Political Violence
Political Violence
Political Violence
Political Violence
When one regards the conflicts of the past century, Hegel’s description of history
as a “slaughter-bench” seems apt.1 The two world wars the century witnessed were ex-
traordinarily violent. In the First, the combatants were subject to an industrial scale
and poison gas. The Second World War added to these horrors with its concept of “total
war,” which was defined as a war directed against the totality of the enemy nation: its
schools, factories, cities, in short, the entirety of its civilian population. In pursuit of this
policy, cities were firebombed, populations were deported or systematically starved, and
non-combatants generally were subject to much the same violence as armies in the field.
This extension of violence to civilian populations continued in the conflicts that followed.
It was particularly marked in the liberation struggles and the civil wars that have ex-
tended from the post-war period to this day. While violence between nations has not
been lacking, the organized intra-state violence of civil wars and the violence of “failed”
states have come to the fore. Again and again, we witness outrages against defenseless
populations, their robbing and murder by marauding bands. Such violence seems a con-
tinuation of the violence that arises whenever the withdrawal of the forces of civil order
looting and gang violence with its settling of scores seems inevitably to errupt. As the
example of countries from Somalia to Iraq has shown, such violence only ceases when
In noting these facts, I do not mean to suggest that the past century or our own are
good part of the political and diplomatic efforts of mankind can be understood in terms of
our attempts to deal with violence. Viewed in this light, the ultimate issue may well be
how one prevents political differences from becoming violent. What makes such a ques-
tion so difficult for the West is our tradition of equating freedom with sovereignty.
Sovereignty is the prerogative to rule. It expresses, in Hannah Arendt’s words, “the ideal
arises: “If we wish to be free, we must be sovereign. Given our dependence on others,
the self-sufficiency required for sovereignty implies being master over them. We thus
face the choice between ruling and being ruled. To rule, we must engage in violence, we
must deprive others of their ability to rule us.” This argument implies that freedom and
violence are conjoined. It indicates that the thrust towards freedom is itself an impetus
towards violence. If we grant this, then we cannot say that the ideal of political life is the
maximum consonant (or harmonious) expression of the freedom of each of the citizens.3
Rather, the conjunction of violence and freedom implies that politics consists not so
The fact that limiting freedom does not always contain violence should make us
pause. In fact, our failures with regard to containing political violence indicate how im-
perfectly we understand its nature. In what follows, I am going to argue that the West’s
equation of freedom and sovereignty is, in fact, a conflation, one based on a deeper con-
fusion of two very different attitudes we can have towards our others. My claim will be
3
that it is only by untangling them that we can gain a practical understanding of the nature
of political violence.
going to abstract from the question of international violence. This can be done by accept-
ing the argument that such violence is the result of a lack of an international political or-
der, one with the power to enforce its decrees on individual states. To the point that such
an order becomes effectively binding, individual states, at least with regard to the ques-
tion of violence, can be considered to be federated into a single state, one with an en-
the question of how to avoid intra-state violence. Such violence, it is asserted, can be
prevented through a binding constitution. The constitution sets, as it were, the rules of
the game for managing conflicts of interest. In doing so, it places limits on the ability of
1
Hegel describes “history as the slaughter-bench at which the happiness of
peoples, the wisdom of states, and the virtue of individuals have been victimized”
(Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, The Philosophy of History, trans. J. Sibree
[New York: Dover Publications, 1956], p. 21.
2
Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition (Chicago: The University of
Chicago Press 1958), p. 234.
3
This is Kant’s ideal. He writes: “A constitution of the greatest possible hu-
man freedom according to laws, by which the liberty of every individual can con-
sist with the liberty of every other … is … a necessary idea, which must be
placed at the foundation not only of the first plan of the constitution of a state, but
of all its laws” (Critique of Pure Reason, B373).
4
interests, to the point that they involve the law, become conflicts over the interests that
should be represented in writing the law. As such, they can be settled by elections. The
same holds for conflicts regarding who should execute the laws. The president in the
American system is chosen by vote. Parliamentary systems, have their own varied ways
of choosing the prime minister. The same holds for conflicts involving who should inter-
pret the laws. The constitution, in setting up the judiciary, regulates this as well.
The difficulties with this response are well known. The electoral system can be-
exclusion of classes of voters. The judiciary can become politicized through the partisan
terests. Such politization can include the judges called on to interpret the constitution.
Here, the constitution itself, rather than regulating political conflict, becomes an object of
competing, irreconcilable interests. At end of this process, the constitution can lose its
binding authority. In the absence of such authority, there is nothing to prevent either the
executive or the legislative authorities from ignoring the “rules of the game” it represents.
solidarity. It holds that the ultimate bulwark against factionalism rending the constitution
is a certain social cohesion or consensus—one that translates into a sense of respect for
the law and with this into a respect for the constitution itself. Charles Taylor, for exam-
ple, warns that “democratic society will collapse” without such “foundations” as “consen-
sus,” “solidarity,” and “cohesion.”4 You need these foundations to insure not just that
people will “pay their taxes without being hounded, but also people will become soldiers
4
“A Conversation with Charles Taylor,” Symposium 9:1 (2005), 124.
