This document discusses the concept of "reality effect" in literature through analyzing seemingly insignificant descriptive details included by authors. It argues that traditional structural analyses of narratives overlook or dismiss such details as "superfluous" or serving only indirect functional purposes. However, if analysis seeks to be exhaustive of the entire narrative surface, it must account for these trivial notations, which seem to serve no clear purpose from a structural perspective. The inclusion of such useless details is an inevitable and distinctive aspect of Western narratives. The document questions what significance, if any, this apparent insignificance holds.
This document discusses the concept of "reality effect" in literature through analyzing seemingly insignificant descriptive details included by authors. It argues that traditional structural analyses of narratives overlook or dismiss such details as "superfluous" or serving only indirect functional purposes. However, if analysis seeks to be exhaustive of the entire narrative surface, it must account for these trivial notations, which seem to serve no clear purpose from a structural perspective. The inclusion of such useless details is an inevitable and distinctive aspect of Western narratives. The document questions what significance, if any, this apparent insignificance holds.
Original Title
The reality effect. Roland Barthes (versión ocred)
This document discusses the concept of "reality effect" in literature through analyzing seemingly insignificant descriptive details included by authors. It argues that traditional structural analyses of narratives overlook or dismiss such details as "superfluous" or serving only indirect functional purposes. However, if analysis seeks to be exhaustive of the entire narrative surface, it must account for these trivial notations, which seem to serve no clear purpose from a structural perspective. The inclusion of such useless details is an inevitable and distinctive aspect of Western narratives. The document questions what significance, if any, this apparent insignificance holds.
This document discusses the concept of "reality effect" in literature through analyzing seemingly insignificant descriptive details included by authors. It argues that traditional structural analyses of narratives overlook or dismiss such details as "superfluous" or serving only indirect functional purposes. However, if analysis seeks to be exhaustive of the entire narrative surface, it must account for these trivial notations, which seem to serve no clear purpose from a structural perspective. The inclusion of such useless details is an inevitable and distinctive aspect of Western narratives. The document questions what significance, if any, this apparent insignificance holds.
Barthes, Roland. “The Reality Effect.” 1969. The Rustle of Language.
Trans. Richard Howard. Ed. Francois Wahl. Berkeley: U of California P, 1989. 141-148.
The Reality Effect
When Flaubert, describing the room occupied by Mme Aubain,
Félicité's employer, tells us that “an old piano supported, under a barometer, a pyramidal heap of boxes and cartons” (“A Simple Heart,” from Three Tales); when Michelet, recounting the death of Charlotte Corday and reporting that, before the executioner's arrival, she was visited in prison by an artist who painted her portrait, includes the detail that “after an hour and a half, there was a gentle Knock at a little door behind her” (Histoire de France: La Révolution)-—these authors (among many others) are produc- ing notations which structural analysis, concerned with identi- fying and systematizing the major articulations of narrative, usually and heretofore has left out, either because its inventory omits all details that are “superfluous” (in relation to structure) or because these same details are treated as “filling” (catalyses), assigned an indirect functional value insofar as, cumulatively, they constitute some index of character or atmosphere and so can ultimately be recuperated by structure. It would seem, however, that if analysis seeks to be exhaustive (and what would any method be worth which did not account for the totality of its object, i.e., in this case, of the entire surface of the narrative fabric?), if it seeks to encompass the absolute detail, the indivisible unit, the fugitive transition, in order to assign them a place in the structure, it inevitably encounters notations which no function (not even the most indirect) can justify: such notations are scandalous (from the point of view of structure), or, what is even more disturbing, they seem to correspond to a kind of narrative luxury, lavish to the point of offering many “futile” details and thereby increasing the cost of narrative information. For if, in Flaubert's description, it is just 141 142 From History to Reality The Reality Effect 143 possible to see in the notation of the piano an indication of its is entirely different: it has no predictive mark; “analogical,” owner's bourgeois standing and in that of the cartons a sign of its structure is purely summatory and does not