Commentary Critique of Pure Reason
Commentary Critique of Pure Reason
Commentary Critique of Pure Reason
A COMMENTARY
TO
K A N T’S ‘C R I T I Q U E
OF
P U R E R E A S O N’
BY
NORMAN KEMP SMITH, D.PHIL.
McCOSH PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY, PRINCETON UNIVERSITY
AUTHOR OF
‘STUDIES IN THE CARTESIAN PHILOSOPHY’
TO THE MEMORY
OF
ROBERT ADAMSON
GRATEFULLY DEDICATED
PREFACE
The Critique of Pure Reason is more obscure and difficult than
even a metaphysical treatise has any right to be. The
difficulties are not merely due to defects of exposition; they
multiply rather than diminish upon detailed study; and, as I
shall endeavour to show in this Commentary, are traceable to
two main causes, the composite nature of the text, written at
various dates throughout the period 1772-1780, and the
conflicting tendencies of Kant’s own thinking.
The Commentary is both expository and critical; and in
exposition no less than in criticism I have sought to
subordinate the treatment of textual questions and of minor
issues to the systematic discussion of the central problems.
Full use is made of the various selections from Kant’s private
papers that have appeared, at intervals, since the publication of
his Lectures on Metaphysics in 1821. Their significance has
not hitherto been generally recognised in English books upon
Kant. They seem to me to be of capital importance for the
right understanding of the Critique.
Some apology is perhaps required for publishing a work of
this character at the present moment. It was completed, and
arrangements made for its publication, shortly before the
outbreak of war. The printers have, I understand, found in it a
useful stop-gap to occupy them in the intervals of more
pressing work; and now that the type must be released, I trust
that in spite of, or even because of, the overwhelming
preoccupations of the war, there may be some few readers to
whom the volume may be not unwelcome. That even amidst
the distractions of actual campaigning metaphysical
speculation can serve as a refuge and a solace is shown by the
memorable example of General Smuts. He has himself told us
that on his raid into Cape Colony in the South African War he
carried with him for evening reading the Critique of Pure
Reason. Is it surprising that our British generals, pitted against
so unconventional an opponent, should have been worsted in
the battle of wits?
The Critique of Pure Reason is a philosophical classic that
marks a turning-point in the history of philosophy, and no
interpretation, even though now attempted after the lapse of a
hundred years, can hope to be adequate or final. Some things
are clearer to us than they were to Kant’s contemporaries; in
other essential ways our point of view has receded from his,
and the historical record, that should determine our judgments,
is far from complete. But there is a further difficulty of an
even more serious character. The Critique deals with issues
that are still controversial, and their interpretation is possible
only from a definite standpoint. The limitations of this
standpoint and of the philosophical milieu in which it has been
acquired unavoidably intervene to distort or obscure our
apprehension of the text. Arbitrary and merely personal
judgments I have, however, endeavoured to avoid. My sole
aim has been to reach, as far as may prove feasible, an
unbiassed understanding of Kant’s great work.
Among German commentators I owe most to Vaihinger,
Adickes, B. Erdmann, Cohen, and Riehl, especially to the first
named. The chief English writers upon Kant are Green, Caird,
and Adamson. In so far as Green and Caird treat the Critical
philosophy as a half-way stage to the Hegelian standpoint I
find myself frequently in disagreement with them; but my
indebtedness to their writings is much greater than my
occasional criticisms of their views may seem to imply. With
Robert Adamson I enjoyed the privilege of personal
discussions at a time when his earlier view of Kant’s teaching
was undergoing revision in a more radical manner than is
apparent even in his posthumously published University
lectures. To the stimulus of his suggestions the writing of this
Commentary is largely due.
My first study of the Critique was under the genial and
inspiring guidance of Sir Henry Jones. With characteristic
kindliness he has read through my manuscript and has
disclosed to me many defects of exposition and argument. The
same service has been rendered me by Professor G. Dawes
Hicks, whose criticisms have been very valuable, particularly
since they come from a student of Kant who on many
fundamental points takes an opposite view from my own.
