Chierchia's infinitival [-Agr] morpheme certainly applies

to the verbs hitbarer (become clear) and nimsar (be

reported). Thus, Chierchia's approach can provide no

explanation for the contrast between 57a, b on the one

hand and the b examples in 55 and 56 on the other. On

the other hand, given the sentential approach to

infinitives adopted here, a fairly simple explanation is

available, namely, an explanation in terms of the

restrictions on the distribution of an expletive pro.

Thus, the minimal difference between 57a, b, on the one

hand, and 55b and 56b, on the other, is that in 57a, b the

matrix subject position is assigned nominative Case and

therefore an expletive pro is licensed in that position.

In 55b and 56b the subject of the embedded infinitive is

324

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
"Caseless" . Such an account is only available under a

clausal analysis of infinitives since in 57a, b it is the

higher subject position of the raising predicates which

makes the difference, rather than a (possible) lower

subject position of the infinitive.

Note that if the analysis of verbal gerunds suggested

here is correct, then it must be assumed that an

infinitival VP can function as a predicate. A verbal

gerund in this analysis involves an infinitival VP and an

obligatorily present subject NP. This, again, is in

conflict with Chierchia's (1984) approach to infinitives

as individual projections of propositional functions.

However, the view of infinitives as individual

correlates of propositional functions seems to run

independently into some problems. Consider the following

example .

59- The president is to cross the street tomorrow

morning

Here it seems as though the infinitival "to cross the

street..." is predicated of the subject rather than

being "referentially identified" with it. Chierchia

(1984) associates the copula be with the

"predicativizing" function ' ’ , the reflex of the

nominalizing function '. It is not obvious, however,

325

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
that it is the operation of this function which is

involved in the interpretation of 59. If that was the

case then the same would be expected to apply in the


8
following example .

60- The problem is to cross the street

It is clear, however, that the problem in this example is

not interpreted in such a way that cross the street is

predicated of it. Note also that in this example the

problem is clearly a (both underlying and surface)

subject. This is shown by the fact that it can undergo

Subject-Aux Inversion as follows,

61- is the problem (really) to cross the street?

Under a sentential analysis of infinitives these

contrasts receive a simple account. Assuming that the

copula be functions as some sort of "raising" predicate

(it may either be the head of a VP or else be dominated

by I , the choice here is not important for the present

issue) , 59 above can be analyzed as involving a post-

copul ar IP (62a below) whereas 60 may be assumed to

involve a post-copular CP (62b below) .

326

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
62- a) IP

/ \
NPi I ’i
the / \
president I VPi

/ \
V IPi
is / \
NP I '' i

1 / \
et I VPi

1 1
to cross the
str e et

327

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
b) IP

/ \

NPi I*i

the / \

problem I VPi

/ \

V CPi

I / \

is COMP IPj

Ri ,Rj / \

NP l'j

I / \

ej I VPj

I / \

to Vj NP

I I

cross the

street

In 62b above it is the external theta role o£ CP which is

assigned to the subject NP rather than the external theta


9
role of a lower verb as is the case in 62a . It seems

that a VP approach to infinitives such as the one

developed in Chierchia (1984) is incapable of making the

distinction which is reflected by these two structures.

328

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
4.3 Nominal Gerunds

4.3.1 Introduction

Unlike verbal gerunds, nominal gerunds are NP's and

have the regular distribution of NP's. Accordingly, the

account to be proposed in this section will involve a

nominalization-type of structure in which a nominal bound

morpheme, GER, which is assumed to be the underlying head

of the construction, governs a VP. The derivational

operations assumed will be similar to the ones proposed

for Action Nominalization constructions. The

differences between the two constructions and the set of

properties characteristic of the nominal gerund will be

shown to follow from one single assumption about the

nature of GER. We may first, however, proceed to a

detailed presentation of the facts.

The following examples show a nominal gerund as

subject, direct object, indirect object and as a member

of a bound genitive construction respectively.

63- a) Suv —o Sei ha-diktator garam le-behala

return-his Sei the dictator caused to panic

"The return of the dictator caused panic"

329

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
b) irgan -nu et Suv ha-poalim la-avoda

organized-we OM return the workers to work

"we organized the return of the workers to work"

c) ha-bxirot samu kec le heyote-nu miut

the elections put an end to being -us a minority

"The elections put an end to our being a minority"

d) uvdat headr -o Sel ha-nasi garma le

fact absence-his Sei the president caused to

behala

panic

"The fact of the president's absence caused panic"

In view of these distributional facts, i t is clear that

the structural analysis to be assigned to the nominal

gerund must be radically different from the one assigned

to the verbal gerund in which no head noun is assumed.

The probably most intriguing fact about the nominal

gerund concerns the kind of verbs of which the gerundive

form may occur in it. As was mentioned earlier, the

class of these verbs is rather limited and includes some

13 to 15 verbs in all. The following is a sample of some

of the verbs which are most typical of this construction,

in their gerundive form.

330

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
64- bo "coming"

Suv "return"

cet "leaving"

header "being absent"

healem "dis appearing "

himace "being present

heyot "being"

It is fairly clear from this sample that the property

common to these verbs has nothing to do with any

phonological or morphological characteristics. Rather,

as the results of linguistic research in recent years

have shown, verbs similar in meaning to those listed in

64 seem to be grouped together with respect to various

syntactic processes in a large number of different and

completely unrelated languages and have become known as

ergative (or unaccusative) verbs. Such verbs are

assumed to be lexically specified as having only an

internal argument and no external theta-role to assign.

In the following, I will assume that the class of verbs

which may occur in the nominal gerund construction in

Hebrew is exactly the class of ergative verbs in this

language. Thus, the main task of the analysis will be to

show what i t is about the nominal gerund which allows

only ergative verbs to occur in it. This will be shown

to correlate with a certain number of other

331

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
characteristic properties of the construction. In what

follows I will first enumerate the properties that seem

to be relevant, classifying them as either

characteristically nominal or verbal. I will then

proceed to a presentation of an analysis.

4.3.2 Nominal Properties of Nominal Gerunds

Among the nominal properties of the nominal gerund

the most important one has already been pointed out,

namely, its NP-like distribution as demonstrated in 63.

Next, unlike verbal gerunds, a nominal gerund

construction allows the occurrence of a Sei phrase as in

the following examples.

65- a) Suv -o Sei Dan

return-his Sei Dan

"The return of Dan"

b) headr -o Sei ha-nasi

absence-his Sei the president

"The president's absence”

If a nominal gerund is headed by a noun, as it is most

plausible to assume in view of the distributional facts,

then it is also plausible to assume that in examples

332

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
such as the following, the (logical) subject is assigned

genitive Case, that is, it is in the bound genitive

construction with the head noun.

66- a) Suv ha-poalim la-avoda

return the workers to work

"The return of the workers to work"

b) header ha-talmidim me ha-kita

absence the students from the class

"The absence of the students from class"

The examples in 65, on the other hand, are instances of

the double genitive construction. In such a

construction, the clitic pronoun attached to the head

may be said to be in the bound genitive construction with

it. In the analysis of double genitives suggested in

chapter 2, the Sel-phrase is assumed to be related to the

pronoun by a certain mechanism available at the level of

LF rather than being directly related to the head noun.

Given the availability of bound and double genitives in

nominal gerunds, one might expect to find also instances

of the free genitive in this construction. Here,

however, a rather interesting gap is revealed. As the

examples below show, the free genitive is impossible in

the nominal gerund.

333

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
67- *a) ha-Suv Sel ha-poalim la-avoda

the return Sel the workers to work

*b) ha-header Sei ha-talmidim me ha-kita

the absence Sei the students from the class

The analysis to be presented soon will provide a natural

explanation for this gap.

Finally, unlike the verbal gerund, a nominal

gerundive head may be modified by an adjective as in the

following examples.

68- a) Suve-nu ha-mukdam la-avoda

return-our the early to work

"Our early return to work"

b) headr -o ha-maftia Sei ha-nasi

absence-his the surprising Sei the president

"The president's surprising absence"

4.3.3 Verbal Properties of Nominal Gerunds

Here, two main facts are to be mentioned. First,

the head of a nominal gerund may never appear on its own.

It must always be accompanied by a subject.

334

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
69- *a) ha-Suv la-avoda

the return to work

*b) ha-cet me ha-kita

the leaving from the class

I assume that this property may count as "verbal" since

it is most likely related to the lexical requirements

which may be attributed to the related verb. Thus, the

deverbal nouns corresponding to the gerundive forms above

may appear unaccompanied by a subject.

70- a) ha-Siva la-avoda

the return to work

b) ha-yecia me ha-kita

the leaving from the class

"The leaving of the class"

Here, the lexical requirements of the related verb are

not a t work, presumably, because the nouns Siva (return)

and yeci'a (leaving, departure) may be lexically derived

and thereby lose the complementation requirements of the

corresponding verb.

One last relevant fact to be reported concerns the

occurrence of adverbs. As the following examples show,

adverbs are perfectly admissible in nominal gerunds.

335

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
71- a) cet -am Sel ha-poalim be-hekdem

leaving-their Sel the workers early

"The workers leaving (departing) early"

b) Suv —o Sei ha-nasi im redet ha-

return-his Sei the president with fall the

xaSexa

darkness

"The return of the president with the fall of

darkness"

71b shows a verbal gerund figuring as an adverb in a

nominal gerundive construction. In fact, it is possible

for both an adverb and an adjective to occur in a nominal

gerund.

72- a) cet -am ha-muskam Sei ha-poalim

leaving-their the agreed upon Sei the workers

be-hekdem

early

"The worker's agreed upon early leaving (departure)"

b) Suv -o ha-maftia Sei ha-nasi

return-his the surprising Sei the president

im redet ha-xaSexa

with fall the darkness

"The president's surprising return with the fall of

darkness”

336

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Examples such as 72 a,b may sound a little overburdened

but they are certainly possible. Most crucially, if an

adverb and an adjective are ever to cooccur in a nominal

gerund, the adjective must precede the adverb.

73- a) Suve-nu ha-maftia

return-our the surprising

"Our surprising return"

a) Suve-nu im redet ha-xaSexa

return-our with fall the darkness

"Our return with the fall of darkness”

c) Suve-nu ha-maftia im redet ha-xaSexa

return-our the surprising with fall the darkness

"Our surprising return with the fall of darkness"

*d) Suve-nu im redet ha-xaSexa ha-maftia

return-our with fall the darkness the surprising

Thus, the distribution of adjectives and adverbs is most

likely conditioned by the syntactic configuration

underlying this construction, and the analysis to be

outlined in the following section will attempt to provide

an account for it.

We may, at this point, summarize the facts reported

in this and the last section as in the following table.

337

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
74- A- Nominal Properties

i) NP-like Distribution

ii) The occurrence of adjectives

iii) The admissibility of Sel-phrases

(but the impossibility of Free Genitives)

B- Verbal Properties

i ) Obligatoriness of an argument

ii) The admissibility of adverbs

4.3.4 The Structure of Nominal Gerunds

The proposed underlying structure of a nominal

gerund, as alluded to previously, is the following.

75- NP

/ \

N'

/ \

N VP

I / \

GER V NP

In this configuration the bound morpheme GER is the head,

which subcategorizes for a VP. This configuration is in

338

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
fact identical to the one underlying Action

Nominalization constructions and the only difference

between the two is in the element occupying the head

position in each. It therefore must be the case, if our

approach is correct, that the differences between the two

constructions are derived from the different properties

that may be attributed to NOM and GER respectively. NOM

was characterized as a head noun having an external

theta-role R and an internal theta role R to which a

genitive NP may be related in the identificatory

relation.

76- Argument structure of NOM: (Ri ,Rj )

It was assumed that the internal theta role of NOM is

assigned the external theta-role of the VP governed by

it. This is what it means for NOM to inherit the

external theta-role of VP. The internal R-role of NOM

may be further linked with the referential theta-role of

a genitive NP, the result of this linking being that the

genitive NP is interpreted as the subject of VP.

339

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
77- DP

/ \

D NP

I / \

POSS NP N*

I / \

Dan N VPj

Rj I / \

NOM V NPk

Ri,Rj I |

eat the

2,k apple

The assumption made here with respect to GER is simply

that it has no internal R-role and is therefore incapable

of being assigned the external theta-role of the VP

governed by it. Consequently, it is also incapable of

"transmitting" that theta-role to an NP occupying the

specifier position of the construction. The lexical

representation of GER is thus simply the following.

78- a) Argument structure of GER: (Ri , )

b) Subcategorization frame of GER: [ VP]

Being a noun, GER has its own external referential theta-

340

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
role which allows it and the configuration of which it is

the head to occupy argument positions in a sentence.

Let us now look at the thematic structure of a

nominal gerund.

79- DP

/ \

NPi

/ \

N'i

/ \

Ni VP

I / \

GER Vj NPj

Ri

In this configuration, the external theta-role of GER is

vertically assigned, first to the dominating N* and then

to NP. An NP governed by the verb may be assigned the

internal theta-role of that verb. If the verb heading

the VP in 79 had an external theta-role, that theta-role

would be vertically assigned to VP. At this point,

however, it wouldn't be possible for this theta-role to

be assigned to GER, given the argument structure of GER,

in particular, its lack of an internal R-role.