contain that trajec- disorder and a kind of lapse in status likely to connote the tory of choices and alternatives which gives narration atmosphere of the Aubain household, no purpose seems to the appearance of a huge traffic-control center, furnished with justify reference to the barometer, an object neither incongruous a referential (and not merely discursive) temporality. This is nor significant, and therefore not participating, at first glance, an opposition which, anthropologically, has its importance: when, in the order of the notable; and in Michelet's sentence, we have under the influence of von Frisch's experiments, it was assum the same difficulty in accounting structurally for all the details: ed that bees had a language, it had to be realized that, while these that the executioner came after the painter is all that is necessary insects possessed a predictive system of dances (in order to the account; how long the sitting lasted, the dimension and to collect their food), nothing in it approached a description, location of the door are useless (but the theme of the door, the Thus, description appears as a kind of characteristic of the so-call softness of death's knock have an indisputable symbolic value). ed higher languages, to the apparently paradoxical degree that Even if they are not numerous, the “useless details” therefore it is justified by no finality of action or of communication. The seem inevitable: every narrative, at least every Western narrative singularity of description (or of the “useless detail”) in narrat of the ordinary sort nowadays, possesses a certain number. ive fabric, its isolated situation, designates a question which has Insignificant notation* (taking this word in its stong sense: the greatest importance for the structural analysis of narrative. This apparently detached from the narrative's semiotic structure) is question is the following: 1s everything in narrative significant, related to description, even if the object seems to be denoted and if not, if insignificant stretches subsist in the narrative only by a single word (in reality, the “pure” word does not exist: syntagm, what is ultimately, so to speak, the significance of this Flaubert's barometer is not cited in isolation; it is located, placed insignificance? in a syntagm at once referential and syntactic); thus is underlined First of all, we must recall that Western culture, in one of its the enigmatic character of all description, about which a word major currents, has certainly not left description outside mean- is necessary: the general structure of narrative, at least as it has ing, and has furnished it with a finality quite “recognized” by been occasionally analyzed till now, appears as essentially pre- the literary institution. This current is Rhetoric, and this finality dictive; schematizing to the extreme, and without taking into is that of the “beautiful”: description has long had an aesthetic account numerous detours, delays, reversals, and disappoint- function. Very early in antiquity, to the two expressly functional ments which narrative institutionally imposes upon this schema, genres of discourse, legal and political, was added a third, the we can say that, at each articulation of the narrative syntagm, epideictic, a ceremonial discourse intended to excite the someone says to the hero (or to the reader, it does not matter admi- ration of the audience (and no longer to persuade it); this which): if you act in this way, if you choose this alternative, this discourse contained in germ—whatever the ritual rules of its is what will happen (the reported character of these predictions use: eulogy or obituary—the very idea of an aesthetic finality of does not call into question their practical nature). Description language; in the Alexandrian neo-rhetoric of the second century * In this brief account, we shall not give examples of “insignificant” notations, A.D., there was a craze for ecphrasis, the detachable set piece for the insignificant can be revealed only on the level of an immense structure: (thus having its end in itself, independent of any general once cited, a notion is neither significant nor insignificant; it requires an already function), whose object was to describe places, times, people, or analyzed context. works of art, a tradition which was maintained throughout the 144 From History to Reality The Reality Effect 145 Middle Ages. As Curtius has emphasized, description in this landscape had the motionless look of a painting”); the writer period is constrained by no realism,; its truth is unimportant (or here fulfilis Plato's definition of the artist as a maker in the even its verisimilitude); there is no hesitation to put lions or third degree, since he imitates what is already the simulation of olive trees in a northern country; only the constraint of the an essence. Thus, although the description of Rouen is quite descriptive genre counts; plausibility is not referential here but irrelevant to the narrative structure of Madame Bovary (we can openly discursive: it is the generic rules of discourse which lay attach