René Zavaleta Mercado
René Zavaleta Mercado
René Zavaleta Mercado
E D I T E D BY
The series takes as its charge radical new directions in the engage
ment with the literary culture of the non-European. The point of
departure here is the scandalous notion that the literary figure of the
Global South is as human as the European, complex, subject to the
dynamism of history, fluid, unrepresentable, and impossible either
to essentialize or reduce to any glib counter essentialism.
As such, elsewhere texts emphasizes those aspects of this sub
ject s dynamism that have been radically de-emphasized in the stock
metropolitan representations. So, the series centers the intellectual
dimension of literary culture elsewhere. The regions that Orientalists
represented as non-idea-producing areas are revealed to be the oppo
site. Furthermore, modernity of ideas is engaged by the series’
metatheoretical under-standing of the process of translation, the
mechanism through which the unfixed nature of intellectual work
may be most fully acknowledged. Finally, elsewhere texts under
stands theory as commitment, emphasizing that genre of theoretical
discourse which through its engagement—its heightened sense of
the social power of ideas and rhetorics—calls into question the sup
posed abstract transcendence of the god terms ‘theory’, ‘text’, ‘idea.
This engaged dimension of the elsewhere text insists on the histori-
cism of theory at the same time as it forges a new intellectual glob-
ality embodied here in intellectual work translated for the critical
traditions of Asia, Africa, the Caribbean and Latin America in ail
their diversity.
s
VW-p
R E N É ZAVALETA M ER CA D O
T R A N S L A T E D BY A N N E F R E E L A N D
LONDON NEW Y O RK C A L C U T T A
f ' CT c*
' ; ni i 1* * )
L- O v t Vi / ’
Seagull Books, 2018
vii
ELSEWHERE TEXTS
General Introduction
G ayatri C hakravorty Spivak
xvi
INTRODUCTION
l
Prologue
17
CHAPTER ONE
98
CHAPTER TWO
190
CHAPTER THREE
284
Afterword
A nne F reeland
299
Bibliography
:
__
ELSEWHERE TEXTS
General Introduction
1 M artin Heidegger, W hat Is Called Thinking? (J. Glenn Gray trans, and
introd.) (New York: Harper and Row, 1968).
2 Jacques Derrida, The Other Heading: Reflections on Todays Europe (Pascale-
Anne Brault and Michael B. Naas trans) (Bloomington: Indiana University
Press, 1992).
viii • GAYATRI CHAKRAVORTY SPIVAK
of the most popular critical anthologies and you will see corrobora
tion of the essentialist conviction that goes with the historical claim.
The counter-essentialism is reflected in the choice of critics from ‘the
rest of the world’, and today’s espousal o f‘the global South’. Just being
non-white is the counter-essence.
The influential Norton Anthology of Theory and Criticism, for
example, lets in only Maimonides before the modern university sys
tem kicks in.3But even if they had let in Khaled Ziadeh, Marta Lamas
and Marilena Chaui, the material would be determined by the epis
temological procedures of that system.4 Norton lets in W. E. B. Du
Bois, the first African-American to get a doctorate from Harvard,
the man who felt that ‘of the greatest importance was the opportunity
which my Wanderjahre [wandering years] in Europe gave of looking
at the world as a man and not simply from a narrow racial and
provincial outlook’.5 Du Bois emphatically claimed that the African-
American was the best example of the subject of the Declaration of
Independence (the Founding Fathers were standing in). It is there
fore significant that here he claims to inhabit the persona of Wilhelm
Meister, Goethe’s hero, with trajectory not fully reversed. Meister
came to the United States to act out the European Enlightenment
in this new land—a trip described in Goethe’s Wilhelm Meisters
Wanderjahre [Wilhelm Meister’s Travels]—a hope which Du Bois
nuanced, perhaps as soon as his scholarship to the Friedrich Wilhelm
University from the Slater Fund for the Education of Freedmen was
3 Vincent B. Leitch (ed.), The Norton Anthology of Theory and Criticism (New
York: W. W. Norton, 2010).
4 These authors were published by Palgrave in a series similar to this one,
under the same editorial collaboration.
5 Cited in Henry Louis Gates Jr., ‘The Black Letters on the Sign: W. E. B. Du
Bois and the Canon in The Oxford W. E. B. Du Bois, Volume 8: Black Folk
Then and Now: An Essay in the History and Sociology of the Negro Race (New
York: Oxford University Press, 2007), p. xvi.
GENERAL INTRODUCTION • ix
6 Julie Rivkin and Michael Ryan (eds), Literary Theory: An Anthology (Malden,
MA: Wiley Blackwell, 2004).
• GAYATRI CHAKRAVORTY SPIVAK
7 An example that has stayed with me over the years remains Diane Bells
excellent Daughters o f the Dreaming (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press, 1993), which, in response to requests for inclusion of Third World mate
rial, put in Trin-ti Min-Ha and me, longtime faculty persons in prestigious
United States universities!
8 This continuity and the discontinuous are beautifully staged in the film
Bamako (2006) by Abderrahmane Sissako. Jean-François Lyotard gave a clear
articulation of the problem of discontinuity in The Différend: Phrases in Dis
pute (Georges Van Den Abbeele trans.) (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press, 1988).
9 My most recent experience is to encounter a Maori activist bookseller and
an Indian feminist at such a convention, who had never heard of Frederick
Douglass, where only in response to my questions did the South African par
ticipant admit to political problems with translation between indigenous lan
guages, and the m ainland Chinese participant to the barrier between
M andarin and Cantonese. Examples can be multiplied.
GENERAL INTRODUCTION » xi
reader must learn that ‘theory’ need not look the same everywhere,
that for the independent mind, too much training in producing the
European model in stylistic detail might hamper. In my teacher
training work in rural India, it is the illiterate man who understands
things best because his considerable intelligence has not been hob
bled by bad education or gender oppression. The lesson here is not
that everyone should be illiterate but that strong minds should not
be ruined by bad education or imperatives to imitate.
The caution would apply to Neighborhood and Boulevard by
Khaled Ziadeh (belonging to our earlier series, see note 4)—not bad
education, obviously, but the imperative to imitate ‘French Theory’.11
Ziadeh, in spite of his time at Sorbonne, was not tempted. He theo
rizes by space and repetition; Hosam Aboul-Ela’s introduction to that
book walks us through it. There are plenty of people writing in Ara
bic who produce work competitive with the best in European-style
‘theory’. Reading Ziadeh, as Aboul-Ela points out, we have to learn
to recognize ‘theory’ in another guise. My own work profits from his
account of the de-Ottomanization of the city by the French into an
‘Islamic’ space; because I think de-Ottomanization, still active in our
time, has a history as old as the Fall of Constantinople, and, reterri
torialized, backwards into Byzantium. Today’s Khilafat movement
can be read as an example of how imperial historical violence can
produce a counter-violence of no return.
Our series has only just begun. I have described our goal with appro
priate modesty: to translate theoretical material operating outside
1 1 1 use this phrase with the French nationalist irony reflected in François
Cusset, French Theory: Foucault, Derrida, Deleuze et Cie et les mutations de la
vie intellectuelle aux États-Unis (Paris: Éditions la Découverte, 2003), available
in English translation as: French Theory: How Foucault, Derrida, Deleuze, &
Co. Transformed the Intellectual Life of the United States (Jeff Fort trans., with
Josephine Berganza and Marlon Jones) (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press, 2008).
GENERAL INTRODUCTION • xiii
New Years message for 2017: ‘Whoever doesn’t fight collectively will
lose singly’.12
Read our series as a first step, then. Come to the projected con
ferences if they happen, where all of the authors and translators will
gather to ask: What is it to theorize elsewhere, in our world?
IN T R O D U C T IO N
SINCLAIR THOMSON
the first time in English for an international audience. What are the
reasons for bringing out his book today?
I
If we follow Zavaletas own method here, we can address our question
from both specific historical-political and general conceptual angles.
Zavaleta died at a time when an important historical cycle of left-
popular political struggle had recently peaked and a socialist alter
native whose potential had been briefly glimpsed was now rapidly
dissolving. From the 1950s to the time of his death, Zavaleta had
himself moved from a revolutionary nationalist affiliation towards a
more orthodox Leninism and ultimately to an increasingly creative
and heterodox Marxist position. From the late 1970s to the early
1980s, democratic trade-union struggle, with proletarian centrality
and key collaboration from the peasantry, had successfully brought
to an end 20 years of right-wing military dictatorship. The role of
the national trade-union confederation (Central Obrera Boliviana
[Bolivian Workers Central] or COB) in the UDP government had
initially posed the promise that the power of workers could chart a
new course for economic and political organization in the country.
Yet the administration finally imploded amid state economic mis
management and private-sector financial speculation, staggering
hyper-inflation and government inability to channel the mass mobi
lizations flooding the streets and plazas of the capital. The full-blown
chaos set the stage for a counter-revolutionary turn in 1985, imme
diately after Zavaletas death, which would lead to a consolidated
neoliberal regime, one of the first in the world to operate under civil
ian rather than military political control.
A generation later, there nevertheless emerged a new conjunc
ture reminiscent of Zavaletas own times. The neoliberal cycle in
Bolivia began to fall apart in the years after 2000 as a series of popular
insurgencies swept away the old regime and created an opening for
new leftist, indigenous and nationalist projects. The process in
XV I 11" • SINCLAIR THOMSON
1 Emir Sader, The New Mole: Paths o f the Latin American Left (New York:
Verso, 2011), pp. 75-9.
SELF-KNOWLEDGE AND SELF-DETERMINATION * xix
Sader deserves credit for perceiving the creativity and insight of the
left analysis in Bolivia in the 2000s. Yet he did not ask what gave rise
to this current of critical Marxist thought. The answer has to do with
the rich tradition of radical nationalist, indigenista and left political
writing in Bolivia going back to the time of Bolivia’s national revo
lution in the mid twentieth century. Despite the collapse of Marxism
as a political and intellectual option in much of the West and despite
the deep defeats of popular forces in Bolivia in the late twentieth cen
tury, an organically rooted intellectual tradition persisted in the polit
ical subsoil. The foremost figure in that radical tradition was none
other than René Zavaleta Mercado, and the Comuna group was in
many ways a new generational offshoot from that long tradition of
political reflection.2 If that generation of critical left thought has
recently acquired some visibility internationally, especially with the
election of García Linera to the vice-presidency of the MAS govern
ment in 2006, it is now time for the deeper tradition out of which it
emerged to come to light. It seems opportune to revisit the rich
legacy left by Zavaleta at a time when Bolivia has become, more than
ever in its history, an international reference point for activists in
social movements and intellectuals on the left.
II
If Zavaleta continued to offer appreciable reserves and resources for
critical political thinkers in the revolutionary conjuncture of the early
twenty-first century in Bolivia, it was ultimately because of the over
all coherence and depth of his theoretical project. The rationale for
translating Zavaleta for an international readership today ultimately
rests on the value of this project.
could only be carried out through a serious inquiry into the specific
historical and political processes that had given rise to the society in
question. Such an engagement provided an alternative to the sterile
option of applying an abstract framework devised for another reality
or to the empty option of holding reality to a standard it could only
meet in some imagined and ever-postponed future. Instead, the task
was to work off a more universal frame while producing intermediate
concepts elaborated through concrete analysis of particular historical
and political realities. What makes Zavaletas approach so rich, deep
and dynamic is that he acknowledged the partiality of the theorists
intellectual position and saw that conceptual production itself
inevitably depended on the very historical and political conditions
that the theorist sought to understand. There was, however, no alter
native method for a society at the margins of advanced capitalism to
come to know itself and thereby to determine itself.
Ill
Zavaleta was in fact only embarking on this ambitious project when
it was cut off. If he certainly had not drawn any sort of theoretical
closure and we do not know how he might have gone on to revise
and refine his work, he did succeed in outlining some general pos
tulates and generating a cluster of concepts that indicate the overall
direction and potential of his approach.
Some of these notions are of more global applicability. For exam
ple, the first of the hypotheses announced in the prologue to his
book immediately indicates his distance from vulgar or economic-
determinist interpretations of modern state formation as a reflection
of surplus accumulation. Bolivia did not produce a modern state in
the nineteenth or early twentieth century not because the country
was poor but because it was incapable of internalizing its surplus and,
more fundamentally, because it had neither the social ‘receptivity*
nor the state ‘willingness* (disponibilidad) to do so. A second example
comes from the third set of hypotheses in the prologue where he
xxii • SINCLAIR THOMSON
7 For a review of the historiographic positions in this debate, see Steve J. Stern,
‘Feudalism, Capitalism, and the World-System in the Perspective of Latin
America and the Caribbean, The American Historical Review 93(4) (October
1988): 829-72.
SELF-KNOWLEDGE AND SELF-DETERMINATION * xxv
IV
9 Silvia Rivera Cusicanqui and Rossana Barragán (eds), Debates post colo
niales: Una introducción a los estudios de la subalternidad (La Paz: SEPHIS/
Aruwyiri, 1997).
10 René Zavaleta Mercado, Lo nacional-popular en Bolivia in Obra completa,
vol. 2 (La Paz: Plural,
2013). Plural had also republished the work in an inde
pendent edition in 2008.
xxviii • SINCLAIR THOMSON
V
Zavaletas book can be seen as part of a long current within Marxism
in which grounded historical-political analysis has served as the basis
for elaboration of key conceptual categories. Marx’s 18th Brumaire
and Gramsci’s ‘Notes on Italian History’ are two preeminent exam
ples. The connections between Zavaleta and Gramsci’s historical
writing go beyond the general inspiration that the latter provided or
Zavaletas specific redeployment of some of his language and
inquiries. There is the fact that Gramsci was himself writing from
the southern periphery of European capitalism in the early twentieth
century. There is also the similar truncation and open-endedness of
their projects. The very incompleteness of Gramsci’s work left it open
to multiple readings and appropriations, like those made by Zavaleta
himself. By the same token, if Zavaletas life was cut off before his
project had come to fruition, it allowed for a subsequent generation
to pick up the themes and pursue the implications under new his
torical circumstances.
France in 1848 or Italy during the Risorgimento might be some
what familiar to an international readership, perhaps in part thanks
to Marx and Gramsci themselves. For an audience unversed in
Bolivian, Peruvian and Chilean history, one of the challenges of
reading Zavaletas final work is its level of historical specificity. Such
readers are advised to consult Anne Freeland’s afterword to this book
which provides a concise overview of the historical processes exam
ined by Zavaleta.
We might draw an additional comparison here between Zavaletas
methodological approach to Bolivian history and Gramsci’s approach
to subaltern history. Like social historians in the present, Gramsci
was aware of the difficulty of writing the history of subaltern social
groups (and hence of Italian history as a whole). Given their relative
lack of consolidation within the state and the corresponding limits
to the accessibility of their experience for the researcher, any attempt
to write subaltern history would inevitably be fragmentary and
SELF-KNOWLEDGE AND SELF-DETERMINATION • xxxiii
I. Introduction
The problem that this study seeks to investigate is that of the forma
tion of the national-popular in Bolivia, that is, the connection
between what Max Weber called social democratization*1 and state
form. By this we mean the different patterns of socialization as they
existed and their indices of power, as well as the so-called mass pro
jects. In other words, the relation between programme and reality.
Our study of this problem will refer to the period between 1952 and
1980, although its causal explanation will bring us back to the War
of the Pacific (1879-84).2 It should be understood as a general argu
ment about the Bolivian social formation, empirically supported by
data from the period. From a methodological perspective, we will
proceed by isolating certain events, circumscribed in time, or
regional situations, circumscribed in space. This is a response to a
scarcity of information and it undoubtedly entails a symbolic selec
tion. In defence of this method it must be said that no social science
is possible otherwise in a country like Bolivia.
II. Background
7(12) (September 1982): 11-30; Obra completa, YOL. 2, pp. 513-29; ‘De Banzer
a Guevara Arze: la fuerza de la masa, Cuadernos de Marcha (Mexico) 2(3)
(Septem ber-October 1979): 29-41; Obra completa, YOL. 2, pp. 471-93.
8 See Zavaleta, ‘Movimiento obrero y ciencia social ’ The conduct o f the peas
ant leaders in relation to the guerrilla of 1967 is especially eloquent. See René
Zavaleta Mercado, ‘El Che en el Churo’, Semanario Marcha (Mexico), 10 O cto
ber 1969, pp. 16-18; subsequently published in Temas Sociales 7 (1971): 10-
22; Obra completa, VOL 2, pp. 621-32.
9 See note 41.
10 See Ramiro Condarco Morales, Zárate, el temible Willka: Historia de la
rebelión indígena de 1899 (La Paz: Talleres Gráficos Bolivianos, 1965).
11 See Carlos Badía Malagrida, El factor geográfico en la política sudamericana
(Madrid: Reus, 1946); Jaime Mendoza, El macizo boliviano (La Paz: Imp. Am ó
hnos., 1935), etc.
PROLOGUE • 5
20 This is evident in the events of Sacaba, Tolata and Epinaza in 1974 and the
great peasant movement in support of the workers strike of November 1979.
21 We know, for example, that US diplomats were sure in March 1952 that
Movimiento Nacionalista Revolucionario (Revolutionary Nationalist Move
ment, MNR) would never rise to power, when an insurrection would erupt
just days later. With Sergio Almaraz, I was able to see correspondence on this
matter in the archive at the Calvo office in La Paz.
22 See Jackson Eder, in his memoirs, cited in Laurence Whitehead, The United
States and Bolivia: A Case o f Neo-colonialism (Oxford: Haslemere, 1969) and
Victor Andrade, M y Missions fo r Revolutionary Bolivia, 1944-1962 (Pitts
burgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1976).
23 See Herbert S. Klein, Orígenes de la revolución nacional boliviana: La crisis
de la generación del Chaco (La Paz: Juventud, 1968); Liborio Justo, Bolivia: La
revolución derrotada (Buenos Aires: Juárez Editor, 1971); Luis Peñaloza, His
toria del Movimiento Nacionalista Revolucionario: 1941-1952 (La Paz: Direc
ción Nacional de Informaciones, 1963).
8 • RENÉ ZAVALETA MERCADO
24 It was surely the success of the peasant mobilization that ensured the sur
vival of the MNRs power in the critical years of 1952-56.
25 The substitution of the ‘m ilitary-peasant pact’ by an alliance between the
peasantry and the COB towards 1978 and the support of the UDP in the three
elections that Siles Zuazo won between 1978 and 1980.
26 See Juan Rojas and June C. Nash, He agotado mi vida en la mina: Una his
toria de vida (Buenos Aires: Nueva Visión, 1976); Domitila Barrios de C hun
gara and M oema Viezzer (eds), *Si me permiten hablar: Testimonio de
Domitila, una mujer de las minas de Bolivia (Mexico City: Siglo XXI, 1977),
available in English as: Let Me Speak! Testimony o f Domitila, a Woman o f the
PROLOGUE • 9
Bolivian Mines (New York; M onthly Review Press, 1978); Carlos Soria
Galvarro, Con la revolución en las venas: Los mineros de Siglo XX en la resisten
cia antifascista (La Paz: Editorial Roalva, 1980).
27 See Gonzalo Romero, Reflexiones para una interpretación de la historia de
Bolivia (Buenos Aires; Imprenta López, 1960); Jorge Siles Salinas, ‘Reflexiones
sobre la ejemplaridad* in Lecciones de una revolución: Bolivia, 1952-1959 (San
tiago: Editorial Universidad Católica, 1959), pp. 27-36; Marcelo Quiroga
Santa Cruz, La victoria de abril sobre la nación (La Paz: Burillo, 1964); Jorge
Siles Salinas, La aventura y el orden: reflexiones sobre la revolución boliviana
(Santiago: Bustos y Letelier, 1956).