Consequently, GER cannot serve as a mediator for theta-

341

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
role assignment between VP and an NP occupying its

specifier position. On the other hand, i t would also be

impossible for the external theta-role of VP to be

vertically assigned to N* and consequently to an NP in

the specifier position. This is because N’ already has

an external theta-role, namely, the referential argument

of GER. Thus, there is no way in which an external

theta-role of VP may be satisfied in a configuration such

as 79. It follows that the only verbs that may occur in

such a configuration are those which have only an

internal theta-role to assign and no external theta-

role. The occurrence of a non-ergative verb in this

construction will always result in ungrammaticality due

to an impossibility to satisfy a theta role.

The derivational stages following the underlying

structure in 79 consist, first, of a head movement of the

verb to GER, followed by a movement of NP to SPEC in

which position it may be assigned genitive case in the

manner usual for bound genitives .

342

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
80 DP

D NP

POSS N*

N VP

N NP

GER

b) DP

D NP

POSS NP N

N VP

GER

343

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
c) DP

/ \

D NP

/ \ / \

N D NP N'

/ \ 1 / \

V N POSS N VP

1 1 / \

GER e V e
1
I

Given , this analysis, all of the facts described in

the two preceding sections and summarized in 74 can be

directly accounted for.

Beginning with the properties classified as nominal,

the distributional properties of nominal gerunds are

explained on the basis of the argument structure of GER

and the fact that it functions as the head of NP. The

occurrence of adjectives in nominal gerunds is clearly

natural within this analysis.

The most interesting among the "nominal" properties

of nominal gerunds are the facts concerning genitive

relations between the head noun and the subject NP. As

illustrated in 80 above, an NP moved to the specifier

position may be in the bound genitive construction with

344

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
the head. This is, in fact, the only way for the

internal-* argument-NP to be assigned Case since none of

the verbs occurring in this construction is a "Case-

assigner". However, if that NP happens to be a pronoun

(81a) , then it may be "doubled" by an NP in a Sel-phrase

(81b). In this the properties of GER play no role. The

Sel-NP, in this case, is licensed by being related to the

pronoun, which is assigned a theta-role independently.

This way of being licensed is, however, not available for

the Sel-NP in 81c. In the absence of a pronoun, the only

way for it to be integrated into the structure would be

by being related to a thematic index in the argument

structure of the head noun. But this, in the case of GER

(and unlike the situation in Action Nominalisations) is

not available.

81- a) Suv-o

return-his

"his return"

b) Suv-o Sei Dan

return-his Sei Dan

"Dan's return"

*c) ha-Suv Sei Dan

the return Sei Dan

Let us look at 81c more closely. Given that a Sel-phrase

345

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
is adjoined to a nominal projection, presumably N* , it

cannot occupy an argument position in VP but must be

situated outside of i t . Thus, "the closest" that 81c

could get to a grammatical configuration would be

something like the following,

82- NP

/ \
the N’

/ \
N' VPt

/ \ / \
N Sel NP Vi NPi

/ \ Il I
V N Dan e e

I
GER

In 8 2 the only theta-role of the verb is assigned

internally to the object position which is, presumably,

occupied by a trace. Given that a trace cannot satisfy a

theta-role, the theta-role is vertically assigned to VP

from which it would be assigned to an argument in the

argument structure of the head noun. A Sei- phrase would

have its referential theta-role "linked" (coindexed) to

this argument and in this way end up being coindexed with

346

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
the theta-role originating from VP. In this way it would

be licensed as an argument. However, since GER has no

internal (R-) argument, none of this is possible and the

structure is ruled out. Thus, 81c is doubly ruled out as

a case in which a theta-role of the verb cannot be

satisfied and in which a Sel-phrase cannot be licensed as

an argument.

As to the "verbal" properties listed under B in 74,

the obligatoriness of an argument follows from the

present analysis since the lexical requirements of the

verb, figuring in the underlying structure of a nominal

gerund, must be satisfied.

Equally to be expected on the basis of this analysis

is the admissibility of adverbs, in particular, the

respective distribution of adverbs and adjectives

demonstrated in 71-73.

To conclude, the discussion in this section has

demonstrated, I believe, that the properties of the

nominal gerund may be given a fairly exhaustive

explanation on the basis of certain general assumptions

about the nature and distribution of theta-roles,

augmented by certain assumptions about the syntax, and,

in particular, the argument structure of a certain class

of nominal bound morphemes, the morpheme relevant for

this case being GER.

347

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Footnotes to Chapter IV

cf . Gesenius ' Hebrew Grammar

2
Berman (1978) notes some isolated cases of
phonological differences between infinitives and gerunds
for which I have no explanation. Thus, certain
consonants in certain verbal roots undergo spirantization
in the gerundive but not in the infinitival form, for
example :
Inf. - liSbor (to break) Ger. - bi-Svor
Inf. - lispor (to count) Ger. - bi-sfor

3
It is plausible that, as argued in Hazout (1989) , the
infinitival clause in 14 does not occupy the subject
position but is rather related, in some way or another,
to the pronoun Ze occupying that position. This, however,
does not affect the distinction made here between
infinitives and verbal gerunds. The infinitive in this
case is still an argument and is interpreted as the
"semantic** subject of the clause.

4
The fact that I+V (or V+I, the order is irrelevant)
adjoins to the right rather than to the left of P may be
taken care of in a simple manner by assuming that P is
lexically subcategorized for an element to its right,
that is, P is a prefix for the purpose of word formation
operations applying in the syntax.

This was pointed out to me by Edwin williams.

* Note that this discussion presupposes the assumption


about the non-existence of PRO. But, clearly, even if
one were to assume the availability of PRO, it would
still be excluded from the subject position of 47 since
this position is governed by the preposition in COMP.

348

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
7
One issue not touched upon in this analysis concerns
the possibility of negation in verbal gerunds. Negation
in the verbal gerund, as opposed to infinitives, is
impossible.

i) XaSuv lo lirot et ha-seret


important not to see OM the film
"It is important not to see the film"
*ii) be- lo reot Dan et ha-seret
with not seeing Dan OM the film
*iii) be- reot lo Dan et ha-seret
with seeing not Dan OM the film

It seems that the analysis proposed here makes possible a


simple account of this fact, and of the observed
differences between infinitives and the verbal gerund, in
terms of the movement operation which the derivation of
the verbal gerund is assumed to involve. This would
follow if we assume that the (verbal) negation particle
lo (not) heads its own maximal projection
Neg-P. Given this assumption, the following would be the
structure of a verbal Gerund following the movement of V
to I (irrelevant details are omitted) .

iv) CP
/ \
P Neg-P
/ \
Neg IP
I / \
lo I’
I \
I VP
/ \
V I

We may say that the head of Neg-P in this configuration


selects IP. It follows that movement of the derived head
V+I to P would result in a violation of the ECP. In the
following configuration Neg-P is a barrier between the
moved head and its trace.

349

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
v) CP
/ \
P Neg-P
/ \ / \
P Ii Neg IP
/ \ I / \
V I lo I’
/ \
I VP
I
et

Such a situation does not arise in the derivation of


infinitival clauses since no further movement from I to C
takes place in such cases.

* Williams (1983a) suggests that some types of copula


constructions involve a reversal of order between subject
and predicate, so that a surface subject is in fact an
underlying predicate. Subject-Aux inversion is one of
the tests used by Williams (1983a) to establish the
status of a constituent as a subject. Of-course, it is
crucial for the present argument that the problem in 60
is a subject rather than a predicate, but it seems to me
that the Subject-Aux-Inversion test is not so
absolutely crucial since one finds also examples such as
the following.

(i) a) to know John is to love him


b) to love is to rejoice

Here both subject and predicate are infinitives so the


question of reversal of order becomes irrelevant since
one of the two infinitives must be the "deep" predicate.
Assuming, for instance, that the surface predicate in
(i)a to love him is also the underlying one, it is clear
that the theta role assigned to the subject is not the
external theta role of love. Under the analysis proposed
here it would be the external theta role of CP, a
possibility which is not available to Chierchia (1984).

9
As pointed out to me by R. Higgins, cases which
involve an "identif icational” type of interpretation can
have a complementizer for or indirect questions of
various sorts as in the two following examples
respectively .

350

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
i) The problem is for you to cross the street in five
seconds
ii) The problem is what to do with John

On the other hand, the presence of a complementizer is


never possible with a raising type of interpretation.
These facts clearly support the claim that the two types
of interpretation involve two different structures.

351

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
CHAPTER 5

THE SYNTAX OF PARTICIPIAL CONSTRUCTIONS

5.1 Introduction

5.1.1 An overview

Hebrew and Arabic, like many other languages,

manifest an extremely large variety of participial

constructions. By this we mean constructions in which

the participial (Benoni in Hebrew) form of the verb

occurs as what seems to be the head of these

constructions. The situation here is similar to the one

observed in the previous chapter with respect to Hebrew

infinitival and gerundive constructions. It is the

same morphological form, a certain combination of verb

root and vowel pattern, which occurs in a vast array of

constructions, ranging over different category types

(nominal, verbal and adjectival) in both their function

and distribution.

The mixed nature of Benoni participles is manifest

at both the lexical and the phrasal levels. Thus, one

finds both in Hebrew and in Arabic participial forms that

352

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
have been lexicalized as nouns as well as forms which

have been lexicalized as adjectives.

To start with, Benoni agent nouns such as the nouns

occurring in the following examples are fairly common.

1- a) (H) ha-menahel siyem et avodat-o

the director finished OM work-his

"The director finished his work"

b) ( A ) ra?ay-tu 1-kaatib-a fi- 1-maktabat-i

saw -I the writer-Acc in-the-library -Dat

"I saw the writer in the library"

Unlike participial forms which occur in phrasal

structures, such nominal forms lose the "verbal force" of

the related verb, that is, mainly, complementation

requirements associated with a particular verb.

The same is true with respect to Benoni adjectives.

Thus, the adjectival Benoni forms in the following

examples are related to the strictly transitive verbs

Samala (include) and saxaf (sweep away) respectively.

2- a) ( A ) maSruu9 Saamil

project inclusive

"An inclusive project"

353

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
b) (H) had axa soxefet

success sweeping

"A sweeping success"

Obviously, Benoni forms can occur as "strict" verbs

at the head position of a VP in sentential structures

such as the following.

3- a) (H) Dan ohev et acmo

Dan likes OM himself

b) (A) zaid-un ?aakilu ttufaaHat-a

Zaid-Nom eating the apple-Acc

"Zaid is eating the apple"

Moving on to participial constructions at the

phrasal level, section 2 of this chapter will present a

discussion of a nominal construction to be referred to as

Agent Nominalization in which a Benoni form seems to

figure as head. The Benoni head of this construction,

although acting as a noun in that it relates to its

complement in the bound form of genitive construal and in

allowing the occurrence of an adjective, still preserves

some of its verbal force as attested by the fact that its

complement is obligatory and that the occurrence of an

adverb is permitted.

Finally, section 3 of this chapter will be concerned

354

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
with another type of participial construction, the Benoni

Relative, a construction which in its use and

distribution may be either adjectival or nominal. In its

internal structure, however, the Benoni Relative may be

said to be "more verbal" than the Agent Nominalization

construction since the object of a verb in this

construction is assigned accusative Case rather than

being in the bound genitive configuration with it.

Thus, the picture that emerges while observing the

variety of participial forms and constructions is quite

perplexing. Nevertheless, there is a clear sense in

which the forms and constructions just mentioned are felt

to be related and it is again a question whether it is

possible to provide a general account of participial

constructions which would reflect this basic intuition.

As stated above, it is clear why this vast range of

phenomena is felt to belong together, namely, it is the

same morphological form, the same combination of

consonantal root and vowel pattern, which occurs in all

these forms. As just observed, identical lexical forms

of different categorial identity seem to exist side by

side. It would therefore seem reasonable to assume that

such forms are separately listed in the lexicon with

their distinct categorial identities. This may be

assumed to be the case with the Hebrew menahel

(directing, Verb) and menahel (director, Noun) , as well

355

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
as the Arabie Saamil (including, Verb) and Saamil

(including, Adjective) . It is therefore also reasonable

to assume that the two morphological components of a

Benoni form, namely, a verb form (which is itself the

combination of a verb root and a Binyan pattern) and the

(discontinuous) affix of the Benoni are also available as

separate entities in the lexicon. We have already seen

that such an assumption must be made in some other cases.

One such case was discussed in chapter 3 (section

3. 2. 2. 3) in which it was demonstrated that there are

strong reasons to assume that the underlying morpheme

CAUSE as well as the entire range of verb forms are

independently available in deep structures of the

double Accusative variant of causative constructions. We

may therefore make the further step with respect to

Benoni forms of assuming that the lexical entity

represented by the af fixai form of the Benoni, the

present participle, is multiply listed in the lexicon as

either nominal, adjectival or verbal (INFLectional) .

A lexically listed form of a certain categorial type

may be assumed to have certain lexical properties typical

of the particular syntactic category of which it is a

member. For example, we may assume that a nominal bound

morpheme to which we will refer by the designation B

(from Benoni) has an argument structure of the type

generally assumed to be associated with nominal heads

356

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
and, in particular, nominal bound morphemes such as the

ones studied in the two previous chapters, namely, NOM

and GER. Equally, a participial bound morpheme,

identical in form, of adjectival type may also be assumed

to be available as the underlying head of certain

adjectival constructions.

