A Perspectival Definition of Knowñedge
A Perspectival Definition of Knowñedge
A Perspectival Definition of Knowñedge
Claudio F. Costa
Abstract
In this paper an improved formulation of the classical tripartite view
of knowledge is proposed and defended. This formulation solves
Gettier’s problem by making explicit what is concealed by the
symbolic version of the tripartite definition, namely, the perspec-
tival context in which concrete knowledge claims are evaluated.
( i ) ( ii ) ( iii )
( Df .k1) aKp ≡ p & aBp & aEBp ( where p = proposition,
a = person, B = belief ,
E = reasonable justifying
evidence) .
It is well-known that this formulation has given rise to a challenge
to the rationality of our knowledge which is known as counterex-
amples of Gettier’s kind. These counterexamples have lead to a
multiplicity of answers which have typically generated new difficul-
ties, even suggesting that the conceptual analysis of knowledge is a
kind of degenerative research program without good prospects.
Our overall diagnosis of the situation is much more optimistic:
the classical view of propositional knowledge, as presented in
the formulation above, though not incorrect, is an oversimplifi-
cation of conceptual structures that have always belonged to the
praxis of our natural language, concealing a perspectival and
potentially dialogical dimension of our knowledge evaluations. It
is this concealing that leads to misunderstandings of the Get-
tierian kind. This diagnosis calls for a therapy which consists in
152 CLAUDIO F. COSTA
( i ) ( ii ) ( iii )
( Df .k 2 ) aKp ≡ p & aBp & (aEBp & ( E => p )) .
1
R. F. Almeder: ‘Truth and Evidence’, The Philosophical Quarterly, 24 (1974), pp. 365–68.
2
W. E. Hoffmann: ‘Almeder on Truth and Evidence’, The Philosophical Quarterly, 25
(1975), pp. 59–61.
3
Robert Fogelin: Pyrrhonian Reflections on Knowledge and Justification (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1994), pp. 22–23.
What DE says is intuitively clear. Let us suppose for now that the
knowledge evaluator is the teacher s, who asks the schoolgirl a
where the city of Angkor is located, and that a answers (correctly)
p: ‘Angkor is in Cambodia’. To judge that a knows p, s must know
that a knows p, and in order to know this, according to the
tripartite definition, s must also know that p is true (that Angkor
4
Knowledge evaluators must always assume previous knowledge. This brings in to play
the threat of infinite regresses, e.g. ‘. . . sKsK(aKp)’ or ‘. . . sKsKp’. However, s can easily
take the place of a in further evaluations. Moreover, in cases like sK(aKp) and sKp, where
there is no possible distinction between evidence for truth and justifying evidence, further
evaluation turns out to be pointless.
E3 = ‘Ships seem to sink below the horizon when they sail out of
view’. In this case, for s ‘E* = {E1, E2, E3. . . En}’, and each of these
pieces of evidence is considered by s at t – assuming the truth of
his stock of beliefs at time t – to be sufficient to falsify the propo-
sition p2. This means that s knows (or believes he knows) at time t
that ‘E* & (E* ~> ~p2)’, namely, that the probability of ~p2 being
true is very high or that p2 is certainly false.
A third case is that in which s doesn’t know the truth value of
the proposition. For example: Suppose that s doesn’t know
whether the proposition p3 ‘Aston Rowant is bigger than Kingston
Blount’ is true. In this case, s’s corpus of evidence for p3 is empty:
E* = Ø.
Looking back to Df.E*, we come to the conclusion that a
subject s can access E* in three different ways:
relevant beliefs held by s (such as the belief that his car’s gas tank
does not have a leak, that the fingerprints were not planted, that
this is not a new kind of tumour . . .) are consistent with the
conditionals, it follows that if the antecedent true, the consequent
should very probably also be true. Hence, it seems that the sign
‘~>’ gives s enough of a sense of ‘being sufficient’ or ‘being
enough’ or ‘making true’, insofar as he interprets it as making its
consequent true with a very high probability, assuming the truth
of the relevant beliefs belonging to the stock of beliefs held by s at
the time of his evaluation.
Now that we have explained our concept of E* it is time to
return to our task of restating sKtj(p) in a precise and fully explicit
way. We have seen that sKtj(p) can be rendered as sKtj(there is at
least one piece of evidence E, such that E is sufficient for the truth
of p), where the evidence and its role were only mentioned. Now,
using E* we can restate what is contextually assumed in the con-
dition of truth as it appears in the DE as:
( i ’) sK tj ( E * & ( E * ∼> p )) .
Indeed, when s is aware of an E* at tj, and when for him E* has
some element viewed as sufficient for the truth of p, then s con-
cludes either deductively (using the modus ponens) or inductively
(using the rule of induction) that p must be true, which amounts
to the same thing as the satisfaction of the conditions of truth! In
this way, ‘E* & (E* ~> p)’ only makes explicit what we (as place-
holders for s) implicitly mean by ‘p’ in the condition of truth. As
we will see, this analysis will suffice as a restatement of the condi-
tion of truth which does not play down the role of the knowledge
evaluator.
The next step is to improve DE substituting (i’) for (i) and (iii’)
for (iii), as follows:
5
Thanks to professors Richard Swinburne and João Branquinho for helpful advice and
support.