M. C. Dillon Merleau-Ponty and The Transcendence of Immanence Overcoming The Ontology of Consciousness
M. C. Dillon Merleau-Ponty and The Transcendence of Immanence Overcoming The Ontology of Consciousness
M. C. Dillon Merleau-Ponty and The Transcendence of Immanence Overcoming The Ontology of Consciousness
M E R L E A U - P O N T Y AND T H E T R A N S C E N D E N C E OF
I M M A N E N C E : O V E R C O M I N G T H E ONTOLOGY OF
CONSCIOUSNESS*
M.C. DILLON
Department o f Philosophy, University Center at Binghamton, State University o f New
York Binghamton, N Y 13901
395
396
Two points are relevant here: (a) perception is associated with the
unreflective and (b) that domain is conceived as foundational to the
domain of thought and reflection. Perceptual experience takes place in
an unreflective modality. As Merleau-Ponty says in another place, "if
I wanted to render precisely the perceptual experience, I ought to say
that o n e perceives in me, and not that I perceive" (PP 215; PP-F 249).
The point is that the " I " which emerges only with reflection is absent
from perceptual engagement in the world rendering that experience
anonymous or general: v the p h e n o m e n o n presences itself to anyone
who would witness it. This is consciousness at the foundational level;
Other modes of consciousness - reflection, deliberation, predication,
hallucination, dreaming, etc. - are founded u p o n it. "All
consciousness is, in some measure, perceptual consciousness" (PP 395;
PP-F 452). Here, then, is the basis for an equation - consciousness =
perception = phenomenal presencing - that would seem to allow
Merleau-Ponty to drop one of the terms, consciousness, and evade the
spectre of dualism that haunts it. "... The certainty of vision and that
of the thing seen are of a piece" (PP 399; P P - F 457); no separation
between percept and p h e n o m e n o n seems to be required: why then
infect the percept with the germ of consciousness and expose
phenomenology to the malaise of incipient ontological bifurcation?
The answer to this question has already been stated. It centers on the
problem of reflexivity.
respect ... and this is finally because I am situated [in the world]
and because it comprehends me (PP 408; PP-F 467).
.., We are nothing but a view of the world . . . . (PP 406; PP-F
465).
... We are the world that thinks itself . . . . (VI 136n; VI-F 179n).
If we are the world that thinks itself, then the thinking of the world
is not separate from the world; and if reflexivity is intrinsic to the
thinking of the world, it does not require the establishment of an
ontological category demarcating another kind of being disjunct from
worldly being. The human body, a worldly being, has developed the
capacity to thematize the reflexivity inherent in the ability to perceive
which it shares with all organisms.l~
The explicit ontology of The Visible and the Invisible centers around
the element of flesh as the implicit ontology of the Phenomenology
centers around the thesis of the primacy of phenomena. Neither 'flesh'
nor ' p h e n o m e n o n ' should be conceived as resurrecting the traditional
category of substance.
We must not think the flesh starting from substances, from body
and spirit - for then it would be the union of contradictories -
but we must think it ... as an element, as the concrete emblem of
a general manner of being (VI 147; VI-F 193-94).
These basic terms, 'flesh' and ' p h e n o m e n o n , ' name a way of being
(une mani~re d'etre) which subtends the polarizing distinctions of
language (body v. spirit, visible v. invisible, etc.) at the level of
ontology, but re-admits them all at the level of empirical taxonomy.
Merlau-Ponty's ontology is a radical rejection of dualism, but it is not
a traditional monism. There is one manner or style of being which all
things share, but this is compatible with the existence of many kinds
of things. It is not the case that rocks, plants, and animals are different
compositions of a single fleshly or phenomenal being; it is the case that
404
The true Cogito does not define the subject's existence in terms
of the thought he has of existing, and furthermore does not
convert the indubitability of the world into the indubitability of
thought about the world, nor finally does it replace the world
itself by the world as meaning. On the contrary it recognizes my
405
thought itself as an inalienable fact, and does away with any kind
of idealism in revealing me as 'being-in-the-world' (PP xiii; PP-F
viii).
that my world may not coincide with the world: the discovery that m y
world may be different from the worlds of others (or the ideal unity
of the world in itself) is the discovery of the unique perspective which
is my self. Once I discover it, I cannot doubt my finitude - although
I was not born with this awareness and may spend my entire life in
flight from it.