Our strategy then will be to analyze a participial

form into its two morphological components and to allow

one of them, namely, the bound morpheme referred to here

as B , to assume different categorial identities and to

occur as head in different underlying configurations.

Such an approach would have a clear advantage in that i t

does not multiply the number of basic category types that

are generally assumed to exist. Rather, as will be seen

in the following sections, it attempts to explain the

mixed nature of participial constructions only on the

basis of some assumptions regarding the existence of

certain abstract elements and the underlying

configurations in which they may occur. This, in

addition to certain derivational strategies that are

available within the general theory of grammar, will make

it possible for us to explain a fairly large array of

phenomena. It is this strategy which was employed in our

analysis of Action Nominalizations and gerundive

constructions .

Before going into a detailed analysis of nominal and

357

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
adjectival constructions involving the Benoni, I will

present in the next subsection a brief discussion of

participial forms in their verbal use in an attempt to

show that this use of the Benoni participle lies outside

the proper domain of verbal nouns with which this

dissertation is concerned.

5.1.2 Participles As Verbs

The so far most thoroughly studied constructions

involving a verbal use of the present participle have

been present tense sentences such as the following (for

recent work on this cf. Doron (1983) and Rapoport (1987)

on Hebrew and Mushaweh (1986) on Arabic) .

4- a) (H) Dan ohev et Dina

Dan loves OM Dina

"Dan loves Dina"

b) (A) huwa daarib-un zayd-an

he beat -Norn Zayd-Acc

"He is beating Zayd"

The verbal characteristics of the participial verb form

in the examples above include, first, its ability to mark

the NP object following it with Accusative Case. This is

358

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
seen in both the Hebrew and the Arabic examples above.

Another reason for viewin? the examples in 4 as involving

a verbal form is that the position occupied by the

participial form in these sentences can be occupied by a

tensed, past or future, verb form.

5- a) (H) Dan yohav et Dina

Dan will love OM Dina

"Dan will love Dina"

b) ( A ) huwa daraba zaid-an

he beat Zayd-Acc

"He beat Zayd"

A present participle verb form may certainly be modified

by an adverb.

6- a) (H) Dan oxel bananot maher

Dan eats bananas quickly

b) ( A ) huwa ?aakilu 1- xubz-a bi-sur9a

he eating the bread-Acc quickly

"He is eating the bread quickly"

One of the more intriguing questions concerning the

verb form in 4 has traditionally been the one concerning

its temporal specification. Thinking in terms of

temporal distinctions such as past, present and future,

359

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
the question may be raised as to whether a sentence such

as the following, or the INFL node which may be assumed

to figure in its underlying representation, is specified

as Present or is simply unspecified for tense.

7- (H> Dan oxel bananot

Dan eats/is eating bananas

A sentence like 7 may be interpreted as either describing

an action taking place at the moment of utterance, or

else receive a generic type of interpretation by which it

would be describing an activity habitually repeated over

a long period of time. This indeterminacy in temporal

interpretation may be better appreciated when one

observes cases in which a sentence such as 7 occurs as a

subordinated clause.

8- (H) Dina taxSov Se Dan oxel bananot

Dina will think that Dan eats/is eating bananas

Here, the activity described by "Dan eats/is eating

bananas" may be understood as taking place at either the

future time of the higher clause or at the present

moment, that is, the moment of utterance, or simply

generically as a habitually repeated activity. This

seems to provide simple but fairly solid support in

360

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
favour of a claim (cf. Doron (1983) and Rapoport (1987))

that so called present tense sentences are in fact not

specified for tense. It is simply not clear what it

would mean to say that they are specified for tense given

that such a specification wouldn't seem to have any

effect on the interpretation of such sentences.

In the spirit of Doron (1983) and Rapoport (1987) we

may assume a classification of Hebrew (and Arabic)

clauses according to which the INFL node in present tense

sentences of the type in 7 is specified as having

AGR(eement) features but as lacking specification for

tense (which may be represented as [0 TENSE]). This, as

opposed to infinitival clauses of which the INFL node

lacks AGR(eement) features and is specified as [- TENSE]

and tensed, past and future, sentences of which the INFL

node has both AGR(eement) features as well as

specification as [+ TENSE] (with possibly a further

specification as [+/- PAST] or something of this sort) .

It is in this respect, that is, their lack of tense

specification, that present tense sentences are felt to

be more "nominal" than their past or future counterparts.

There is however a clear and strong difference between

sentences of the type in 7 and sentences involving a

strictly nominal form of the present participle. Such a

difference may be expressed in terms of aspectual

361

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
distinctions such as completion or non-completion of an

action. The following pair illustrates this point.

9- a) (A) Zayd-un kaatib-u 1-kitaab-i

Zayd-Nom writer-Nom the book -Gen

"Zayd is the writer of the book"

b) (A) Zayd kaatib-u 1-kitaab-a

Zayd writing-Nom the book -Acc

"Zayd is writing the book"

In 9a it is predicated of Zayd that he is "the writer of

the book”. In this case the participial form is a noun

and kitaab (book) is in the genitive Case. The only

available interpretation in this case is one in which the

action of writing the book has been completed. 9b

differs in its surface form from 9a only in the Case

marking of kitaab (book), accusative in this case.

However, the interpretation of 9b must be such that the

book is understood as being still in the process of

writing.

Thus, there is a clear difference between nominal

and verbal uses of the present participle in both their

syntax and interpretation and it is therefore perfectly

justified to assume the existence of a participial form

which is strictly verbal in category. As noted above,

the analysis of "present tense" sentences has enjoyed

362

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
much attention in recent years. This includes both

sentences of the type exemplified in 4 and 7 above as

well as sentences involving non-verbal predication.

However, in view of the above observations, this use of

the present participle lies outside the proper domain of

verbal nouns and therefore no further discussion of i t

will be undertaken in this chapter.

5.2 Agent Nominalizations

As was noted earlier, certain participial forms are

lexically listed as nouns. This is the case with agent

nouns such as Somer (guard) and menahel (director) in

Hebrew and kaatib (writer) and muttarjim (translator) in

Arabic. These nominal forms can clearly occur in a

sentence unaccompanied by any arguments that would

normally be required by the related verb.

10- a) (H) ha-Somrim sagru et ha-knisa

the guards closed OM the entrance

b) (H) ha-menahel lo hegia

the director not arrived

"The director didn't arrive”

363

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
11- a) ( A ) raja9a 1-kaatib-u min bayruut

returned the writer-Nom from Beirut

"The writer returned from Beirut"

b) ( A ) qutila 1-muttargim -u

was killed the translator-Nom

"The translator was killed"

Given our claim that such forms are lexically listed as

nouns rather than derived by some general syntactic

process, we might expect to find verbs for which a

lexically listed nominal form is missing. This

expectation is clearly borne out. Thus, the Hebrew verbs

Savar (break) , nasa (carry) or heenik (give) simply lack

an agent nominal counterpart. These missing nominal

forms would be the ones appearing in the following

ungrammatical examples.

12- *a) (H) rai-nu et ha-Sover

saw -we OM the breaker

*b) (H) Dan nifgaS im ha-nose

Dan met with the carrier

*c) (H) ha-maanik lo hegia la- pgiSa

the giver not arrived to the meeting

The same situation obtains in Arabic. Thus, the verbs

kassara (break) , ajjala (postpone) and ?akala (eat) lack

364

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
a nominal counterpart of which the predicted form would

be the one appearing in the following ungrammatical

examples .

13- *a) (A) ra?ay-na 1-mukassir-a

saw- we the breaker -Acc

*b) (A) daxala l-mu?ajjil -u ba9da

entered the ’'postponer"-Nom after

1-muHaadarat-i

the lecture -Dat

*c) ( A ) jalasa l-?aakil-u fi l-mat9am

set the eater-Nom in the restaurant

It might therefore come as a surprise that participial

forms such as the ones appearing in 12,13 may occur as

head nouns as, for example, in the subject NP's of the

following sentences.

14- a) (H) Sovre ha-xalon barxu

breakers the window ran away

"The breakers of the window ran away"

b) (H) nos?e ha-alunka avdu ba- derex

carriers the stretcher got lost on the way

"The carriers of the stretcher got lost on the way"

365

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
c) (H) maanike ha-trumot hegi-u la- kinus

givers the donations arrived to the meeting

"The givers of the donations arrived to the meeting"

15- a) ( A ) haraba mukassir-u SSubbaak-i

ran away breaker -Norn the window -Gen

"The person who broke the window ran away”

b) (A) ?insarafa mu?ajjil -u 1-muHaadarat-i

left "postponer"-Nom the lecture -Gen

"The person who postponed the lecture left"

c ) ( A ) jalasa ?aakil-u ttufaaHat-i fi

sat eater -Norn the apple-Gen in

l-mat9am -i

the restaurant-Dat

"The person who ate the apple sat in the restaurant"

The reason for this difference between 14,15 on the one

hand and 12,13 on the other seems to be fairly clear.

The ungrammatical cases in 12,13 are cases in which a

lexically required complement of the participial form is

missing. Such requirements are satisfied in 14,15 which

are therefore grammatical.

It is generally known that strict observance of

complementation requirements is a property more typical

of verbs than of nouns. In this sense we may at least

say that the participial noun forms in these examples

(14,15) preserve some of the verbal force of the related

366

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
verbs. This, obviously, does not exhaust the issue since

it is not clear what it would imply to say that these

nominal forms preserve, or inherit, some of the verbal

force of the related verb. Indeed, the question is

whether these verbal properties to which we are referring

loosely with the expression "verbal force" should be

attributed to the nouns themselves or, rather, to the

related verbs. Some support to the view that this

"verbal force" should be attributed to the related

"underlying" verbs rather than to the nouns themselves

comes from the fact that there are participial agent

nouns which are related to strictly (or strongly)

transitive verbs but which may appear unaccompanied by

any complement which would normally be required by the

corresponding verb. Thus, the verbs nihel (direct) ,

9allama (teach) and racax (murder) are all transitive as

shown by the following ungrammatical examples.

16-*a) (H) Dan nihel

Dan directed

*b) ( A ) 9 al lama muHammad

taught muhammed

*c) (H) ha-Soter racax

the policeman murdered

367

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
These should be compared with their grammatical

counterparts .

17-a) (H) Dan nihel et ha-yeSiva

Dan directed OM the meeting

b) ( A ) 9allama muHammad al-?awlaad-a ddars -a

taught muhammed the kids- Acc the lesson-Acc

"Muhammed taught the kids the lesson"

c ) (H) ha-Soter racax et ha-asir

the policeman murdered OM the prisoner

The agent nouns corresponding to the verbs in the

examples above do not seem to inherit the transitivity of

these verbs.

18- a) (H) ha-menahel hegia

the director arrived

b) ( A ) xaraja l-mu9allim-u mini 1-madrasat-i

went out the teacher -Norn from the school-Dat

"The teacher left the school"

c) (H) ha-roceax barax

the murderer escaped

If agent nouns are related to the corresponding verbs by

some general process, i t is hard to see why such a

process would affect only certain verbs in a certain way

368

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
to the exclusion of others. Thus, an attempt to

attribute a certain "verbal force" to the "transitive"

agent nouns of examples 12-15 will leave us without an

explanation for why in some cases a derived agent noun

may lose its "verbal force" whereas in other cases it

doesn't. It seems fairly reasonable to assume that the

"verbal force" manifested by the participial agent nouns

of examples 12-15 is indeed the verbal force, that is,

the complementation requirements that may be attributed

to the related verbs rather than to the noun itself.

This suggests that these constructions (14,15), to which

we will refer from now on as Agent Nominalizations,

involve an underlying verb and a certain derivational

process by which the surface nominal form of what seems

to function as the head of these constructions is

derived .

Another piece of evidence which seems to support

such a conclusion has to do with adverbial modification

in Agent Nominalization constructions. Di-Sciullo and

Williams (1987) (citing Tom Roeper) observe the following

English example.

19- The swimmer across the river

Their observation is that this example can only mean "the

swimmer who is across the river" parallel to "the man

369

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
across the river" . It cannot mean "the one who swims
1
across the river" . In Di-Sciullo and Williams' terms,

an adjunct modifier of a word cannot be interpreted as an

adjunct modifier of the non-head part of that word.

Thus, being the non-head of the morphologically complex

word swimmer , the verb swim is inaccessible to

modification. Consider now the following example of

Agent Nominalization in Hebrew.

20- (H) doxafe ha-sirot me-ever la- nahar

pushers the boats across to the river

In this example the most likely interpretation is "those

who push the boats across the river" rather than "the

pushers of the boats who are across the river". Here the

modifier seems to apply to the VP meaning "push the

boats". In particular, the modifier seems to have access

to the verb daxaf (push) which is the non-head part of

the noun doxef (pusher) . Thus, if the general rule is

that modifiers don't have access to non-head parts of

words then it must be concluded that the verb daxaf

(push) is available for modification as an independent

word at some syntactic level of representation. But this

necessarily implies that the word doxef (pusher) is in

these constructions the output of a syntactic, rather

than a morphological process. The fact that the noun

370

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
doxef (pusher) does not exist independently, that it may

only occur in an Agent Nominalisation construction

followed by a direct object, provides further support to

this conclusion.