5
and go to war, people will participate in its decisions and vote.” What is needed is some
kind of “identification with the whole.” He also states: “That is where communitarianism
comes in for me … many liberal theories completely ignore the conditions of this kind of
creation without which you don’t have a liberal society, you don’t have a democratic so-
ciety.”5 Taylor’s point is that the state insures its foundation by the “reinforcement of
common values” through programs designed to promote these. The difficulty with this
solution can be drawn from the very context of Taylor’s remarks, which is that of his
home province, Quebec. Many Quebecois did not feel sufficient solidarity with the rest
of Canada to accept the draft during the Second World War. The programs subsequently
instituted to insure common values deepened the solidarity among the French, but not
with the ethnic groups forming the rest of the country. In the last referendum on indepen-
dence, which followed the failure of constitutional talks, the break-up of Canada was
averted by the narrowest of margins. At present, the constitution continues to be the chief
point of conflict between the Quebec nationalists and those who oppose them. The diffi-
culty, then, of relying on the creation of common values is that commonality can all to of-
ten reduce itself to the solidarities of race, language, or class and their associated values.
When it does, such commonality ignores the alterity that is essential to modern, pluralis-
tic states.
The Canadian example can furnish us with another means for holding a nation to-
gether. This is the use of state power. In response to the activities of the Quebec Libera-
tion Front in 1971, the Canadian prime minister, Pierre Trudeau, invoked the War Powers
Act, suspending civil liberties. Although the Act was of short duration, it did forcibly ex-
5
Ibid., 121.
6
hibit, through the presence of police and soldiers, the state’s legal monopoly of the means
of violence. In other countries, such “states of emergency” can be frequent and long last-
ing. At the end of this prospect is the permanent suspension, not just of civil liberties, but
of the constitution itself. The state becomes transformed into an opponent of political life
as this is normally understood. Politics itself, with the loss of the constitution that regu-
lates the rules of its game, comes to an end and is replaced by a tyranny.
II
limiting state powers, provisions that declare, in the words of the American Bill of
Rights, that “Congress shall pass no law that ….” The difficulties with such safeguards
are both practical and theoretical. On a practical level, the constitution by itself is a mere
piece of paper. It has no enforcing powers. Powers of enforcement belong to the state,
the very state that can, in declaring a state of emergency, suspend the constitution. On
the theoretical level, the difficulty can be put in terms of the position that nations with
their constitutions are the result of a founding violence. Once called into existence, they
Thomas Hobbes’ argument for this is instructive. He traces the origin of violence
among men to their natural equality. He writes: “Nature hath made men so equall in the
faculties of body, and mind … [that] the difference between man and man is not so con-
siderable as that one man can thereupon claim to himselfe any benefit, to which another
may not pretend as well as he” (Leviathan, p. 94).6 Given this equality, they all feel that
they have the same hope of acquiring these benefits. Competition arises and, with this,
6
Hobbes’s Leviathan : Reprinted from the Edition of 1651 (London: Oxford
University Press, 1962). All references in the body of the text will be to this work.
7
enmity. In Hobbes’ words: “And therefore if any two men desire the same thing, which
nevertheless they cannot both enjoy, they become enemies,” the result being that men
“endeavour to destroy or subdue one another” (ibid, p. 95). Each, in fact, so fears the
others that he attempts to subdue them in advance. With this, we have the natural condi-
tion of man “which is called Warre; and such a warre as is of every man against every
man” (ibid., p. 96). According to Hobbes, the only way to get out of this condition,
where the life of man is “solitary, poore, nasty, brutish, and short,” is through each person
laying down his rights to use all means to defend himself. This is done by his transfer-
ring them to the state. To found a state, in other words, involves the state’s monopolizing
the violence that each of us formally employed to defend himself (ibid., p. 131). The
founding thus occurs when the sovereign “hath the use of so much Power and Strength
conferred on him that by [the] terror thereof he is inabled to forme the wills of them all to
Peace at home and mutuall ayd against their enemies abroad” (ibid., p. 132).
Two things are striking in this account. The first is that it follows the paradigm
that equates freedom and sovereignty, sovereignty being taken as self-sufficiency and
mastery. To be free, one must be master. Thus, anticipating that others will try to gain
the same goods that he desires, each person, with an eye to his self-sufficiency, attempts
to overcome them. In Hobbes’ words, he endeavors “by force or wiles to master the per-
sons of all men he can, so long till he see no other power great enough to endanger him.”7
When states are founded, the paradigm continues with their attempting to master one an-
7
“And from this diffidence of one another, there is no way for any man to secure
himselfe, so reasonable, as Anticipation; that is, by force, or wiles, to master the
persons of all men he can, so long, till he see no other power great enough to en-
danger him” (Leviathan, p. 95)
8
other, that is, in their being in an open or concealed state of war. In both cases, the
process is fueled by a competition for “benefits.” It also rests on the presumed equality
of the combatants. This is the second striking element. It is the fact that we cannot see a
sufficient difference between us to justify our giving someone else an advantage over us.
Hobbes brings the point home by comparing men with other social species such as bees.
Bees have no competition for honor and glory. All distinctions between them are natural.
