Auerbach IntensionalityGdelTheorems 1985
Auerbach IntensionalityGdelTheorems 1985
Auerbach IntensionalityGdelTheorems 1985
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophical
Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition
II
(2) is often used as an expression of the Godel result. Since (1) and (2) are
not prima facie synonymous, nor does (2) look wholly mathematical, what
warrants both the assertion of (2) and the claim that it is an expression of the
First Incompleteness Theorem?
Getting from (1) to (2) is a special case of the problem I characterized
above - getting from mathematical A to nonmathematical B. One thesis
needed is: In this context ix is an extension of Q' implies 'x is sufficiently
strong'.4 In fact the result extends to theories into which Q is interpretable,
but this is a refinement which need not detain us.
(3) is a relatively careful rendering of one of the many things that Godel is
often said to have proved. Sometimes it is put: 'The consistency of (a formal
system of) arithmetic is underivable in (that formal system of) arithmetic'.
In many texts such words are offered as glosses of some technical result
(usually proved only sketchily, if at all) labeled 'Godel's Second Incomplete-
ness Theorem'. Since what are derivable, or fail to be, are the formulas of a
formalism, I take it that (3) is an acceptable rendering of the slightly looser
remarks.6
These looser remarks, or sometimes (3), are the usual material for philo-
sophical writings concerning the philosophical significance, or consequences,
of the Godel Second Theorem." Since (3) isn't the mathematically proved
Second Theorem, such writings would be helped by an argument that (3)
1III
ism is consistent (recall (3)). Unlike the situation with some of the informal
intuitive descriptions of the First Theorem (and with my description of the
'consequent' above) that are often given, this apparent semantic character is,
I shall argue, intrinsic. The constraints on the antecedent are different in kind
from those on the consequent.
To draw the contrast between the two Theorems more sharply: The First
Theorem predicates a simple syntactic property of members of a large class of
formal systems. This property, incompleteness, is simple in at least the follow-
ing respect - it is definable in terms that do not invoke anything akin to a
translation, or formalization, relation; T is incomplete just in case there is a
sentence of T such that neither it nor its formal denial is derivable in T.
The Second Theorem (as glossed by (3)) predicates a certain more com-
plex property of members of a large class of formal systems. Call this proper-
ty 'KURT'. T has KURT if and only if any sentence of T that says that T
is consistent is not derivable in T. We will be seeing what it takes to render
this definition coherent, for 'T' taken as a variable.
What is the underivable formula of the Godel Second Incompleteness
Theorem? Let us call it, restricting our attention for the moment to just one
formalism, CON(P)8. Call the underivable formula of the First Theorem 'G'.
A proof of the Second Theorem establishes that 1- CON(P) -+ G (in fact
H CON(P) e G) and so, not H CON(P). In the light of these facts what would
make CON(P) importantly different from G?
Let Pf(y, x) be an open sentence of P that numeralwise expresses9 the
proof relation (assuming some fixed Godel numbering of syntactic objects,
and sequences of them, satisfying the usual constraints) and Fm(x) an open
sentence of P that numeralwise expresses sentencehood. Using PF (and a
symbol representing a substitution function), a proof of the First Theorem
constructs G, a formula equivalent in P to Vy - Pf(y, g), where g is the
Godel number of that very formula, G. 3 x(Fm(x) & - 3y Pf(y, x)) mimics,
in quantificational structure, a standard definition of consistency. Let such a
formula be (temporarily) CON(P). Note that this does not pick out a particu-
lar sentence G nor a particular sentence CON(P) since many formulas of P
will numeralwise express the proof relation. This produces a fatal equivoca-
tion in the preceding paragraph.