We will, thus, assume that Agent Nominalisations are

derived from an underlying structure and in a

derivational manner similar to what was assumed for

Action Nominalisations and the Nominal Gerund which were

studied in previous chapters. Note that such an

assumption implies that the process involved in the

derivation of Agent Nominalisations is general and

should, in principle, apply to any verb. This seems to

be supported by the facts. As noted, among others, by

Berman (1978) with respect to Hebrew, all Benoni

(participial) forms can occur as head nouns of an Agent

Nominalisation construction. On the other hand, only a

small set of all Benoni forms may occur as independent

nouns .

Thus, lexically listed agent nouns are strict nouns

and therefore do not preserve the verbal force of the

related verb. Being lexically listed is, clearly, an

arbitrary property and there is no reason to expect such

a process to apply to all verbs. On the other hand, a

process such as nominalisation which applies to verbs

simply by virtue of being verbs is expected to be general

and this indeed seems to be the case. We are therefore

371

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
justified in assuming such a process and as will be seen

a bit later more evidence may be brought in favour of

this assumption, based on the analysis of Arabic

causative constructions developed in chapter 3.

We turn now to the actual analysis. We are assuming

that constructions such as 21-22 below, involve a

nominalization-type of underlying structure and

derivation.

21- a) (H) oxle basar

eaters meat

"meat eaters"

b) (H) noale sandalim

wearer sandals

"Those who wear sandals"

22- a) (A) daarib-u 1-walad-i

"beater "-Norn the boy -Gen

"The one who beat the boy"

b) ( A ) qaatil-u rrajul-i

killer-Nom the man-Gen

"The one who killed the man"

The configuration underlying 21,22 is the following,

372

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
23- DP

/ \

D NP

1 / \
POSS N*

/ \

N VP

1 / \

B V NP

23 is a typical Nominalization configuration in which a

nominal bound morpheme, B in this case, subcategorizes

for a VP. The surface form related to 23 is derived, just

like all other nominalization constructions studied so

far, in three successive steps. The first of these steps

is a head movement of the verb to B, resulting in the

following configuration in which the circled subtree is

the derived Benoni head noun.

373

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
24- DP

/ \
D NPi

I / \
POSS N*

/ \
N VP

Vt N NP 2

The following stages i n the derivation involve a movement

of the object NP to SPEC, a position in which it can be

assigned genitive Case and stand in the bound genitive

form with the head noun in the usual manner. NP2 in 24

above can not be assigned accusative Case. This is the

same phenomenon as observed for subjectless Action

Nominal! zat ions in Chapter 3, and it can be explained in

the same way as will be demonstrated below.

25 and 26 illustrate the two additional steps in the

derivation.

374

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
25- DP

/ \

D NP‘

1 / \

POSS NP2J N'

/ \

N VP

\ / \

Vi N V ej

1 1

B ei

26- DP

/ \

D NPi

/ \ / \

N D NP 2 N’

/ \ 1 / \

V N POSS N VP

1 1

B ei

It is now c l e a r t h a t , j u s t l i k e other n o m i n a l i z a t i o n

c o n s t r u c t i o n s , the main properties o f Agent

N o m i n a l i z a t i o n s may be explained m a i n l y on the b a s i s of

some assumptions concerning the p r o p e r t i e s o f the nominal

375

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
head B. This must be so given the identical underlying

structures and derivation assumed for all three

constructions. The most salient property of the Agent

Nominalization construction which distinguishes it from

both Action Nominalizations and Nominal Gerunds is that,

while these two are interpreted as referring to some

event (destruction, eating) or state (absence, being

somewhere) , an Agent Nominalization construction is

necessarily interpreted as referring to the agent of an

action, that is, the entity, or person, which would be

referred to by the subject of the corresponding sentence.

I assume that this is the main property of this

construction that needs to be accounted for. In fact, it

can be accounted for in a fairly simple fashion and at

the same time be correlated with other properties of the

construction to which we will turn later.

The lexical representation of B may be assumed to be

the following.

27 - a ) Argument structure of B: (Ri , Ri )

b) Subcategorization frame of B: [ VP]

Like any other noun and like NOM and GER, B is assumed to

have an external theta-role R , associated with an index

(i) . Moreover, like NOM and unlike GER, B has an

internal R-role. However, unlike NOM, in the case of B

376

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
the two R roles are coindexed. The thematic structure of

an Agent Nominalisation construction may thus be

illustrated as follows (ignoring the dominating DP node) .

28- NPi

/ \

N’t

/ \

Nt VPt

I / \

B V NP

Ri ,Ri i,k

In the above configuration the external theta-role R is

assigned vertically to N* and then to the maximal

projection NP. VP has an external theta-role which must

be satisfied and can only be satisfied. by being assigned

to the internal argument of B. This is so because it

cannot be vertically assigned to N* and become its

external theta-role since N* already has an external

theta-role. Given, now, that the two arguments in the

argument structure of B are coindexed, we achieve the

result that the NP as a whole is interpreted as referring

to the bearer of the external theta-role of VP. This

looks, and is certainly interpreted, as if the external

R-role is assigned the external theta-role of VP.

377

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Clearly, the NP (or DP) as a whole is assigned a theta-

role from the outside by virtue of occupying a certain

position in a sentential construction. But this does not

result in any ill-formedness since the two coindexed

arguments are represented separately. This is a natural

possibility given the kind of representations suggested

here.

This is then the analysis proposed here for the

Agent Nominalization construction. It clearly accounts

for the main observation concerning the interpretation of

this construction and as will be demonstrated soon it

also accounts for its other properties. However, before

going into these particular issues, let us return briefly

to one of the more general issues.

One of the main issues regarding the analysis of

Action Nominalization constructions was related to the

question concerning a syntactic as opposed to a

lexicalist approach to these constructions. The approach

adopted in this work may be characterized as a strongly

syntactic approach. One of the main arguments, probably

the strongest, developed in Chapter 3 in favour of a

syntactic approach was based on the analysis of

causative constructions in Arabic. As the analysis of

these constructions in Chapter 3 (section 3. 2. 2. 4)

demonstrated, the double accusative variant of causative

constructions involves a syntactic process of head

378

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
movement of which a causative verb form is the output.

The dative variant, on the other hand, was shown to

involve a lexically inserted causative verb which is the

output of a lexical process. The argument developed in

Chapter 3 was that, since Action Nominalization

constructions allow for both the double accusative as

well as the dative variant to occur, there is a strong

reason to believe that the option of a syntactic

derivation of the type suggested in this work is, in

principle, open.

Given the syntactic analysis suggested here for

Agent Nominalizations and the fact that these

constructions occur both in Hebrew and in Arabic, we

should expect to find causative Agent Nominalizations in

both their double accusative and their dative variants.

If this turned out to be the case then the syntactic

analysis just illustrated would receive a fairly strong

support. The following examples show that this is indeed

so.

29- a) ( A ) mudarris-u l-?awlaad-i ddars -a

teacher -Norn the kids -Gen the lesson-Acc

"The one who teaches the kids the lesson"

b) ( A ) mudarris-u ddars -i li- l-?awlaad-i

teacher -Norn the lesson-Gen to the kids-Dat

"The one who teaches the lesson to the kids"

379

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
30- a) ( A ) muSarrib -u l-?awlaad-i

"make drink-er"-Nom the kids -Gen

1- Haliib-a

the milk -Acc

"The one who makes the kids drink the milk"

b) ( A ) muSarrib -u 1-Haliib-i li-

"make drink-er"-Nom the milk -Gen to

1- ?awlaad-i

the kids -Dat

"The one who makes the kids drink the milk"

The a examples above show the double accusative variant.

In these examples it is only the second NP which shows

accusative Case marking. This is due to the absence of

an overt subject NP. We will see soon how this is

accounted for along the lines of the general account of

this phenomenon suggested in Chapter 3. Crucially, a

reversal of order between the two NP's is completely

impossible, under the same interpretation.

31-*a) (A) mudarris-u ddars -i l-?awlaad-a

teacher -Norn the lesson-Gen the kids -Acc

*b) (A) muSarrib -u 1-Haliib-i l-?awlaad-a

"make drink-er"-Nom the milk -Gen the kids-Acc

380

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
The same word order restriction holds of the

corresponding sentential constructions and is readily

explained if the underlying structure of the a examples

in 29,30 is assumed to be the same except, of course, to

the B morpheme governing the causative substructure in

the constructions examined here. The underlying

structure of a double accusative Agent Nominalization is

thus the following in which each one of the underlying

verbal heads, CAUSE and V , takes one of the two NP's as

its complement.

32- DP

/ \

D NP

I / \

POSS N'

/ \

N VP

I / I \

B V NP VP

11/ \

CAUSE the V NP

kids I I

drink the milk

learn the lesson

381

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
As was argued with respect to Action Nominalisations in

Chapter 3, a lexicalist approach to these constructions

would be unable to account for these facts since it can

provide no way to establish an asymmetry between the two

NP's. A reversal of order between the two NP’s is only

possible in the dative variant as in the b examples in

29,30.

Some remaining issues need to be touched upon in

order for our analysis to be complete. First, in view of

the underlying structure suggested here for Agent

Nominalizations , the one illustrated in 28, one might

wonder whether an NP could occur in the specifier

position of this configuration, in the way that this is

possible in active Action Nominalizations such as the

following (33). Clearly, the specifier position is

available for an NP to occur in both Action and Agent

Nominalizations .

33- (H) axilat Dan et ha-tapuax

eating Dan OM the apple

"Dan ' s eating the apple"

The corresponding Agent Nominalization which might look

as either of the examples below is clearly impossible.

It is important to appreciate that this is not obvious

since, as we know, at least in principle a Nominalization

382

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
type of structure does allow the possibility for two

genitive NP's to occur. But this is clearly impossible

as the following examples show.

34-*a) (H) oxel Dan et ha-tapuax

eater Dan OM the apple

*b) (A) mukassir-u zayd-en SSubbak -a

breaker -Norn zayd-Gen the window-Acc

*c) ( H ) oxel Dan Sei ha-tapuax

eater Dan Sei the apple

Clearly, a subject NP must be missing in order for the

structure to be grammatical.

35- a) (H) oxel ha-tapuax

eater the apple

"The eater of the apple"

b) ( A ) mukassir-u SSubbak -i

breaker -Norn the window-Gen

"The breaker of the window"

To see why the examples in 34 are impossible we may look

a t an underlying structure of an Agent Nominalization in

which the specifier position is occupied by an NP.

383

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
36- DP

/ \
D NP11

I / \
POSS NP2 N’ i

Ri / \
Ni VPi

I / \
BV NPa j
Ri , Ri i, j

In this configuration the external t h et a - r o le o f VP i s


assigned to the internal argument of B. Now, the only
way f o r NP2 to be thematically lic en se d wi thi n this
configuration would be by having its external R-role
coindexed with the internal argument o f B a s represented
in 3 6 . However, this brings about a s i tu a t io n i n which

NPi and NP2 share the same r e f e r e n t i a l index. That i s ,


i n a configuration like 3 6 , the NP a s a whole i s
dependent for it reference on an NP contained in i t .
This is a violation o f the ” i within i condition" (cf.

Chomsky ( 1 9 8 6 ) ) which prohibits the coindexation of a


phrase with a phrase that contains it ( *

i[....Xi ]). obviously, th is explanation relies on


our assumptions concerning the thematic structure of
these constructions. The f a c t that these assumptions

384

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
make possible such an explanation may be seen as

providing a strong support in favour of them.

These assumptions receive further support when it

comes to accounting for the facts concerning genitive

relations between the head noun and the complement NP in

Agent Nominalisations.

The examples given so far all involve cases in which the

head noun and the complement NP stand in the bound

genitive construction to each other. The question now is

whether the other types of genitive construal, the free

and the double genitive, which occur only in Hebrew, are

also possible.

Considering first the double genitive, we might say

that it is marginal but not totally excluded. Thus, the

following examples are clearly possible.

37- a) (H) nose-ha Sei gufat he-harug

carriers-her Sei body the dead

"The carriers of the dead body"

b) (H) horg-av Sei ha-nasi

killers-his Sei the-president

"The killers of the president"

c ) (H) oxle-ha Sei ha-uga

eaters-her Sei the cake

"The eaters of the cake"

385

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Crucially, the forms nose (carrier) , horeq (killer) and

oxel (eater) do not exist independently as agent nouns

and it is therefore clear that the examples in 37 involve

Agent Nominalizations rather then simple NP's. In many

cases, however, double genitive variants of Agent

Nominalizations are unacceptable and it is possible that

this has to do with the generic type of interpretation

associated with these constructions. Thus, unlike Action

Nominalizations and Nominal Gerunds which may refer to a

particular event, Agent Nominalizations are most

typically used to refer to an agent who is habitually

involved in a certain type of activity. It is possible

that this type of interpretation is incompatible with

the definiteness inherent to the meaning of pronouns. In

cases in which an agent may be construed as being part of

a particular, rather than generic, event the use of a

pronoun becomes possible as in the examples given in 37

above. The underlying structure of the examples in 37

would be the following.

386

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
37- DP
/ \
D NP
I / \
POSS N*
/ \
N VP
I / \
BV NP

Pronoun
The adjunction of a Sel-phrase at a l a t e r stage results
in the following configuration.
39- DP
/ \
D NP
I / \
POSS NP N'
I / \
Pronoun N’ VP
/ \ / \
N Sel NP V e
/ \ I
V N e
I
B

387

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
39 undergoes the additional movement operation generally

involved in the formation of bound genitives, as assumed

in this work. The NP in the Sel-phrase is not

thematically related to the morpheme B , but is rather

dependent on the pronoun for its licensing and

interpretation as is generally the case for clitic

doubling in genitive constructions.