As shown by Merleau-Ponty in his writing on the role of the specular
image in the genesis of self-awareness, the experience of the cogito is
an experience of self-objectification: I discover myself in the mirror
only when I identify myself with the body-image I see over there, apart
from myself. This is also an intrinsic m o m e n t in Sartre's doctrine of
the look: I find myself only when I am caught up in the gaze of another
and experience myself from the alien vantage of an other. There is an
essential paradox here - reflection, my explicit consciousness of
myself, is the taking up of a distanced perspective on myself - my most
intimate experience of myself is an experience of self-alienation or self-
transcendence. Here is the root of the contradiction around which
Sartre's ontology centers. " T h e for-itself is what it is not and is not
what it is" - this phrase can now be translated to read: "incarnate
consciousness discovers its own identity in the process of self-
estrangement." The self reflected upon is an object posited as different
from the subject reflecting. From my vantage here, I see my body-
image there reflected in the mirror and feel myself bifurcated: I am not
the body-object that is the ground of my identity.
The manner in which Sartre responds to this paradox places him in
the midst of a long tradition of spiritualism. He is one who defines the
spirit - now called subjectivity or consciousness - in opposition to the
body. The spiritual self or soul discovered in the process of reflection
- in the process of coming of age which coincides with the intense
reflexivity of adolescence and the time of a cross-culturally apparent
rite of spiritual passage (bar mitzvah, confirmation, etc.) - this
spiritual self is the subject that defines itself in conflict with the body-
object it seeks to exclude and transcend through acts of ascetic denial
and mortification of the flesh. The spirit is born of shame, shame of
the body, which is an internalization of the look of the culture at large
which refuses to accept the sexuality of the changeling now becoming
manifest in publicly visible secondary sexual characteristics. The
changeling is a social and spiritual outcast who gains readmission to
the community in a ritual designed to reinforce his reflective self-
alienation.
408
thinking thing, then a further reflection can make itself aware of that
fact and go on to understand that I as the product (rather than the
Condition) of thought.
Here the role of language is crucial. Recall a passage quoted earlier:
"the tacit cogito is a cogito only when it expresses itself" (PP 404; PP-
F 463). When the tacit reflexivity of perception is expressed in
language, it becomes the cogito, the 'I think.' The I of subjectivity, the
reified agent of thought, comes into being through language, and the
resulting grammatical habit becomes the basis of a philosophical
prejudice.
NOTES
9. My essay, "Merleau-Ponty and the Reversibility Thesis," Man and WorM, Vol.
16 (1983) provides the elaboration and defense of this thesis that length
limitations preclude setting forth here.
10. One need not attribute sentience to all things to maintain the standpoint being
defended here. Rocks and mountains do not live or feel as organisms do, trees
lack eyes and cannot see as we do, animals are capable of only rudimentary levels
of thought, and so on" none of these basic distinctions need be forsaken in order
to sustain the claim that we are worldly beings.
11. "The Child's Relations with Others," trans. William Cobb, in The Primacy of
Perception, ed. James M. Edie (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1964).
"Les relations avec autrui chez l'enfant" from the series Cours de Sorbonne
(Paris: 1960).
12. "Merleau-Ponty and the Psychogenesis of the Self," Journal of
Phenomenological Psychology, Vol. 9, No. 1-2 (Autumn, 1978).
13. "Erotic Desire," Research in Phenomenaology, Vol. XV, 1985. See also
"Merleau-Ponty on Existential Sexuality: A Critique," Journal of
Phenomenological Psychology, Vol. 11, No. 1 (Spring, 1980).
14. Merleau-Ponty, "The Primacy of Perception and Its Philosophical
Consequences," trans. Edie, in The Primacy of Perception, p. 13.