10 # REN£ ZAVALETA MERCADO
above all, the establishment of what has been called ‘social Darwinism’
as the internal ideology of the oligarchic state.30This is of course not
the same thing as a democratic revolution in which great masses are
active and take up arms, those in which military action is more or
less global, such as the Mexican Revolution, or insurrections like that
of Bolivia in 1952 that are concretized in a concentrated nucleus
which later distributes its revolutionary effects, only after these have
been mediated by ideological subsumption, etc.31 In any case, even
if we accept such objections, we would have to speak in terms of a
lack of extension or depth of these constitutive moments, but not of
their nonexistence. It is clear that the course of Bolivian history pre
pared the way for this type of innovation.
Here the explanation of the weak constitution of the nation-state
on the basis of a supposed lack of economic surplus is an unfortunate
commonplace.32 Bolivia would never have had the articulatory eco
nomic capacity required to produce more advanced institutions. This
would not explain, on the other hand, why countries like Cuba in
the 1920s and Argentina during the half century that spans from
1880 to 1930 failed nonetheless, as did Bolivia, in the construction
of modern political superstructures.
In the nineteenth century, Bolivia disappears from the world mar
ket for all practical purposes.33 A state apparatus is then organized
CHAPTER ONE
V fI
18 • RENE ZAVALETA MERCADO
3 In the War o f the Pacific, Chile fought against Peru and Bolivia between
1879 and 1884; the so-called Federal Revolution was a civil war between the
departm ents of the south, under the leadership of Chuquisaca, and those of
the north, basically La Paz. See Condarco Morales, Zarate, el temible Willka.
4 Although it had been at times, for example, with Santa Cruz. A true distinc
tion between the government as apparatus and the ruling class does not for
mally exist until the Revolution of 1952. Still, here we must take into account
the tendency of the state to return to society—as a result of its power, it returns
to society far stronger—and, conversely, the continuous impulse of every
aspect of society, but more forcefully of certain particular groups, towards the
state. The more or less prolonged stability of the state and of society is the
privilege of but few societies.
THE STRUGGLE FOR THE SURPLUS * 19
14 J. Valerie Fifer, Bolivia: Land, Location and Politics since 1825 (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1972).
15 Josep M. Barnadas, Charcas: Orígenes históricos de una sociedad colonial
( 1535-1565) (La Paz: CIPCA, 1973).
16 Hernando Sanabria Fernández, Breve historia de Santa Cruz (La Paz: Juven
tud, 1973).
17 John V. Murra, Formaciones económicas y políticas del mundo andino (Lima:
IEP, 1975); Ramiro Condarco Morales, El escenario andino y el hombre: Ecología
y antropogeografía de los Andes Centrales (La Paz: Librería Renovación, 1971).
24 • RENÉ ZAVALETA MERCADO
lost the forms of its totalization, as a coherent totality. The very idea
of totalization or general intersubjectification18 refers to something
that is never acquired once and for all, and thus the nation can exist
more within a collective project or prognosis than within an exhaus
tive homogeneity; moreover, even what has been generalized sooner
or later tends towards its transformation into a conservative symbol
of the particular. Intersubjectification must, therefore, be constantly
reproduced. Men such as Prudencio Bustillo who were the vanguard
or spirit of the consciousness of the state (not of social consciousness,
because that would be an overstatement; we say this because in prac
tice the Bolivian state itself would have been Bustillo)19 had warned
of this ineluctable situation. It was not, after all, so complicated, and
ultimately, Bustillo is but the common sense of a truly parochial lack
of common sense. Portales himself would have had no more than a
rhetorical existence had he not produced the War of the Pacific. An
insensitivity to the seriousness of the conflict is evident in Daza
(although it is also evident in the rest of the men of state, including
Baptista and, of course, Arce, who resolved to join in his enemies’
victory, founding a whole school).20 What is worth noting in all this,
18 See p. 47.
19 Ignacio Prudencio Bustillo, La misión Bustillo: Más antecedentes de la
Guerra del Pacífico (Sucre: Imprenta Bolívar, 1919). At any rate, it is an isolated
case. It can easily be said that there would be no bourgeois national conscious
ness of such depth until Montenegro. At some point Bustillo’s polemic against
Alberdi published under a pseudonym should discussed.
20 Aniceto Arce was an associate of Melchor Concha y Toro, of whom
Ramirez Necochea says: ‘A n influential liberal politician. Member of Parlia
m ent for more or less 30 years. [ . . . ] He opposed the Balmaceda government
and, when civil war broke out, he declared himself on the side of Congress.
He m ade a name for himself as a businessman; he had powerful banking and
m ining interests; he extended his activities to Bolivia and was closely associ
ated with British capital’ (Hernán Ramirez Necochea, Balmaceda y la contrar
revolución de 1891 [Santiago: Ed. Universitaria, 1969], p. 84. Arce said: ‘The
only hope for Bolivia’s salvation is Chile’s need to enlist it to ensure its own
THE STRUGGLE FOR THE SURPLUS • 25
originary idea of space, because that space was the matrix of the pri
mordial organization of life, is opposed to a patrimonial conception.
It is well known, however, that space plays a determinative role in
the relation to the state, that is, we have here two competing concep
tions that are both spatialist. On the seigneurial side, which is that
of the state, we have the hereditary notion of power in its double
sense: on the one hand, as the idea of private power (the rosea)27 and,
on the other, as an extension of the seigneurial or feudal relation to
the land, an absolute dominion over the land as an entitlement tied
to a lineage, as a general principle of power. That regional or partic-
ularist conflict is so intense within the Hispanic contingent and, on
the other hand, that the coexistence of Aymaras and Quechuas is so
natural, although in theory the whites are said to ultimately belong
more or less to a single ethnic group while, strictly speaking, a
Quechua should be as foreign to an Aymara as a Spaniard, bears wit
ness to the existence of these two conceptions or principles.28 It is
27 This local epithet speaks to the Bolivian ruling class’ sense of being an abso
lute minority. It is said to have been first used by Bautista Saavedra.
28 All this is quite complicated. It is not clear that Aymara was the language
of La Paz, for example, and there is some evidence that it might have been
Puquina (Alfredo Torero, El quechua y la historia social andina [Lima:
Studium, 1975], p. 57). Moreover, ‘nobody has found valid reason to maintain
that Quechua existed in Bolivia prior to the arrival of the Incas,’ although there
is no doubt that Quechua ultimately became the lingua franca of the colony
(Gary Parker, ‘Falacias y verdades acerca del quechua’ in Alberto Escobar
(ed.), El reto del multilingUismo en el Perú [Lima: IEP, 1973], p. 117). In other
words, the borders between Quechua and Aymara were never absolute. This
means that there is an identity, even if it is produced between two languages,
which is like a paradigm of intersubjectivity. Meanwhile, the Hispanic sector,
which is assumed to be of greater homogeneous and monolingual provenance,
is very far from such an identification. The fragmentation of reality proper to
the gamonal mentality has cost the Hispanic group dearly. Indeed, it remains
to be seen whether the chief obstacle to nationalization in Bolivia is not in
fact the degree of cultural and symbolic dispersion of its ruling class and not,
as has been said almost by reflex, the presence of the indigenous.
28 # RENÉ ZAVALETA MERCADO
not that the oligarchs like Arce or Pacheco had no sense of belonging
to the space, but that the feelings they had were connected to a
seigneurial notion of space. This is the deep origin of what is called
regionalism in Bolivia, that is, the incapacity for an experience of
space as a national reality or even as something not directly linked
to a personal relation to the land, as something conceived trans-
personally or collectively.29
A country, or a society (or human nucleus), wages war with what
it is, but also with what it is not. If a war is a radical event, if it is uni
versal, it creates social receptivity. If it is not, it can shatter the society
that it was supposed to defend. The true optimum for this purpose
is produced when, as is said to have occurred with the ancient
Scandinavians, the society goes to war en masse, that is, when no
particle of the social body is unaffected by the war. For this to occur,
first of all, the social corpus as such must feel itself to be unified to a
certain extent (the principle of connection) and, on the other hand,
and this is related to the first point, it must regard the object of the
war as something central, vital and unrenounceable, something that
must not be lost except when all is lost. Where the nation does not
exist, men cannot be asked to take part in a national war or to possess
a national sensibility in relation to the territory. That of the Bolivian
ruling class is a particularist idea of the nation. These men experi
enced the dispossession of the coast as something inessential, as if,
conserving the main part of the country, it was merely an incidental
loss (this is why they accepted money for a territory that should
never have been for sale), because such was their mentality: this
land had no seigneurial connection whatsoever nor did it have a
seigneurial use; to lose it, then, was like losing nothing at all, a mere
inconvenience.30
33 ‘From Cobo we learn that the use of fertilizers was one of the things the
Europeans learnt in Peru’ (Murra, La organización económica, p. 61). We
m ight also m ention the effects of irrigation on the coast, etc., for the state.
34 Alcides Arguedas, Raza de bronce (Buenos Aires: Losada, 1972).
35 Guevara Arze, Plan inmediato.
36 Mendoza, El macizo boliviano.
37 ‘The Pacaxas [ . . . ] had possessions on the Pacific coast, apparently inter
spersed with those of the Lupaga’ (Murra, Formaciones económicas y políticas,
p. 753). ‘The Aymara-speaking kingdoms extended their control not only
towards the Pacific, but also to the edge of the rainforest and beyond’ (ibid.,
p. 77).
38 The ‘Colorados’ join the fight in El Alto de la Alianza with the rallying cry
‘Long live the youth o f La Paz!’ See Alcides Arguedas, Historia general de
Bolivia, p. 1338.
THE STRUGGLE FOR THE SURPLUS • 31
We might say that at the heart of the War of the Pacific was a conflict
over the surplus because, as we shall see, Chile wanted to be Peru,43
which, with Potosí, had been a symbol of the wealth of the world,
surplus as magic; Bolivia thought that it was not Peru because Chile
had snatched the philosopher’s stone from it and Peru wanted only
to go back to being itself, at least that of the guano surplus, but to do
it better this time. Everyone here was seduced by the idea of a
panacea. Meanwhile the Federal Revolution, which is the next
moment of this history, would pose the question of the axis of the
state, understood as a pivot of the spatial articulation of the country
(one of the aspects of the optimum), which already brings us to the
core of the national question as one of the central problems of the
Bolivia of that time, that is, as a relation of the territory to the terri
tory and of men with men, space understood as a relation to space
but also as a struggle among men and between men and the spaces
they inhabit.
We must return to the question of Bolivia’s non-combativeness.
It is true that the first thing that strikes us in the War of the Pacific
is the lack of a collective will (this is not an exaggeration) to fight for
a portion of the territory that was vital to the core of the country,
that is, the refusal (because the people were unarmed and as a con
sequence of the field of vision of the elite) to see it as something abso
lutely crucial. Here we must distinguish between territory that has
been socially incorporated or appropriated and that which has not,
because this indicates the extent to which it has penetrated the ulti
mate ethos of a nation. There are inherent or essential territories,
that is, those without which a people cannot be what it is, and
marginal or supplemental territories, which are those that accom
pany or complement the vital core. Since Atacama was a limit or
frontier made fit for human life by the Andeans and no one else,44
and considering, moreover, that neither Spaniards nor Araucanians
had ever settled there, the Andeans considered it in their collective
soul to be part of their central home, which, incidentally, goes against
Tamayos exceedingly narrow latifundista ideas on the subject.45 In
other words, it belonged to the intellectual horizon of the Aymara,
to their spatial discourse. In a radical rupture with this general con
ception of the space, the seigneurial class experienced its disposses
sion with a kind of ease or indifference scarcely moderated by the
flagrant humiliation with which the rather inexperienced Chilean
emissaries, newly risen to glory, were inclined to treat them.46
In any case, had there not been a general failure to understand
that the territory in question was one socially incorporated into the
innate logic of the nation, the nation would not have been able to
lose it without first facing the loss of the whole of the nation itself. A
man or a nation of sound mind does not lose something vital without
losing or at least risking his very life. Here, however, the territory was
lost because those who knew that they were losing it thought of it as
dispensable.
Just as today it is perpetually said on the subject of imperialism
that since we cannot beat it we must live under it, it was said then
that Chiles material superiority was so insuperable that retreating to
the mountains was the only reasonable option. This was false, of
course, even from a military standpoint. Even under radically infe
rior conditions, the dispossessed nation fights with a certain para
doxical advantage because it moves within itself, on the condition
that what is at stake belongs to it, something that, as we have seen,
was only true for a buried part of the nation.47 The very fact that the
invader moved with greater ease in that environment shows that, in
terms of immediate, effective belonging, Bolivia, because it was Arce’s
Bolivia and not Willkas,48 was even farther from that Bolivian terri
tory than was the Chilean state.49 That was the real conquest. The
war was just its inevitable consummation.
Arce himself was determined that the vanquished partner was
the victor,50 and indeed his role in this history is that of the advocate
of a repetition, with the silver of Colquechaca,51 of Chiles felicitous
coastal nitrate venture. It is surprising, to say the least, that this man
is even today considered a paragon of Bolivian patriotism. No less
can be said of Baptista, who proposed an alliance between Bolivia
and Argentina, or of Montes, who sought unification with Chile (no
longer just as a partner but to form a single country, in which Bolivia
52 Montes at one point in fact came to propose the fusion of Bolivia and Chile
into a single country, a notion decried by Franz Tamayo.
53 In the local lore, indeed, the names Arce, Baptista and Montes are never
absent from the pantheon of national heroes, which can only be explained as
a whitewashing of the facts within the history of a single continuous caste that
persists to this day.
54 In exchange for its coast, Bolivia took 2,500,000 pounds sterling. Brazil
paid no more than 1,000,000 for all of Acre.
55 ‘The territory [ . . . ] is the first and most sacred of national possessions,
because it contains within it all of the others’ (Rafael Bustillo, in a letter to
President Morales dated 12 March 1872 [Querejazu Calvo, Guano, salitre,
sangre, p. 91]).
36 • REN£ ZAVALETA MERCADO
mode of production, for very different reasons.58 The role of the wit
ness is decisive here, although in the first case it is collective, and in
the second case it is so only in a differed way. In examining the con
struction of a discourse, would it be of little account to ask where the
discourse occurs? Hegemony, if it is produced, is produced somewhere.
It is, therefore, linked to a symbol-space, to a kind of geological totem.
The god of Andean culture is the space determined by the Andean
mountain chain, which, of course, cannot have the same function as
the Pyrenees or the Apennines for the Spaniards or the Italians.59 In
any case, to derive ideological and state forms from a space, like the
Andeans, is not the same thing as to conquer a territory not bound to
the peoples own identity, something which, in order to succeed, must
be the consequence of a previously existing identity.60 In this case, the
people constructs its space; in the other, the space forms the people.61
But what was really at issue here between Peru, Bolivia and
Chile? The thesis that on one side was perfect treachery and on
the other total innocence is ultimately untenable. It is a fact, for
example, that just as Portales formulated a policy against Santa Cruz,
the latter assumed the categorical superiority of Peru and Bolivia.
We should say, rather, that it was a confrontation between a vain self-
satisfaction, that of Peru to a greater extent but also that of Bolivia,
since they were ingenuous countries,62 and a certain sense of adven
ture, a certain inferiority complex and a precociousness of the
they achieve their totalization. That is, totalization plus the qualita
tive form in which totalization is realized.
[T]he same division of labour that turns them into indepen
dent private producers also makes the social process of pro
duction and the relations of the individual producers to each
other within that process independent of the producers
themselves; they also find out that the independence of the
individuals from each other has as its counterpart and sup
plement a system of all-round material dependence.71
We have, in the first place, generalized circulation, that is, every
one produces for another and no one for himself. This in itself speaks
to a specific form of totalization, no doubt superior to previous
orms. The crux of the issue resides, however, not in the simple fact
of generalization but in the interaction that comes with it, which is
an interaction among free men, that is, if circulatory totalization itself
contains a moment of receptivity or emptiness, because man has
been untethered from the conditions of his previous discourse, he
immediately gives himself over to the formation of a new ideology,
the ideological substitute, which is a particularly powerful intersub
jectivity for it is grounded in the will of juridically free men. This
interpenetration clearly must be greater than that produced among
men who do not construct such an interaction but are passively
homogenized because they have a common master.72 If the existence
of juridically free man is a sine qua non of capitalism and such are
the collective-ideological consequences of originary accumulation,
this nonetheless should not be oversimplified. Ultimately, we can
Even Potosí emphatically proved that it is not the surplus that matters
but who appropriates it and for what. Great surpluses like that of
Argentina in the last third of the nineteenth century and the first of
the twentieth, that of Chiles nitrates and copper, even that of
Venezuela’s oil and Cuba’s heyday, attest to the absolutely supplemen
tary role of this factor.78 The history of the period immediately prior
to the war shows how a great surplus, that of the guano boom, had
not sufficed for the construction of a nation. On the other hand,
Mexico in the period between 1910 and 1920 and then in the 30s
produced a very high level of state receptivity without the benefit of
a large surplus. Here receptivity was the result of the activity of the
society. Even Chile ultimately had demonstrated that state receptivity
is one thing and the surplus is another. Indeed, when Chile took hold
of an immense surplus, its social optimum was impoverished and it
clearly once enjoyed a considerable level of state accumulation on
the basis of a rather modest surplus.79
From all this it should be clear that the concept of the surplus is
not to be privileged a priori. In a tentative analogy, it could be said
therefore that the surplus refers to absolute profit and to formal sub
sumption, while receptivity is connected to real subsumption or the
internal or essential reorganization of the productive act. The signif
icance of the surplus here, however, derives from the fact that it is a
requirement of large-scale reproduction which, in turn, contains the
whole logic of the new experience of time. Since it is as if men today
live many days in the space that used to occupy a single day, since
they have taken hold of time and concentrated it, they must construct
far more elaborate mechanisms so that this precarious agglutination
does not explode. A separate excursus would certainly be in order
regarding the relation between surplus and receptivity, and of both
to the structure of the state, the expansion of the state, and the theory
of mediations.80 The form in which the surplus exists and the form
of its absorption, then, determine the very succession of modes of
production. On the other hand, capitalism itself is the history of the
construction of its state or, in other words, the history of the capitalist
state is that of the production, distribution and application of the
surplus. To be precise, it is clear that the surplus does not have an
autonomous function because the optimum is composed, in reality,
of the relation between surplus and receptivity. Where there is no
receptivity, the surplus has no function. The greater the degree of
receptivity, the more we must take into account the datum of the sur
plus. Receptivity, as we have seen, can ultimately exist even with a
meagre surplus, although with a greater degree of material social
erosion.81
that the state must act as a person in civil society to assert its auton
omy or separation.83The modern state must then adapt to expanded
reproduction or perpetual mobility and, on the other hand, also to
the totalization of society, that is, general circulation (or the general
ized social market). In the binary or transfigurative movement that
things in this structure tend to have, it could be said that, perhaps as
a result of the accumulation of time, a much more decisive measure
of organic solidarity or subjective interpenetration emerges here as
well as far more structural forms of contradiction, contestation and
counterhegemony. Solidarity, therefore, as well as dissent or resistance,
are inscribed with the mark of their provenance from men who com
mand the use of their own will. The work of interaction modifies sub
jects in relation to one another; they are reformed by one another.
This necessarily produces, at least in its prototype, a particular mode
of totalization that constitutes the unequivocal specificity of the phe
nomena of the nation and the state in capitalism.