The picture seems to be much clearer when it comes

to free genitives. These are clearly impossible, as

demonstrated by the following pairs.

40- a) (H) nos?e ha-alunka

carriers the stretcher

"The carriers of the stretcher"

*b) (H) ha-nos?im Sei ha-alunka

the carriers Sei the stretcher

41- a) (H) horge ha-xayot

killers the animals

"The killers of the animals"

*b) (H) ha-horgim Sei ha-xayot

the killers Sei the animals

42- a) (H) oxle ha-uga

eaters the cake

"The eaters of the cake"

*b) ( H ) ha-oxlim Sei ha-uga

the eaters Sei the cake

388

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
These contrasts receive a simple explanation within the

theta-theoretic approach suggested here. To see this we

might look at what would be the underlying structure of

the b examples above (ignoring the irrelevant DP node) .

43- NPi

/ \

(the) N’t

/ \

N’ VPi

/ \ / \

N Sel NP V e

I R (k ) i,l

B (i)

Rt ,Ri

In the configuration above Sel NP is adjoined at the N*

level at a "later" stage in the derivation. A t this

stage, the external theta-role of VP is already assigned

to (coindexed with) the internal argument of B . The

internal theta-role of the verb (1) may only be assigned


»
to a trace in object position, since no lexical NP

occupies this position, and is therefore unsatisfied.

It cannot be assigned vertically to VP and become its

external theta-role since VP already has an external

theta-role. Thus, the internal theta-role of the verb

389

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
remains unsatisfied. Furthermore, the Sel NP could only

be thematically licensed by being coindexed with the

internal argument of B. But this, first, is not the

intended interpretation since in this way the Sel-NP ends

up being interpreted as a subject (external argument)

instead of an object (internal argument) . Secondly, this

results in an ill-formed representation for the same

reason pointed out for 36 above, namely, the Sel-phrase

ends up being co indexed with the higher NP node in

violation of the "i within i condition". Otherwise, the

Sel-NP must have a different index which would leave it

simply without a theta role.

It now remains to account for the fact concerning

the impossibility of accusative Case marking of a direct

object in these constructions. The following examples

are clearly impossible as NP's. (They are well formed as

VP's, but this is irrelevant).

44- *a) (H) nos? in et ha-alunka

carriers OM the stretcher

*b) (H) horgim et ha-xayot

killers OM the animals

*c) (H) oxi im et ha-uga

eaters OM the cake

45- *a) ( A ) mukassir--u SSubbak -a

breaker ■
-Norn the window-Acc

390

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
*b) (A) mu?ajjil-u 1-muHaadarat-a

"postponer"-Nom the lecture -Acc

*c) (A) ?aakil-u ttufaaHat-a

eater -Nom the apple-Acc

Here the same explanation seems to be available as the

one suggested in Chapter 3 for the same phenomenon

observed in subjectless Action Nominalizations. Thus, in

a configuration such as the one repeated below, the bound

morpheme B plays the same role as the morpheme NOM in the

cases studied in Chapter 3.

46- DP

/ \

D NPi

/ \

N't

/ \

Nt VPi

I / \

B V NP

Rt ,Ri i,k

B in this configuration is "nominal" in the sense of the

definition of this notion in 145 of Chapter 3, that is,

B, or rather, its internal R-role is assigned the

391

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
external theta-role of VP and in this way it functions as

an argument. Thus, in both this case and the case of

subjectless Action Nominalizations the bound morpheme

heading the construction fulfills the function of a

missing subject. Given that B in 46 is "nominal", the

assignment of accusative Case to the object NP is not

licensed and the only way for it to be assigned Case

would be by moving to the specifier position in which it

can receive Case in the manner usual for bound genitives.

To conclude, I believe to have shown in this section

that the general approach to nominalization constructions

developed in the two previous chapters makes possible a

straightforward and fairly exhaustive treatment of the

Agent Nominalization construction. As demonstrated, by

maintaining an identical structural analysis for Agent

Nominalizations as the one assumed for Action

Nominalizations and nominal gerunds, while making

minimal assumptions about the argument structure of the

abstract nominal element B, we were able to account for

virtually all of the relevant facts relating to the Agent

Nominalization construction.

392

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
5.3 Benoni (participial) Relatives

By the term Benoni Relative we are referring to

constructions such as the underlined parts of the

examples below.

47- a) (H) ha-ovrim al ha-xok yeanSu

the violating on the law will be punished

"Those who violate the law will be punished”

b) (H) ha-talmidim ha-mesaymim et avodat-am

the students the finishing OM work their

"The students who finish their work”

48- a) ( A ) akrahu al-mufuuna 9uhuud-a -hum

I hate thé keeping promises-Acc-their

"I hate those who keep their promises'*

b) ( A ) ttalamiith -u 1 kaatib-u 1-

the students-Nom the writing-Nom the

?imtiHaan-a

test “Acc

"The students who are writing the test"

The a examples above show a Benoni Relative in its NP-

like function. It may occupy argument positions such as

subject (47a) or object (48a). The b examples, on the

other hand, show a Benoni Relative in its adjectival

function. It is from this type of use of this

393

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
construction that the term Benoni Relative derives.

Indeed, the Benoni Relative in these cases appears in

the same function as a relative clause and its internal

structure seems to be, at least in some respects,

sentence-like. It is also for this reason that the

initial definite article (ha/al) in this construction was

felt by a number of authors (e.g. Berman 1978) to be some

sort of complementizer. However, as I will attempt to

show in this section, such an assumption is not

necessary and an analysis in which the initial element in

these constructions is taken to be a standard definite

article is fairly plausible. An analysis along these

lines seems to be possible, as will be argued, for the

Benoni Relative in both its adjectival and its NP-like

function. This double function will be irrelevant and

therefore ignored in most of the discussion. The

surface form of a Benoni Relative may be schematically

represented as follows ,

49- ( ha/al - Benoni form - X ]

In this representation X stands for anything which might

follow a verb in a regular sentential structure, in

particular, any complement that may be required by a

particular verb. The examples below show benoni forms

followed by a direct object, an infinitival complement

394

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
and a prepositional complement respectively. 50a shows

also a post-verbal adverb.

50- a) (A) al-?akiluuna ta9aam-a l-?axariin

the eating food -Acc the others-Gen

daaiman

always

"Those who always eat the food of others"

b) (H) ha-mesarvim le-hibaxen

the refusing to be tested

"Those who refuse to be tested"

c ) (H) ha-mitanyenim ba -nose

the interested in the-topic

"Those who are interested in the topic”

In its interpretation, a structure such as 49 is similar

to that of Agent Nominalizations in that the construction

as a whole is interpreted as referring to the entity

which would be denoted by the subject of the

corresponding sentence. One clear difference between

this construction and the Agent Nominalization

construction is demonstrated by example 50a, namely, it

allows for accusative Case marking of the direct object.

Thus, the Agent Nominalization corresponding to 50a would

be 51a, to be contrasted with the ungrammatical 51b. (51b

would be fine as a VP but this is irrelevant) .

395

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
51- a) ( A ) ?aakilu t9aam-i 1 -Taxariin

eàter food-Gen the- others

"The eater of the food of others"

*b) ( A ) Taakilu t9aam-a l-?axariin

eater food-Acc the-others

Given our assumptions about the configurational

conditions for accusative Case assignment as developed so

far, we must assume that the direct object in 50a is

governed by an underlying verb and is in a

configurational context involving a VP in the domain of a

non- "nominal" +F element (in the sense of 145, chap. 3) .

In this sense the Benoni Relative may be assumed to

involve a nominalisation process a t a higher level (in

terms of the tree structure) than what was suggested for

Agent Nominalisations. Exactly what this means in terms

of the technical analysis will be presented soon.

However, given our claim that the underlying structure of

a Benoni Relative involves a VP in the domain of a +F

element of some sort, the question may be raised as to

how much of a sentential structure is indeed involved in

this construction. In this respect, the differences

between this construction and the standard relative

clause are quite instructive. The facts presented below

have already been noted in the literature (cf. Berman

(1978)) and they clearly indicate that Benoni Relatives

396

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
do not involve a sentential construction but, most

probably, only a VP.

In discussing a possible sentential analysis, one

point must be made clear. A question that naturally

arises if such an analysis of Benoni Relatives is assumed

is where would the definite article be located in such a

structure. On this point it has been common practice to

speculate (e.g. Berman (1978)) that the definite article

in these constructions is some sort of complementizer.

Such a view, although not technically elaborated

anywhere in the literature, would seem natural in view of

the interpretation and function of these constructions,

especially in their adjectival use. There is no need to

go into the exact details of such a possible analysis.

The only point relevant for our needs is that in any

reasonable sentential analysis of Benoni Relatives the

definite article would necessarily be located above, or

outside, the sentence (IP) level. Thus, a sentential

analysis of Benoni Relatives would look roughly as

follows .

397

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
52- CP/?

/ \
c/? IP

1 / \
ha/al I*

/ \
VP

/ \

The point is, however, that something like the schematic

structure above must be wrong. Here we may start with

some £acts concerning the distribution of adverbs.

53- (H) ha-anaSim Se (tamid) holxim (tamid) ba-

the people that (always) walk (always) in the

rxov

street

"The people who always walk in the street"

54-*a) (H) ha-anaSim ha tamid holxim ba- rxov

the people the always walk in the street

b) ( H ) ha-anaSim ha holxim tamid ba- rxov

the people the walk always in the street

"The people who- always walk in the street"

Given the standard assumption that the Hebrew relative

clause complementizer Se is the head of CP (the same can

398

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
be demonstrated with respect to the Arabic complementizer

?allad* i ) , we would not expect it to have any effects on

the distribution of adverbs within the domain dominated

by IP. As 53 shows, this is exactly so. The situation

with Benoni Relatives is however different. As 54a

shows, an adverb may not intervene between the initial

definite article and the benoni verb which would,

presumably, be located in the position I in 52 after the

application of head movement adjoining V to I. Rather,

an adverb must follow the verb as in 54b. These fact are

not to be expected if something like 52 was the correct

analysis.

A significant fact concerning the type of adverbs

allowed may also be pointed out. Thus, sentential

adverbs are perfectly fine in relative clauses (55a) but

impossible, or very odd, in Benoni Relatives (55b) .

55- a) (H) ha-anaSim Se kanir'e/lelo safek ovdim

the people that probably/certainly work

kaSe

hard

’’The people who probably/certainly work hard"

??b) (H) ha-anaSim ha-ovdim kanire/lelo safek

the people the work probably/certainly

kaSe

hard

399

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
This contrast would be unexpected if both standard

relatives and Benoni Relatives were assumed to involve a

sentence level structure. I

Contrasts between Benoni Relatives and standard

relatives may also be observed with respect to negation.

These contrasts may be observed with the regular negation

word lo (not) , as well as the negation particle eyn which

appears normally only in present tense Benoni sentences.

56- a) (H) ha-anaSim Se I lo ovdim kaSe

the people that not work hard

"The people who don't work hard"

*b) (H) ha-anaSim ha-| lo ovdim kaSe

the people the | not work hard

57- a) (H) ha-anaSim Se 1 eyn-am medabrim ivrit

the people that not-they speak Hebrew

"The people whoi don't speak Hebrew"

*b) (H) ha-anaSim ha | eyn-am medabrim ivrit

the people the| not they speak Hebrew

Given, again, the standard (assumption that the relative

complementizer Se (that) isl the head of CP and the

grammaticality of the a examples in 56 and 57, it must be

that the negative particles| lo and eyn are located at a

lower position in the tree (structure than the COMP

position. Thus, an assumption that the definite article

400

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
ha / al is the head of CP in the Benoni Relatives of the

B examples would leave us, again, without an explanation

for the apparent conflict between its occurrence and the

occurrence of a negation word.

We may, at this point, note the rather significant

fact that some form of negation is not altogether

excluded from the position preceding a Benoni form in

these constructions. In particular, the Arabic

adjectival negation morpheme Rayr (non-) is perfectly

acceptable in this position.

58- (A) annaas-u al Rayr ?aakiluuna t9aam-a 1-

the people the non eat food-Acc the

?axariin

others

"People who don't eat the food of others"

This fact would follow naturally if the Benoni Relative

was assumed to involve an adjectival, rather than

sentential, structure of some sort. We will see soon how

this may be done.

Another important fact which would seem to support a

"non-verbal" and therefore non sentential analysis, as

opposed to a hypothesis of the type represented in 52,

has to do with the verb form which is permitted to occur

in Benoni and standard relatives respectively. In a

401

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Benoni Relative it is only the Benoni (participial) form

which may ever occur.

59- * a) (H) ha-anaSim ha- siymu/yesaymu et ha-

the people the f inished/will finish OM the

avoda

work

*b) ( A ) annaas -u al ?akalu/ya?kulu

the people-Nom the ate/will eat

ta9aam-a -hum

food -Acc-their

On the other hand, such a restriction is non-existent

when it comes to standard relative clauses.