They are, thus, distinguished from men by the fact that “the agreement of these creatures
is Naturall; that of men is by Covenant only, which is Artificiall.” Thus, nature regulates
the actions of the bees towards their common good. Men, however, have no such con-
straints. Their artificial covenant thus requires “a Common Power to keep them in awe
and to direct their actions to the Common Benefit” (Leviathan, p. 131). This stress on
of our “natural state.” Family, friends, tribal loyalties are all left out of account. Each in-
dividual is like the others since each is abstracted from the social context—the circum-
stances of family, history and fortune—that might differentiate him. In the state of na-
ture, our life, according to Hobbes, is “solitary.” The question that we will have to con-
sider is whether this atomistic view of human nature is presupposed in the equation of
freedom with mastery. If it is, we will have to work out more clearly its role in the vio-
lence this equation entails. At issue will be whether our failures to understand and,
hence, contain violence can be traced to this atomistic view of human nature.
III
According to Hobbes, we should not think the state of nature as a condition that
entirely disappears with the founding of the state. Its persistence, he notes, is attested to
9
by the fact that men go armed when they go on a journey, that they lock their houses
when they depart and, in fact, keep certain chests locked even when they are at home
(Leviathan, p. 99). In such cases, they acknowledge that in the absence of state power
(for example, in the isolated areas one passes on a journey), a natural condition of war
internal principle of the state. In his words, “Hobbes … was perfectly aware … that the
state of nature did not necessarily have to be conceived as a real epoch, but rather could
be understood as a principle internal to the State revealed in the moment in which the
State is considered ‘as if it were dissolved.’”8 Such dissolution occurs not just when a
natural disaster, such as a hurricane, disables the forces of public order with the resulting
rioting and looting. It appears when the sovereign declares a ”state of exception” or
“emergency” suspending civil rights. During this time, the sovereign can kill, imprison,
or generally molest the citizens of the state with impunity. The crimes that the sovereign
forbids his subjects, he allows himself. What shows itself in such a state of emergency is,
according to Agamben, the violence that first established the state. Thus, the state of
“sovereign” exception is instituted not as some law, but in order to establish the situation
The point Agamben is making can be put in terms of Walter Benjamin’s distinc-
tion between the violence that founds and that which preserves the state. According to
lence that preserves the law is present in the means that the police use to enforce the law.
In enforcing it, they preserve the state. The violence that makes the law, by contrast,
founds the state. Thus, in the conflicts that give rise to the state, the terms of the victori-
10
ous party become the founding law. In Benjamin’s words, “the moment of instatement
does not dismiss violence; rather at the very moment of law-making, it specifically estab-
lishes as law not an end unalloyed by violence, but one necessarily and intimately bound
to it, under the title of power. Law-making is power making, assumption of power, and
to that extent an immediate manifestation of violence.”11 This violence shows itself in the
use of police powers to enforce the laws. It appears in its original form “when the state
… can no longer guarantee through the legal system the empirical ends that it desires at
any price to attain.” At this point, the police “intervene ‘for security reasons’ in countless
cases where no clear legal situation exists.”12 The action of the police in such cases, is
“law making” because its “function” is “the assertion of legal claims for any decree.”13
What is at issue here is the legal space itself, which is that of public order. As both Ben-
jamin and Agamben note, the role of the police is fraught with ambiguity. It is law-pre-
serving, since its ends are given by the laws of the state, and its use of power “is subject
to the restriction that it may not set itself new ends.” Yet as the representative of the
founding violence, police power represents something prior to the law. Thus, “unlike
law, which acknowledges in the ‘decision’ determined by place and time … a claim to
8
Giorgio Agamben, Homo Sacer, Sovereign Power and Bare Life, trans.
Daniel Heller-Roazen (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998), p. 36.
9
In Agamben’s words, “What is at issue in the sovereign exception is not so
much the control or neutralization of an excess as the creation and definition of
the very space in which the juridico-political order can have validity.” This
means that “in its archetypal form, the state of exception is therefore the principle
of every juridical localization, since only the state of exception opens the space in
which the determination of a certain juridical order and a particular territory first
becomes possible” (Homo Sacer, p. 19).
11
The paradox here is that the sovereign authority manifested by the police is both
inside and outside the state. Thus, insofar as the police exercise a law-making function,
they express this authority as prior to the state, that is, as prior to its laws. When a state
of emergency is declared and civil rights are suspended, the only thing at issue is the
restoration of public order. In Agamben’s words, “What is at issue in the sovereign ex-
ception is not so much the control or neutralization of an excess as the creation and defi-
nition of the very space in which the juridico-political order can have validity.” This
means that “in its archetypal form, the state of exception is therefore the principle of ev-
ery juridical localization, since only the state of exception opens the space in which the
determination of a certain juridical order and a particular territory first becomes possi-
ble.”15 Here, there is no question of law, but of the establishment of law, that is, of the
public space in which law can appear. Hobbes puts this point by noting that in the state
of nature, there is no law. In such a state, “nothing can be Unjust. The notions of Right
and Wrong, Justice and Injustice have there no place.” The reason for this is clear:
(Leviathan, p. 98). Given that the sovereign represents this common power, he grounds
the law. But as such, he is outside of it. Thus, as Hobbes states, “there can happen no
breach of Covenant on the part of the Sovereign” (ibid, p. 134). What he represents
within the state is the natural violence that is prior to the state. In Agamben’s words, “in
10
“Critique of Violence” in Walter Benjamin, Selected Writings, Volume 1, 1913-
1926, ed. Marcus Bullock and Michael W. Jennings (Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap
Press of Harvard University Press), p. 243.