The very sense of time, the idea of the provisionality of the
world, that is, the expansion of circulation and generalized inter
action, because the old particularity has been destroyed and one
cannot take refuge within what no longer exists but only in the par
ticularity proper to the collective (no one acts for himself and the
self ultimately resides in the first person plural),84 would have trans
lated into the simple suppression of capitalism if here the originary
construction of ideology in its new form, that is, the superstition of
the indestructibility of the state, had not taken place. The establish
ment of consent, whether by means of an impression of power of the
state or through the seduction of a new culture, is only the extension
of the real subsumption of labour under capital. There is an element
83 In truth, the more organic the insertion or inclusion of the state in society,
the m ore consistent its autonomy founded on distance. This should not be
confused with the state that has not differentiated itself from the units of soci
ety, that which has no choice but to act as a faction that governs arbitrarily.
84 Zavaleta, ‘Clase y conocimiento’, p. 3.
THE STRUGGLE FOR THE SURPLUS • 49
85 Clauss Offe.
86 Peruvians like Pardo used the guano surplus to abolish indigenous tribute,
which was like an attempt to win Peru its independence from the Indians.
Around 1830, indigenous and casta tribute in practice made up half of all tax
revenues (Ernesto Yepes del Castillo, Perú 1820-1920: Un siglo de desarrollo
capitalista [Lima: IEP, 1972], p. 43). The surplus conquered in the Pacific, on
the other hand, enabled the ‘Chilean experts’ [duchos de Chile] (the expression
is Mattes) to ‘win their independence from the state (Jobet, Ensayo crítico del
desarrollo económico-social de Chile, pp. 67-8).
87 The history of the relation between the Bolivian state and the tin barons,
who in practice never contributed anything, is an example of absolute non
contribution to total capital and its consequences. They were ruined by their
own greed.
50 • REN£ ZAVALETA MERCADO
88 Pierre Vilar, A History o f Gold and Money, 1450-1920 (Judith White trans.)
(New York: Verso, 1991).
89 Both Marx and Gramsci use the term ‘m oral’, in the sense of ‘moral-
historical’ or ‘intellectual and moral reform’. This does not refer merely to the
theft of man’s labour power in the first case, or the internal form of valoriza
tion of conduct in the second. It seems to us that in both cases it involves the
principle of action according to ends, the transformation of which ought to
be in daily life and the hegemonic internalization of the present foundations
of the social.
THE STRUGGLE FOR THE SURPLUS • 51
existing product, which is the path of reform; this is feasible too but
at a higher cost. Reforms excite or move people in a way that is even
more dangerous than revolutionary measures. Finally, especially at
decisive political moments, new canons of the moral-historical mea
sure itself can be generated, that is, there can be a moral act that
founds a new surplus. Even the appropriation of that measure, in
what can be called the negative formation of ideology, the apology
for self-plunder, can be conceived as a foundational event.90
Let us turn now to consider the behaviour of the three countries
engaged in the struggle for the surplus, which is the motivating core
of the conflict, although it is surely attended by powerful dispositions
accumulated in the social or collective unconscious91 of each. The
idea of possessing Peru or destroying what could not be possessed
of it (to possess the fortune it never had) was no doubt a bitter col
lective compulsion in Chile92 which, moreover, proved to be an
organic people or a nation although this could not be explained by
the general market. This concept is often used as a cipher, as if it
could explain everything. But in itself it ultimately leads nowhere if
it is not integrated into a certain deliberation on the problem of the
social optimum, as a necessary theoretical matrix, and if we do not
take into account the fundamental inability of the three countries
93 The war in fact marks the end of the self-determinative tendencies that
ostensibly existed in the previous Chilean state. ‘Harvey, working with North,
played a prom inent part in the operations carried out during the war
(Ramírez Necochea, Balm acedayla contrarrevolución de 1891y p. 45). There
could be no other outcome. ‘In 1889, the British dominated the vital centres
of industry’ (ibid., p. 28), Curtis, an American cited by Ramirez Necochea,
said, ‘Valparaiso, with its trade entirely controlled by the British, its market
transactions conducted in pounds sterling, its English newspaper and exten
sive use of the language, was no more than a British colony’ (ibid., p. 39). The
great protagonists of diplomatic intrigue such as Carlos Walker Martinez, a
good friend of Baptista, and Concha y Toro, an associate of Arce, were con
crete agents of the British. In the end, there was no doubt that Chile had made
a lot of money but that it was less a of country than it had been before.
THE STRUGGLE FOR THE SURPLUS • 53
lives for the surplus and their common failure when it came to the
transformation of the surplus into self-determination, along with
certain other significant factors such as the seigneurial worldview,
indicate that these are countries that have something in common,
which perhaps has to do with a certain quality of their colonization
that we might call ‘Peruvian’.94 Of course all this should be qualified,
but certain identities can become entangled in a tragic history like
the one that transpired here. War is an atrocious mode of relation
between societies but it is a mode of relation nonetheless.
In one case after another, the idolization of the surplus is always
the same. With the level of development that the Incas had reached
and with the demographic volume that they had attained practically
overnight, the conquest itself entailed the acquisition of an unpre
cedented surplus. The conventional indices, moreover, fail to
adequately explain a certain elasticity or capacity for sudden regen
eration that the Peruvian economy continually displayed over the
course of its history.95 For example, independence did not devastate
the territory as it did in Upper Peru, Venezuela or Mexico. And yet
Peru had to sustain a good part if not all of the cost of the other side,
94 ‘No Spaniard came to Chile with such modest intentions. All of them were
lords or aspired to be. The West Indies were the perfect environment for a men
tality that belonged to a feudal society in decay and in an arena too confined to
satisfy the ambitions of the many hopeful lords that were the Spanish hidalgos.
On the other hand, those who previously could not even come close to claiming
such a rank could do so the moment they set foot on American soil. All of them
viewed the Indian as a true serf destined to ennoble their new masters’ (Alvaro
Jara, Guerra y sociedad en Chile: La transformación de la guerra de Arauco y la
esclavitud de los indios [Santiago, Ed: Universitaria, 1971], p. 40).
95 To the point that, of this country destroyed in 1870, it could be said
that, between 1917 and 1921, ‘in contrast to what was then occurring with
other Latin American countries, Peru had no problems balancing its budget’
(Julio Cotier, Clases, Estado y nación en el Perú, [Lima: IEP, 1978], p. 143).
Exports rose from 91.6 million sols in 1913 to 269 million sols in 1919. Cotton
exports grew twentyfold between 1900 and 1919, sugar grew sixfold and cop
per eightfold.
54 # RENÉ ZAVALETA MERCADO
1 imported into Britain was greater than that of any other single national prod
uct imported from Latin America’ (W. M. Matthew, ‘The Imperialism of Free
Trade: Peru, 1820-70’, Economic History Review 21 [3] [December 1968]: 563).
For 25 years, Britain maintained closer relations with Peru than with any other
________________________________________________________________________
THE STRUGGLE FOR THE SURPLUS * 55
Latin American country. Still, it is also true that Chile was the fifth largest
supplier of wheat to England and that in the months leading up to the war
Chile came to be a more im portant trading partner of the British than any
other country in the region with the exception of Brazil. (Hernán Ramírez
Necochea, Historia del imperialismo en Chile [Santiago: Austral, 1970)).
99 Chiles trade increased from 65,452,467 pesos in 1879 to 136,280,478 pesos
in 1890 (ibid.). Export taxes on nitrates and guano increased suddenly from
15.4 million pesos to 35.4 million pesos in 1881 (Jobet, Ensayo crítico del
desarrollo económico-social de Chile, p. 73).
100 Chile, according to González Prada, ‘was infected with the Peruvian
malady’.
56 # RENÉ ZAVALETA MERCADO
101 The current indices of each country, if favourable to Chile, are no more
so than those before 1879.
102 In this case, there was certainly a collective instinctual resolve that new
territories should not be lost. It is nonetheless striking that Bolivia made much
greater sacrifices for the Gran Chaco, which was practically empty, than for
the coast, which was a great source of wealth.
THE STRUGGLE FOR THE SURPLUS • 57
Marx wrote that wars are not waged between countries but
between gross products. Today we can affirm that this betrays a certain
—necessary—economistic bias. Gross product is really only a valid
criterion of comparison between countries with a similar level of cap
italist development and even then certain qualifications would have
to be made. It is, first of all, a purely statistical datum and refers only,
somewhat crudely, to the quantitative aspect of a society. A society
with a greater gross product might not have it concentrated or might
not be able to concentrate it when it wants to do so, while one with
an inferior gross product might have the ability to mobilize it effec
tively, swiftly and at the opportune moment. Thus in this conflict
(and this approximates the logic of dependency theory) the more
powerful, the country possessing the greatest gross product, should
necessarily have won. Even with a greater gross product in absolute
terms, the social optimum can be inferior (this is the case with
Argentina at present, for example).107 In reality, then, since Peru lost
the war when it was richer than ever,108 the conflict is between dif
ferent types of social equations or the degree to which each of them
is the bearer of an optimum. We must explain what it is that we mean
by what we have reiteratively called the social equation or optimum,
which is nothing but the relational quality of a society. We will base
our discussion on a passage from Antonio Gramsci:
107 In Argentina, the Falklands tragedy exemplifies the high price of a low
optimum in the relation between society and the state.
108 Peru exported more guano in 1876 than at almost any other year, apart
from exceptional years such 1869 and 1870, and even then it exported almost
twice as much in nitrates and triple the figure from 1870, just six years earlier.
Even sugar exports increased almost twentyfold and amounted to almost half
the income from guano. Sugar production rose from 4,500 tons in 1871 to
60,763 tons in 1878 (Luis Raúl Esteves, Apuntes para la historia económica
del Perú [Lima: Imprenta Calle de Huallaga, 1882], p. 16). W hile revenues
remained constant between 1865 and 1868, spending increased from 13.36
million pesos to 20.5 million pesos (Yepes del Castillo, Perú 1820-1920,
p. 84). It was not as a result of economic inferiority that Peru lost this war.
THE STRUGGLE FOR THE SURPLUS • 61
This does not mean that the tactics of assault and incursion
and the war of maneuver should now be considered to be
utterly erased from the study of military science; that would
be a serious error. But in wars among the most industrially
and socially advanced states, these methods of war most be
seen to have a reduced tactical function rather than a strate
gic function; their place in military history is analogous to
that of siege warfare in the previous period.
The same reduction must take place in the art and sci
ence of politics, at least in those cases pertaining to the most
advanced states, where civil society’ has become a very com
plex structure that is very resistant to the catastrophic ‘irrup
tions’ of the immediate economic factor (crises, depressions,
etc.): the superstructures of civil society resemble the trench
system of modern warfare. Sometimes, it would appear that
a ferocious artillery attack against enemy trenches had lev
elled everything, whereas in fact it had caused only superfi
cial damages to the defenses of the adversary, so that when
the assailants advanced they encountered a defensive front
that was still effective. The same thing occurs in politics
during great economic crises. A crisis does not enable the
attacking troops to organize themselves at lightning speed
in time and in space; much less does it infuse them with a
fighting spirit. On the other side of the coin, the defenders
are not demoralized; nor do they nor do they abandon their
defensive positions, even in the midst of rubble; nor do they
lose faith in their own strength of their own future. This is
not to say that everything remains intact----
And finally:
In the East the State was everything, civil society was primor
dial and gelatinous; in the West, there was a proper relation
between State and civil society, and when the state tottered,
a sturdy structure of civil society was immediately revealed.
62 • R E N t ZAVALETA MERCADO
114 Lenin: ‘The peasant [ . . . ] becomes the sole subject of agriculture and is
gradually transformed into the capitalist farmer (‘The Agrarian Question in
Russia Towards the Close of the Nineteenth Century’) [Translated from the
Spanish. This reference is untraceable.—Trans.]. This has to do with the mode
of constitution of the free individual. In other words, a ‘pact’ between free
individual smallholders is one thing, and it is quite another if the peasants are
subjugated, by debt or in any other way, even if they have been granted juridi
cal ‘freedom’.
THE STRUGGLE FOR THE SURPLUS • 65
115 O r also, o f course, the radical difference between Baptistas soldiers and
the volunteers in South Africa or Ethiopia.
THE STRUGGLE FOR THE SURPLUS * 67
our analysis of this history leads us to seek more structural and con
stant causes.
‘Chile,’ [Oswald] Spengler once wrote, ‘is a robust state.’ Let us
leave aside for now the general question of the state in Chile and
reduce the exposition to its elements or essence. Whether Chile was
or was not then already a robust state remains to be seen; in reality,
it is demonstrable, rather, that the Chilean state was capable then and
there of constructing a state policy, which in turn was able to engage
the entire society, to lead it towards the objective of war. It is perhaps
worth pausing to consider this question, that of the construction of
a state policy. With states as with individuals, decisions that are in
fact imposed by circumstance or external conditions are often
attributed to the will of their executors; in some cases, the subjective
support for the decision might even believe itself to be resolving
something that in reality has been determined by events.11617
This is particularly true for the world of the periphery, the pro
letarian nations.1,7 As we have seen, the problem of receptivity is
always decisive. In normal circumstances, they are countries that lack
receptivity, that is, self-determination. This emerges under certain
conditions, such as in moments of conflict between core countries,
or through the social receptivity that results from a general crisis or
the seizure of an unforeseen surplus.118 What we call the economic
policy’ of these countries is often no more than the sum of measures
demanded by the hegemonic core. This is of course relative. Every
society, even the weakest and most isolated, always possesses some
119 Despite the fact that the state had ownership of Peru’s guano since 1840
and its nitrates since 1878, despite the fact that all loans had been controlled
by the state, this did not proffer a privileged position in relation to Chile.
‘Harvey, working in partnership with North, occupied a special place in the
operations carried out during the war’ (according to Ramirez Necochea’s
account [Balmaceda y la contrarrevolución de 1891, p. 45]). To some extent at
least, British capital would favour Chiles acquisition of the deposits and then
decide what to do with Chile itself. Indeed: ‘John Thomas N orth had con
tributed a sum of 100,000 pounds sterling [to the anti-Balmacedists]’ (ibid.,
p. 192). A British trading company, one of whose centres was the Gibbs house,
maintained that a Chilean victory could be beneficial in the long term because
this republic was the m ost efficient and energetic of the South American
Pacific. (Basadre, Historia de la república del Perú, 1822-1933, VOL. 8, p. 30).
So it is not that the British decided the war in Chile’s favour but that they
immediately understood Chile would inevitably win.
120 The m om ent o f greatest receptivity was certainly 1952, when the MNR
rose to pow er despite the disapproval o f the United States. The lowest,
perhaps, with the immediate loss of that receptivity, was reached in 1956 when
Jackson Eder com m andeered the political life of the state.
THE STRUGGLE FOR THE SURPLUS # 69
which was the secret of Lima and then, long after, of Charcas. The
truth is that every nascent state is born in relation to another state
or paradigm or tendency. It must be something desirable, but not
remote. Such is the function of alterity for the state. One cannot
found oneself in relation to oneself. The other for Chile was always
Peru. Chile, a state constituted against the Indians, in spite of the
Indians, and excluding the Indians; Peru, a state built on the backs
of the Indians and therefore with a concupiscent tolerance for them;
Chile, a state fashioned out of a frugal surplus; Peru, the paragon of
a surplus without a state. Peru (which in this ideologeme includes
Potosí), the locus of vast natural resources, and Chile, endowed with
limited natural resources, at least for the period. All of this is, ulti
mately, illusory because time proved that the most important source
of natural wealth in Bolivia then was that which it lost.
Portales said that power in Chile is sustained by ‘the weight of
night’.*126 Herein lies the essence of the authoritarianism of the
Chilean state. If the people is awake, democracy is not possible.
Democracy is founded on the force of night, that is, the slumber of
the people. Here we have an early theorist of the social market state.
Authoritarianism, however, is only of consequence if it is converted
into power; without this, it is no more than a feeling. A state, in effect,
can only formulate policy within the sphere of its ideological or at
least its actual reach, as the actualization of something that exists as
a potentiality or virtuality in the administrative and repressive appa
ratus, because the state is itself plus the radius of its legitimacy or
authority. If it is true that to be is to choose oneself, as André Gide
once wrote, the production of policy has to do with the logic of ends
white men in Lima with ties to the Spanish families’ (quoted in Basadre, His
toria de la república del Perú 1822-1933, vol. 2, p. 149).
126 The full passage is richer: ‘The social order in Chile is maintained through
the weight of the night and because we have no keen, astute, and discerning
men; the general tendency of the masses towards repose is the guarantee of
public peace (letter from Portales to Joaquim Tocornal, 17 May 1832).
72 • REN£ ZAVALETA MERCADO
without which the state would respond only to the instinct of self-
preservation of the strongest. History would be a stupid, continuous
line in which the powerful always prevail. The capacity to imagine
or a kind of telos is what distinguishes man from spider because he
weaves towards a preconceived object.127 Hence we must infer the
conscious substantiality of the state, that is, if the state has no self-
consciousness or self-certainty, it is not a state but a factual conse
quence of the confrontations, hostilities and pacts between anomic
groups in civil society.128 If utopian action can respond to a future
determination (not effective in the present), certainly the optimum
requires a selection of possible objects and apposite means, that is,
the call to action must be something underlying or latent in the social
equation. Therefore, if the true production of politics is like the self-
determination of the subject, it is in fact also the expansion of the
social subject. This does not depend only on free will in the sense
that to be is to choose oneself, but to do so successfully. Why, then,
was Chile, that Chile, able to produce a state policy while Peru and
Bolivia achieved only its simulacra? Bolivia struggled just to remain
where it was. Surely it attempted a to produce a policy, but its 10 cents
per quintal of nitrate not only provoked the war but also led to its
condition of geographic inferiority.129 Peru, in turn, tried belatedly
avant (and succeeded): ‘The economic crisis that had reached its peak with
the declaration of the inconvertibility of banknotes in 1878 came to an unex
pected end with the War of the Pacific. And we say that it came to an unex
pected end because with the war the country came into possession o f vast
resources’ (Daniel Martner, cited in Jobet, Ensayo crítico del desarrollo
económico-social de Chile, p. 65). This is indisputable, for Chile conquered the
world’s only natural nitrate deposits. The direct prelude was, first, the Peruvian
stagnation of 1873 and the subsequent expropriation of the nitrate fields in
1878. ‘These events [the Peruvian crisis and expropriation] are those which
established for the Chilean capitalist class the need to conquer the nitrate fields
as a solution to the economic and financial crisis that was ruining the country’
(ibid., p. 64). According to Alberto Edwards, ‘without the War of the Pacific,
the Pinto government might well have ended in a revolution’ (cited in ibid.).
THE STRUGGLE FOR THE SURPLUS # 75
132 Gonzalez Prada said that ‘Chile was infected with the Peruvian malady.’
This seems to be corroborated by the following facts: ‘the nitrate region was
transform ed into a British factory. Through it and through the supremacy
that the British had achieved in the economic life of the country prior to the
War of the Pacific, Chiles total subordination to British imperialism was
secured’ (Ramirez Necochea, Historia del imperialismo en Chile, p. 103).
‘A round 1890, the British dominated the main towns of the north, especially
those of Tarapaca, exercising an unchecked influence in that province’ (ibid.,
p. 102). Note that it is a date very close to the end of the war.
The national subordination of this same state that had been capable of
setting its own objectives was obvious, that is, the Chilean optimum had dete
riorated. ‘Valparaiso [ . . . ] with its trade entirely controlled by the British, its
market transactions conducted in pounds sterling, its English newspaper and
76 • RENÉ ZAVALETA MERCADO
to the point that we might say that the constitutive ideology often
cuts across several modes of production and historical periods. Yet
the omnipresence of this moment cannot mean the absolute hege
mony of the past or origin. Over the course of this study we will see
the role assigned not only to the principle of selection in history,
which is the foundation of anthropocentrism, but also to comple
mentary constitutive moments, to the flux of historical reform within
an originary movement.133
Chile, then, was blessed with a sharply delineated constitutive
moment, and one that included the whole of society and supplied the
extensive use of this language, was no more than a British colony’ (Ramirez
Necochea, Balmaceda y la contrarrevolución de 1891, p. 39).