I have also to thank my colleague, Professor Oswald
Veblen, for much helpful discussion of Kant’s doctrines of
space and time, and of mathematical reasoning.
Mr. H. H. Joachim has read the entire proofs, and I have
made frequent modifications to meet his very searching
criticisms. I have also gratefully adopted his revisions of my
translations from the Critique. Similar acknowledgments are
due to my colleague, Professor A. A. Bowman, and to my
friend Dr. C. W. Hendel.
I have in preparation a translation of the Critique of Pure
Reason, and am responsible for the translations of all passages
given in the present work. In quoting from Kant’s other
writings, I have made use of the renderings of Abbott,
Bernard, and Mahaffy; but have occasionally allowed myself
the liberty of introducing alterations.
Should readers who are already well acquainted with the
Critique desire to use my Commentary for its systematic
discussions of Kant’s teaching, rather than as an
accompaniment to their study of the text, I may refer them to
those sections which receive italicised headings in the table of
contents.
NORMAN KEMP SMITH.
LONDON, January 1918.
CONTENTS
INTRODUCTION
PAGE
I. TEXTUAL—
Kant’s Method of composing the
Critique of Pure Reason xix
II. HISTORICAL—
Kant’s Relation to Hume and to Leibniz xxv
III. GENERAL—
1. The Nature of the a priori xxxiii
2. Kant’s Contribution to the Science of
Logic xxxvi
3. The Nature of Consciousness xxxix
4. Phenomenalism, Kant’s Substitute
for Subjectivism xlv
5. The Distinction between Human and
Animal Intelligence xlvii
6. The Nature and Conditions of Self-
Consciousness l
7. Kant’s threefold Distinction between
Sensibility, Understanding, and Reason lii
8. The place of the Critique of Pure
Reason in Kant’s Philosophical System lv
THE CRITIQUE OF PURE REASON[1]
Title 1
Motto 4
Dedication to Freiherr von Zedlitz 6
PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION 8
Comment on Preface 10
Dogmatism, Scepticism, Criticism 13
PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION 17
The Copernican Hypothesis 22
Introduction 26
Comment upon the Argument of Kant’s
Introduction 33
How are Synthetic a priori Judgments 43
possible?
The Analytic and Synthetic Methods 44
Purpose and Scope of the Critique 56
Kant’s relation to Hume 61
Meaning of the term Transcendental 73
THE TRANSCENDENTAL DOCTRINE OF ELEMENTS
Part I. THE TRANSCENDENTAL AESTHETIC 79-
166
Definition of Terms 79
Kant’s conflicting Views of Space 88
Section I. SPACE 99
Kant’s Attitude to the Problems of
Modern Geometry 117
Section II. Time 123
Kant’s Views regarding the Nature of
Arithmetical Science 128
Kant’s conflicting Views of Time 134
General Observations on the
Transcendental Aesthetic 143
The Distinction between Appearance
and Illusion 148
Kant’s Relation to Berkeley 155
The Paradox of Incongruous
Counterparts 161
Part II. THE TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC 167
Introduction 167
I. Logic in General 167
II. Transcendental Logic 170
III. The Division of General Logic into
Analytic and Dialectic 172
Division I. THE TRANSCENDENTAL ANALYTIC 174
Book I. THE ANALYTIC OF CONCEPTS 175
Chapter I. THE CLUE TO THE DISCOVERY OF
ALL PURE CONCEPTS OF THE UNDERSTANDING 175
Section I. The Logical Use of the
Understanding 176
Comment on Kant’s Argument 176
Stages in the Development of Kant’s 186
Metaphysical Deduction
Section II. The Logical Function of the
Understanding in Judgment 192
Section III. The Categories on Pure
Concepts of the Understanding 194
Distinction between Logical Forms
and Categories 195
Chapter II. DEDUCTION OF THE PURE
CONCEPTS OF THE UNDERSTANDING 202
Analysis of the Text: the Four Stages in 202-
the Development of Kant’s Views 234