This construction does not guarantee that such a CON(P) says that the
formalism is consistent. It is not essential to a proof of the First Theorem
that the Godel sentence say of itself that it is underivable. (Indeed, it is only
IV
I have claimed that the difference between G and CON(P) is that a G may be
constructed from an open sentence that numeralwise expresses the proof
relation and that numeralwise expressibility is the only constraint needed to
show such a G to be underivable; a CON(P), constructed as above, may be
derivable. Concerning saying that, I have pointed out that the plausibility of
regarding G as saying that G is not derivable arises, inter alia, from regarding
Pf as expressing the proof relation, but that this plays no role in establishing
(1) or (2). But suppose we take this plausibility at face value and benefit
from the heuristic value of being able to explain the workings of G1 by
adverting to the simple logic of the antinomies. Then a CON(P), constructed
as above, should say that P is consistent. But then, I have claimed just above
and will show below, either (3) is false or the account of says that is defec-
tive. Furthermore, abandoning all accounts of says that would eviscerate
the Second Theorem. I will now establish and illuminate these claims.
Rosser exploited numeralwise expressibility's inability to distinguish co-
extensive relations. By constructing a new open sentence that numeralwise
expresses y is a proof of x but which had special properties as well, Rosser
was able to improve the G6del result. Letting Pf numeralwise express the
proof relation, Rosser used
This reads 'y is a proof of x and there is no shorter proof of the negation of
x'. A moment's reflection reveals that, for a consistent formalism, this
numeralwise expresses what Pf does. An even simpler device will make the
derivability of "consistency" more blatant. Define Pf' as
(5).
(S) 3 3y 4(y, k)
Then, although the instance of (5) involving Pf is not derivable, the instance
in which Pf ' replaces F, i 3 y(Pf(y, k) & i Pf(y, k)), is a theorem of logic.
What isn't derivable in the formalism is that Pf and Pf' are coextensive and so
numeralwise express the same relation.
In a sense, the G's constructed from such deviant Pf conditionally assert
their own underivability. The condition is that the formalism is consistent.
This condition the formalism cannot discharge. (These intuitive readings are
discussed below.) The prima facie incorrectness of 'y is a proof of x and y
isn't a proof of 0 = 1' as expressing y is a proof of x is not misleading; a
proper account of the Second Theorem must respect this fact.
VI
and
'La, a2' is true under I iff the only even prime is less than 3.
It should be clear by now that this won't help. A cogent argument for (6)
will have recourse to a proof of a generalized Second Theorem. Viewed as a
semantics the Feferman treatment assigns true to (6) by virtue of (5.6). The
key to the linkage is the occurrence of the formulas a as part of the formal-
ized consistency sentence. The a's are assigned by the semantics as represen-
tatives of formal systems. We can think of them as fixing the reference for
proper names of the formalism. (5.9) demonstrates that a (6) whose semantics
treated co-extensive a's indiscriminately would be false.
The skeptic might now object to the implicit syntax, that is, the parts,
and say that the superficial form of (6) is misleading.
(7) might be offered. The skeptic goes on to say that an appropriate technical
account, says Feferman's supplies the sentences CON<. This account must,
of course, bow to the requirements set by (5.9); this will force the skeptic
to identify formal theories with RE a 's.
Having been forced to the bifurcation (RE/non-RE) of the class of oa's
numeralwise expressing each set of theorems, the skeptic has sacrificed two
things: 1) an explanation of the bifurcation and, more importantly for
present purposes, 2) a reason for regarding (7) as a remark about consistency.
The skeptic is unable to distinguish the First and Second Theorems in any
interesting way (cf. Section III). For if (7) is to be about consistency, by way
NOTES
' Resnik (1974) and Detlefson (1979) are recent exceptions that take account of the
special features of the Second Theorem.
2 See Boolos-Jeffrey (1974), Boolos (1978) and Monk (1976).
(1) first appears in Tarski (1960).
4 The converse implication supports a valid deductive argument from (1) to (2). Un-
fortunately the converse implication is false; weaker theories than Q are sufficiently
strong. The suggested implication is true, but not sufficiently helpful. A complete analysis
would bring out the contextual nature of 'sufficiently strong'. Alternatively, one could
use the converse implication, replacing the predicate 'is an extension of Q' with 'has
those features of Q that are relevant to the proof of G 1', or some illuminating coextensive
predicate.