60- a) (H) ha-anaSim Se siymu/yesyamu et ba-

the people that f inished/will finish OM the

avoda

work

"The people who finished/will finish the work"

b) ( A ) annaas-u llad’iina ?akalu/ya?kulu

the people who ate /will eat

ta9aam-a -hum

food -Acc their

"The people who ate/will eat their food"

402

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
In fact, it would not be implausible to assume that

certain cooccurrence restrictions could be invoked which

would establish a certain correlation between the type of

element functioning as head of C P , in a configuration

such as 52, and a particular (temporal) specification of

I. We will see, however, that a simple account of the

facts in 59 is possible which is also in line with the

standard function of ha/al as definite articles.

Finally, there seems to be a fundamental difference

between standard relatives and Benoni Relatives which has

to do with the general phenomenon of relativization. In

a standard relative clause any NP position may be

relativized. The examples below show relativization

affecting a subject and an object respectively.

61- a) ( A ) al- ?awlaad-u llad'iina ?akalu

the children-Nom who ate

ta9aam-a -hum

food -Acc-their

"The children who ate their food"

b) (H) ha-yeladim Se Dina raata

the children that Dina saw

Clearly, in Benoni Relatives it is only the subject which

may be "relativised". In this, Benoni Relatives and

standard relatives are fundamentally different and the

403

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
analogy commonly suggested between them loses much of its

force. Given the above considerations, it seems safe to

conclude that a view of the initial definite article in

Benoni Relatives as some sort of complementizer as well

as a sentential analysis of these constructions are most

probably wrong.

Rather, I will assume that the definite article in

these constructions occupies the same position that a

definite article occupies in any DP or DegP. The main

feature of the analysis proposed here will be based on

the general strategy adopted in this work. Thus, in the

manner that this was done for previously examined

constructions, we will assume that the Benoni,

participial, head is syntactically rather then lexically

derived .

A participial form, as observed earlier, is a

combination of two morphological units, a verb form and a

Benoni affix. Here, again, we will make use of the idea

that the lexical content represented by the Benoni affix

may be multiply lexically listed under different

categorial identities. This idea is fairly plausible in

view of the fact observed in section 5.1.1 that

identical Benoni words exist which belong to different

categories. Thus, in addition to the nominal morpheme B

which was postulated to figure as head of Agent

Nominalization constructions in the previous section, we

404

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
will postulate the existence of an adjectival morpheme

B . The adjectival B subcategorizes for a VP and figures

as the head of an AP in the underlying structure of


3
Benoni Relatives which we assume to look as follows .

62- DegP

/ \

Deg AP

I / \

ha/al A’

/ \

A VP

I / \

B V XP

The only step in the derivation of a surface form of

Benoni Relatives consists of a head movement adjoining V

to B. The output of this operation is a Benoni verb

form.

405

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
63- DegP

Deg AP

ha/al

VP

Vi XP

This is another instance of what has been characterized

in this work as a syntactic analysis. There is no need

here to go into a detailed discussion of this point. It

will suffice to point out that these constructions, just

like Action and Agent Nominal izat ions discussed earlier,

allow the occurrence of causative constructions and, in

particular, the double accusative variant of these

constructions as in the two examples below. The

assumption of a syntactic derivation is therefore well

supported .

406

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
64- a) ( A ) al-muSarribuuna ?awlaad-a-hum

the "make drink-er-s” kids Acc their

al Haliib-a

the milk -Acc

"Those who make their kids drink milk"

b) ( A ) al-mu9allimu ayya-hu assuluuk -a

the teaching OM-him the behavior-Acc

1-Hin

the good

"The one who teaches him good behavior"

The two most crucial details in this analysis

concern the theta-theoretic properties of the adjectival

morpheme B and the definite article. Beginning with B,

unlike its nominal counterpart it has no arguments.

Thus, it is devoid of any thematic content and is similar

in this respect to INFL, the head of IP. It follows

that, unlike its nominal counterpart, the adjectival B

does not block the upward propagation of the external

theta-role of VP. The adjectival B is thus incapable of

being assigned the external theta-role of VP and is

therefore non- "nominal" in the particular sense of this

notion employed in this work. Being a non- "nominal" +F

element, i t provides the environment for the assignment

of Accusative Case. Thus, the adjectival B is a

morphological "nominalizer" in that i t subcategorizes for

407

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
a VP complement and provides a landing site for head

movement of which a Benoni form is the output, but it

lacks the thematic properties of nominalizers such as the

elements assumed to figure as heads of the various

nominalization constructions studied earlier. Rather,

this thematic function is fulfilled by the definite

article which is situated at the head position of DegP

and it is in this sense that this construction may be

said to be a nominalization at a higher level.

Thus, the thematic properties of the construction,

which in an Agent Nominalization are derived from

certain assumptions about the argument structure of the

nominal morpheme B, are derived in a Benoni Relative from

similar assumptions with respect to the definite article

ha/al. We will assume that ha/al (the) has the same

argument structure as the nominal B , namely, i t has an

external and an internal R-roles which share the same

index .

65- Argument Structure of ha/al: (Ri , Ri )

The thematic structure of a Benoni Relative may be

illustrated as follows.

408

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
66- DegPi

/ \

Degi APi

I / \

ha/al A’i

Ri ,Ri / \

A VPi

I / \

B V XP

i,k

In this structure the external theta-role of VP is,

vertically assigned to A* and to AP and is then assigned

to the internal argument of ha/al. The referential

theta-role of the definite article is vertically assigned

to DegP and it is by virtue of this property that the

structure as a whole may have an NP-like distribution.

Given that the two arguments of the definite article are

coindexed, the construction as a whole is interpreted as

denoting to the bearer of the subject theta-role.

It is assumed that the same structure as the one

illustrated in 66 underlies the adjectival use of Benoni

Relatives in constructions such as the following.

409

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
67- (H) N p [ ha-anaSim d« 3 p[ ha-rocim le-hikanes]

the people the want to enter

"the people who want to enter"

Thus, structures of the type in 66 have a double

referential/ modificational use. It is interesting to

note that this is not an isolated case of such a double

function. Arabic relative clauses headed by the relative

pronoun ?allad* i (that) (or its feminine or plural

variants) seem to behave in exactly the same way. The

following pair of examples shows the same "?allad* i-

phrase" functioning in one case as the subject of a


4
sentence (68a) and in the other (68b) as a relative

clause modifying a head noun.

68- a) ( A ) ?allad *i ya jma9u-na huwwa tawajjuhu-

that unites -us it being confronted-

-na ma9an ?ila l-isti9maar

-our together to the imperialism

"what unites us is our common confrontation with

imperialism"

410

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
b) ( A ) ssiraa9 ?allad'i yajma9u-na huwwa

the struggle that unites -us it

ssiraa9 Deda l-isti9maar

the struggle against the imperialism

"the struggle which unites us is the struggle

against imperialism"

Likewise, the somewhat archaic Hebrew examples below show

a phrasal constituent headed by the particle aSer

figuring in one case in referential function as a direct

object (69a) and in the other (69b) as a modifying

relative clause.

69- a) (H) kvar Saxax-nu et aSer lamad-nu

already forgot-we OM what learned-we

"we already forgot what we learned”

b) (H) Saxax-nu et ha-Siur aSer lamad-nu

forgot-we OM the lesson what learned-we

"we forgot the lesson that we learned"

In fact, the most obvious case of an expression which can

occur in this double function are simple definite

adjectives as in the following pair.

411

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
70- a) (H) ha-qdolim mesoxaxim al politika

the big discuss about politics

"the "grown-ups" discuss politics"

b) (H) ha-yeladim ha-qdolim mesoxaxim al

the boys the big discuss about

politika

politics

"the big boys discuss politics"

I will assume that definite adjectival phrases have a

structure corresponding to Benoni Relatives as follows.

71- DegPi

/ \

Degi APi

I / \

ha/al A'i

Ri ,Ri I

At

Xi ,

Thus, the definite article under this view is a

" nominal iz er " although not in its morphological


8
functioning but only in its thematic functioning . In

both a simple definite AP as in 71 above, as well as in

the more complex Benoni Relative in 66, the definite

412

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
article takes a complement which, on its own, can only

be used as a predicate, and produces an overall structure

which may be used as a referential expression.

It follows from these considerations that, for a

Benoni Relative to have an NP-like distribution, i t must

have an initial definite article. It is the definite

article which provides the referential theta-role which

makes it possible for a constituent to function as an

argument. This is obviously true as demonstrated by

earlier examples and by the following pair.

72- a) (H) ha-rocim le-hikanes xayavim le-Salem asara

the want to enter must to pay ten

dolar

dolars

"those who want to enter must pay ten dolars”

*b) (H) rocim le-hikanes xayavim le-Salem asara

want to enter must to pay ten

dolar

dolars

On the other hand, a Benoni Relative in its adjectival

function does not need to be preceded by a definite

article. It only has to be preceded by a definite

article if the noun it modifies is definite.

413

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
73- a) (H) ha-anaSim ha-Sotfim et ha-ricpa halxu

the people the wash OM the floor went

habayta

home

"The people who wash the floor went home"

b) (H) anaSim Sotfim et ha-ricpa niru

people wash OM the floor were seen

derex ha-xalon

through the window

"People washing the floor were seen through the

window"

The underlined part of 73b in which a definite article is

missing would have the following structure in which the

external theta-role of VP becomes the external theta-role

of DegP by upward propagation. This is possible since

the head of DegP in this case is not occupied by an

element with an argument structure.

414

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
74- DegP’>i

/ \

DegP * i

/ \

Deg APi

/ \

A’i

/ \

A VPi

/ \

V NP

I I

wash the floor

îr j

To conclude, we may now see briefly how all of the facts

reviewed earlier as arguments against a relative-

clause-type analysis follow naturally from the present

analysis. First, as was observed, neither adverbs nor

negation words may intervene between the definite article

and the Benoni head. The relevant examples were the

following.

415

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
75-*a) ( A ) annaass-u ddaaiman ?aakiluuna

the people-Nom the always eat

ta9aam-a l-?axariin

food -Acc the others

*b) (H) ha-anaSim ha- lo/eyn-am holxim ba-

the people the not/not-they walk in the

rexov

street

Given the structure in 62/63, it is clear what is wrong

with 75 a,b, namely, adverbials and negation words

couldn't occur in a position following the head DegP and

preceding the head of an AP. In 75a, b the adverb and the

negation can only be construed as dominated by the AP

node outside of the VP domain. But this is impossible

since both adverbs and negation words of this type are

limited in their distribution to verbal, or sentential,

environments .

On the other hand, the head of an AP may be

morphologically complex and include a negation particle

such as the Arabic particle Rayr (non) as in 58, but such

cases are exempt from the configurational restrictions

that are a t work in 75. I repeat here example 58 for

convenience .

416

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
76) (=58) (A) nnaas-u 1-Rayr îaakiluuna

the people-Nom the not eat

ta9aam-a l-?axariin

food -Acc the others

"The people who don't eat the food of others"

The head of AP in this case would have a structure as

illustrated below. The rest of the structure is

identical to the cases observed earlier.

77- DegP

/ \

Deg AP

/ \

A'

/ \

A VP

/ \

Rayr B

non-

It is also clear why the following example, in which

tensed forms of the verb occur, is bad.

417

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
*78- (H) ha- anaSim ha-halxu /yelxu ba- rxov

the people the walked/will walk in the street

The adjectival morpheme B is simply not specified for

tense since adjectives in general do not carry temporal

information.

Finally, it is clear from the proposed analysis why

it is only the subject which may be "relativized" in

Benoni Relatives, namely, it is only the external theta-

role of VP which may be vertically assigned in the

proposed configuration and, in this way, become the

external theta-role of the AP as a whole.

418

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Footnotes to Chapter V

1
As pointed out to me by R. Higgins, Roeper's claim
about the interpretation of 19 is wrong. Clearly, the
example is biased against an adverbial construal of
across the river given the presence of the initial
definite article. According to R. Higgins, examples like
the following are possible

(i) She is a fisher in muddy water

in which in muddy water modifies the fishing rather than


the fisher. Obviously, this observation does not raise
any difficulty to the analysis of Agent Nominalizations
suggested in this chapter but simply raises the
possibility that a similar approach may be necessary for
some corresponding constructions in English.

2
Note that if the analysis so far is accepted as
reasonably satisfactory then it becomes inconceivable to
claim that the impossibility of accusative Case
assignment is due to passivization. The fact that the
explanation of this phenomenon suggested here is
applicable to both Action and Agent Nominalizations
shows, in my view, its superiority over a passivization
analysis.

3
The DegP analysis of AP's is due mainly to Abney
(1987) who makes use of observations of Jackendoff
(1977) . See appendix to Chapter 2 for an application of
this idea to the analysis of adjectival bound genitives
in Hebrew and Arabic.

Example 68a is taken from Al-Ahraam Sep 27 1990.

■ Given this analysis of definite articles and in view


of the assumed argument structure of nouns, something
needs to be said about the way the two components, a
definite article and a noun, combine to produce the

419

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
argument structure of a DP headed by a definite article.
This can be accomplished in a simple fashion as
illustrated in the following structure.

(i) DPi
/ \
D'i
/ \
Di NPi
I I
ha/al N*i
Ri ,Ri I
Ni
R1

In this configuration the external theta-role of NP,


which percolates up from the head noun to NP, is linked
to the internal argument of ha/al. Given that the two
arguments of ha/al are coindexed, the external argument
of ha/al, and therefore DP, will always end up being
coindexed with the external theta-role of N.