12
Hobbes the state of nature survives in the person of the sovereign who is the only one to
preserve its ius contra omnes. Sovereignty thus presents itself as the incorporation of the
state of nature in society.”16 The police manifest this incorporation. They are both law-
making and law-preserving.17 They represent both the constituting power of founding vi-
olence and the constituted power of an established legal system. The ambiguity of their
function is that of the power of the sovereign. In Agamben’s words, “the sovereign
power divides itself into constituting power and constituted power and maintains itself in
to the question of intra-state violence. If Hobbes, Benjamin and Agamben are correct, vi-
olence both founds and preserves the state. The state functions by internalizing the vio-
lence of nature. This implies that it has no inherent limits. In particular, it implies that its
“constituting power neither derives from the constituted order nor limits itself to institut-
ing it.”19 What we face here is a fundamental ambiguity. Existing at the point of inter-
section between the constituting violence and the constituted legal order, the state permits
itself what it forbids its citizens. In Agamben’s words, “The sovereign sphere is the
cise sense, it grounds the legal order by violating it, that is, by excepting itself from the
order’s precepts. We cannot, then, appeal to it to banish the specter of intra-state vio-
11
Ibid., p. 248.
12
Ibid., p. 243.
13
Ibid.
14
Ibid.
13
lence. Inherent within the sovereign sphere is the exception to whatever order we try to
impose through it. It itself contains the exception that can be used by political parties,
IV
selves. In the war of “every man against every man,” every man is an “enemy to every
man” (Leviathan, pp. 96-7). For Hobbes, the causes of this original war are our natural
equality—the fact that nature made us essentially similar in mind and body—and a com-
petition for benefits. Given our natural equality, we cannot see why others should enjoy
some benefit and we should not. There is, in other words, a natural egotism in which
each of us asks, “why should you have this and I not?” For Hobbes, “without a common
Power to keep [us] all in awe” and enforce a series of conventional decisions regarding
To see the limitations of this tradition, we need to consider its alternative. It is, in
its own way, as extreme as the tradition stemming from Hobbes. While in Hobbes’ atom-
istic view, man’s natural state is solitary and ruled by egotism, Aristotle sees the isolated
15
Homo Sacer, p. 19.
16
Homo Sacer, p. 35.
17
“Critique of Violence,” p. 243.
18
Homo Sacer, p. 41.
19
Ibid., p. 43.
20
“Critique of Violence,” p. 88.
14
individual as an empty abstraction. As he observes, humans are never alone. Given our
finitude and neediness, starting from our very conception there never was a point when
we were not with others He writes, “in the first place, there must be a unity of those who
cannot exist without each other; namely, of male and female” (“Politics,” 1252a 27; p.
1127).21 Beyond this, there is the resulting family of children, cousins, uncles, etc., the
grouping of families into villages, and the coalescence of villages into the state. In Aris-
totle’s words, “When several villages are united in a single complete community, large
enough to be nearly or quite self-sufficing, the state comes into existence, originating in
the bare needs of life and continuing in existence for the sake of a good life” (1252b 27-
29; p. 1129). For Aristotle, then, the formation of the state is driven by “bare needs of
life.” It continues its development until these needs are met, that is, until the collection of
men is “large enough to be nearly or quite self-sufficing.” This self-sufficient state is the
“final cause” or inherent goal of the growth of the human community. Just as a plant ex-
hibits its nature when it reaches maturity, so the human community reveals its nature at
For Aristotle, to call something “natural” means that it has an inborn goal to its
growth, one that directs it to a certain completion.22 Thus, all the stages of the plant’s de-
21
“Politics,” trans. Benjamin Jowett, in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed.
Richard McKeon (New York: Random House Press, 1941). All page references
to the “Politics,” will be to this translation.
22
In Aristotle’s words, “‘nature’ as genesis is a process towards [the prod-
uct’s] ‘nature.’ … what grows out of something proceeds to something or
‘grows,’ not towards that from which it starts, but that towards which it tends.
Hence, its final shape is its ‘nature’” (Aristotle’s Physics, trans. Richard Hope
[Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1961], 193b 14-18, p. 25).
15
velopment—from the seed to the sapling and thence to the seed-producing individual—
are “natural” since all follow a plan of growth—one that leads to realizing an inborn goal.