I. Enumeration of the Four Stages 203
II. Detailed Analysis of the Four Stages 204
Kant’s Doctrine of the Transcendental
Object 204
III. Evidence yielded by the
“Reflexionen” and “Lose Blätter” in
Support of the Analysis of the Text 231
IV. Connected Statement and Discussion
of Kant’s Subjective and Objective
Deductions in the First Edition 234
Distinction between the Subjective and
the Objective Deductions 235
The Subjective Deduction in its initial
empirical Stages 245
Objective Deduction as given in the
First Edition 248
The later Stages of the Subjective
Deduction 263
The Distinction between
Phenomenalism and Subjectivism 270
Transcendental Deduction of the
Categories in the Second Edition 284
The Doctrine of Inner Sense 291
Kant’s Refutations of Idealism 298
Inner Sense and Apperception 321
Book II. The Analytic of Principles 332
Chapter I. THE SCHEMATISM OF PURE 334
CONCEPTS OF THE UNDERSTANDING
Chapter II. SYSTEM OF ALL PRINCIPLES OF
PURE UNDERSTANDING 342
1. The Axioms of Intuition 347
2. The Anticipations of Perception 349
3. The Analogies of Experience 355
A. First Analogy 358
B. Second Analogy 363
Schopenhauer’s Criticism of Kant’s
Argument 365
Kant’s Subjectivist and Phenomenalist
Views of the Causal Relation 373
Reply to Further Criticisms of Kant’s
Argument 377
C. Third Analogy 381
Schopenhauer’s Criticism of Kant’s
Argument 387
4. The Postulates of Empirical Thought
in General 391
Chapter III. ON THE GROUND OF THE
DISTINCTION OF ALL OBJECTS WHATEVER INTO
PHENOMENA AND NOUMENA 404
Relevant Passages in the Section on
Amphiboly 410
Alterations in the Second Edition 412
Comment on Kant’s Argument 414
Appendix. The Amphiboly of the
Concepts of Reflection 418
Division II. THE TRANSCENDENTAL
DIALECTIC 424
Introductory Comment upon the
composite Origin and conflicting
Tendencies of the Dialectic 425
The History and Development of
Kant’s Views in regard to the Problems of
the Dialectic 431
Introduction 441
I. Transcendental Illusion 441
II. Pure Reason as the Seat of
Transcendental Illusion 442
Book I. THE CONCEPTS OF PURE REASON 446
Section I. Ideas in General 447
Section II. The Transcendental Ideas 450
Section III. System of the
Transcendental Ideas 453
Book II. THE DIALECTICAL INFERENCES OF
PURE REASON 455
Chapter I. THE PARALOGISMS OF PURE
REASON 455
First Paralogism: of Substantiality 457
Second Paralogism: of Simplicity 458
Third Paralogism: of Personality 461
Fourth Paralogism: of Ideality 462
Second Edition Statement of the
Paralogisms 466
Is the Notion of the Self a necessary
Idea of Reason? 473
Chapter II. THE ANTINOMY OF PURE REASON 478
Section I. System of the Cosmological
Ideas 478
Section II. Antithetic of Pure Reason 480
Comment on Kant’s Method of
Argument 481
First Antinomy 483
Second Antinomy 488
Third Antinomy 492
Fourth Antinomy 495
Section III. The Interest of Reason in this
Self-Conflict 498
Section IV. Of the Transcendental
Problems of Pure Reason in so far as they
absolutely must be capable of Solution 499
Section V. Sceptical Representation of
the Cosmological Questions 501
Section VI. Transcendental Idealism as 503
the Key to the Solution of the
Cosmological Dialectic
Section VII. Critical Decision of the
Cosmological Conflict of Reason with
itself 504
Section VIII. The Regulative Principle of
Pure Reason in regard to the Cosmological
Ideas 506
Section IX. The Empirical Employment
of the Regulative Principles of Reason in
regard to all Cosmological Ideas 508
Solution of the First and Second
Antinomies 508
Remarks on the Distinction between the
Mathematical-Transcendental and the
Dynamical-Transcendental Ideas 510
Comment on Kant’s Method of
Argument 510
Solution of the Third Antinomy 512
Possibility of harmonising Causality