Harvey himself declared to the Financial Times that a conversation of a
few minutes between the Chilean minister and a man with the capability of
Colonel North would be sufficient for the purpose’ (ibid., p. 55)
W hether such subordination was a general fact or not is still open to
question, but it did not exist to this extent prior to the Chilean victory. What
is indisputable is the contagion of the ‘Peruvian virus’ in the form of political
corruption: Gonzalo Bulnes, for example, ‘took advantage of his position as
governor of Trapacé to carry out major nitrate deals in the province that had
been entrusted to his governance’ (Resumen de la Guerra del Pacífico, p. 27).
An account in El Tarapacá (28 August 1886) makes clear that this had not
been common practice before: ‘This is the first time that a civil servant has
given up his post to devote himself to business affairs that had previously been
w ithin the domain of the state.’
Afterwards, this conflation of the positions of partner of the British or
o f the capitalists and civil servants would become increasingly frequent. This
reveals a growing erosion of the relative autonomy of the Chilean state that
would reach its peak when Jorge Alessandri, one of the Chilean millionaires,
became president, which already implies a complete abandonment of the con
ventions o f the Chilean oligarchy in the tradition of Portales. At the same time,
it is telling that a population that had increased between 1843 and 1865 at a
rate o f 2.35 p er cent would slow its growth rate to 1 per cent between 1865
and 1907—a not a result o f demographic modernization but of poverty.
133 See E rnst Bloch, Sujeto-Objeto: El pensamiento de Hegel (Mexico City:
FCE, 1949).
THE STRUGGLE FOR THE SURPLUS • 77
relatively valid for the Chiriguanos. Still, without facing the same danger of
exterm ination as the first Spanish colonies in Chile, for the inhabitants of
eastern Charcas, the consequences in terms of provocation o f the state were
less serious as a result of the support of Charcas and Lima, which was imme
diate, and because of the greater spatial dispersion or lower numerical
concentration of indigenous aggression.
139 Ibid., p. 21.
140 This is almost an established principle: the greater the state consciousness,
the less individualist consciousness there is in m ilitary resistance (because
this does not apply to the economic). ‘Where Indian resistance was scarce or
insufficient, the indigenous com m unity survives—arduously—to this day
(Romano and Tenenti, Los fundamentos del mundo moderno, p. 183). On the
other hand: ‘Its efficiency (that of the conquest] was greater in those territories
in which the indigenous masses, as a result of their greater social development,
had been subjected to a social and productive regime that compelled them to
render a surplus to the ruling caste’ (Jara, Guerra y sociedad en Chile, p. 19)
which, o f course, was not the case with Chile or with any frontier region.
THE STRUGGLE FOR THE SURPLUS * 79
Jara notes, on the other hand, the private character of the con
quest inherent to what was called the hueste indiana, a private enter
prise with a necessary seigneurial tendency at its core. In those
conditions it was clearly impossible for ‘the conquerors-turned-
encomenderos141 to successfully shoulder so heavy a burden over so
many years.’142
But it was not just an offensive failure; what was at stake was the
very survival of the new community, now undeniably besieged. The
rebellion that began in 1598 destroyed the seven existing cities and
the whole of the south was recovered by the Indians. We must ask
what role such a brutal, imminent, and global threat plays, for the
Araucanian objective was clear: the Spaniards, ‘subjects and slaves,
obeying the Indians as their lords, and the Indians, ruling like mas
ters and proprietors.’143 The answer to this is the emergence of the
state whose point of origin is the army: ‘Then, and only when the
abyss was opening, a state army paid for entirely with public funds
as had long been the norm in Europe was created.’144
In what did this opening of the abyss consist? In a willingness to
accept whatever was necessary for the survival of that which was
threatened, that is, of that society that even if in the most embryonic
way nonetheless possessed the elements of its initial recognition. On
the other hand, the claim that war forced the substitution of the pri
vate nature of the hueste indiana by the national and state army car
ries important implications. The seigneurial privileging of the private
sphere gives way here to the requirements of a national form of
repression, because in absolutism the state precedes the nation.
We find in these passages, cursory as they are, traces of the
Chilean optimum. We can say then that a general war organized the
components of Chiles constitutive crisis. The frontier army becomes
the foundation of the future Chilean state, a fact that is significant in
itself.145The nucleus of a society’s constitutive determination defines
things and distinguishes them from one another. An originary inter-
subjective act constituted by agriculture or the logic of the councils,
for example, is not the same thing as one constituted by a military
imperative to rule and obey because the price of not doing so is anni
hilation. Men do not change their habits without good reason and
those men (those of the hueste indiana) who had come to be their
own masters in the seigneurial utopia of the time would not have
accepted the implacable and precocious logic of the regular army if
not for an urgency that prevailed over any kind of belief. This is the
145 W hich means that the constitutive act is war, and, therefore, in the core
ideological discourse, it would refer in the future to the logic of war. Hence,
it makes a difference whether the constitutive act is a charismatic or messianic
moment, if it is an act of submission or negative war, or an act of victory, active
war, or war directed outwards. Moreover, the m ode of the ‘frontier arm y’,
which is a consequence of the frontier mentality, in turn organizes its own
economy: ‘A far-from-trivial market for the consumption of the products of
the creole economy, since the last quarter of the sixteenth century and espe
cially as o f 1600, was constituted by the frontier army’ (ibid., p. 37). In other
words, the state is born of its repressive apparatus or army; the army exists
outw ardly and not inwardly; and, finally, the economy is produced by the
state.
THE STRUGGLE FOR THE SURPLUS • 81
151 Challenge and response, used in this sense of the induction of a constitu
tive act, are Arnold Toynbees terms. However, Tamayo employs the same con
cept in 1910: ‘Is a rich and fertile environm ent better for man, for a race?
Perhaps not, because the ease of such an existence would hardly stimulate and
develop mans (or a races) activity and strength. A hard and barren environ
ment would then be preferable, because then man would be forced to exert
himself, and his greater effort would impel his historical progress’ (Creadon
de la pedagogía nacional, chap . 53).
152 Murra, Formaciones económicas y politicos; Emilio Choy Ma, Antropología
e historia (Anthropology and History) (Lima: UNMSM, 1979).
153 See note 140.
154 This is Stalin’s concept: ‘A nation is not merely a historical category
but a historical category belonging to a definite epoch, the epoch of rising
capitalism’ (Joseph Stalin, Marxism and the National Question: Selected
Writings and Speeches [New York: International Publishers, 1942].)
84 • RENÉ ZAVALETA MERCADO
155 ‘Peru today is a coastal formation (José Carlos Mariátegui, Siete ensayos
de interpretación de la realidad peruana [Lima: Amauta, 1975(1928)], p. 205;
available in English as: Seven Interpretative Essays on Peruvian Reality
[Marjory Urquidi trans.] [Austin: University of Texas Press, 1971]).
156 The transform ation of the spirit of the state into social potentiality is an
unduly neglected aspect of most analyses of the so-called Hegelian-M arxist
theories of the state (see David Gold, Clarence Y. H. Lo and Erik Olin Wright,
‘Recientes desarrollos en la teoría marxista del Estado capitalista in Heinz
Rudolf Sonntag and Héctor Vallecilos [eds], El Estado en el capitalismo con
temporáneo [Mexico City: Siglo XXI, 1977], pp. 23-61).
157 It is indeed still to be seen whether the Peruvian axis of nationalization
will be Lima and its ideology, which is viceregalism, or a contingent democratic
interpellation with an necessarily indigenous connotation. ‘Peru,’ Mariátegui
wrote, ‘must choose either the gamonal or the Indian (Siete ensayos, p. 194).
¡
158 The mita, for example, was used in mining—a non-capitalist form was
carried over to a commercial form of exploitation. Yanaconaje was the recu
peration of a pre-existing form, etc.
159 This is what the creole was called in its courtier version. From perra
[whore (literally, bitch)] and chola [half-breed; educated or assimilated Indian
woman]: the Peruvian lover of a viceroy, Amat, was called Perricholi.
160 Basadre, cited in Yepes del Castillo, Perú 1820-1920, p. 38.
161 Murra, Formaciones económicas y políticas.
.
86 • RENÉ ZAVALETA MERCADO
165 This expression, more felicitous as such than as a concept, belongs to the
historian Pablo Macera.
166 There is a subtle shift even within the seigneurial articulation itself.
Its axis becomes strictly Hispanic. Previously, ‘if an Indian was of noble caste
( . . . ) then his nobility was as valid as a Spaniards and he neither paid tribute
nor was required to fulfil the duties of the mita, and was eligible to occupy
adm inistrative and military positions’ (Jan Szeminski, ‘La insurrección de
Tupac Am aru II: ¿Guerra de independencia o revolución?’, Estudios Lati
noamericanos 2 [1974]: 9-40). After Amaru, an organized annihilation of the
traditions of the Inca state and a forced hispanicization were carried out, and
the creoles understood that without the support of the Spaniards they were
in no condition to maintain their situation. [ . . . ] Above all, they had to trans
form their culture and renounce all family, cultural, and other ties with indige
nous society’ (ibid.). Finally, there was even an attempt to eliminate the
Quechua language in what was like an inversion of Apaza’s programme which
had prohibited the use of Spanish. This is [José Antonio de] Areche’s ideolog
ical legacy.
167 John H. Rowe speaks of ‘the tradition of using the indigenous nobility
for the execution of administrative orders’ (‘El movimiento nacional inca del
siglo XVIII’ in Alberto Flores Galindo (ed.), Sociedad colonial y sublevaciones
$$ • RENE Z AVALETA MERCADO
'Making one body of Indians and creole Spaniards, doing away with
the Europeans, who were to be killed making no distinction of per
sons, class or age, because the government had to be wholly sloughed
oft?168 It is now clear beyond all doubt that Amaru was referring to
the entire people and not only to the Indians: ‘Documents from the
time of the campaign reveal that José Gabriel Amaru expected the
support of powerful groups in Cuzco.’169 This, then, was an Incan
interpellation of the whole society, a call for unification within cer
tain models of legitimacy and not outside of them. In a way, this is
akin to Bolivars programme and that of the great majority of those
who fought after independence, but inverted, because here the inter-
pellative nucleus was constituted by the indigenous.
With Amaru, on the other hand, there is a political articulation
of the Andean spatial system, now embodied in the consequences of
the Potosí market. As the owner of a transport company that served
that market, this space was Amaru’s only possible frame of reference.
In reality the uprising was centred on the Potosí region; it could be
said that where this region ended, the influence of [José Antonio de]
Areche, that is, of Lima, began. This also explains the fact that the
abolition of the m ita and the right of Indians to occupy government
posts, indeed the emancipation of black slaves, figure among the first
points of his programme.170
populares: Tupac Am aru II, 1780 [Lima: Retablo de Papel, 1976], pp. 11-66;
here, p. 15). It is true, moreover, that Condorcanqui filed a legal claim that
took four years for his direct descent from the Inca lineage to be recognized.
He would not have sought such recognition within the Spanish juridical sys
tem had he already had the intention of abolishing it.
168 Dám aso Katari, one o f the leaders of the Chayanta rebellion (Boleslao
Lewin, La rebelión de Tupac Am aru [Buenos Aires: Hachette, 1943], p. 282).
169 ‘But at the same time the m ovement became too powerful for the middle
and upper classes, which up until then had been their potential allies’ (Corn-
blit, ‘Levantamientos de masas en Perú y Bolivia, pp. 112-13).
170 The points o f the program m e were: (1) the appointm ent of Indians
to adm inistrative positions; (2) the right to travel to Spain w ithout prior
THE STRUGGLE FOR THE SURPLUS # 89
permission from the local authorities; (3) access to ecclesiastic ranks; (4) more
education for the Indians; (5) the abolition of the Potosí mita; (6) the abolition
of the reparto de efectos [forced distribution of goods] (Rowe, ‘El movimiento
nacional inca del siglo XVI11’, p. 35). O f these points, at least the first four are
oriented towards the integration of the Indians within the system, that is, its
democratization and not its abolition. As for the last two, the abolition of the
mita implied a defence of the community because the mita had produced the
forasteros. The sixth point refers to the resistance to forced commercialization.
171 The leaders of the rebellion in O ruro were Spaniards (the Rodriguez
brothers), and Tomás Katari had named a Spaniard governor of Tupiza.
172 Indigenous aristocrats such as Pum acahua and Coquehuanca fought
against Amaru (Cornblit, ‘Levantamientos de masas en Perú y Bolivia).
173 According to Segurólas diary written during the siege (ibid.).
90 • RENÉ ZAVALETA MERCADO
177 In the Althusserian sense: ‘All ideology hails or interpellates concrete indi
viduals as concrete subjects’ and “transform s’ individuals into subjects (it
transforms them all) by that very precise operation which I have called inter
pellation or hailing’ (Althusser, ‘Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses’,
P- 173).
178 Szeminski, ‘La insurrección de Tupac Amaru II’.
92 • RENÉ ZAVALETA MERCADO
179 Rowe, ‘El movimiento nacional inca del siglo XVIIf, p. 53.
180 Bolívar himself, who had said that ‘these Peruvians are the most miserable
m en for w ar’ (21 December 1825) and that he would not mince words on
Lima—‘Crim inal Babylon, ‘they see us as the usurpers of Peru’, ‘a country
cursed with a moral plague’—would nonetheless admit of the Indian soldiers
of the Spanish forces: ‘The excellence of the Spanish army in Peru in marching
w ithout losing strength. The loyalist soldiers walk fifteen or twenty leagues a
day, and they carry their food in a little coca pouch and in another of barley
or cooked or toasted maize (10 February 1824).
181 The m yths about the border have always been very crude. Mitre, for
example, believed that Argentina extended up to where a certain kind o f man
resided. This was not so. The separatist movements in Salta or the Confeder
ation are not born o f presumed racial identities nor, of course, of Santa Cruzs
head. The sphere o f the m arket that had been centred on Potosí made things
seem to be in their natural place.
THE STRUGGLE FOR THE SURPLUS * 93
182 A culture of fear of the Indians emerged after Amaru but this fear had
existed previously: ‘It had been revealed [to a priest] under the seal of confes
sion that the plan was to attack the Palace and take out the guards at midnight,
take the armoury and kill Your Majesty’s ministers and principal persons and
rise with the city, as the capital of the kingdom; the Indian conspirators
demanded the restoration of an ancient empire (Report to the viceroy Manso
de Velasco, cited in Rowe, ‘El movimiento nacional inca del siglo XVIII’ p. 50).
183 But this was not, as we have seen, the only thing he said about
Peru. [Simon Bolívar, El Libertador. Writings of Simon Bolivar (Frederick H.
Fornoff trans.) (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), p. 27. In Zavaleta’s
manuscript, Bolivar’s famous phrase is condensed to ‘Peru, gold and slaves.’]
O* • RENE ZAVALETA MERCADO
184 Tulio Halperín Donghi, Revolución y guerra: Formación de una élite diri
gente en la Argentina criolla (Mexico City: Siglo XXI, 1972), p. 79.
185 Although it was extensive. We will return to this in the following chapters,
especially in reference to the formation of the working class. In our view, the
strong mitima roots of the pre-Columbian population, the forasteros of
Amarus time, the ccajchas and obrajes played a major part in the construction
of the tenets of the proletariat.
186 ‘Gamonalism, within the central and unitary republic, is the ally and agent
of the capital in the regions and provinces (Mariátegui, Siete ensayos, p. 202).
Indeed, it would be absurd to reduce the role of gamonalism to one of frag
mentation. It was a backward kind of mediation and the gamonal, in a way,
was a mediator and functionary of the state. In reality, gamonalism as such
was an extra-economic form of extraction of a surplus. Alberto Flores Galindo
suggests that we might speak, as Fontana did, of an aggregate of isolated rural
cells’.
THE STRUGGLE FOR THE SURPLUS • 95
in the modern sense but also regressed with respect to their previous
condition. ‘The new independent state was incapable of imposing its
hegemony at the level of the entire territory called Peru.’187
Gamonal mediation, like any other mediation, has no intrinsic
value. It is the same as the corporation or the union, which can suc
cessively become apparatuses of the state, organs of mediation or
counterhegemonic structures.188 Mutatis mutandis, the traditional
figure of the gamonal might have been a divisive element in Peru—
in fact, it had not only fostered anarchy but was also the backward
form of centrality of an extremely weak social equation. Once Limas
centrality—based on the colonial pact—was broken, the Peruvian
provinces acquired conditions of increased contact with the emerging
world market compared to the scattered Bolivian provinces, which
had no such contact at all. In a process that bears some resemblance
to that of Central America, each region could communicate auto
nomously with the world and only inefficiently with its own
presumed centre.189 Given the ancestral weakness of the state in
Charcas,190 if the same condition of autonomous geographic access
had existed, perhaps the country itself would have fallen apart. In a
way, the habits of bureaucratic centralization, to which must be
added the further effect of the surplus, saved the unity of Peru
through hereditary rule. But the gamonal component had to be
added to the bureaucratic and seigneurial lustre of the general ide
ology, while in Bolivia the long stalemate between caudillism and the
masses in action permitted only a feeble reconstruction of the
seigneurial, which had nearly lost its will to live.191 In any case, the
shift from a centralized power structure to a country of gamonales
revealed the emergence of the centrifugal form that the state contract
had assumed in Peru—a bankrupt form, utterly impotent before the
challenges it faced. If this did not happen in Bolivia it is because the
gamonales were themselves weak in their own impoverished and
autarkic regions, reduced to mere subsistence, with no capacity for
connection to the world. The society itself, moreover, had gotten
used to living in its traditional stalemate. It is the Peruvian gamonal
form that explains the disunity expressed in the country’s three gov
ernments at the time of the war (because, in contrast to Chile, which
had adopted forms of rational legitimation in the constitution of
power with Portales, here there were no such forms at all), its non
transformation into a national war except when the fighting had
reached the very heart of the country, even the flight of its president
in at the height of the conflict.192 By this we mean only to say that if
Peru and Bolivia had had something even remotely comparable to
Chiles social optimum, that is, a fluid relation between the state and
society, they would have prevailed on Peruvian territory, even if Chile
had a certain superiority in terms of its gross product.193 To cite a
191 Adolfo Ballivián, in his style and person, is an example of a kind of deca
dence that overtook the traditional aristocracy in Bolivia. José María Linares
is really no less representative of this.
192 Basadre, Historia de la república del Perú, v o l . 8; Heraclio Bonilla, Un
siglo a la deriva: Ensayos sobre el Perú, Bolivia y la guerra (Lima: Instituto de
Estudios Peruanos, 1980).
193 Economic arguments about military matters are one thing; military
arguments about the economy, another. The Chilean ‘military investment
was superior in tactical and strategic terms. This was well thought out by the
political leadership. Still, the merit of this campaign lay in its low cost relative
to the scale of its success. To achieve this, in conditions of any degree of nor
mality or equilibrium, an overwhelming economic superiority would be
required. It was the existence or semi-existence at the level of the state of the
Peruvian and Bolivian societies that made the war into a kind of target practice.
THE STRUGGLE FOR THE SURPLUS • 97
5 Mitre, Los patriarcas de la plata, pp. 56-7. References in the passage are to:
José María Dalence, Bosquejo estadístico de Bolivia (Chuquisaca: Ymprenta
108 # RENÉ ZAVALETA MERCADO
de Sucre, 1851); José Fellman Velarde, Historia de Bolivia, tomo II: La Boli-
vianidad semifeudal (La Paz: Los Amigos del Libro, 1970).