Aristotle’s claim is that the same holds for the state. In his words: “And therefore, if the
earlier forms of society are natural, so is the state, for it is the end of them, and the nature
of a thing is its end” (“Politics,” 1252b 30; p. 1129). This identification of nature with
the end implies that it is only at the end of a natural process that we can grasp the essence
the end stage makes sense of the various stages of the organism’s growth. These stages
reach their natural culmination when the organism is self-sufficient, that is, becomes ca-
pable of functioning on its own in such a way that it can (for example, through flowering
and bearing seeds) continue the species. Thus, Aristotle continues, “For what each thing
is when fully developed, we call its nature, whether we are speaking of a man, a horse, or
a family. Besides, the final cause and end of a thing is the best, and to be self-sufficing is
The assertion that “the state is a creation of nature” sets the context for the claim
that “man is a political animal.” The claim signifies that he can reach his natural, self-
sufficient end only within the state. Thus, for Aristotle, “the state is by nature clearly
prior to the family and to the individual.” This signifies that just as a part of a body can-
not survive apart from the body, so the “individual, when isolated, is not self-sufficing”
(“Politics,” 1253a 27; p. 1130). This insufficiency is not just economic. It is not simply
a function of the fact that since no person can be a “jack of all trades,” human survival
depends upon a division of labor and, hence, on the resulting exchange of goods and ser-
23
“What is was to be” (to ti hen einai) translates literally the Aristotelian
term usually translated as essence.
16
vices. It has to do with the very sense of what it means to be human. This sense, for
Aristotle, is unthinkable apart from the state. Thus, a person who is unable to live in so-
ciety or has no need of it is, he writes, either “a beast or a god” (ibid., 1253a 29; p. 1130).
He is either below or above humanity, but is not human. In fact, a single individual “may
be compared to an isolated piece at draughts” (ibid., 1253 a 5; p. 1129). Apart from the
board and the other pieces, the piece has no sense. The same holds for the human being.
Separated from the state, he is separated from “law and justice.” He becomes “the most
unholy and the most savage of the animals.” His very nature degenerates into “armed in-
There are, in fact, two very different senses of “nature” at work here. For Hobbes, “na-
ture” designates the primitive condition of man before the founding of society. The con-
dition is one of violence and is expressed in the “war of every man against every man.”
For Aristotle, nature expresses the end of the process that results in society. Man realizes
his nature through his social relations. The violence of man apart from society is not an
expression of his primitive condition, but rather of his political (or social) nature. What it
designates is his inability to morally function on his own. In this view, violence is not
“founding” with regard to the state. What is founding is the drive towards moral and eco-
nomic self-sufficiency. The very impulse that leads to the founding of the state leads as
How can we decide between these two very different views of our nature? Which
can better account for the fact of violence? For both, violence characterizes our nature
17
outside of society. Both see the breakdown of the social order as leading to violence. At
issue, however, is the violence that occurs within the social sphere—in particular, the vio-
lence that leads to the breakdown of the political order. Aristotle suggests that our rela-
tions to others are primarily co-operative. The insufficiencies of our individual natures
are such that we have to cooperate to survive. For Hobbes, however, our relations to oth-
ers are primarily competitive. Given our natural equality, we necessarily want what oth-
ers do and compete with them for it. Without a sovereign power to keep us in “awe,” this
competition must lead to the breakdown of the state. Which is correct? We cannot adju-
dicate their claims without understanding more clearly the competitive and cooperative
relations we have to each other. At the basis of all such relations is our recognition of
others. When does this recognition lead to violence? Is it only the recognition underly-
ing the competitive relation that has the possibility of violence? Or does the recognition
required for cooperation also conceal this possibility? To pursue these questions, I shall
As Edmund Husserl pointed out, the basic structure of human recognition can be
described in terms of an analogy that we are continually making and adjusting in our rela-
tions with others. This analogy has four terms. Three of them are directly experienced,
the fourth term (much like a “fourth proportional” in mathematics) is filled in or “solved”
in terms of the three. Two of the experiential terms are the appearing of myself and my
other. I directly observe my own behavior and speech. I also observe the other’s bodily
inner life. I experience immediately the intentions and interpretations that explain to me
18
what I do and say. I cannot, of course, similarly observe the other. This fourth term,
There are two ways to conceive this filling it. I can say that if the other behaves
as I would in a similar situation, then I recognize him as person who controls his behavior
as I would. I acknowledge him as making sense of his situation in the same way that I
would were I in his place and, thus, recognize him as a subject like myself. This recogni-
tion is a result of my filling in the fourth term of the proportion: my appearing bodily be-
as a person like myself by “solving” for the fourth proportional, that is, by transferring to
of a given situation. As Husserl points out, this transfer is verifiable insofar as it is based
on the observed similarity of our behavior. Thus, to the point that the other does not be-
have as I would, I do not recognize him as a subject. My behavior, in other words, func-
tions as the standard for verification. In Husserl's words, “The experienced animate or-
ganism of the Other continues to manifest itself as actually an animate organism solely
organism precisely when it does not agree in its behavior.”24 “Harmonious,” here, means
harmonious with my own behavior. The Other's actions must “agree” with this in order
to establish the similarity necessary for the transfer. As Husserl expresses this, the
Other's ego is “determined as thus governing his body (and, in a familiar way, constantly
confirms this) only insofar as the whole stylistic form of the sensible processes that are
19
governing of my body.”25
self. If we follow it strictly, a person who behaved differently than I would could not
provide me with the evidence required to make the transfer. Lacking this, I could not rec-
ognize the person as a subject. In other words, were I to recognize others only to the
point that their behavior matched my own, any recognition I had of others would actually
and say that the other’s behavior must also function as a standard. This means that in my
encounter with the other, I do not just assume that he will behave as I would in his situa-
tion, thereby taking myself as a standard. I also assume that were I in his situation, I
could well act as he does. In other words, I take his behavior as a standard for verifying
my selfhood. In doing so, I imaginatively put myself in his situation in order to regard
the world in terms of his categories, his interpretations of a given situation. In this view
of the filling in of the fourth proportional, the transfer between us goes both ways. I rec-
grasping the situation. But I also transfer to myself his different grasp of this situation.