through Freedom with the Universal Law
of Natural Necessity 513
Explanation of the Relation of Freedom
to Necessity of Nature 514
Comment on Kant’s Method of
Argument 517
Solution of the Fourth Antinomy 518
Concluding Note on the whole
Antinomy of Pure Reason 519
Concluding Comment on Kant’s
Doctrine of the Antinomies 519
Chapter III. THE IDEAL OF PURE REASON 522
Section I. and II. The Transcendental
Ideal 522
Comment on Kant’s Method of
Argument 524
Section III. The Speculative Arguments 525
in Proof of the Existence of a Supreme
Being
Section IV. The Impossibility of an
Ontological Proof 527
Comment on Kant’s Method of
Argument 528
Section V. The Impossibility of a
Cosmological Proof of the Existence of
God 531
Comment on Kant’s Method of
Argument 533
Discovery and Explanation of the
Transcendental Illusion in all
Transcendental Proof of the Existence of a
necessary Being 534
Comment on Kant’s Method of
Argument 535
Section VI. The Impossibility of the
Physico-Theological Proof 538
Section VII. Criticism of all Theology
based on speculative Principles of Reason 541
Concluding Comment 541
APPENDIX TO THE TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC 543
The Regulative Employment of the Ideas
of Pure Reason 543
Hypotheses not permissible in Philosophy 543
On the Final Purpose of the Natural
Dialectic of Human Reason 552
Concluding Comment on the Dialectic 558
APPENDIX A.
THE TRANSCENDENTAL DOCTRINE OF
METHODS 563
Chapter I. THE DISCIPLINE OF PURE REASON 563
Section I. The Discipline of Pure Reason
in its Dogmatic Employment 563
Section II. The Discipline of Pure
Reason in its Polemical Employment 567
Section III. The Discipline of Pure
Reason in regard to Hypotheses 568
Section IV. The Discipline of Pure 568
Reason in regard to its Proofs
Chapter II. THE CANON OF PURE REASON 569
Section I. The Ultimate End of the Pure
Use of our Reason 569
Section II. The Ideal of the Highest
Good, as a Determining Ground of the
Ultimate End of Pure Reason 570
Section III. Opining, Knowing, and
Believing 576
Chapter III. THE ARCHITECTONIC OF PURE
REASON 579
Chapter IV. THE HISTORY OF PURE REASON 582
APPENDIX B.
A more detailed Statement of Kant’s
Relations to his Philosophical
Predecessors 583
INDEX: A, B, C, D, E, F, G, H, I, J, K, L, M,
N, O, P, Q, R, S, T, U, V, W, Z 607
NOTE
In all references to the Kritik der Reinen Vernunft I have
given the original pagings of both the first and second editions.
References to Kant’s other works are, whenever possible, to
the volumes thus far issued in the new Berlin edition. As the
Reflexionen Kants zur Kritik der reinen Vernunft had not been
published in this edition at the time when the Commentary was
completed, the numbering given is that of B. Erdmann’s
edition of 1884.
ABBREVIATIONS
Berlin edition of Kant’s works W
Pagings in the first edition of the Kritik der reinen Vernunft
A
Pagings in the second edition B
Adickes’ edition of the Kritik der reinen Vernunft (1889) K
INTRODUCTION
I. TEXTUAL
KANT’S METHOD OF COMPOSING THE ‘CRITIQUE OF PURE
REASON’
DEDICATION
TO
Pure.—In the title of the section the term pure[199] (rein) is,
as the subsequent argument shows, taken as exactly equivalent
to a priori. As Vaihinger notes, the adjective apriorisch had
not yet been invented. The opposite of pure is here empirical
(empirisch).[200]
All our knowledge begins with experience.[201]—This is a
stronger statement than any in the corresponding paragraphs of
the first edition. Had Kant proceeded to develop its
consequences, he would have had to recast the entire
Introduction, setting the problem of empirical knowledge
alongside that of the a priori.[202] As it is, he is forced[203] to
subdivide the absolutely a priori into the pure and the mixed.