6 Hernando Sanabria Fernández, ‘Preámbulo’ in Moreno, La Audiencia de
Charcas, p. 9.
7 Mendoza, El macizo boliviano.
THE WORLD OF THE FEARSOME WILLKA • 109
that can be culled from the works of Murra, Choy and Condarco. This
theory of the sterility of the non-Spanish inheritance is connected in
its more or less Darwinist sense to Arguedas’ theses, which, in essence,
are nothing but those of José Antonio de Areche. In any case, if Bolivia
is a thought, it is no doubt as a result of a certain prolonged coexis
tence of contradictory conceptions of its own formation.
The problem here lies in determining to what point it is legiti
mate to conduct a genetico-structural analysis of an existing forma
tion; in other words, if it is true that the domestication of the potato,
for example, in the way that Marx speaks of those formations whose
base is constituted by communal property now dissolved, has some
thing to do with Bolivia’s present. It must be said here not only that
the communal forms have not been dissolved by the (hypothetical)
nucleus of irradiation, but also that, even to the extent that this has
occurred, which is slight, they could not be dissolved without the
nucleus that irradiates or suppresses preserving a certain residue or
partial determination by the very thing that it irradiates or sup
presses. Of course we cannot dismiss the problem posed by Sanabria,
which is the question of the plausibility of the juridical origins of the
formation, with the stroke of a pen. We could say that the organiza
tion of the highest spheres of the juridico-political system in fact
comes from the Audiencia of Charcas, but this means only that it
was the superstructure of the Potosí market; the Potosí market in
turn was a particular form of mercantilization that surely had to
adapt to the principles of the primordial formation, which is that
which the Spaniards encountered at the time of conquest. If the point
of departure is defined in so voluntarist a way, that is, if it refers to
the current Bolivian nation-state, it could just as well be said that its
project is unfinished as that it began with independence as the
juridico-official moment of its existence. Its obvious that for the pur
poses of a social history like that which we propose to write, ‘Bolivia’
itself is but a moment in a much longer progression.
110 # RENÉ ZAVALETA MERCADO
15 Witold Kula, Teoría económica del sistema feudal (México City: Siglo XXI,
1979), cited in Juan Carlos Garavaglia, ‘Un modo de producción subsidiario:
la organización económica de las comunidades guaranizadas durante los sig
los XVII-XVIII en la formación regional altoperuana-rioplatense in Carlos
Sempat Assadourian, Ciro Flamarión S. Cardoso, Horacio Ciafardini, Juan
Carlos Garavaglia and Ernesto Laclau, Modos de producción en América Latina
(Buenos Aires: Siglo XXI, 1973), pp. 161-92.
16 Silvia Rivera Cusicanqui, ‘La expansión del latifundio en el Altiplano
boliviano: Elementos para la caracterización de una oligarquía regional,
Allpanchis: Revista de Pastoral Andina 13 (1979): 189—218; here, p. 196.
THE WORLD OF THE FEARSOME WILLKA • 115
Of this there is doubt: the only stable business in Bolivia was the
Indians. We should add that this caste’s only innate and unrenounce-
able belief has always been the conviction of its superiority over the
Indians, a non-negotiable belief, with or without liberalism, with or
without Marxism.
The precapitalist trap, moreover, was only comparable to the
social siege laid by the Indians. Consequently, the surplus from the
small hacienda and from trade, especially that of luxury goods, was
the basic source of the capital’ of men like Aramayo or Arce. In any
case, as Genovese said, ‘the road to power lay through the plantation’.19
Even in the mines, the workers were paid as far as possible in
kind, that is, in products that often came from their employers’ lands.
And this was not the only precapitalist or protocapitalist aspect. The
ccajchas, for example, functioned in a way that resembles what has
been called the putting-out system. They were own-account (petty-
bourgeois) workers commercially subordinated to capital but with
no productive relation to it, in the sense that they did not work under
its command. The ‘voluntary mita or doblada are certainly not cap
italist forms of exploitation or recruitment. It is reasonable to main
tain that, from the very moment the Spaniards set foot on these
lands, the most consistent precapitalist element is the theft of labour
power. All the phases of capitalism to this day have been based on
this logic of appropriation and this translates, naturally, into demo
graphic indices.
In any case, ‘inclinations’ or great existential choices prove most
eloquent when it comes to the miners’ vision of the world, granted
only as the upper echelon of the dominant bloc. Theirs were not
bourgeois sentiments. They are related, on the one hand, to the
almost obsessive association with foreign capital (Chilean or British
or French), and, on the other, to investment in land. The two great
phases of originary accumulation in Bolivia (the silver and tin sur
pluses), then, involve at once the insertion of Bolivian capitalism in
20 Ibid., p. 18.
118 • RENÉ ZAVALETA MERCADO
21 Guillermo Lora, Historia del movimiento obrero boliviano, VOL. 1 (La Paz:
Los Amigos del Libro, 1967), p. 80.
THE WORLD OF THE FEARSOME WILLKA • 119
were conservative acts of desperate masses and it’s true that their vic
tory would have led to a wretched fate, but this does not make their
enemies right.
We have, on the other hand, what we might call the unconscious
tasks of history. As we shall see when we review the conditions of the
formation of the modern multitude in the twentieth century, this,
the multitude, does not exist in itself but in the form of its determi
nation. In general, it is said that the crisis of the state and, above all,
its hegemonic fraying is the aperture through which the constitution
of the multitude emerges. Belzu, like Katari, interpellated the masses.
Its true that the Bolivian masses have a tumultuous and violent char
acter, like Katari; they would thereafter be belcistas in a paradigmatic
way, with their cult of spontaneity and the notion that the movement
creates itself. In any case, for whatever reason, the introduction of
the masses into history precipitated by Belzu (although not only by
him) is what gives the period its true dimensions because it is part
of the acquisition of a temperament.
Belzu, therefore, like Amaru and Katari, was the bearer of a pro
gressive rallying flag in an objective sense. This does not require even
that the objective tasks coincide with a consciousness of them. The
artisans, for example, were an objectively more advanced force than
other sectors of Bolivian society at the time. Like the forasteros of the
countryside, they exhibited different levels of a state o f separation.
There is an important distinction to be made here. The forastero is
literally detached from his traditional connection to the land; his
condition in agriculture itself is already the condition of a man who
has broken his ancestral ties because he is either in a land that is not
his or that is his without imposing upon it the general paraphernalia
of ideologemes that come with ancestral belonging. The artisan,
meanwhile, is an individual and, if he has not been separated from
his means of production, he benefits from the relative concentration
of the city; he is an urban, or concentrated, individual. Forasteros,
ccajchasy belcista artisans are part of the social legacy out of which
the proletariat would later emerge.
122 • REN£ ZAVALETA MERCADO
that was the weak currency, a false solution which was nonetheless
the only one possible, and had no chance of coming to power until
it intersected with the division, through Belzu, of the repressive appa
ratus that was then the whole state or almost the whole state. Imme
diate violence was in reality the only manifestation of the force of
that state that had not managed to solve its most basic problems.
We have, on the other hand, the seigneurial party organized
around the general principle of free trade. It consists of landowners
who in their origins belong to either the core of the seigneurial or to
its fringe, who accumulate wealth by way of commercial capital,
through which they are linked to the dynamic zones of British influ
ence, Chile in particular, that had developed within the logic of the
replacement of an economy of state monopolies and interior centres
by one of ports, which signals the passage from colony to indepen
dence, especially following the Peace of Utrecht. It would perhaps be
useful to add some remarks here on the seigneurial as nucleus, and
its fringe or periphery. No ruling class or caste exists in isolation; it
must have a kind of‘reserve army’ or area of irradiation surrounding
it. If it has been said that the ideas of the ruling class are ‘in every age
the ruling ideas’, it is because, whatever their degree of latent legiti
macy, their hegemonic reach or seductive capacity as a discourse
must at least reach the area called the effective majority’ within the
sphere of the state, that is, the decisive areas in terms of social control.
It is the sector of oligarchic reinforcement. This is what explains the
easy relations between Melgarejo and Adolfo Balliviân or between
poor hidalgos like Arce and Pacheco and the Aramayos—that is,
from a long-term perspective, the oligarchy is the nucleus that emits
the seigneurial interpellative call along with all those who believe in
it and, above all, its margin of recruitment or reserve. It is important
to take into account here the draw of upward mobility via politics or
economic accumulation. Neither Montes nor Barrientos belonged to
the seigneurial elite but only to its area of credibility or co-optation,
which cannot include truly popular men. It is a sector equivalent to
what Genovese calls that of the ‘poor whites*.
THE WORLD OF THE FEARSOME WILLKA • 125
To sum up: to say that the people contains the nation or is the nation
itself is true only in the sense that if the nation does not include the
whole people it is not truly national. To be a nation is to recognize
all as the same, in some measure and in a particular habitat. This,
however, would be a romantic version of nationalization, which is
often a far more imperative and authoritarian event. It would seem
logical to posit a process in which men act together to produce some
thing common to all but not specifically corresponding to any of
them. This is what best approximates the democratic revolution
understood as a national revolution. It is a somewhat chimerical idea.
In reality, nationalization has occurred through passive revolution,
by the junker path, and of course there have been reactionary or
THE WORLD OF THE FEARSOME WILLKA * 127
Such are the outlines of what can properly be called the battle of the
two bloodlines or lineages in Bolivia. It is a theme that pervades not
only this study but, of course, also the history itself that is its object.
Every society, in fact—we saw this in the case of Chile—has a col
lection o f‘invisible beliefs’ or, as it were, a religion that binds it (reli-
gatio) in Durkheims sense of this concept. The production of the
social substance or general equivalence conceived as something that
34 Romano and Tenenti, Los fundamentos del mundo moderno, pp. 185-6.
35 G. W. F. Hegel, Phenomenology o f Spirit (A. V. Miller trans.) (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1977), p. 117 (§193).
THE WORLD OF THE FEARSOME WILLKA • 137
‘[T]he lord [ . . . ] is the power over this thing, for he proved in the
struggle that it is something merely negative.’36
The slave is also the foundation of the ‘idealism’ of the master
because he, the master, is in a paradigmatic way the non-witness of
material transformation; on the contrary, he is the man who does
not touch the earth. So: ‘The lord relates himself mediately to the
thing through the bondsman.’37
This is, therefore, exactly the opposite of the command of capital
and the decline of the bourgeoisie begins when it abandons this func
tion of productive leadership and is depersonalized in relation to
capital. This aspect is perhaps the most revealing of the conduct of
the seigneurial caste in relation to the fundamental productive act
of this society, which has always been agriculture. It is a sector that
does not participate except in the appropriation of the surplus, that
is, in the beginning of circulation, and, as a class that is in essence
circulationist, its power derives from the repressive and monopolistic
control of the market.
On the other hand, the slave or serf in a state of territorial frag
mentation (although the very idea of the community raises doubts
about this) is no more apt as a witness to the transformation of nature
because he has access only to a magical or at least intuitive and pre-
rational experience; but at least in him the possibility of acquiring
that rationality exists since he is in close contact with the process of
transformation. The master, meanwhile, is external to it in practice,
is materially alien to the transformation of nature and, in his view,
the slave becomes the part of his being (of his body) that is in contact
with the thing. He sees, therefore, through the mediation of another.
In a somewhat crude understanding of the problem, the
seigneurial is identified (with the certainty common to all popular
conceptions) with the traditional ruling class, even over the course
of its mutations and successions, and in this sense the total lord, that
is, lordship across time, resembles the total capitalist. This identifi
cation is beyond doubt in that, in the conjunction of representation
and the repressive act, ‘fear of the lord is [ . . . ] the beginning of wis
dom’38 and, ultimately, the conception of the world is universalized
until the slave effectively sees himself with the eyes of the master. If
hegemony arises with a class that considers itself capable of assimi
lating the whole of society’,39 then this is a kind of hegemony.
In other words, the seigneurial articulation is that which is based
on an originary hierarchical pact, which can be factual or contrac
tual, that is, it is not founded on equality but on an essential inequal
ity among men. This is at once a mechanism for the construction of
consent because it constitutes a graduated hierarchical structure.
This means that there is always someone lower in rank (which can
be based on economic or racial criteria, or on lineage or even region).
The fact that no one is ever last and all are hijos de algo40 legitimates
the entire conceptual scale.
That the logic of the master becomes that of the slave is aptly
demonstrated in Memorial de los Charcas: ‘Now in this general visi
tation that has been made by order of Don Franscisco of Toledo,
viceroy of these lands, we have been stripped of the authority and
lordship that we had over our subjects and vassals as though we were
not natural lords just as the dukes and counts and marquis are in
Spain, which we consider a great affront and injury.’41
Their desire, then, was to be assimilated into the Spanish power
structure and not for an instant the abolition of servitude, but the
return of their own Indian vassals [yanaconas]: ‘They have stolen all
the yanaconas we had by making them tributary Indians.’42
43 [On Gabriel René Moreno, see, for example, Carlos Medinaceli, Estudios
críticos (Sucre: Editorial Charcas, 1938), pp. 16-18.1
THE WORLD OF THE FEARSOME WILLKA • 143
44 [Literally, a screw thread. A local term for the political and economic elite
during the period of the tin barons.]
144 # RENÉ ZAVALETA MERCADO
45 [‘Santiago and close ranks, Spain, a famous battle cry o f the Reconquista.]
46 [An epithet for Salamanca (El Hombre Símbolo).]
THE WORLD OF THE FEARSOME WILLKA • 145
51 Ibid., p. 44.
THE WORLD OF THE FEARSOME WILLKA # 153
52 Ibid., p. 276.
154 • RENÉ ZAVALETA MERCADO
over the Indian and his traditional and personal right to power. The
Willka idea of power, in contrast, refers to a transpersonal assump
tion of command; the impersonality of power is what guarantees its
perpetuity. The caudillos assume the position of Willka, that is, of
leadership, and incorporate the title into their being; the family is the
ayllu and the country is the final expansion of the ayllu.
There is, in fact, a first Willka, one who resisted Melgarejos bar
baric decree against the communities in 1866. This Willkas mother,
a ‘revered and stately’ nonagenarian, was savagely murdered by
Leonardo Antezana, Melgarejo’s cousin. It was also a Willka who led
that infernal pursuit of the Melgarejists, charging across the wilder
ness towards Peru. In the Federal Revolution itself, finally, there are
at least three successive Willkas, although there is no doubt that
Zárate is the Fearsome. The function of the title is similar to that of
Caesar and there is certainly very little of a ‘Western flavour to it. In
any case, if ever it has been possible to speak of historical memory,
here, where Zárate is born in the same town as Apaza and a third or
fourth Willka avenges the death of the first Willkas mother, where
the same area that is pillaged under the leadership of a Willka is capa
ble of responding with another Willka more than thirty years later,
there is no doubt that this constitutes a perfect example.
Willka is, moreover, the ‘representative of the ayllus subject to
his authority’,53 like Zapata of Anenecuilco. How official this was,
among Indians no doubt little inclined to legalistic disputes with
written documents, is something that must be confirmed by further
research. In any case, it is significant that they went to war ‘with their
own system of authorities’,54 which tells us that just as we maintain
that the productive patterns of Andean agriculture were unchanged
by the juridical form of appropriation of the surplus, we could go a
step further to say that the apparent state system (chief magistrate,
etc.) coexists, as it were, with the real state system or the furtive,
53 Ibid., p. 95.
54 Ibid., p. 348.
THE WORLD OF THE FEARSOME WILLKA * 155
60 Ibid., p. 208-9.
61 Alfredo Jáuregui Rosquellas, La ciudad de los cuatro nombres, cronicario
histórico (Sucre: Imprenta La Glorieta, 1924), p. 302. Cited in Condarco
Morales, Zarate, el temible Willka, p. 208-9.
i
r
• RENÉ ZAVALETA MERCADO
The foundation of all this was a mastery of the terrain that trans
lated into a military advantage. Thus, to say that a great number of
Indians stretched out in a chain along the Andean routes and
guarded the main roads’62 reveals the strategic use of a constant
presence or continuous struggle because there could be Paceño or
Chuquisacan whites in one place or another, but there could never
not be Aymara Indians. This produced a sense of insecurity and
uncertainty in the former and a sense of perseverance in the Indian
combatants. The peasant transformed his weakness—his dispersion
—into a perpetual erosion of all others forces.
The endless siege of contiguity in space and time, identification
through noise, that is, the calls of the blowing horn and japapeos
(oqueos), and a symbolic presence in the elements: ‘The dense clouds
of dust kicked up by the Indian hordes’.63 Thus it was not entirely true
that ‘the only arms used by the Indians were slings [huarakas], clubs
[macanas], pikes and no more than one gun for every 20 men’.64
The application of these tactics produced a situation of general
war that involved the entire population and all the resources offered
by the environment. Such a total mobilization (which nonetheless
would have its own internal contradictions) has three necessary con
ditions: first, the existence of an identity that is not just communal
[comunaria] but ethnic in its millenarian expression; second, there
must be a plan, and this means also recognized leadership and orga
nized masses; third, the war must continuously expand because its
prolongation in the previous terms would make it into regular war,
which is the terrain of the karas.65
The basis of this insurrection, like that of any other, because this
is something like a law of the revolutionary event, is the effective and
66 Ibid., p. 325.
67 Napoleón Fernández Antezana, La hecatombe de Mohoza (La Paz:
Tipografía de La Unión, 1905), p. 26. Also cited in Condarco Morales, Zárate,
el temible Willka, p. 172.
160 • RENÉ ZAVALETA MERCADO
68 Rodolfo Soria Galvarro, Los últimos días del gobierno Alonso: Reportage
para la historia (Valparaíso: Universo de Gmo. Helfmann, 1899), p. 72.
69 Jáuregui Rosquellas, La ciudad de los cuatro nombres, p. 302. Cited in
Condarco Morales, Zarate, el temble Willka, p. 196.
70 Cited in Condarco Morales, Zárate, el temble Willka, p. 258.
THE WORLD OF THE FEARSOME WILLKA • 161
71 Ibid, p. 226.
72 Ibid., p. 138.
73 Cited in Sergio Almaraz, El podery la caidat p. 79.
162 • RENÉ ZAVALETA MERCADO
78 Ibid., p. 296.
79 Fernández Antezana, La hecatombe de Mohoza, p. 61.
80 Saavedra, ‘Proceso Mohoza’, p. 129.
164 • RENÉ ZAVALETA MERCADO
de jure and de facto capital, with the argument that although he was
a native of La Paz, he was a senator for Sucre. All of La Paz rose up
in support of Pando, even as they voted against his proposal. In sum:
he could not win the war without the Indians; he had to fight for the
lives of the Chuquisacans against the Indians themselves; he ordered
the death of the very man who was the symbol and instrument of his
victory; and, in the end, he died in Kenko at the hands of Paceño
whites perhaps because they suspected, even after Willkas death, that
he was an accomplice of the Indians. A strange fate for a man forever
adrift amid of the forces of history.
Let us see, then, what was contained within the millenarian
ideologeme of the patria india.
*
The history of Zarate and its premises bring us back to the beginning
of this excursus. The logic of reduction or sacrifice appears as a path
that must be followed before a central thought-concrete that is also,
within the logic of Marxism, a concrete appropriation or subordina
tion of the captured object, can be obtained. It seems that history,
which is something like the longue durée of politics, is the proof that
the object of appropriation exists as such. And yet it also seems that
this does not confer knowledge as the conscious organization of what
has been appropriated if that particular class of subjects or determi
nants of the era that are the concrete forms of totalization is not pro
duced. It’s true that the original picture of the system of production
and consumption as a circular process’81 or the formation of a com
mon foundation or even of the ‘historical foundation pose the ques
tion of what constitutes the effective nucleus of the interpellative call.