it to no functional sequence nor to any characterial, down the law. atmospheric, or sapiential signified), it is not in the least scan- Moving ahead to Flaubert, we see that the aesthetic purpose dalous, it is justified, if not by the work's logic, at least by the of description is still very strong. In Madame Bovary, the descrip- laws of literature: its “meaning” exists, it depends on conformity tion of Rouen (a real referent if ever there was one) is subject not to the model but to the cultural rules of representation. to the tyrannical constraints of what we must call aesthetic All the same, the aesthetic goal of Flaubertian description is verisimilitude, as is attested by the corrections made in this thoroughly mixed with “realistic” imperatives, as if the referent's passage in the course of six successive rewritings. Here we see, exactitude, superior or indifferent to any other function, gov- first of all, that the corrections do not in any way issue from a erned and alone justified its description, or—in the case of closer consideration of the model: Rouen, perceived by Flaubert, descriptions reduced to a single word—its denotation: here remains just the same, or more precisely, if it changes somewhat aesthetic constraints are steeped—at least as an alibi—in refer- from one version to the next, it is solely because he finds it ential constraints: it is likely that, if one came to Rouen in a necessary to focus an image or avoid a phonic redundance diligence, the view one would have coming down the slope condemned by the rules of le beau style, or again to “arrange” a leading to the town would not be “objectively” different from quite contingent felicity of expression;* next we see that the the panorama Flaubert describes. This mixture—this interweav- descriptive fabric, which at first glance seems to grant a major ing—of constraints has a double advantage: on the one hand, importance (by its dimension, by the concern for its detail) to aesthetic function, giving a meaning to “the fragment,” halts the object Rouen, is in fact only a sort of setting meant to receive what we might call the vertigo of notation; for once, discourse the jewels of a number of rare metaphors, the neutral, prosaic is no longer guided and limited by structural imperatives of the excipient which swathes the precious symbolic substance, as if, anecdote (functions and indices), nothing could indicate why in Rouen, all that mattered were the figures of rhetoric to which we should halt the details of the description here and not there; the sight of the city lends itselí—as if Rouen were notable only if it were not subject to an aesthetic or rhetorical choice, any by its substitutions (the masts like a forest of needles, the islands like “view” would be inexhaustible by discourse: there would always huge motionless black fish, the clouds like aerial waves silently breaking be a corner, a detail, an inflection of space or color to report; against a cliff ); last, we see that the whole description is constructed on the other hand, by positing the referential as real, by so as to connect Rouen to a painting: it is a painted scene which pretending to follow it in a submissive fashion, realistic descrip- the language takes up (“Thus, seen from above, the whole tion avoids being reduced to fantasmatic activity (a precaution which was supposed necessary to the “objectivity” of the ac- * A mechanism distinguished by Valéry, in Littérature, commenting on Bau- delaire's line “La servante au grand coeur .. .”: “This line came to Baudelaire .... count); classical rhetoric had in a sense institutionalized the And Baudelaire continued. He buried the cook out on the lawn, which goes fantasmatic as a specific figure, hypotyposis, whose function was against the custom, but goes with the rhyme,” etc. to “put things before the hearer's eyes,” not in a neutral, 146 From History to Reality The Reality Effect 147 constative manner, but by imparting to representation all the All this shows that the “real” is supposed to be self-sufficient, luster of desire (this was the vividly illuminated sector of that it is strong enough to belie any notion of “function,” that discourse, with prismatic outlines: ¿llustris oratio); declaratively its “speech-act” has no need to be integrated into a structure renouncing the constraints of the rhetorical code, realism must and that the having-been-there of things is a sufficient principle seek a new reason to describe. of speech. The irreducible residues of functional analysis have this in Since antiquity, the “real” has been on History's side; common: they denote what is ordinarily called “concrete reality” but this was to help it oppose the “lifelike,” the “plausible,” (insignificant gestures, transitory attitudes, insignificant objects, to oppose the very order of narrative (of imitation or “poetry”). All redundant words). The pure and simple “representation” of classical culture lived for centuries on the notion that reality the “real,” the naked relation of “what is” (or has been) thus could in no way contaminate verisimilitude; first of all, because