24
Cartesianische Meditationen, ed. S. Strasser, The Hague: Martinus Ni-
jhoff, Hua I, 144.
25
Ibid., p. 148. This is also the case with the “higher psychical occur-
rences.” They have “their style of synthetic connections and their form of occur-
ring which can be understandable to me through their associative basis in my own
style of life, a style empirically familiar to me in its average typicality” (ibid., p.
149).
20
made explicit in our discourse. Listening to and observing him, I do not simply interpret
what he says and does in terms of my own categories and interpretative intentions.
Rather, I suspend these to open myself up to his ways of making sense. Interpreting my-
self in their terms, I place my own categories in question. This includes a questioning of
the intentions that I direct to the other. In a certain sense, to grasp the other as other, I
have to take such intentions as inadequate. The other, I must assume, will exceed these.
sense of the world. Recognizing him as other assumes that he will add something new to
them.
If the above is correct, then our recognition of others contains the basis for both
competition and cooperation. The type of relation depends on the direction of the trans-
fer. To the point that I take myself as a standard, recognition results in competition. Co-
myself to his interpretations. To see this, let us first consider the aspect of recognition
that leads to competition. Taking myself as the standard, I recognize others as subjects
only to the point that they behave as I do. To the point that my others do so, I regard
them as desiring and seeking the same things as I do and hence as competing with me for
these. The result is the sense of “natural equality” where, as Hobbes writes, no one can
“claim to himselfe any benefit, to which another may not pretend as well as he”
(Leviathan, p. 94). This, for Hobbes, leads to the violence of the competitive struggle.
Such violence, in other words, is a function of our “natural equality,” which itself is a
function of our recognizing subjects only to the point that they are similar to ourselves.
21
Such recognition also implies that we cannot find any basis among subjects for the dis-
tinctions that social organization requires. These distinctions must accordingly be set by
the competitive struggle, that is, by the resulting relations of power. Once they are set,
the second aspect of this account of recognition comes to the fore. This is that I do not
recognize as subjects the others who do not behave as I do. Thus, once I reduce others to
an inferior status, the way is open for me to exploit them. In the extreme case, as with
“subject populations,” the way is open to treat them as mere things, that is, to act without
any moral restraint at all. The resulting violence can, in such cases, run the gamut from
the various forms of racial and economic exploitation to the various genocides that
of recognition. Seeing another person step into the bus with you, you recognize him as a
competitor for a remaining seat. In economics, the competition can range from being ri-
vals for a position to the struggle of competing firms for market share. The “creative de-
struction” of capitalism, where firms and their associated towns suffer the devastation
brought by losing the competitive battle, is never far from such recognition. Its prospect
shakes the competitors out of their complacency. Confronting them with the thought not
just of the other enjoying the benefits they seek, but of the consequences of their loss,
they are spurred to greater efforts. Shaking, here, is not just economic, but also social.
Loss of social status is also a loss in one’s claims to be recognized as a subject by the
members of the class from which one has fallen. One no longer has the means to behave
such instances amounts to facing the loss of both economic and social selfhood.26
22
The second aspect of recognition, which focuses on the alterity of the other,
stands outside of this competitive relation. To the point that the other is other, one cannot
assume in advance that he will seek the same benefits that one desires. The same holds
for his talents and interests. This difference opens the way for a division of labor and the
resulting exchange of goods and services. From an Aristotelian perspective such an ex-
change is essential. It follows from the inherent insufficiency of the isolated individual.
Humans must cooperate to survive. Such cooperation involves their taking on different
roles, each one making up for the deficiencies of the others. It is in terms of such cooper-
ation and the resulting exchanges that Aristotle frames his concept of justice. As he
points out in his Ethics, its sense is that of fairness or equity—isos. It signifies fairness in
exchange. The basic question of justice is: what is an equitable exchange? When, for ex-
ample, a house builder and a shoemaker come to the market, how many shoes would it
take to equal a house? Shoes, of course, cannot be directly exchanged for a house.
people who are different and unequal. But they must be equalized; and hence everything
that enters into an exchange [e.g., between the shoemaker and the house builder] must
Two things are remarkable in this statement. The first is the assertion of the dif-
26
This may be the insight behind Hegel’s description of the deadly fight for
recognition between the two pre-selves in the section, “Lordship and Bondage in
the Phenomenology of Spirit.
27
Nichomachean Ethics, trans. Martin Ostwald (New York: Macmillan Pub-
lishing Company, 1962) 1133a 17-19, p. 125.
23
ple who are “like” or “equal” to each other. It presupposes their alterity. This means that
the humanity that makes up a community is “plural” in the sense that it involves an irre-
ducible otherness. The second, which is indicated by the mention of money, is the funda-
mental role of economic justice. Given that people form a state to make up for their in-
foundation. The self-sufficiency of the human in the state thus presupposes two factors.