That is to say, of interpellation and totalization when these exist. It is
clear, therefore, that there can be no totalization without reduction
from above and from without to the intermittent and aleatory forms
of rule—by way of the pronouncements of the caudillos, barbaric or
not, who responded to fortuitous forms of determination that came
from a base that now had no surviving articulation between its parts
except the aura that remained from the habit of coexistence.
The caudillos are, however, only an expression of the gamonal-
ization of power, that is, the latifundium as the horizon of visibility
once the traditional spatial links of the Potosí market and even of the
crushing juridical authority of Charcas had been destroyed or weak
ened. A book like Últimos días coloniales en el Alto Perú [The Last
Days of the Colonial Era in Upper Peru] reveals the point to which
this, the colonial subcentres and subcultures, certainly not without
their own charms and provincial patriotism, contained second-hand
cultural and political frameworks of a closed, localist kind, like
Chuquisaca: ‘a ceremonious, contentious, and false court*,83 which
included the doctors, a class of that instinct no less rationalist than
idle, which always trained its members in colonial society to under
stand and consult and lead, and whose members on more than one
occasion had shown a proud esprit de corps’.84
The motley composition of the colonial, interrupted only by the
continual crises that surfaced with such terrifying force with Katari,
the Fifteen Days’ War, Belzu, and Willka, was therefore like an omen
of the inevitable splintering of a certain mutilated unification that
had lost its fetishistic and seductive power.
In politics in general, and even more so in what we might call
structural politics (as opposed to what is known as superstructural
politics), unresolved questions weigh so heavily that they impede the
functioning of the whole relation. The moveable capital was like a
symbol of this dissociation because it was obvious that it represented
a decision continually deferred. Later came what we might call the
second spatial question, with the lack of effective legitimacy in a
83 Ibid., p. 140.
84 Ibid., p. 297.
THE WORLD OF THE FEARSOME WILLKA * 167
Marx wrote that ‘The community itself appears as the First great force
of production.’85 The form of socialization or of the collective is
something that has always been of great importance and we have
always known that some forms are more effective than others, at least
in relation to certain ends. The problem of the optimum itself, which
we addressed in the previous chapter, in fact has to do with this. The
nation, for example, is a specific form of civil existence and associa
tion, but not every civil society is a nation. In principle, therefore,
this tells us only that there are homogeneous men who share a single
identity. In other words, it would seem to be a problem belonging to
the value sphere, as Weber would have it: the nation exists where men
feel themselves to be a nation. It is understandable, of course, that it
is thought logical that homogeneous men produce a unified political
will more readily or that the will of the state is expanded and fulfilled
more efficiently, more directly, in a civil society that receives it with
homogeneous forms, forms that respond in a similar way to the same
incitement. But things are surely more contradictory and compli
cated than this because what we might call the depth or density of
the constitution of a nation is of no small importance, nor is the cer
tainty or penetration of the state, because a state can have at its dis
posal forms that are very advanced but alien to its society, etc.
incorporated into the spirit of the masses, that is, the internal con
tours of society, all this surely indicates one level or another of devel
opment of the ‘productive force that is totalization. The sometimes
tragic force of classes and of the multitude but also of states and of
nations in our time is the manifestation of these profound social
events.
The problem, as is well known, is larger than all this. Nations, of
course, are the basis or the units of the world market, that is, the
mediations between globality and concrete labour. In a kind of dou
ble life, however, the world system is a rival to the constitution of
nation-states and at the same time the measure of its success depends
largely on the extent to which it is capable of being internalized
within nation-states, which means obstructing their identity or
sovereignty, and this is the catch. Every nation-state, on the other
hand, is the enemy of another nation-state; no rhetoric can change
this and in this regard no one looks out for anything but ones own
interests understood as something utterly non-negotiable. This
occurs to an extreme degree in the relations between the original
nation-states and the latecomers.
The ideal internalization of the core nation-state in the periphery
is clearly demonstrable: not for nothing do we speak of the national-
popular and, on the other hand, all the peripheral ruling classes are
unconditional partisans of the logic of the world market.
We can derive from the foregoing propositions certain limita
tions of the nation-state in the world today. It is certainly true that,
on the one hand, the privileged locus for the realization or honing of
certain productive forces like the free man and his correlate that is
impersonal power, formal subsumption as a precondition for the pri
macy of the ideological as the memory of punishment above actual
punishment or force or the repressive apparatus, is the nation-state.
On the other hand, real subsumption itself holds little interest for us
as something devised in Galileo’s tower but only insofar as it is con
verted, like equality, which is its premise, into a general intuition, and
THE WORLD OF THE FEARSOME WILLKA • 173
the way and end in frustration and which elements of the nation have
indeed been effectively achieved in Bolivia.
It is not unprofitable to refer to Stalins definition since, although
nobody speaks in these terms today, it is still the most succinct.94 For
example, with regard to the ‘stable community, historically consti
tuted’, what is meant here surely is that it is not simply a matter of a
racial community or of a tribal contract but refers instead to a ‘series
of significant chronological groupings’, as Pierre Vilar puts it. This is
true, but nobody can deny that the racial community (and even more
so the ethnic community) is a contributing element, favourable and
sometimes decisive in processes of nationalization. If it is an impre
cise and evaluative category, it nonetheless belongs to the order of
powerful and primary facts. It is not necessary to claim that this
category lacks effective significance in order to fight racism. Man’s
physical externalization surely constitutes a sign that cannot be
dismissed, although of course, perhaps as a result of its very
irrefutability, it produces only an apparent identity. The force of its
manifestation stands in stark contrast to the relativity of its content.
It’s true that a deep intersubjectivity is often founded on the
supremacy of identity over heterogeneity and this is a m anner of
approach like any other. It is good, moreover, that men insist on what
they are.
It is a fact, however, that is always preliminary and rudimentary
and peoples that locate the key to their community in this are nec
essarily primitive peoples or nonprimitive peoples that have reverted
to the primitive. Still, it is undeniable that in many cases (and this
proves that it is senseless to theorize the national independently of
historical context or particular cases) racial sympathy has constituted
a causal link in the process of national recognition. Moreover, there
is no doubt that the nature of the events incorporated determines
the national selection, and this is what we might call a constitutive
Its true, on the other hand, as Gramsci (who was Sardinian) said,
that a language is a conception of the world. Language is also, how
ever, a dynamic process. What we call a national language is ulti
mately nothing but the modus vivendi between the languages or
elements that take part in the process of nationalization or, as it were,
the linguistic terms in which the pact has been instituted and, in this
case (not for nothing does Gramsci himself say that ‘the new culture
[ . . . ] was born in dialect’95), they qualify the centralizing language
or the latter is imposed through a Darwinian process of selection,
that is, through the destruction of other languages. As conceptions
of the world, languages traverse and exceed their formalization. Thus
conceived, a language should contain the subjection, oppression and
expression of the thing and its opposites, that is to say, it is a discourse
on the world. In any case, it is not a neutral social fact. If discourse
is nothing but representation, it is nothing at all: it is assumed to
morphologically absorb the social fact and it is at the same time the
programme that a society lays out for itself. The indigenous or
African inflection of the different varieties of Spanish spoken in
Bolivia and in the rest of the Americas does not constitute a mere
deficit in relation to Golden Age Spanish. It is the form of appropri
ation of the language or the linguistic consequences of its insertion
in a new world.
The linguistic and interlinguistic elements in Bolivia serve as a
point of entry into this problematic. Not just because of the patently
Darwinian suppression of Puquina but also as a result of the tenacity
or persistence of Aymara, which is the linguistic equivalent in
its power of resistance of the communal form as conceived by
Grieshaber and others. In any case, Quechua, which is now seen by
many as an originary language, was in reality adopted as a result
of the introduction of mitima96colonies, that is, it was a cultural impo-
upon the individual. The level of consensus with which formal sub
sumption takes place of course gives a distinct connotation to each
constitutive pact. It is this generalized interaction that produces the
social or national substance that can also be called value and herein
lies the material base of the national in the capitalist mode of
production.
If we agree, then, that there are different economic lives in com
mon, we could say that on the contrary the existence of pre-market
forms of economic life in common is sometimes the most formidable
obstacle to a nationalization of the capitalist sort because it crystalizes
and preserves the precapitalist or noncapitalist nation.
In this regard, if horizontal integration is extremely important
(from the suppression of tariffs to the erection of a national market
infrastructure to the abolition of non-rational units of exchange, such
as womens currency, etc.), the aspect of vertical integration is even
more important because it relates to the democratic conceptualization
of society. Equality is unity, or at least there is no true unity except
among equals. Hence the mass base of self-determination: a people
made up of equal men tends naturally towards self-determination;
non-democratic self-determination, therefore, is founded in a mere
messianic impulse or depends on the whim of those who rule; it is
not a structural fact.
On the other hand, the composition of the total worker and of
the general capitalist cannot be external to elements like those we
have just described and are therefore results of the collective habits
originating in the market understood as universal interaction. This
is especially true with regard to the latter, the collective capitalist,
because the less private the retention of surplus value the more
national it is. In other words, its not enough for things to be national
in appearance or on the surface; the circulation of surplus value and
even the rate of the rotation of capital (because certainly the more it
circulates the more unified it is) speak to the qualitative implications
of unification. The state, ultimately, is nothing but the production of
THE WORLD OF THE FEARSOME WILLKA • 181
100 Carl Jung, Collected Works of C. G. Jung (Gerhard Adler ed., R. F. C. Hull
trans.) (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University, 1966), p. 2508.
THE WORLD OF THE FEARSOME WILLKA • 183
know what that meant; rather, they wasted whatever they could
snatch up of the accidental surplus in the augmentation of their
seigneurial symbols, land in particular. After Melgarejo and the farce
of free trade with the conservatives, they could not aspire, moreover,
to any kind of moral-political prestige, rural or urban.
CHAPTER THREE
Does what has been called ‘Darwins immanence mean that natural
selection was an inevitable myth or ideologeme of the circumstances
of originary accumulation? We could say, indeed, that this and its
extension to the social sciences that is social Darwinism, the claim
that ‘the supremacy of one people over another was the inevitable
outcome of the biological laws of the universe’,1were ideas too con
temporary with a certain specific process, which is nothing less than
the rise of the West. Darwin himself, to be sure, seems to have had
little to do with these particular opinions. They constitute, rather, a
certain reading of the so-called dismal science (that of Malthus) by
way of Spencer. An exegetic and facile reading, moreover, like every
thing that man wrote or thought. He founded a school of abhorrent
but powerful ideas.
But what doubt is there that the first element in man’s self
recognition (and recognition should mean to re-encounter oneself)
is his appearance, his material face, his mode of appearing before the
world, his existence as phenomenon? To be, certainly, is also to
appear. We must, however, distinguish between this ‘folk racism, a
popular system of prejudice’2 (because prejudices constitute the his
tory of the world) through which every group harbours an essential
mistrust and abhorrence of its neighbour (at least provisionally),
what can be called a universal and ancestral contempt among men,
who despise all that they do not know, that is, ‘folk racism’, and the
rather doctrinarian intent to systematize this as an interpretation of
the world. That such thinking is dangerous, like almost any other
used in this way, is abundantly clear. But it is equally clear that it is a
danger to which mans basic nature tends. The natural sciences them
selves are today imbued with and enveloped in these prejudices,
whence we can see that it is an ideologeme that runs right through
to the final flourishes in the construction of the scientific paradigms
themselves. It has always been a matter of proving pre-existing
prejudices.
In any case, it was Wallace, who had been the co-author of some
work by Darwin, who wrote: ‘In every generation the inferior would
inevitably be killed off and the superior would remain—that is, the
fittest would survive,’3 whence Spencer deduced the expression
‘survival of the fittest’. It was a creed destined for formidable success.
Its emergence, if we wish to contextualize it, must be located in the
process of universal subjectification (the constitution of subjects)
that derives from the ‘entitlement’ or birth of the state of separation
that is from the beginning simultaneous with or attended by what
has been called possessive individualism.
We maintain, therefore, first, that racial difference as appearance
or phenomenon is an originary fact. It is not something that can be
ignored in the process of anagnorisis. Second, that we are speaking
here of an ancient feeling among men, that of group empathy, whose
ancestral tendency towards a mistrust of the other is but the form of
aversion or resistance to the unknown whose object is human.
Finally, that the intense subjectification proper to the new forms of
totalization was not possible without a negation of its constitutive or
original points of reference, which were precisely the germs of other
totalities or nations.
It seems to us that with race the same thing happens as with
many other ideologemes: they need not be rational in themselves in
order to serve rational ends. Anti-Semitism is barbaric but it has
produced certain instances of ‘national recognition which is not
In any event, since ours is an age that has chosen to recognize itself
through its great men, in a kind of heroic conception of a history that
THE TORPOR OF CENTURIES # 193
This Indians face, his gaze, his features, are of stone like the
granite of his mountains. There is no expression in that face:
there are no contractions; it chews and swallows inertly. I
have studied it many times, since my childhood, filled with
fear for humanity. The Aymara walks past the white man
without looking at him, or glancing at him out of the corner
or his eye. In the high peaks, in the immense steppes, only
the traveller, cholo or viracocha, crosses his path. It seems
that on such occasions, a spontaneous sympathy should
instinctively draw man to man, but the Aymara never greets
you. Not a syllable of his barbarous dialect issues from his
throat: and we hardly hear its timbre when, crouching in the
door of his hovel, he answers gruffly: janihua, which is a
refusal of all service.
And then: ‘What kind of sensations stir in him? . . . And how
can we discover them with our fear of the unthinkable? They dont
speak in their stuttering, they only gesticulate like imbeciles.’
These are the words of Baptista who, according to Prudencio
Bustillo, was ‘the greatest political mind ever produced by the Bolivian
race.*6
On the other hand, Gabriel René Moreno, the most renowned
of Bolivian writers, took for granted that mestizos and Indians were
subalterns ‘as a consequence of the very cells that make up their
wicked nature and deficient minds’;7 and he spoke of the Inca Indian
as ‘sombre, foul, elusive, meek, stupid and sordid’;8 therefore:
The men of Chuquisaca wanted to subject [it] to the Indian
laws and decrees of Toledo; laws and decrees made to crush
and wring the Inca Indian, shrewd, devious, filthy, taciturn,
9 Gabriel René Moreno, Nicomedes Aritelo (Santa Cruz: UGRM, 1960), p. 53.
10 Ibid., p. 32.
11 Cited in Juan Albarracín Millán, Orígenes del pensamiento social contem
poráneo de Bolivia (La Paz: Juventud, 1976), p. 193.
12 Cited in ibid., p. 194.
13 Saavedra, ‘Proceso Mohoza’, n.p.
196 • REN£ ZAVALETA MERCADO
As to Willka’s ideals, Saavedra does not deny them but for him
they are the ‘obsessions’ o f‘bloodthirsty orangutans’. It is, in short, ‘a
degenerate race in the process of its final dissolution’. Saavedra who
is, moreover, as leader of the artisans, a kind of predecessor of pop
ulism, is then the author of this ‘tragic racist pamphlet’ that according
to Albarracin is ‘perhaps the most anti-Indian piece of literature in
all of Bolivian sociology as a document of white racism’.14 The Indian
is ‘no more than a beast of burden, miserable and abject, who warrants
no compassion and must be exploited to the point of inhumanity and
indignity’15 and, in short, ‘if we must eliminate them, because they
constitute an obstacle to our programme, let us do it frankly and
energetically’;16 ‘If he [the Indian], consumed by suffering, rebels
against his oppressors [ . . . ] then he must be crushed like a danger
ous animal.’17
States, like individuals—like men—cannot live things without
representing them, that is, without conceptualizing them. These are
the founders of the ideology of the oligarchic state. They were based,
as we will see in the following chapters (which look at the state that
was constructed against this one), on something that long preceded
the oligarchic state and that would survive long after its destruction.
It is one of the elements of the deep ideology of this society, at least
that of the elite, seigneurial and Hispanic stratum. As we have seen in
the particular articulation of the seigneurial (the structure of complic
ity), this itself necessarily includes important sectors of the oppressed
because there is always one beneath the last of the inferior ranks and
the consecration of hierarchies does not recognize an intelligible
logic. What is interesting in this case is that the ideology of the his
torical foundation, in a kind of suicidal outburst, expresses itself also
thanks to their support, it was incongruous for him to share the the
ses of the very men he had defeated, those of Baptista or Saavedra,
who called for the unsparing and immediate extermination of the
Aymara. That all this would end in the consolidation of so anodyne
and so ‘Montista a government proves that a kind of impersonal rea
son was being fulfilled. Within this logic it was acceptable to exter
minate the cambas’, to solicit Willkas support, to betray and murder
Willka, and then later or simultaneously to express the opinion that
the cambas’ should be exterminated and the Aymara leader elimi
nated. Pandos conscience was clear after all this because this is how
an entire community thought (within the scope of the caste).
Moreno, in turn, a thoroughly modern man, had thoroughly
understood the logic of Argentine Europeanization. Indeed, he had
denounced
the plan to isolate and Europeanize Argentina in America
[and the] so-called porteñismo of the isolation of Río de la
Plata to achieve this Europeanization of workers, capital, and
commerce most expediently. [ . . . ] So Buenos Aires, which
had invited her sisters, the most properly Argentinian
provinces, to reap the fruits of Europeanization, will break
its American ties decisively for itself and in their name, to
enjoy this Europeanization together.19
If this same man could so lucidly grasp the interpellation of Char
cas, that is, the subsequent Potosí market, as well as the role played
by Belcismo, for which he was himself labelled a red like his country
man the illustrious but confused [Andrés] Ibáñez, even if only out of
envy or intrigue, why did he have to succumb to such a humiliating
role as that of a regional intellectual, as had occurred already in a more
ambiguous way in Archivo de Moxosy Chiquitos and in a unequivocal,
that is, a purely provincialist way in Nicomedes Antelo?
Every age has an ideology. There are certainly ages that have only a
vague notion of their own ideological contents but this, ideology, will
take its final shape sooner or later; this is what Marx meant when he
said that the ideas of the age are those of the ruling class, although
we could also say this the other way around: the ruling class becomes
the ruling class by reading, from its position of lucidity, the ideas that
will be dominant or that are dominant only in a potential and
obscure way. In other words, ideology results from the social sub
stance and not the social substance from ideology; even negative or
critical ideology expresses elements that will develop inexorably.
Therefore, the struggle has predefined the context in which the ideas
that will make it explicit will emerge.
This clearly applies to the case that constitutes the object of our
study. Social Darwinism, the idolization of the surplus, even
xenophilia, were the results of class struggle in the specific context
of the defeat of the diffuse and vast party that was called Belcismo.
THE TORPOR OF CENTURIES • 201
Hegel called self-certainty and what we can call the form of its class
character. On both ends, if this, which is a law of the modern state,
is not fulfilled, we have a kind of failure. An identity between legiti
mation or the explicit ideological emission and self-consciousness
exists, for example, in backward states. The result is that this reac
tionary synthesis produces a transience or instability of the state. On
the other extreme, a true identity between what the state is and how
it appears would make the state useless. It would have to disappear
ipso facto. And yet, the state can only develop self-certainty in accor
dance with the requirements of civil society, which it serves through
its legitimating or explicit ideology. Here Bacons dictum holds true:
nature—like society—to be commanded must be obeyed.