[204]
SECTION I
SPACE
SECTION II
TIME
DIVISION I
THE TRANSCENDENTAL ANALYTIC
DIVISION II
IDEAS IN GENERAL[1386]
Kant connects his use of the term Idea with the meaning in
which it is employed by Plato. He urges upon all true lovers of
philosophy the imperative need of rescuing from misuse a
term so indispensable to mark a distinction more vital than any
other to the very existence of the philosophical disciplines.
”[For Plato] Ideas are the archetypes of the things
themselves, and not, like the categories, merely keys to
possible experiences. In his view they issued from the
Supreme Reason, and from that source have come to be shared
in by human Reason…. He very well realised that our faculty
of knowledge feels a much higher need than merely to spell
out appearances according to a synthetic unity, in order to read
them as experience. He knew that our Reason naturally exalts
itself to forms of knowledge which so far transcend the bounds
of experience that no given empirical object can ever coincide
with them, but which must none the less be recognised as
having their own reality and which are by no means mere
fictions of the brain.”[1387]
Plato found these ideas chiefly, though not exclusively, in
the practical sphere. When moral standards are in question,
experience is the mother of illusion.
“For nothing can be more injurious or more unworthy of a
philosopher than the vulgar appeal to so-called adverse
experience. Such experience would never have existed at all, if
those institutions had been established at the proper time in
accordance with Ideas, and if Ideas had not been displaced by
crude conceptions which, just because they have been derived
from experience, have nullified all good intentions.”[1388]
Even in the natural sphere Ideas which are never themselves
adequately embodied in the actual must be postulated in order
to account for the actual. Certain forms of existences “are
possible only according to Ideas.”
“A plant, an animal, the orderly arrangement of the cosmos
—probably, therefore, the entire natural world—clearly show
that they are possible only according to Ideas, and that though
no single creature in the conditions of its individual existence
coincides with the Idea of what is most perfect in its kind—
just as little as does any individual man exactly conform to the
Idea of humanity, which he actually carries in his soul as the
archetype of his actions—yet these Ideas are none the less
completely determined in the Supreme Understanding, each as
an individual and each as unchangeable, and are the original
causes of things. But only the totality of things, in their
interconnection as constituting the universe, is completely
adequate to the Idea.”[1389]
Though Kant avows the intention of adapting the term Idea
freely to the needs of his more Critical standpoint, all these
considerations contribute to the rich and varied meanings in
which he employs it.
Reflexionen and passages from the Lectures on Metaphysics
may be quoted to show the thoroughly Platonic character of
Kant’s early use of the term, and to illustrate its gradual
adjustment to Critical demands.
“The Idea is the unity of knowledge, through which the
manifold either of knowledge or of the object is possible. In
the former, the whole of knowledge precedes its parts, the
universal precedes the particular; in the latter, knowledge of
the objects precedes their possibility, as e.g. in [objects that
possess] order and perfection.”[1390] “That an object is possible
only through a form of knowledge is a surprising statement;
but all teleological relations are possible only through a form
of knowledge [i.e. a concept].”[1391] “The Idea is single
(individuum), self-sufficient, and eternal. The divinity of our
soul is its capacity to form the Idea. The senses give only
copies or rather apparentia.”[1392] “As the Understanding of
God is the ground of all possibility, archetypes, Ideas, are in
God…. The divine Intuitus contains Ideas according to which
we ourselves are possible; cognitio divina est cognitio
archetypa, and His Ideas are archetypes of things. The
[corresponding] forms of knowledge possessed by the human
understanding we may also entitle (in a comparative sense)
archetypes or Ideas. They are those representations of our
understanding which serve for judgment upon things.”[1393]
“Idea is the representation of the whole in so far as it
necessarily precedes the determination of the parts. It can
never be empirically represented, because in experience we
proceed from the parts through successive synthesis to the
whole. It is the archetype of things, for certain objects are only
possible through an Idea. Transcendental Ideas are those in
which the absolute whole determines the parts in an aggregate
or as series.”[1394] “The pure concepts of Reason have no
exemplaria; they are themselves archetypes. But the concepts
of our pure Reason have as their archetypes this Reason itself
and are therefore subjective, not objective.”[1395] “The
transcendental Ideas serve to limit the principles of experience,
forbidding their extension to things in themselves, and
showing that what is never an object of possible experience is
not therefore a non-entity [Unding], and that experience is not
adequate either to itself or to Reason, but always refers us
further to what is beyond itself.”[1396] “The employment of the
concept of understanding was immanent, that of the Ideas as
concepts of objects is transcendent. But as regulative
principles alike of the completion and of the limitation of our
knowledge, they are Critically immanent.”[1397] “The
difficulties of metaphysics all arise in connection with the
reconciling of empirical principles with Ideas. The possibility
of the latter cannot be denied, but neither can they be made
empirically intelligible. The Idea is never a conceptus dabilis;
it is not an empirically possible conception.”[1398]
Kant[1399] appends the following ‘Stufenleiter’ (ladder-like)
arrangement of titles for the various kinds of representation.