verisi appears as a resistance to meaning; this resistance confirms the militude is never anything but opinable: it is entirely subject great mythic opposition of the true-to-life (the lifelike) and the to (public) Opinion; as Nicole said: “One must not consider things intelligible; it suffices to recall that, in the ideology of our"time, as they are in themselves, nor as they are known to be by obsessive reference to the “concrete” (in what is rhetorically one who speaks or writes, but only in relation to what is known demanded of the human sciences, of literature, of behavior) is of them by those who read or hear”; then, because History was always brandished like a weapon against meaning, as if, by some thought to be general, not particular (whence the propensity, in statutory exclusion, what is alive cannot not signify—and vice classical texts, to functionalize all details, to produce strong struct versa. Resistance of the “real” (in its written form, of course) to ures and to justify no notation by the mere guarantee of “reali structure is very limited in the fictive account, constructed by ty”); finally, because, in verisimilitude, the contrary is never definition on a model which, for its main outlines, has no other impos- sible, since notation rests on a majority, but not an absolu constraints than those of intelligibility; but this same “reality” te, opinion. The motto implicit on the threshold of all classi becomes the essential reference in historical narrative, which is cal discourse (subject to the ancient idea of verisimilitude) supposed to report “what really happened”: what does the non- is: Esto (Let there be, suppose . . .) “Real,” fragmented, interstitial notati functionality of a detail matter then, once it denotes “what took on, the kind we are dealing with here, renounces this implic place”; “concrete reality” becomes the sufficient justification for it introduction, and it is free of any such postulation that speaking. History (historical discourse: historia rerum gestarum) is occurs in the structural fabric. Hence, there is a break betwe in fact the model of those narratives which consent to fill in the en the ancient mode of versimilitude and modern realism; but interstices of their functions by structurally superfluous nota- hence, too, a new verisimilitude is born, which is precisely realis tions, and it is logical that literary realism should have been— m (by which we mean any discourse which accepts “speech-ac give or take a few decades—contemporary with the regnum of ts” jus- tified by their referent alone). “objective” history, to which must be added the contemporary Semiotically, the “concrete detail” is constituted by the direct development of techniques, of works, and institutions based on collusion of a referent and a signifier; the signified is expel the incessant need to authenticate the “real”: the photograph led from the sign, and with it, of course, the possibility of developing (immediate witness of “what was here”), reportage, exhibitions a form of the signified, i.e., narrative structure itself. (Reali of ancient objects (the success of the Tutankhamen show makés stic literature is narrative, of course, but that is because its realis this quite clear), the tourism of monuments and historical sites. m is only fragmentary, erratic, confined to “details,” and becau se 148 From History to Reality the most realistic narrative imaginable develops along unrealistic lines.) This is what we might call the referential illusion.* The truth of this illusion is this: eliminated from the realist speech- act as a signified of denotation, the “real” returns to it as a signified of connotation; for just when these details are reputed to denote the real directly, all that they do—without saying so— is signify it; Flaubert's barometer, Michelet's little door finally say nothing but this: we are the real; it is the category of “the real” (and not its contingent contents) which is then signified; in other words, the very absence of the signified, to the advantage of the referent alone, becomes the very signifier of realism: the reality effect is produced, the basis of that unavowed verisimilitude which forms the aesthetic of all the standard works of modernity. This new verisimilitude is very different from the old one, for it is neither a respect for the “laws of the genre” nor even their mask, but proceeds from the intention to degrade the sign's tripartite nature in order to make notation the pure encounter of an object and its expression. The disintegration of the sign— which seems indeed to be modernity's grand affair—is of course present in the realistic enterprise, but in a somewhat regressive manner, since it occurs in the name of a referential plenitude, whereas the goal today is to empty the sign and infinitely to postpone its object so as to challenge, in a radical fashion, the age-old aesthetic of “representation.” Communications, 1968
* Anillusion clearly illustrated by the program Thiers assigned to the historian:
“To be simply true, to be what things are and nothing more than that, and nothing except that.”