How did the oligarchic state behave in relation to this law? With
a heedlessness that cost it dearly. It exaggerated the significance of
its victory and identified its internal ideology with its explicit ideol
ogy. Its easy to have a certain unanimity if you exclude all your ene
mies and this is what the oligarchic state did with its victory over
Belcismo and Willka; but very soon a ‘subterranean revenge would
come, as we shall see. That the warring parties—conservatives, lib
erals, republicans—were so much in agreement as to the spirit of the
state shows that it was a question of dissension within the state party.
It also indicates that, after the exclusion of the Indians and the ple
beian masses from the politico-legal country, the system enjoyed a
kind of deformed hegemony: it was the country that had been
besieged by Willka and the proclamation of its ideological pro
gramme was an excess of the hour of victory. Meanwhile, that the
supposed discourse of legitimation, the outward ideology, and the
discourse of the states identity coincided is what explains the brevity
of its life and the suddenness of its downfall.
The revolutionary-nationalist school labelled this line of thought
anti-patriotic. This led to an ethico-Manichean discourse on the
national-popular. What is certain is that all of them, with the excep
tion again of Arguedas, who was nothing but a bureaucratic hack in
THE TORPOR OF CENTURIES • 203
of the population; in this sense the only population that exists is that
which has been incorporated into the state or, as Kelsen said, into
the ‘human sphere of validity of the state’, which certainly need not
be equivalent to what exists in crude demographic terms. The Indi
ans of the Amazon are self-determined in the middle of the rainforest
and therefore do not exist for Brazil as a state except when they
become an obstacle to it, because we are using a technical definition
and not an ethical one. These are well-known principles. Now, the
object of the state with regard to ideas is also the production of the
substance of the state or of ideas valid for the state, not of all ideas.
The same can be said of the state as producer: when the state pro
duces steel, it does not produce steel but state substance and this
would be equally true if it produced shoes. In the sphere of ideas,
what should interest it are the ideas that can be validated within the
state, that is, ideas that can become the spirit of the state, for the sate
itself and also for civil society. When a ruling class produces ideas
that cannot be metabolized as its own by civil society, the state nec
essarily exists in a relation of non-belonging to its very object or end
which is, precisely, society. To be durable, of course, domination must
be to some extent in the interest of the dominated; otherwise, soli
darity is blocked from the outset.
It is said, to absolve Pando or Saavedra or Montes, that they merely
shared the ideas of their time; we could just as well claim that they
were, on the other hand, incapable of being contemporary with their
own time. All this is debatable, but to forget oneself, which is some
thing concrete, in the service of the general spirit of the times, is already
the beginning of ones dependency or non-self-determination. If the
‘ideas of the age said all this, it would mean that the worlds ideas
favour the good fortune of some nations and the decline or elimina
tion of others. The role of truth would be terrible indeed if its func
tion were always to serve the victor. What is clear, in any case, is that
there are no neutral ideas and that the ideas of the world serve those
who produce them and who have succeeded in imposing them.
THE TORPOR OF CENTURIES * 209
From these poisoned roots arose that tree that wanted only to
fall. The problem is that all this could not remain shut up in the
closet, but would necessarily break out. Things would come to light
fully only when the state came to face the rest of the world, which it
would do through war. This is perhaps the central problem with
which any student of the events of Bolivian history since then and
even since the War of the Pacific must contend: the sense of ground
lessness and bewilderment that all these events assume, as if life had
lost its skeleton, a generalized absurdity. Incoherence, then, is not a
mere metaphor but the defining attribute of the character of that
state, as it would later be of its conduct in the Chaco War, of its
behaviour in relation to the surplus, of the mad fanaticism with
which the upper echelon of this society fought against all democratic
forms, even the most basic.
What is strange in all this is the impotence of the intellect.
Salamanca was not, by any means, a man of less talent than Batlle,
as anyone who had known him would have attested. Baptista is said
to have been a brilliant man; Moreno was unquestionably a better
writer than Vicuña Mackena or Rodó; Saavedra was a man as impos
ing as Irigoyen and more cultured. Toro, as we shall see, was at least
potentially a man of no less talent than Estigarribia. Here personalist
interpretations of all kinds are clearly inadequate. We can presume,
however, that Batlle believed in the equality of immigrants because
he himself was an immigrant in a country of immigrants. Each in
his own way felt himself to be part of what he did. In other words:
knowledge cannot be constructed against reality with impunity, nor
is knowledge ever independent from what one is.
*
war, which opens this phase of the state, the Chaco War, which
reveals its aspiration , and the April insurrection, which neutralizes
it, would have only a grotesque atmosphere, like a maelstrom of
depravity and monstrosity in the midst of a burning house. The sub
stance of the era is determined by the oligarchy in its pristine form,
that is, by the seigneurial regrouping around the mining surplus and
its major firms. We see here, uninterrupted by caudillos (in the man
ner of the nineteenth century) or popular uprisings, the oligarchy in
its historical form, in the full deployment of its beliefs, rituals and
principles. The people as such had been eclipsed with Melgarejos
victory and Zarates disastrous campaign. We could say that this is
the period of the rosea in its actuality or nakedness, certainly invalu
able for the biography of a class but inexorable in demonstrating the
inviability of capitalism in Bolivia.
The devastating failure of the oligarchic project stands in stark
contrast to the cheerful certainty of its formulations. It is an era of
bold assertions. Everyone seemed to know where things were going
and it was an age in which Bolivia was unwavering. Amid the ruins
of an exclusive sphere of public opinion, it was a society that believed
too firmly. It was also, of course, the time when Bolivia was closest
to political and national extinction. Montes and his foolish, tri
umphant pride turned Bolivia into a panglossian village, starving to
death and capable of nothing but self-satisfied. Although based on a
kind of apartheid, in this at least the liberals were unarguably suc
cessful: in selling consent almost by the pound. This shift towards
groundless illusions was part of a certain enigmatic fantasy that
enveloped the misfortune of the age.
It is, then, the age of abject consciousness or of false consciousness.
The local political jargon speaks of the superstate or feudal-mining
state, all terms that are modest approximations of varying efficacy
to the scrutiny of an obvious fact that was the merely apparent or
pseudological existence of the state, an existence tangled up in its
real subordination to the dominant nucleus of ‘big mining and its
214 • RENÉ ZAVALETA MERCADO
periphery, the rosea, that is, the mining superstate. And so when the
university reform movement launched the slogan ‘mines to the state
and land to the Indians it became a pivotal rallying call, because in
Bolivia the main oppressed groups were the Indians and the state. It
was a slogan that perfectly fulfilled its function as such, incisively
and with perfect concision.
It is here that we must begin a digression on sovereignty or self
certainty or authority, which is the ethos of the state and means being
beholden only to itself. This is something that should not be reduced
to the absurd. Obviously, no one has or can acquire infinite self-
determination. What the concept implies is that a self-determinative
ethos is always present in the spirit of ones acts. In any case, not to
know what one is at least in the materiality of ones historicity is
already a form of non-existence or subordination.
We should perhaps emphasize the solipsistic nature of the sterile
digressions of recent attempts at a general theory of the state, based
on the principle of alocalism in political analysis. Indeed, if we can
speak of a mode of production in universal terms we must stop at
the moment of the regulative model, which is the limit of its validity,
that is, it can only comprehend the most strictly quantifiable aspects
of abstract labour and no more than some general outlines of the
superstructural phenomena, such as the freedom of modern men.
It is in a way a discussion exhausted not through elucidation but
through sheer accretion. In any case, it is clear that if there is a
structural order through which there exists a certain univocality with
regard to the capitalist mode of production or regulative model in
such different formations as France, the US, Mexico and Argentina,
this implies the principle of mundiality, that is, the logic of world
history, which is a new dimension like the sense of temporality.
Mundiality as generalization means, in a way that seems somewhat
paradoxical, that nations or particularities are also deeper and more
differentiated. In the past, the identity of a nation came from its iso
lation; here it is a choice because each nation must define itself in
THE TORPOR OF CENTURIES * 215
undoubtedly spatial. Space is a central fact of the past but it also con
tains what a country aspires to be—it contains the principle of hope.
In its conception of the territory, which it did not aspire to integrate
nationally but to organize around the requirements of the mining
companies (an impermanent fetish) and of course in outright denial
of the spatial foundations of social memory, it was clearly a state
incapable of realizing its own objectives. In its conception of a
sphere of legitimacy that was oligarchic in its origin, which means
exclusive, based on the logic of the separation of citizens and pongos
or interdictos, it was a state that condemned itself to an apparent or
spectral existence. It ultimately accepted the demographic and spa
tial boundaries conceded by its neighbours. Given that during the
entire period there was not a single president without some degree
of connection to the mining companies, with the obvious exceptions
of Busch and Villarroel, who already belong to the phase of its dis
solution and decline, it is undeniable that to speak here of the rela
tive autonomy of the state is ludicrous. The concept of the modern
state did not exist in the proud and empty heads of the men of the
oligarchic caste.
What characterized this power bloc that only for ease of exposi
tion we call the oligarchy, in brief, was a certain lack of appetite for
self-determination. This must be conceived in terms of a long
process. It is not a question of the necessary mobilization of self
determinative action by a catastrophic event: it is, rather, the social
production of a systematic desire or impetus. If self-determination
had to be realized immediately, there would only be such an impulse
when it—self-determination—existed fully, which is absurd. The
peculiarity of this state is that in none of its acts was there a true
desire for self-determination or when such a desire existed—we are
thinking of Salamanca and his party—it was in relation to factors
that were absolutely secondary like the Paraguayans and not in
relation to the central problems of sovereignty. For Salamanca
sovereignty was about the Gran Chaco and not about history. The
THE TORPOR OF CENTURIES • 219
that is, economic privilege based on race and religion, only accentu
ated this alienation and those who profited from it ended up con
structing their own tiny country or subculture, which was the
oligarchy. An oligarchy that had barely begun to crack the protocul-
tural codes of the place could not counterpose a national idea to that
of their foreign assailants because they felt more alien to the Aymara
or Quechua multitude than to the Chilean army. Everything indicated
to them that ultimately their allies were latter—the foreigners—and
not the former. Its not that they had no patriotic feeling but that in
them the logic of the lineage, exaggerated to the point of absurdity,
had always been more decisive than the logic of the nation.
With power monopolized in so few hands, in which the suppres
sion of the principles of equality and dignity was legally sanctioned
and was practically a tenet of the state, Montes and his cohort of sell
outs acted, after Zarates defeat, in accordance with all the deep con
victions of a caste so mysteriously alien to its own home.
*
Not all of their thought was so utterly bankrupt. It was Tamayo, cer
tainly an audacious man whose thought went beyond mere confor
mity to the era while still its prisoner, who knew that mulitvocality
was a natural feature of all social propositions, that they should be—
and are always—biunivocal, although he expressed this in a discourse
mired in contradictions that end up destroying the logic of his expo
sition. It is nonetheless instructive to follow the thread of this dis
course, even if only in the most summary way.
In the first place, a powerful but Manichean reaction against the
social Darwinist dogma that was so prevalent at the time:
If by the manifestation of a moral superiority we understand
that air of gravity with which man faces all the events of his
existence, and a profound sense of justice, and more than
justice, of equality, and still more than equality, of love; if
morality consists in being ones own master and only aban
doning oneself and ones own interest for love and service
towards ones fellow; if great morality is manifested in the
accentuation of ones personality, without prejudice and
rather to the benefit of others; if it is, somewhat more pre
cisely, the expression of certain general virtues, such as
working from the time one is able and until one can work
no longer, moderation and observance of customs and the
translation of this into an orderly bodily health; absence of
all radical evil, truthfulness, gravity, absence of all spirit of
mockery, gentleness as a general condition, humanity and
harmlessness, and, along with this, as intellectual qualities,
simplicity, rectitude, precision and moderation; if all this is
a manifestation of moral superiority, no one possesses such
226 • RENÉ ZAVALETA MERCADO
38 Ibid., chap . 8.
39 Ibid.
40 Ibid.
228 • RENÉ ZAVALETA MERCADO
43 Ibid., ch ap . 48.
THE TORPOR OF CENTURIES • 231
was closed to him at the level of the quotidian. Pando chose to serve
his savage dogmas and to pay slavish tribute to ill-conceived ideas
rather than to take on the national programme that was latent in the
form of the rebellion; he sanctioned the legal exile of the Indians,
who, moreover, had risen up in his name. Such a mobilization of sup
port for Pando had its own meanings. It is true that even in the
decade of 1910-20 his name maintained a certain resonance among
the Aymara. It was nonetheless tragic that the Indians themselves
invoked a man with such nefarious racist ideas, which means,
frankly, that in their perplexity, they themselves still harboured the
seeds of their own servitude. That is, they lacked information. With
out this, they could not win.
The cast of leading characters of that era was of course radically
incapable of discerning such glimmers of analytic greatness in
Tamayo. He himself, moreover, acted for that society, filled his poetry
with marvellous elements and gushed the imperiousness of a facile
erudition to the point of disgust, and ended up shut up in a room
for decades. To a considerable extent, the comfortable superiority
that he enjoyed over the men of his time led him to lose all self
perspective and distorted him. The ultranationalist military regime
of the 40s republished his essays, but they reformed neither the soci
ety of the time nor their own institution in accordance with them
and, in general, instead of discerning the transformative lines of this
thought, they made Tamayo into one more household god.
*
1
THE TORPOR OF CENTURIES • 233
46 Ibid., p. 319.
47 Ibid., p.159.
48 Cited in ibid., pp. 161-2. [Zavaletas emphasis.]
49 Ibid., p. 162.
50 Cited in ibid., p. 163.
THE TORPOR OF CENTURIES # 235
had been born in it and, at the same time, towards the subsumption
of the manager model under traditional forms of exploitation. Patino
was living proof that there were no true cultural obstructions to a
rather comprehensive understanding of the world or of capitalism.
It is evident, on the contrary, that he himself represented a case of
possessive individualism without a nation, that is, it was the nation
or those who assumed the monopoly of its name who lacked such
notions of individuality and possession. The seigneurial elements in
Aramayo or Arce were more important, even if only by osmosis, and
cosmopolitan elements were dominant in Hochschild. The real
leader or corporate caudillo, however, was Patino. This is why we
must ask under what conditions it was possible to perform all the
tasks proper to a bourgeois logic and at the same time to directly
renounce its extension as a national logic. The favourable combina
tion of low consumption and a relatively high level of adaptation to
advanced technology on the part of the workers, along with the pre
existence of a certain internal market, seemed to invite a kind of
mimetic effect in the development of capitalism. However, Patino
constituted himself as an exemplar of spurious embourgeoisement
because, bourgeois to the core of his being, he was formally capitalist
but not national. It is in the study of the great figures of the bourgeois
class that we find evidence of the insidious limits of embourgeoise
ment in a formation like the Bolivian. The fact is that it turned out
to be an inhospitable land for it.
Patino, a man from a modest background (although from within
a very particular popular setting, that of Cochabamba, which despite
being a non-industrial subformation was perhaps the oldest and
most distinctly mercantile of Bolivia), acquired the notions that
would take him so far first as an employee of a supply compan)
(Fricke) and later of Huanchaca itself, then the biggest company in
the country. We could say that here certain ideas take hold of him,
such as the particular and subordinate position of Boli\ ia in the
world market, but also the advantages of industrial concentration.
240 • RENÉ ZAVALETA MERCADO
62 Ibid.
THE TORPOR OF CENTURIES • 241
63 Women who sorted through the minerals retrieved from the mines.
64 Manuel Carrasco, Simón I. Patiño: Un procer industrial (Cochabam ba:
Editorial Canelas, 1964), p. 81.
65 Almaraz, El poder y la caída, p. 31
242 # RENÉ ZAVALETA MERCADO
transport of minerals from the interior of the mine to the surface was
performed by workers carrying sacks of metal on their backs. These
sacks had a capacity of 75 kilograms and only two trips could be
made’69
Barbier affirmed that ‘The pulverization, the sulphur emissions
from the silver, the handling of minerals made into bars to be sent
to Europe, killed them like flies.’70
It was a labour regime that seemed to indicate that for the com
panies everything was important except those men. It was, however,
something socially accepted, as was made evident when in 1903 a
law was passed making Sunday a mandatory day of rest for all, with
the exception of the mine workers. The loss of human life through
overexploitation of labour was seen to the end as part of the nature
of things, to the point that Aramayo wrote in his famous Memoran
dum, which lays out his project for the country: ‘The Bolivian worker,
as a result of his primitive education, does not yet have the same
needs that more advanced peoples have.’71
This has been illustrated, in a descriptive mode, in the observa
tion that ‘The company [ . . . ] did not hesitate, despite its heavy
investment in machinery and advanced techniques, to employ
women and children above ground in sorting metals and other tasks
which required extensive labour [ . . . ],’72
All this is only to say that then and much earlier the exploitation
of the labour force was an established custom. Indeed, the mining
industry only continued the Spanish tradition of extermination
through work, which is a systematic practice that persists to this day
and is incorporated into the everyday life of this society.
*
There is a problematic knot that we can call the aporia of Patino. The
sordid and dense enigma of his trajectory has generally been
explained either as the product of a singular personality or as a result
of the call of the world market. When the world needed tin, it pro
duced Patino, etc. These elements of course figure in the process of
the enigma but they do not totally resolve it. Hochschild is an exam
ple of the world coming not to Bolivia but to its tin. And to inherit a
fortune as Aramayo did is not the same thing as to make one. Patino
was at once local, because he was formed here, and contemporary,
that is, originary.
We should perhaps take into account the problems of a mentality
proper to an outwardly oriented economy. The very capacity for par
ticipation in the world market is conditioned by the level of consol
idation of the nation-state, which means that it is dangerous to
become essentially a part of the world before becoming a nation. This
kind of extroversion not only deforms the internal congruence of the
economy but also defines the ideological belonging or loyalty of the
bourgeoisie, even if it has developed locally. It is a complex problem
because exportation deforms, and at the same time the notion of
existence outside of the world is chimeric. On the other hand, a class
is always the class plus its culture or environment, which exceeds it.
Patino, as we have seen, as an individual was a man of a wholly bour
geois character. He introduced technical innovations at the global
level, such as Patino motors, and he succeeded in transnationalizing
himself in an unorthodox manner, that is, from the periphery to the
centre. He was undoubtedly the dominant figure of the era, entirely
without peer; having assumed such perfect mastery over the country,
it would have seemed logical that he would reconstruct it in his image.
For some reason, such a dissemination of the capitalist spirit did not
occur and Patino himself seemed to share the logic of exclusion and
non-incorporation that was proper to the ruling class. He achieved
only a weak and instrumental unification of the dominant bloc, which
would inevitably lead to its collapse. As for self-determination, not
only was no such thing attempted but it was never given a thought
246 • RENÉ ZAVALETA MERCADO
and a resolve not to alter the terms of the internal class relations and
even to undertake their reactionary reform. Patiño, then, as the most
advanced stage of this bloc, wanted to combine real subsumption
with the massive exploitation of labour power.
This, as a discursive model, was tenacious and even successful
in its final expression but it lacked long-term viability. Ultimately,
there are only two ways to build structures of self-determination.
The first, which we have already cited, is through the receptivity that
ensues from democratic concentration. The second is the authori
tarian form or the method of negative hegemony. For this to occur
there must be a kind of absolute victory, implacable and prolonged,
to create the foundation that receives the authoritarian command;
but, also, a coherent continuity of authoritarian rule because at a cer
tain moment this indefinite over-domination turns on the one
charged with exercising it. This form, therefore, requires a state like
the one imagined by Hegel, a state with an ultimate internal certainty.
The project derived from Pat iños process suggests that an authori
tarian route was sought that would submit labour to exploitation by
both capital and the state. The core of its inviability was, however, in
its conception of the state as an instrument of obstruction and
subjugation.