' If (2) strikes one as mathematical, note that all that is really needed for my point is
that passage from (1) to (2) is mediated by theses unsupported by mathematical evidence.
(2) seems mathematical because the mediating theses seem definitional.
6 'Derivable', 'underivable', etc. will be used in connection with formulas of a formalism;
'provable', 'proof', etc., are reserved for the ordinary notions of unformalized mathe-
matical practice. 1 occasionally violate this convention, for the sake of custom, in the
context of discussing is a proof of and the 'proof' predicate. Strict speaking would
demand 'is a derivation of' and 'derivation predicate'. Note that the looser remark cited
in the text offers little obvious guidance regarding a choice between 'underivable' and
(unprovable'.
See Note 1, above.
P p is the well-known Peano arithmetic, so-called because of its name. Q is a well-studied
theory in the language of arithmetic. It has finitely many axioms (seven, all simple and
clearly true in the standard model), all recursive functions are representable in Q, and yet
it is a rather weak subtheory of P (that addition is commutative is not a theorem of Q).
Therc are even weaker theories that will suffice for the F-irst Theorem; Q's virtue is its
finite axiomatizability. See Tarski (1960) and Boolos (1978). For now 'CON(P)' is a
simple term.
9 Numeralwise expressibility is a three place relation among formal systems, relations
among or properties of numbers, and predicates of formal systems. A formal predicate
that numeralwise expresses a relation in an arithmetically correct formal system is there-
by guaranteed to be extensionally correct with respect to that relation. 1 numeralwise
expresses R, R an m-place relation, ill
where '' denotes the function from numbers to their standard numerals in the formal-
ism. All recursive relations are numeralwise expressible in Q and its extensions, including,
of course. P. 1 is said to numerate R, in consistent formalisms, if R(-n) Ho (n).
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Boolos, G.: 1978, The Unprovability of Consistency: An Essay in Modal Logic (Cam-
bridge University Press, Cambridge).
Boolos, G. and R. Jeffrey: 1974, Computability and Logic (Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge).
Detlefson, M: 1979, 'On interpreting Godel's Second Incompleteness Theorem', Journal
of Philosophical Logic 8, pp. 297-315.
Feferman, S.: 1960, "Arithmetization of Metamathematics in a General Setting",
Fundamenta Mathematicae XLIX, pp. 35-92.
Feferman, S.: 1962, "Transfmite Recursive Progressions of Axiomatic Theories", JSL
XXVII, pp. 259-316.
Hilbert, D. and Bernays, P.: 1939, Die Grundlagen der Mathematik, 2nd ed. (Springer-
Verlag, Berlin).
Jerolsow, R.: 1971, 'On Godel's consistency theorem', unpublished manuscript.
Jeroslow, R.: 1973, 'Redundancies in the Hilbert-Bernays derivability conditions for
Godel's Second Incompleteness Theorem', Journal of Symbolic Logic XXXVIII,
pp. 359-367.
Kleene, S. C.: 1950, Introduction to Metamathematics (Van Nostrand, Princeton).
Kreisel, G.: 1965, 'Mathematical logic', in T. L. Saaty (ed.), Lectures on Modern Mathe-
matics III (Wiley, New York).
Lob, M. H.: 1955, "Solution of a Problem of Leon Henkin", Journal of Symbolic Logic
XX,pp. 115-118.
Mates, B.: 1972, Elementary Logic, 2nd ed. (Oxford University Press, New York).
Monk, J. D.: 1976, Mathematical Logic (Springer-Verlag, New York, Heidelberg, Be
Resnik, M.: 1974, "The Philosophical Significance of Consistency Proofs", Journal of
Philosophical Logic 3, pp. 133-147.
Tarski, A., A. Mostowski, and R. Robinson: 1960, Undecidable Theories (North-Holland,
Amsterdam).