Representation (Vorstellung) is the term which he substitutes
for the Cartesian and Lockian employment of the term idea,
now reserved for use in its true Platonic meaning. To entitle
such a representation as that of red colour an idea is, in Kant’s
view, an intolerable and barbaric procedure; that
representation is not even a concept of the understanding.
SECTION II
Caird, E., xx, 1 n., 23, 51, 102 n., 114, 117, 183, 194, 195,
262, 296, 314, 328, 340, 357 n., 359 n., 373, 378, 399, 462,
468
Campanella, 74
Canon, 72, 169-70, 174, 332-3, 438, 569 ff.
Cassirer, E., 132
Categorical imperative, xxxvi, lvi-lviii, 571 ff.
Categories, distinction from generic concept, 178 ff.;
de facto nature of the, xxxv-xxxvi, xxxviii, xliv, 30, 57,
185-6, 257-8, 291, 391-2, 398, 400-1, 411;
definition of the, 195-6, 198, 339-42, 404-5;
semi-Critical view of the, 188-9, 217-18, 232, 263-4;
merely logical forms, xxxv-xxxvi, xxxviii, 30 n., 32, 39,
108, 176 ff., 185-6, 191, 195-196, 257-8, 290-1, 325 ff., 339-
40, 398, 404-5, 409-10, 413-14, 467;
valid only for appearances, 259-60;
and schemata, 195-6, 311, 333, 339-342, 467 n.;
metaphysical deduction of the, 183 ff., 192 ff., 287-8;
transcendental deduction of the, 234 ff., 287-8;
all categories involved in every act of consciousness, xli-
xlv, liii-liv, 199-200, 356, 368, 370, 377, 387-91;
have wider scope than the forms of sense, lv-lvi, 20, 25,
290-1, 331, 404 ff.;
restricted by time and space, 342, 357;
in relation to outer and inner experience, 311-12;
how far predicable of the ‘I think,’ 325 ff.;
how far applicable to sensations, desires, etc., xlvi n., 275-6,
279 ff., 312 ff., 384-5, 476;
proof of specific, 242-3, 252-3, 258-9, 287-8, 333, 343-4;
determinate and indeterminate application of the, 325 ff.,
405 ff.;
may be intrinsically inapplicable to things in themselves,
290, 409-10, 413-14;
category of existence, 322, 415 n.;
category of totality and Idea of the unconditioned, 199-200,
433, 451, 480, 529;
mathematical and dynamical, 198, 345-7, 510-11.
See A priori, Understanding
Catharticon, 169, 174
Causality, Kant influenced by Hume’s teaching regarding, xxv
ff., 61-4, 364 ff., 593-600;
Kant’s treatment of the principle of, 363 ff.;
Kant’s subjectivist and phenomenalist views of, 216, 217-
18, 318-21, 351, 373-4;
sensations, feelings, etc. subject to principle of, xlvi n., 275,
279-82, 312, 384-5;
category of, involved in consciousness of time, liii-liv, 365
ff., 377 ff., 387;
and freedom, 492 ff.