420

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
APPENDIX TO CHAPTER 2

ADJECTIVAL BOUND GENITIVES

Bound genitive constructions may be formed also with

adjectival heads. It seems that the analysis of bound genitives

proposed in section 2.1.3 may be naturally extended to

adjectives. The following are typical examples.

1- a) (H) (naar) yefe eynayim

( a boy) pretty eyes

"a boy pretty of eyes”

b) (H) (erec) cfufat uxlusia

(country) crowded population

"a densely populated country”

2- a) (A) walad-un jamiil-u 1-wajh-i

boy -Norn pretty-Nom the face-Gen

"a boy pretty of face"

b) (A) rajul-un Taahir-u 1-qalb -i

man -Norn pure -Norn the heart -Gen

"a man pure of heart”

As example lb shows, adjectival bound genitives are not limited

to expressions of inalienable possession such as body parts and

the like. Rather, it seems that the construction is fairly

productive although ( a t least in Hebrew) clearly marked as

421

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
literary in style. Just like nominal bound genitives, adjectival

bound genitives may not be preceded by a definite article.

3- *a) (H) (ha-naar) ha-yefe eynayim

(the boy) the pretty eyes

*b) (H) (ha-erec) ha-cfufat uxlusia

(the country) the crowded population

The structure of 1,2 would be the following.

4- DegP DegP

/ \ / \

Deg' =====> Deg*

/ \ / \

Deg AP Degi AP

I / \ / \ / \

POSS DP A* Ai Deg DP A'

[Def] I I I

A POSS A

[Def] |

ei

Note that the assumption of POSS as head of DegP is not

necessarily problematic. The "nominalness" of adjectives is

something which has long been noticed by both traditional and

modern linguists. Presumably, it is the same position which will

422

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
be occupied by a definite article in a definite AP/DegP.

There is, however, an interesting variation between Hebrew

and Arabic concerning the distribution of the definite article in

adjectival bound genitives. It seems as though Arabic does

violate the restriction on the occurrence of an initial definite

article. Thus, the definite variants of 2a, b would be rendered

as follows .

5- a) (A) (al-walad-u) jjamiil -u 1-wajh-i

(the boy-Nom) the pretty-Nom the face-Gen

"the boy pretty of face”

b) ( A ) (rrajul-u) TTaahir-u al-qalb -i

(the man -Nom) the pure-Nom the heart-Gen

. "the man pure of heart"

I would like to suggest that 5 a , b are not counterexamples to the

general analysis of bound genitives suggested in this chapter.

Rather, the explanation of these cases would be based on two

points. First, they involve a special type of adjectival

Relative construction. The initial definite article in 5a, b (the

one preceding the adjective, not the head noun) would be the

definite article of a containing adjectival Relative construction

in which the adjectival bound genitive is embedded. Second, the

sequence Def. article-Noun in adjectival bound genitives is

interpreted differently in Hebrew and in Arabic. In Hebrew it is

interpreted as definite whereas in Arabic i t is interpreted as

423

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
non-defini te (or generic?) . Note that this claim about Arabie is

made with respect to "definite" NP's in the specifier position of

AP's alone. This does not necessarily hold for other syntactic

environments in Arabic and, indeed, in most cases it doesn't.

This semantic difference between Hebrew and Arabic may be easily

demonstrated as follows. It is generally known that predicative

phrases (6b, c , 7b, c ) , unlike modifying adjectives in NP's (6a, 7a)

may not be definite, (the impossibility of definite predicates

seems to be a general phenomenon, cf . Higginbotham (1986) , here

we are obviously abstracting away from cases in which identity of

reference is claimed as in: "John is the president").

6- a) (H) ha-yeled ha-gadol

the boy the big

"the big boy"

*b) (H) ha-yeled ha-gadol

the boy (is) the big

c ) (H) ha-yeled gadol

the boy big

"the boy is big"

7- a) ( A ) al-walad-u jjamiil-u

the boy -Norn the pretty-Nom

"the pretty boy"

*b) ( A ) al-walad-u jjamiil-u

the boy -Norn (is) the pretty-Nom

424

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
c ) ( A ) al-walad-u jamiil-un

the boy -Nom pretty-Nom

"the boy is pretty"

However, the following examples show adjectival bound genitives

figuring as predicates of a sentence. The contrast between the

Hebrew and the Arabic examples can only be explained if one

assumes that the predicate in the Arabic example is indefinite,

(the examples in 8 are intended to be sentences not NP's)

8- *a) (H) ha-yeled yefe ha-eynayim

the boy pretty the eyes

b) ( A ) al-walad-u jamiil-u 1-wajh-i

the boy -Norn pretty-Nom the face-Gen

"the boy is pretty the face"

Obviously, the restriction on definite predicates does apply in

Arabic as demonstrated by 7b. Therefore, it must be the case

that the adjectival predicate in 8b is perceived as indefinite.

The grammatical Hebrew counterpart of 8b must not have a

definite article in its predicate.

9- (H) ha-yeled yefe eynayim

the boy pretty eyes

"the boy is pretty of eyes"

425

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
The analysis of special adjectival relatives will be discussed in

detail in chapter 5 of this dissertation. Let us assume that

they have the following structure, in which a DegP or a VP may

figure as complement in an AP.

10- DegP

/ \

Deg*

/ \

Deg AP

I / \

ha/al A*

I \
A [DegP/VPl

Having a definite article as head of DegP, 10 is semantically

definite and may only modify a definite head. The lower DegP in

this configuration may have the usual internal structure of a

DegP, in particular, i t may be an adjectival bound genitive.

We may now look back at example 5. In this example the head noun

is clearly definite since it is preceded by a definite article

and is, of course, interpreted as definite. It may therefore be

modified only by a definite modifier. However, as demonstrated

in 8b, an adjectival bound genitive in Arabic which shows an

occurrence of a definite article and which is, by assumption,

headed by a POSS marked as [Def] is nevertheless indefinite.

426

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Thus, the only way for an adjectival bound genitive to be

definite, and to be able t o modify a definite head, would be for

it to be embedded in an adjectival relative of the type

illustrated in 10. The structure of 5 a,b is the following.

427

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
11- DP

/ \

D NP

I / \

the N’

/ \

N’ DegP

I / \

N Deg AP

I I / \

boy the A*

/ \

A DegP

/ \

Degi AP

/ \ / \

Ai Deg DP A'

pretty POSS the A

pure face/ I

hurt ei

Thus, 5 a,b do not constitute a counterexample to the analysis of

bound genitives proposed here.

428

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
APPENDIX TO CHAPTER III

THE PARTICLE "ET” AND ACCUSATIVE CASE MARKING

>

There is some dispute in recent work concerning

accusative Case marking and the nature of the particle et

which occurs in Action Nominalization constructions. The

dispute is mainly about the question as to whether et

should necessarily be taken to indicate the assignment of

accusative Case by a verb or, alternatively, is itself a

Case assigner. Being a Case assigner, the occurrence of

et in nominal constructions would be necessary because of

the absence of another Case marking element, namely, a

verb. The question is obviously important since much of

the argument developed in this chapter depends on the

assumption that the occurrence of et, and accusative Case

in general, is an indication of the government of an NP

by a verb and, therefore, the occurrence of a verb in

some underlying representation needs to be postulated.

It is, of course, a significant fact, in my view,

that the corresponding construction in Arabic doesn * t

have anything which would be the equivalent of the Hebrew

et. Rather, Arabic Action Nominalizations manifest the

same morphological accusative Case marking which occurs

in simple sentences. Thus, the dispute which developed

with respect to Hebrew would never take place with

429

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
respect to Arabie for which an analysis of the type

suggested in this chapter would be the most reasonable

approach. Much of the dispute concerning the Hebrew data

is caused by the fact that Action Nominalisations with an

indefinite direct object are in many cases less

acceptable than their definite counterparts.

1- a) axilat Dan et ha-uga

eating Dan OM the cake

"Dan's eating of the cake"

??b) axilat Dan uga

eating Dan a cake

But it seems to me that the indefinite counterparts are

not completely ungrammatical. They are perfectly

acceptable if the object NP is "heavier" as in the

following examples.

2- a) axilat Dan tapuxe ec rabim

eating Dan apples many

"Dan's eating many apples"

b) harisat ha-oyev kfarim rabim ba-negev

destruction the enemy villages many in the negev

"The enemy's destruction of many villages in

the negev"

430

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
c) ktivat-o Sel Dan sefer exad asuya lehimaSex

writing-his Sel Dan book one may last

zman rav

time a lot

"The writing of one book by Dan may last a long time"

It is of course an interesting question why the object NP

needs to be "heavier", but this question is probably

independent from the question of Case marking.

We turn now to the suggestion that et is not the

marking of Case assignment by another governing element

but is rather a Case marker itself, that is, a

preposition of some sort. Here we may simply note some

facts showing that the distribution of et is radically

different from that of any other prepositional element

and that therefore any such analogy is wrong.

First there is the known fact that et occurs only

with a definite NP.

3- a) Dan axai et ha-uga

Dan ate OM the cake

"Dan ate the cake"

b) Dan axal uga

Dan ate a cake

431

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Obviously, it is the verb axal (eat) which must be

assumed to be the Case assigner in 3b. There is no

analogous fact when one looks at prepositions. A Case

assigning preposition must always be present.

The possibility to drop e t is attested in other

construction types. One example is relative clauses.

4- a) ha-sef er Se Dina kar?a

the book that Dina read

b) ha-sefer Se Dina kar?a ot-o

the book that Dina read OM it

"The book that Dina read"

5- *a) ha-kesef Se Dan viter

the money that Dan gave up

b) ha-kesef Se Dan viter al-av

the money that Dan gave up on i t

"The money that Dan gave up”

In 4a the relativized element is a direct object and the

position following the verb is empty. Presumably, the

element occupying this position, a variable, must be Case

assigned and the Case feature, it seems, may only be

provided by the verb. In 4b et occurs with a resumptive

pronoun attached to it. As 5a, b show, nothing like this

is possible with a preposition, even a semantically empty

one such as the preposition al (on, about) required by

432

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
the verb viter (give up) . Here the resumptive pronoun

strategy must be employed.

Finally, pronominal direct objects may be cliticized

on the particle e t (6a) or, in the absence of et, on the

governing verb (6b) . This strategy is more commonly used

with infinitival than with finite verbs. Again, nothing

like this may ever happen with a preposition (7a, b).

6- a) Dan roce lirot ot-a

Dan wants to see OM her

"Dan wants to see her"

b) Dan roce lirot-a

Dan wants to see-her

"Dan wants to see her"

7- a) Dan mesarev levater ale-ha

Dan refuses to give up on her

"Dan refuses to give her up"

*b) Dan mesarev levatr -a

Dan refuses to give up-her

In view of this evidence one must conclude, at

least, that et is the only preposition of its kind. But

this obviously begs the question as to what kind of

preposition et is. Given that the NF's with which et

occurs are direct objects with respect to all other

criteria which generally identify an NP as such, i t seems

433

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
that the reasonable characterization of it is as an

object marker rather than a preposition.

Now, it might still be argued (cf. Siloni (1990))

that the occurrence of et in "derived nouns" involves a

different kind, rather than the "ordinary" kind, of

accusative Case marking. But such an approach tends to

ignore the striking parallelism between verbs and their

nominal counterparts. That is, it is only verbs which

assign accusative Case that have nominal counterparts

which also assign accusative Case. In an approach which

takes the two types of Case marking to be different this

correlation seems rather accidental.

434

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
REFERENCES

Abney, S. (1986) "Functional elements and licensing"


Ms. MIT, Cambridge, Mass.

Abney, S. (1987) The English Noun-Phrase in its


Sentential Aspect, Doctoral Dissertation, MIT,
Cambridge , Mass .

Aoun, J . (1978) "Structure interne du groupe nominale en


Arabe", Ms. Universite de PARIS VIII.

Aoun, J . (1979) "Parts of speech: A case of


redistribution", in Belletti A. et al (eds)
GLOW colloquium, Pisa, Italy.

Aoun, J . (1981) The Formal Nature of Anaphoric


Relationships , Doctoral Dissertation, MIT,
Cambridge , Mass .

Aoun, J . and Sportiche D. (1983) "On the formal theory of


Government", The Linguistic Review 2.

Aristotle D e Interpretatione, Oxford University Press,


(1928) .

Bach, E. (1979) "Control in Montague Grammar",


Linguistic Inquiry 10.4.

Bach, E. (1983) "On the relationship between word grammar


and phrase grammar", Natural Language and Linguistic
Theory 1.

Baker, M. (1985) Incorporation: A Theory of Grammatical


Function Changing, Doctoral Dissertation, MIT,
Cambridge , Mass .

Baker, M. (1988) Incorporation: A Theory of Grammatical


Function Changing, The University of Chicago Press.

Baker, M. Johnson K. and Roberts I. (1989) "Passive


arguments raised", Linguistic Inguiry, 20.2.

Bekkum, W. Jac. Van (1983) "The origins of the infinitive


in Rabbinical Hebrew" , Journal of Semitic Studies,
28.2.

Berman, R . (1978) Modern Hebrew Structure, Tel-Aviv,


University Publishing Projects.