The first is the existence of others as other. The second is their equalization through fair
exchanges.
The fact that this aspect of recognition is non-competitive does not mean that it is
without its own form of shaking. To cooperate with another involves taking account of
their perspective of a given situation. To do so, however, can involve putting ones own
categories and interpretations, the ways one makes sense of the world—into question. In
genuine cooperation, the other appears as a self with an authority equal to one’s own. As
such, he is capable of putting ones own selfhood in question. Thus, the more one takes
up his categories, the more one’s own are shaken. At the extreme point, openness to the
other as other can become a trauma, a shaking of one’s very sense of selfhood. Even in
its less extreme forms, the shaking involves different views of the world, different ways
of taking it and, hence, an undermining of one’s certainty with respect to it. The loss of
certainty always involves a certain discomfort. Those who radically question the certain-
ties of a community often provoke a violent reaction. Thus the philosophical shaking ini-
tiated by Socrates resulted in his execution. The same fate overcame Jesus, with his
shaking of the religious certainties of his community. As the mass expulsions and perse-
cutions of ethnic minorities attest, this reaction can be extended to whole groups of peo-
24
ple. To the point that a growing ethnic minority, whose perspectives and standards are
different from the majority, demands recognition, it can expose itself to an extreme reac-
tion. To genuinely recognize a group is to take seriously its standards for interpreting the
world; but this is to place into question one’s own. Rather than doing so, a community
can simply refuse to recognize the “authority” of the minority community—that is, its
right to be the author of its own standards. What this amounts to is a switch in the mode
of recognition from the cooperative to the competitive. In the competitive, one takes one-
self as the standard. Those who do not act as one does, those whose behavior manifests
different standards, are not taken as subjects. Applying this to the minority, the majority
opens the way to the loss of all moral restraint in its actions towards them.
VI
If the above is correct, then the violence that shakes the state is that which com-
bines both forms of shaking. It takes the shaking that is involved in the recognition of the
otherness of the other and transmutes it into the competitive shaking. That the recogni-
tion of the alterity of others is essential for political life follows from its description as the
“art of compromise.” In its accommodating the multiple interests that make up a state,
politics is the way we deal with our plural condition. Thus, in political life, we assume
that others may not share our interpretation of a given situation. Not seeing it as we do,
they will not act as we would. Their interests may, in fact, be opposed to our own.
political compromises. Essential for its action is the recognition of the alterity of the
other parties, of their actually having valid grounds for their positions. When this is re-
placed by the form of recognition that denies the subjectivity of such parties, the process
25
cannot go forward. Thus, whenever the opposing interests are “demonized,” political
curs through the victor’s suppressing his opponents. To the point that the latter resist, the
To see more clearly into the breakdown of political life, we have to take note of
two very different types of freedom: the first is political, the second is natural. The first
originates in the self-separation that the recognition of the otherness of the other occa-
sions. In this recognition, we put ourselves in the situation of the other. We do so in or-
der to grasp his interpretations of a given situation. Doing so, we separate ourselves from
our own situation and corresponding interpretations. To the point that such recognition
succeeds, we regard these from the perspective of the other. The freedom that here arises
comes from the fact that we can consider neither our situation nor the interpretations that
define it as without alternatives. Viewed from the perspective of the other, they have to
be regarded as things that could be otherwise. Thus, they lose their necessity. Rather
than being taken as necessarily determining us, they have to be regarded as within the
purview of our freedom, that is, as things that we could change.28 The content of the re-
sulting freedom is given by our others. Each time we engage in this form of recognition,
we grasp a different way of being and behaving. Whether we approve or disapprove of it,
28
With this, we have the freedom that Sartre describes when he writes: “For
man to put a particular existent out of circuit is to put himself out of circuit in re-
lation to the existent. In this case he is not subject to it; he is out of reach; it can-
not act on him, for he has retired beyond a nothingness. Descartes, following the
Stoics, has given a name to this possibility, which human reality has, to secrete a
nothingness which isolates it—it is freedom” (Jean-Paul Sartre, Being and Noth-
ingness, trans. Hazel Barnes [New York: Washington Square Press, 1966], p. 60).
26
the fact that we recognize the other, not just as other, but as a subject like ourselves, sig-
nifies that we recognizes these alternatives as human possibilities, that is, as possibilities
Given that its origin and the possibilities that form its content come from others,
the freedom just described is social. It cannot exist in any solitary state of nature. Its ab-
sence in such a state is part of the insufficiency of the isolated individual. Insofar as it is
essential to our humanity, we have to say that such humanity only appears in community.
Political life arises from such freedom insofar as it is called on to negotiate some of the
choices that form its content—namely, those that have a collective impact. Insofar as
through political debates, these choices achieve a public presence and, hence, form a part
of the content of our collective freedom, political life also promotes freedom. It is, in
other words, from freedom and for freedom, freedom being both the origin and goal of
political life.29 Such freedom is never abstract. It is always situated in a concrete context,
which is that of the choices we make available to each other. What makes it political is
the fact that it is negotiable in terms of its content. Two factors open it up to compro-
mise. The first is that given our essentially social nature, the unbridgeable alterity of our
humanity is always limited. Humans form a plurality in the above defined sense, yet
there is always an overlap in their interpretations. The meanings they give to various sit-
uations are shared, but not entirely. That they are shared means that there are always
29
Here we agree with the Czech political philosopher, Jan Patoc˚ka. He
writes, “political life in its original and primordial form is nothing other than ac-
tive freedom itself.” It is a life that exists “from freedom for freedom” (Jan Pa-
toc˚ka, Heretical Essays in the Philosophy of History, trans. Erazim Kohák, ed.