See Hume
Clarke, 140, 539, 594
Cohen, H., 51, 102 n., 195, 262, 340
Coherence theory of truth, xxxvi-xxxix, 36 ff., 173 n.;
criterion of truth bound up with the Ideas of Reason, 217-
18, 326 n., 331, 390-1, 414-17, 426-31, 473-7, 511-12, 519-21,
541-2, 558-61
Concept, Kant’s generic or class view of the, 99-100, 105-7,
118-19, 126, 132-3, 177-84, 338-9, 370-1, 377-84, 390-1;
intuition and conception, 38-42, 93-4, 105-9, 118-20, 126,
128-134, 165-6, 167-8, 194, 370, 390-1, 564-6;
construction of concepts, 41, 131-3, 338-9, 418 ff., 564-6;
concepts and images, 337-9;
Kant’s doctrine of the pure concept, xxxix, 394-400, 418 ff.
See Understanding
Concerning the Advances, made, etc.
See Fortschritte
Consciousness, Kant’s views regarding, xxxiv-xxxv, xxxix-
xlv, xliii-xlvii, l-lii;
and the animal mind, xlvii-l;
may be a resultant, xxxiv, xliii-xlv, l-lii, 261-3, 277-9, 327,
459-62, 473-7;
no immediate consciousness of mind’s own activities, xliii-
xlv, l-lii, 263 ff., 273 ff., 293, 295 ff., 322 ff.;
consciousness of time Kant’s datum, xxxiv, 120, 241 ff.,
365 ff., 381 ff.;
absolutist aspect of, xxx-xxxiii, liii, lvi-lvii, 270-1, 274, 282,
285-7, 331 n.
See Apperception, Judgment
Contingency, assertion of, 39 ff., 55, 286-9
Continuity, Kant’s views regarding, 352-355, 488 ff., 509;
principle of, 380-1;
transcendental principle of, 551
Copernicus, 18-19, 22-5
Cosmological Argument, 531 ff.
Criterion of truth. See Coherence theory of truth
Criticism, Kant’s use of term, 1, 9, 13-14, 21;
Age of, 15
Critique of Practical Reason, lvi, lvii, lx, 77-8, 569 ff., 572
Critique of Judgment, lxi, 77, 83, 97-8, 191, 265, 537, 539,
561, 569 n., 574, 575 n., 576, 577 n.
Crusius, xxviii, xxxii, 47
Curtius, E., 336
Jacobi, 300
Jakob, xxviii n.
James, W., 86, 277-8, 459 n., 461 n.
Janitsch, 155, 156
Jones, Sir Henry, 36
Judgment, Kant’s doctrine of the, xxxiv-xxxv, xxxviii, xli-xliv,
xlviii-l, 177 ff., 192 ff., 286 ff.;
the fundamental activity of the understanding, xxxiv-xxxv,
xxxviii, xli-xlii, 133, 181-2, 288, 332, 370;
a priori and empirical, 27-8;
analytic and synthetic, xxv ff., 28 ff., 37 ff., 59-60;
judgment 7 + 5 = 12, 65;
relational types ignored by Kant, 37 ff.;
Kant’s attributive view of, 37-38, 180-1, 197;
as assertion of contingency, 39 ff., 55, 286-9;
Kant’s distinction between judgments of perception and
judgments of experience, 288-9;
existential, 527-31
Vaihinger, Hans, xx, xxv, xxviii n., xliv n., 2, 13, 23, 43, 45 ff.,
52, 53, 59, 60, 64, 65, 66, 81, 87, 104, 105, 109, 112, 113, 117,
127, 130, 139, 140, 143, 147, 148, 156, 161, 162, 202 ff., 261,
268-9, 298-9, 301, 314-315, 579 n., 601 n.
Value, problems of, lvi, lx-lxi
Void, Kant’s doctrine of the, 354-5
Voltaire, xxxi, 436, 539
Von dem ersten Grunde des Unterschiedes der Gegenden im
Raume, Kant’s, 40, 86 n., 140, 162
Watson, J., 1 n., 23 n., 75, 102 n., 117, 183, 195, 196, 198,
262, 328, 462, 468 n., 564
Windelband, 46
Wolff, 192-3, 272, 436, 440, 522, 579, 587, 601-6