435

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Borer, H. (1984) Parametric Syntax, Dordrecht, Foris
Publications .

Borer, H. (1988) "On the morphological parallelism


between compounds and constructs", in Booi j , G . and
Van Marie (eds) , Yearbook of Morphology, Dordrecht,
Foris Publications.

Borer, H. (1989) "Anaphoric Agr", In Jaegli 0. and Safir


K. (eds), The Null Subject Parameter, Kluwer Academic
Publishers .

Borer, H. (Forthcoming) "Derived Nominals and the


Causative-Inchoative alternation: Two case studies
in parallel morphology", Ms. UC Irvine.

Burzio, L. (1981) Intransitive Verbs and Italian


Auxiliaries , Doctoral Dissertation, MIT, Cambridge,
Mass .

Carter R. (1984) "Sous-Categorisation et régularités


selectionelles" , Communications 40.

Chierchia, G. (1984) Topics in the Syntax and Semantics


of Infinitives and Gerunds, Doctoral Dissertation,
University of Massachusetts, Amherst.

Chierchia, G. (1985) "Formal Semantics and the grammar of


Predication", Linguistic Inquiry, 16.3.

Chomsky, N. (1986a) Knowledge of Language, New york,


Praeger .

Chomsky, N. (1986b) Barriers , MIT Press, Cambridge,


Massachusetts.

Cohen, T. (1990) "A Determiner Phrase approach to Hebrew


nominals", Ms. Bar Ilan University

Comrie, B. (1976) "The syntax of action nominals, a cross


linguistic study", Lingua 40.

Cowell, M. (1964) A reference grammar of Syrian Arabic,


Washington, D.C. Georgetown University Press.

Di-Sciullo, A.M. and Williams E. (1987) On the Definition


of Word, MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.

Demirdache, H. (1989) "Nominative NP's in modern Standard


Arabic", Ms. MIT, Cambridge, Mass.

436

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Doron, E. (1983) Verbless predicates in Hebrew, Doctoral
Dissertation, University of Texas, Austin.

Doron, E. (1989) "Derived nominals in Hebrew" Ms. Hebrew


University of Jerusalem.

Dowty, D. (1989) "On the semantic content of the notion


of 'thematic role’" in Chierchia, G., Partee B.H.
and Turner R. (eds) (1989) Properties , Types and
Meaning Vol. II Kluwer Academic Publishers.

Driver, S.R. (1892) A Treatise on the use of tenses


in Hebrew, Oxford, Clarendon Press.

Emonds, J . (1985) A Unified Theory of Syntactic


Categories , Dordrecht, Foris Publications.

Emonds, J . (1989) "Timberlake's nominative objects in


Finnish and old Russian" , Linguistic Society of
America, Annual conference.

Fabb, N. (1984) Syntactic Affixation, Doctoral


Dissertation, MIT, Cambridge, Mass.

Fassi-Fehri, A-K (1982) Linguistigue Arabe: Forme e t


Interpretation , Rabat, Publications de la faculté
des lettres et sciences humaines.

Fassi-Fehri, A-k (1988) "Generalized IP structure, Case


and VS word order", Ms. Faculty of letters, Rabat

Finer, D. (1985) "The Syntax of Switch Reference",


Linguistic Inguiry 16.

Fukui, N. and Speas M. (1986) "Specifiers and


Projections", Ms. MIT, Cambridge, Mass.

Gazdar, G., Klein E. , Pullum G. and Sag I. (1985)


Generalized Phrase Structure Grammar, Cambridge ,
Harvard University Press.

Gesenius, W. (1920) Hebrew Grammar, Oxford University


Press.

Gil, D. (1982) "Case marking, phonological size and


linear order", in Syntax and Semantics, Vol. 16
Academic Press Inc.

Glinert, L. (1989) The Grammar of Modern Hebrew,


Cambridge, University Press.

437

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Grimshaw, J . (1989) Argument Structure, Ms. Brandeis
University.

Haegeman, L. and Van Riemsdijk H. (1986) ’’Verb projection


raising, Scope and the typology of rules affecting
verbs ” , Linguistic Inquiry 17.3.

Hale, K. (1983) "Warlpiri and the grammar of non-


configur ational languages", Natural Language and
Linguistic Theory 1.

Haywood, J .A. and Nahmad H.M. (1965) A New Arabic


Grammar , Cambridge, Harvard University Press.

Hazout, I. (1988) "Nominalization constructions in Modern


Hebrew," Ms. University of Massachusetts, Amherst.

Hazout, I. (1989) "The Hebrew pronoun Ze and the syntax


of sentential subjects", Ms. University of
Massachusetts, Amherst.

Heim, I. (1989) "Articles and definiteness", Ms. UCLA.

Higginbotham, J . (1983) "Logical Form, Binding and


Nominals " , Linguistic Inquiry 14.3.

Higginbotham, J . (1985) "On Semantics", Linguistic


Inguiry 16.4.

Higginbotham, J . (1987) "Definiteness and Predication"


in Reuland E. and Ter Meulen A. (eds.)
The Representation of (In) definiteness, Cambridge ,
MIT Press.

Higginbotham, J. (1989) "Elucidations of meaning",


Linguistics and Philosophy 12.4.

Horn, G. (1975) ”0n the nonsen tential nature of the


Poss-ing construction", Linguistic Analysis 1.4.

Hoyt, K. (1989) "Verb raising in Lebanese Arabic", MIT


working papers in Linguistics 11.

Huang, J . (1982) "Complex predicates in generalized


control", Ms. Cornell University.

Jackendoff, R . (1977) X* -Syntax: a Study of Phrase


Structure, Cambridge, MIT Press.

Jackendoff, R. (1990) "On Larson's treatment of the


double object construction", Linguistic Inquiry
21.3.

438

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Jacobson, P . (1990) "Raising as function composition",
Linguistics and Philosophy 13.4.

Jaeggli, O. (1986) "Passive”, Linguistic Inquiry 17.

Kitagawa, Y. (1986) Subjects in Japanese and English,


Doctoral Dissertation, University of Massachusetts,
Amherst.

Kuroda, S-Y (1968) "English relativization and certain


related problems", Language 44.

Larson, R. (1988) "On the double object construction",


Linguistic Inguiry 19.3.

Lebeaux, D. (1988) Language. Acquisition and the Form


of the Grammar, Doctoral Dissertation, University of
Massachusetts, Amherst.

Lefebvre, C. and Muysken P. (1988) Mixed categories,


Nominalisations in Quechua, Kluwer Academic
Publishers

Levin, B. and Rappaport M. (1986) "The formation of


adjectival Passives", Linguistic Inquiry 17.

Manzini, M.R. (1983) "On control and control theory",


Linguistic Inquiry 14.3.

Milsark, G.L. (1988) "Single -Ing", Linguistic Inquiry,


19.4.

Mohanan, K.P. (1983) "Functional and anaphoric control".


Linguistic Inquiry 14.4.

Moortgat, M. (1987) "Compositionality and the Syntax of


words " .

Muhammad, M.A. (1987) "On the parallelism between IP and


DP", Proceedings of the West Coast Conference on
Formal Linguistics.

Mushaweh, L. (1986) De la Syntaxe des Petites


Propositions , These de Doctorat, Universite de PARIS
VIII.

Muysken, P. (1989) "Predication chains: Case and


argument status in Quechua and Turkish",
Linguistic Inquiry 20.4.

Owens, J . (1984) "The Noun Phrase in Arabic grammatical


theory", Al-9arabiyya 17.

439

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Owens, J . (1988) The Foundations of Grammar: Introduction
to Medieval Arabic Grammatical Theory, Amsterdam ,
John Benjamins.

Pollard, C. and Sag I. (1987) Information based Syntax and


Semantics , CSLI.

Rappaport, M. (1983) "On the nature of derived nominals”,


in Levin, Rappaport and Zaenen (eds.) Papers in LFG,
Bloomington, Indiana.

Rapoport, T. (1987) Popular Nominal and Small Clauses:


A Study in Israeli Hebrew, Doctoral Dissertation,
MIT, Cambridge, Mass.

Raposo, E. (1987) "Case theory and INCL-to-COMP: the


Inflected Infinitive in European Portugese” ,
Linguiste Inquiry , 18.1.

Reinhart, T. (1983) Anaphora and Semantic Interpretation,


The University of Chicago Press.

Reuland, E. (1983) "Governing -Ing", Linguistic Inquiry


14.1.

Ritter, E. (1985) "What eyn't there", Ms. MIT,


Cambridge , Mass .

Ritter, E. (1986) "NSO Noun Phrases in Modern Hebrew", in


McDonough J. and Plunkett B. (eds.) Proceedings of
NELS 17.

Riemsdijk, H. van (1983) "The Case of German adjectives",


in Heny, F. and Richards B. (eds.) Linguistic
Categories : Auxiliaries and related puzzles,
Dordrecht, Reidel.

Riemsdijk, H. van and Williams E. (1981) "NP-Structure" ,


The Linguistic Review 1.

Ross, J.R. (1972) "The category squish: Endstation


Hauptwort", Proceedings of CLS.

Rothstein S. (1985) The Syntactic Forms of Predication,


Doctoral Dissertation, MIT, distributed by IULC.

Rouveret, A. (1980) "Sur la notion de proposition finie.


Gouvenement et Inversion", Language 60.

Rouveret, A. and Vergnaud J-R. (1980) "Specifying


reference to the subject", Linguistic Inguiry, 11.1.

440

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Schachter, P. (1985) "Parts of Speech", in Shopen T. (ed)
Language typology and Syntactic description Vol . I ,
Cambridge Univesity Press.

Scheindlin, R . (1978) 201 Arabic verbs, New York,


Barrons .

Schwarzschild, R. (1989) "The status of the particle *Sr


in Biblical Hebrew", Ms. University of
Massachusetts, Amherst.

Shlonsky, U. (1987) Null and displaced Subjects, Doctoral


Dissertation, MIT, Cambridge, Mass.

Shlonsky, U. (1990) "Construct-State nominals and


Universal Grammar", Ms. Haifa University.

Siloni, T. (1990) "Hebrew noun phrases: Generalized noun


raising", Ms. Universite de Geneve.

Srivasta, V. (1988) "Correlatives in a theory of Relative


Clauses", Ms. Cornell University.

Stern, N. (1979) "The et verbs in Israeli Hebrew",


Hebrew Computational Linguistics 15.

Stowell, T. (1981) The Origins of Phrase Structure,


Doctoral Dissertation, MIT, Cambridge, Mass.

Stowell, T. (1987) "Subjects, Specifiers and X-bar


theory", Ms. UCLA.

Stowell, T. (1989) "Raising in Irish and the Projection


Principle" , Natural Language and Linguistic Theory
7.3.

Toman, J . (1986) "A (word-) Syntax for participles",


Linguistische Berichte 105.

Travis , L . ( 1 9 8 4 ) Parameters and Effects of Word-Order


Variation, Doctoral Dissertation, MIT, Cambridge,
Mass .

Vergnaud, J-R. (1985) Dependences et Niveaux de


Representation en Syntaxe, Amsterdam, John
Benjamins.

Waltke, B. K. and 0* Connor M. (1990) An Introduction


to Biblical Hebrew Syntax, Indiana, Eisenbrauns.

441

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Webelhuth, G. (1989) Syntactic Saturation Phenomena and
the Modern Germanic Languages, Doctoral ,
Dissertation, University of Massachusetts, Amherst.

Williams, E. (1980) "Predication”, Linguistic Inguiry


11.1.

Williams, E. (1981) "Argument Structure and Morphology",


The Linguistic Review 1.

Williams, E. (1982) "The NP cycle". Linguistic Inquiry


13.2.

Williams, E. (1983a) "Syntactic vs. semantic categories",


Linguistics and Philosophy 6.

Williams, E. (1983b) "Against small clauses", Linguistic


Inquiry 14.2.

Williams, E. (1985) "PRO and subject of NP", Natural


Language and Linguistic Theory 3.

Williams, E. (1986) "A reassignment of the functions of


LF", Linguistic Inquiry 17.

Williams, E. (1987a) "Implicit arguments, the Binding


Theory and Control", Natural Language and Linguistic
Theory 5.

Williams, E. (1987b) "NP Trace in Theta Theory",


Linguistics and Philosophy 10.

Williams, E. (1989) "The anaphoric nature of theta


roles " , Linguistic Inquiry 20.3.

Williams, E. (1990) "Clause structure and C-Command", a


talk given at the annual meeting of the Israeli
. Society for Formal Linguistics, Tel-Aviv, June 11
1990.

Wise, H. (1975) A tranformational Grammar of Spoken


Egyptian Arabic, Oxford, Basil Blackwell.

Woisetschlaeger E. (1983) "On the question of


definiteness in "an old man's book"", Linguistic
Inguiry 14.1.

Wright, W. (1988) A grammar of the Arabic language (Third


edition), Cambridge University Press.

Wunderlich, D. (1987) "Partizipien im Deutschen",


Linquistische Berichte 111.

442

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
Zubizarreta, M-L. (1985) "The relation between
morphophonology and mor phosyntax , the case of
Romance Causatives”, Linguistic Inquiry 16.

Zubizarreta, M-L. (1987) Levels of Representation in the


Lexicon and in the Syntax, Dordrecht , Foris
Publications.

443

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.

You might also like