James Dodd [Chicago: Open Court Publishing, 1996], p. 142).
27
some points that can be assumed in political negotiations. The second factor is the non-
coincidence within this coincidence, that is, the non-overlap of their interpretations. This
points to the fact that there are always some benefits that are more attractive to one party
rather than to others and, hence, subject to compromise. They form the negotiatible con-
The case is very different with the natural liberty assumed by the social contract
theorists. They take the basis of political power to be an innate, natural liberty. As John
Locke expresses this, “To understand political power right[ly] and derive it from its origi-
nal, we must consider what state all men are naturally in, and that is a state of perfect
freedom to order their actions and dispose of their possessions and persons as they think
fit.”30 For Hobbes, this freedom “is the liberty each man hath to use his own power, as he
will himself, for the preservation of his own nature, that is to say, of his own life” in the
state of war that exists before society (Leviathan, p. 99). In this state, freedom aims as
mastery. Its understanding of sovereignty is solely in these terms. Thus, the individual’s
relation to his others is competitive rather than cooperative. The others that he does en-
counter are taken to desire the same things that he does. Since the subjects he recognizes
are like him, they cannot enrich the content of his freedom. The same factor makes this
natural liberty incapable of compromise. Since it does not take into account the alterity
of others, that is, their differing interpretations of a given situation, liberty, here, lacks
any negotiable content. For the same reason, it cannot avail itself of the advantages of
cooperating with others, that is, of making use of differing talents and interests for a mu-
tual benefit. Inherently, then, the lack of social context for natural liberty means that
30
John Locke, The Second Treatise of Government, §4 (New York: Library
of Liberal Arts Press, 1952), p. 4.
28
there are no natural limits to it. This is why Hobbes asserts that such limits must come
from outside of the individual, namely, from the “terror” occasioned by the “Power and
Given the essentially violent character of natural liberty, its conflation with politi-
cal freedom necessarily rends the political fabric. This cannot be otherwise given that the
freedom that knows no limits inevitably works to undermine the “rules of the game” of
political life, the very rules that were set up to impose limits on the participants of the
game. The sign of this breakdown is the conflation of freedom with sovereignty, under-
stood as “mastership.” Behind this is the conflation of what we have called political free-
dom with the natural liberty of the social contract theorists. The ultimate basis of the
breakdown is, however, the running together of two different types of intersubjective
recognition: the competitive and the cooperative. It is this conflation, which the shaking
VII
nition. In fact, the conflation of the two aspects of recognition is always possible since
both are equiprimordial as both constitute our recognition of others. In such recognition,
the transfer of the sense of being a conscious subject goes both ways. Each of us trans-
fers to the other our sense of being a subject, that is, our interpretations of what motivates
behavior. We also transfer to ourselves the other’s different grasp of the situation as evi-
denced by his physical and verbal behavior. What this signifies is that both the Hobbe-
sian and Aristotelian analyses, to the point that they privilege one form of recognition
over the other, are both one-sided. Intersubjective recognition is, in fact, both coopera-
29
tive and competitive. Thus, people cooperate in order to compete, while the drive to-
wards cooperation, the drive that, for Aristotle, leads to the founding of the state, can
Given that the situation is always a mixed one, we cannot really maintain the di-
chotomy between the states of nature and society as if the two could be thought apart.
Such states are, phenomenologically speaking, simply code words for two equiprimordial
forms of recognition. This means that the presence of the state of nature in society is the
presence of the competitive relation within the cooperative. This presence of the “sover-
eign exception” is, in other words, within us. In the absence of any social constraints, this
presence is necessarily violent. Thus, political violence occurs when we fail to manage
the competitive relation, that is, fail to impose on it the “rules of the game” of political
life. Such a failure generally involves a failure to recognize its nature, that is, to see that
that the freedom it expresses requires external restraints. What Benjamin and Agamben
refer to as the “founding violence” of the state is, then, a sign of its dissolution. Violence
is not a maintainer of the public space. Its appearance at its breakdown is simply a sign
of the insufficiency of humanity in the absence of such space. This space becomes
eroded when we fail to perceive the difference between the freedom that we gain from
others and the freedom that directs itself against others. When politics becomes a “com-
petitive sport,” when the political and the economic spheres are conflated such that the
recognition that functions in economic competition becomes the model for political life,
the space for political life diminishes. Correspondingly, the possibilities for preventing
political violence also decrease. To prevent such violence, this space, which is essen-
tially a moral one, must be kept open. We must recognize it for what it is: namely, the
30
space multiply determined by our others, the space of the freedom that their alterity af-
fords us. All the rules of the game of political life have to be judged on how they pre-
serve this space. The moral authority of such rules is that of this space itself.
31