To affirm that Bolivia lacked structures of embourgeoisement
raises the question of latent ideas. In principle, a pioneer is a pioneer
—but he should also be a model. Society should at once produce
him and receive him, transformed, as proof of its potential. Patiños
ideas, applied to politics, did not make the Patiñist state more
powerful. This was because he only gathered together latent ideas
with his power. The structures of embourgeoisement or the social
ization of bourgeois ideals, the ideologeme transformed into a pop
ular myth, must be preceded by or simultaneous with intellectual
reform. Instead, in that Bolivia what had taken place was a popular
movement that clung, rightly or wrongly, to archaic forms of its con
stitution that were nonetheless capable of laying siege in a fierce (and
248 • RENÉ ZAVALETA MERCADO
81 [Local pejorative term for a member of the elite; Augusto Céspedes uses
the phrase huayraleva democracy to refer to electoral democracy restricted to
a very narrow political class.]
254 • REN£ ZAVALETA MERCADO
and not historical process. Its life is like a never-ending party where
bad news is not admitted. Perhaps for this reason, the political phase
now before us, on the contrary, is characterized by the stubborn
attempt to establish the criterion of exemplarity over processual logic
in the explanation of events. The project was crude in its essence
because it was based on the political annihilation of the masses, but
it aspired to construct a closed political society that believed in a kind
of reinvention of history, a heroic history constructed almost without
heroes because what heroes there were were elsewhere, their names
unknown.
Salamanca inherited the paradigm of the ‘symbolic man from
Linares. It is a process full of feelings of inexplicability or disorienta
tion. The oligarchic society had squandered one opportunity for
charismatic leadership after another, although certainly, instinctively,
it sought them without end; the pursuit of a charismatic solution to
the unresolved problem of the legitimacy of power is only natural
where the principle of the rational legitimation of power has been
abdicated.
If we adhere to the descriptions offered by Saavedra’s few biog
raphers, we must believe that his intellectual horizon was more con
tem porary than Tamayos. Siles himself, although he was on the
fringes of the rosea gentry, with a conventional training as a Charcas
attorney, was a man with a certain intellectual dignity. Both, however,
stand out as peaks on an otherwise flat landscape. It was a society
obsessed with mere appearances, a collective case of submerged con
sciousness. It was Montes who, through sheer noise, showered this
political society with his paralogy because, with his formidable
euphoria directed primarily towards itself, with his innate sense of
boundless self-satisfaction, he belonged to an environment enam
oured of this, of an optimism that issued from the fervour for the
surplus.
The surplus, however, came, existed in some small measure and
vanished immediately. Then the ‘symbolic man emerged, ‘the most
THE TORPOR OF CENTURIES * 255
meditative and coldest of the Bolivian politicians and also the most
distinguished’, with an ‘intelligence [that] was self-sufficient without
any kind of intercourse with new ideas’, according to Céspedes’ mag
nificent observation.82
It seemed that this society had finally reached its objective. With
‘the simplicity of his oratory, precise and eloquent, rare in those times
in its lack of rhetorical excess’,83 Salamanca’s sobriety, which was like
a kind of inertia, however, came too late because it was impossible
for the system and it was, in any case, accompanied by an illusory
vision of the world that was of the greatest significance. And so, when
the ‘symbolic man’ appeared, it was said that the misfortunes of the
nation had come to an end.
In the following pages, we will see to what point Salamanca’s
ideas about Bolivia corresponded to the radical falsity proper to his
class position: he himself, as a landholder, entirely seigneurial yet a
mestizo, had Indians but could not see them. Even in his disheart
ened vision of a man given over to death from the beginning, he was
confined by a social blindness in the style of Candide, a general
optimism that explains how Bolivia could follow him into a hopeless
venture like that of the Gran Chaco. Here indeed an entire state
organized its own defeat. In this more general sense, if in the micro
history of the oligarchic state Montes means something different
from Saavedra or Salamanca from Siles, they all nonetheless merely
constitute different moments in the process of a state that would run
its course. We are not particularly interested in this discussion or in
the banal internal history of oligarchic democracy between republi
cans and liberals but, rather, in its role in determining subsequent
events and above all in the apocalyptic ordeal that was the Chaco
War. None of them, in the end, figures as more than a straggling
84 Karl von Clausewitz, On War (Michael Eliot Howard and Peter Paret trans)
(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1989), p. 75.
85 The following paragraphs are from Zavaletas Consideraciones generales
sobre la historia de Bolivia, 1932-71 (1977), available in Zavaleta Mercado,
Obra Completa, vol. 2, pp. 35-96.
THE TORPOR OF CENTURIES • 257
the pearl of inland America. Asunción, meanwhile, had its own pres
tige. Was it not, after all, the epicentre of colonial expansion in the
whole of Río de la Plata and then a modest country but also progres
sive and harmonious, comparable in this to the Chile of the time, but
perhaps in a healthier way? There was undoubtedly a kind of weak
arrogance on the part of Charcas and there was no reason why
Asunción should not have harboured a certain vindicationism that
was not related to the Gran Chaco. There is a misunderstanding here.
People tend to see countries from the perspective of the present and
they are not necessarily wrong to do so because things are known in
their conclusion; each country, on the other hand, sees itself with the
eyes of its memory. That a country’s memory stagnates at a moment
in its past or that it becomes mythicized is not really important
because here what matters is what a country believes itself to be. The
component of collective memory in the ideological register is no
doubt greater than is commonly assumed. The Paraguayans, then,
carried their own historical burden.
This is also the case with Charcas. It is generally taken for
granted that the viceroyalty of Rio de la Plata is the relevant frame
of reference for Bolivia in terms of its juridical origins. It is often
assumed that the centre of the viceroyalty was always Buenos Aires.
But the truth is that it was not Charcas that existed in its relation to
the viceroyalty but the viceroyalty that was constituted with its foun
dation in Charcas. In principle, the territory of the viceroyalty was
Charcas. The viceroyalty of Peru was made up of the two audiencias
and that of Charcas comprised what is today Argentina, Bolivia,
Paraguay and Uruguay. Even when another audiencia was created,
that of Buenos Aires, now within the viceroyalty, half of the provinces
and most of the population remained in Charcas. The entire region,
moreover, lived off of Potosí and was constituted by its relation to it.
In both cases, we are dealing with countries whose relative
importance in the region had done none nothing but decline con
tinuously. This, as we shall see, radicalizes the mood of intensity, of
THE TORPOR OF CENTURIES # 259
republic, destined to suffer all the perils of the world, was born. It
was, however, a sureness that did not come from itself and we can
discern in it a paranoia that would later be repeated, if its true that
paranoia consists in a split between intellect and sensibility. The fac
tions or little republics themselves demonstrated not only an inex
plicable and sometimes atrocious capacity for resistance (given that
they were never vanquished by anyone) but also the centrifugal
nature of power for which they laid the foundations (which explains
their inelegant designation as republiquetas). Much later, this would
take the form of a permeation of the national by the indigenous. In
other words, since leaders were nominated by the combatants and
the logistics were determined by the Indians, given that the very exis
tence of a faction means, in concrete terms (although not in a legal
sense), that the landowners do not hold possession of their properties
so long as the military democracy lasts, it is a mass war with all the
features of the classic peasant wars: strong resistance and little chance
of victory. For those fond of transhistorical comparisons, for Toyn
bee, for example, Amarus war or even the war of independence and
Miinzer’s would bear an uncanny resemblance. This is passed down
to the republic and would become a feature of the national character.
It would be a country of great military capacity in its masses, always
unyielding in their home territory, reproducing certain Incan limi
tations because it would be a state with little ability to wage wars out
side its own habitat, as if as a result of an excessive adaptation to its
environment. The faction, with the habits of democracy in arms,
would leave as its legacy a country of what Alcides Arguedas would
call, with all the bitterness of his soul, the ‘barbarous caudillos’ and
the ‘plebs in action. This explains the great distance between two
countries that are otherwise as similar as Peru and Bolivia. It is here,
in part, where the distinctive features of its social character are
forged.
The catastrophic silver bust would put an end to the mercury
mining oligarchy and this meant that it was a country born isolated
THE TORPOR OF CENTURIES • 263
War teaches us a great deal about things. The two least powerful
countries of South America waged the greatest military conflict the
region has ever seen. The Chaco War has been called ‘the vicious
war’88 and perhaps for this reason it is so instructive to consider the
technical military analysis of its events together with the sociological
86 Los doctores de Charcas, a term for the intellectual and political elite at
independence, often mocking its distance from the populace.
87 End of passage from Consideraciones generales sobre la historia de Bolivia.
88 Charles Arnade, La dramática insurgencia de Bolivia (La Paz: Juventud,
1964), p. 11.
264 • RENÉ ZAVALETA MERCADO
because, indeed, it is here, in the national war, that war ‘recovers its
true nature!
What remains to be determined then is whether Salamanca, as
the ‘symbolic man, expressed only himself or if he was the cathartic
fulfilment of a compulsion, that is, if he expressed the necessity of a
real form of something that had already appeared (the oligarchic
state) or if the entire country simply followed him in a fit of temper.
In any case, in contrast to the Paraguayans of Isla Poi, Paraguay was
for Salamanca ‘the little devil’91 and the war not only presented no
danger but it also became an opportunity that had bestowed great
fortune [upon Bolivia]’.92 An opportunity that, moreover, could not
be squandered in the service of pettifogging schemes: ‘Possesssion
of the Gran Chaco cannot be the subject of protocols, of arbitrage or
negotiations.’93
In short, the figure that constituted the symbolic condensation
of the oligarchic political civilization and of course acted as moral
leader of the war from the outset proposed that peace be made in
Asunción because he was obsessed with what we might aptly call the
cartographic objectives of the conflict. At this point, Salamancas
charismatic style was obviously largely founded on the non-negotiable
attitude of a Belcista programme that stirred up internal public opin
ion. This, however, consisted in dangerous boasts in which not even
they themselves believed except when they were turned against them.
Neither society as such nor its heteronational apex seriously believed
that the Gran Chaco was a vital part of the country, and if it was, as
the ‘symbol’ claimed, an existential matter, this was true for Paraguay
but not for Bolivia. Some have attributed this hyperbolization to a
Petrópolis complex. Salamanca, however, identified the country with
the oligarchic political system (to which he had only to supplement
it could defend a territory while in reality there are many other forms
of belonging to a space, but here there was none at all. Bolivia lacked
any kind of territorial sovereignty in the Gran Chaco and there was
not even a ritual relation of legitimacy of the state with the Toba
people; this distinguishes it thoroughly from Atacama. In any case,
Bolivia wasted its unprecedented relative demographic superiority
(unprecedented because this was the only possible case) and surren
dered to Paraguay’s geographic superiority:
Had Bolivia conducted general mobilization during August
and struck promptly, she would likely have attained the river
and won the war. Instead she remained passive, mobilizing
in dribbles; this enabled Paraguay to bring to bear her deci
sive advantage in space, and to achieve earlier concentration
of numerically superior forces.97
We cannot say that Paraguay then had an advanced social
equation as we can, even if only in comparative terms, of Chile in
1879. Between a civil society levelled by the Triple Alliance and an
exogenous state, which succeeded only in being pro-Argentine or
pro-Brazilian, one could not have expected much. Despite these dif
ficulties, the relation between the state and society was more
favourable than in Bolivia and this in itself tells us that the idea of
the state optimum does not necessarily refer to fully developed posi
tions. It was the right state for the corresponding social situation
under the circumstance of an intense mobilizing force. Meanwhile,
in Bolivia, the period was marked by the decline of a state constituted
against its society, out of options and rallied around a kind of jingoist,
arrogant patriotism.
All the Bolivian authors subscribe to Querejazus claim that
Bolivia threw itself into the war ‘when there was a total of 1,251 men
spread out over that vast territory’98 (some 200,000 square kilome
tres), which would prove only that it was a nation of fools. If this was
97 Ibid., p. 91.
98 Querejazu Calvo, Masamaclay, p. 63.
268 • REN£ ZAVALETA MERCADO
the case, it was necessary to make peace at any price, even if only to
gain time to recruit. On the other hand, there would have had to be
a revolution if they had come to such an extreme situation with
such weak preparation, which is to say in which the state didn’t see
it coming at all.
Zooks account is more realistic: ‘At the beginning of October of
1932, each country had total forces of around 20,000, the vital dif
ference being in their deployment. In the main theatre, Bolivia had
about 5,500 with 2,000 more en route, while Paraguay fielded
12, 000.’"
The operative idea here is that of deployment. The sterile relation
between the population and the territory is not so important. The
circulation of men in the territory lends the population itself a greater
productivity of state or national substance. A territory, ultimately,
belongs to us insofar as we can deploy ourselves towards it more
swiftly and with a greater sense of identity than anyone else. In other
words, where we can say: ‘We exist there.’ On the other hand, to go
to an unincorporated space is perhaps the most difficult military task
for any state.
This is a result of the process of decomposition of war, which the
Bolivian armed forces should have learned better from Bolivian his
tory than the Paraguayans from theirs. Not only the war of commu
nications but also an ecological war had begun, and it became clear
that the poverty of the post-Potosi system of circulation produced
men who belonged to their own immediate terrain and not to their
historical landscape. Hence the invariable consequence of the con
stant numerical superiority of the Paraguayans over the course of the
entire campaign. In fact, it must be acknowledged that a greater
human presence in a given place is proof of possession. Indeed:
The Andean Indian [ . . . ] was transported from the Alti-
plano to the Chaco like a beast, unaware of his purpose, and 9
107 Niccolo MachiaveUi, The Prince (George Bull trans.) (H arm ondsw orth:
Penguin, 1975), p. 49.
274 # REN£ ZAVALETA MERCADO
chological and behavioural anomaly that explains the fact that these
men, surely intelligent enough in principle, acted in an erratic and
divisive way. The horizon of visibility of the world was determined
by the social base; this is proof of the effectivity of the social base
upon cognitive activity. It is what explains the persistent degenerative
tendencies of the Bolivian state even after 1952 in its constant incli
nation towards the oligarchization of power.
Zook then falls into the error of insufficient generality in believing
that ‘the close cooperation of President Alaya and Estigarribia lent
added strength to the country and was in no small measure respon
sible for the outcome of the war’.121 This is almost like the attribution
of success to the protestant ethic. On the contrary, this cooperation
was possible because behind it was Paraguay such as it was. This was
essentially founded on the ideological conception of the war as an
absolute danger, a conception that was correct but that also served
an organizing function. On the other hand, it was made possible by
the survival of certain hereditary forms o f‘health’ that came, in their
positive aspect, from the non-aristocratizing and non-seigneurial
formation of that society (largely by the Jesuits) and also from the
internalized habit of compliance with authority, whatever this might
be, a not especially positive inheritance from the great dictators.
At Christmas 1934, a melancholy Salamanca, now deposed,
would say that ‘militarism, which had not been capable of repelling
the foreign enemy, has already imposed its domination in Bolivia.*122
Since a military approach to things was adopted, there was nothing
unusual in the fact that that things would become militaristic. But
the collapse of the oligarchic state continued implacably and not only
because of the inauguration of a period of military rule.
It translated, for example, into an absolute lack of faith in the
men of the country and of the system. Salamanca’s xenophobia was
applied contemptuously to the Paraguayans and timorously to the
the Latin American left as a whole, the other at the level of Zavaletas
individual work. Within the macronarrative of Latin Americanist
social thought, he is placed at the intersection of a discourse gov
erned by the categories of class, people and nation, and one centred
on indigeneity, heterogeneity and subalternity. In the current schol
arship on Zavaleta, his intellectual trajectory is conventionally
periodized into (1) a youthful, nationalist period, (2) an orthodox
Marxist period, and (3) a final, critical Marxist period in which uni
versal (metropolitan) categories are rejected as inoperable for the
theoretical production of non-metropolitan societies.
The concept-metaphor most commonly associated with Zavaleta
and cited to situate him at the threshold of a passage from a tradi
tional Marxist left to a discourse aligned with the struggles of indige
nous movements is that of abigarramiento, translated here sometimes
simply as ‘heterogeneity’ or, in its adjectival form, following existing
English citations of the term, as ‘motley’. Abigarramiento refers to the
coexistence of multiple modes of production and multiple concep
tions of the world within a single national territory and, therefore,
complicates the sequential and deterministic modes-of-production
narrative and constitutes an obstacle to the methods of both modern
social-scientific analysis and liberal democratic politics premised on
the existence of a more or less unified national citizenry. The Bolivian
social formation, for Zavaleta, is abigarrada because precapitalist
(feudal) or noncapitalist (Andean communitarian’) social relations
persist within the space claimed by a formally capitalist nation-state.
As a concept that supplements those received from European
social theory to designate the specificity of a peripheral society, abi
garramiento (too readily taken to stand for Zavaletas theoretical
apparatus as a whole) tends to be read in a vindicatory key, as m ul
ticultural diversity or least as a force of anticolonial resistance. Even
Luis Tapia, the most prominent scholar of Zavaletas work, who cor
rectly identifies and refutes the multiculturalist interpretation,
nonetheless remains within a localist framework, placing Zavaleta
288 • ANNE FREELAND
1 ‘The colonial matrix of power was introduced after Zavaleta Mercado died
(and of course, Zavaletas contribution fueled that conceptualization) [ . . . ]
the tensions juggled in a conceptual apparatus inherited from Karl Marx and
Antonio Gramsci, but growing out of Bolivian society’ (Walter Mignolo, ‘On
Subalterns and Other Agencies’, Postcolonial Studies: Culture, Politics, Economy
8[4] [2005]: 381-407; here p. 397).
2 See p. 1 of this volume.
AFTERWORD • 289
5 The manuscript was first published in book form in Mexico (by Siglo XXI)
under the title Lo nacional-popular en Bolivia (The National-Popular in
Bolivia) in 1986, and has been republished under the same title in 2013 by
Plural in Bolivia, in Volume 2 of Zavaletas complete works, scrupulously
edited and annotated by Mauricio Souza. I have chosen not to abbreviate the
original title of the manuscript as the Spanish editors do, since neither the
rudimentariness conveyed by the term elementos nor the reference to the his
torical are without significance. I also think it is worth keeping the dates that
AFTERWORD • 291
Zavaleta chose to frame his study, which betray its unfinished condition as
well as a gap between the book imagined in the prologue and one that clearly
had taken a different course.
6 ‘Las masas en noviembre’, discussed at the end of this Afterword.
organic relation between society and the state was already evident,
in this analysis, at least since the War of the Pacific; the difference
here is that a large portion of the population was effectively mobi
lized, and it is this mobilization that gave rise to a collective subject
(Zavaleta would say an intersubjectivity) capable of apprehending its
exclusion and thus of producing an organic crisis and ultimately an
alternative hegemonic project—that of the ‘state of 1952’.
for the present must take gendered power relations into account
in supplementing the current discourse of indigeneity. For an anti
colonial feminist perspective, the reader might turn to the work of
Silvia Rivera Cusicanqui, the most robust scholar of contemporary
indigenous movements in Bolivia and of their cooptation from both
the neoliberal and left-populist positions.
Bibliography
BIBLIOGRAPHY # 301
Fifer, J. Valerie. Bolivia: Land, Location and Politics since 1825. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1972.
Flores G alindo, Alberto. Arequipa y el sur andino: Ensayo, de historia
regional (siglos X V II-X X ) [Arequipa and the Southern Andes: Essays on
the History of the Region, Seventeenth to Twentieth Centuries]. Lima:
Horizonte, 1977.
Francovich, Guillermo. La ftlosofta en Bolivia [Philosophy in Bolivia]. La
Paz: Juventud, 1966.
Frank, A. G. Capitalism and Underdevelopment in Latin America. New York:
Monthly Review Press, 1967.
----- . Mexican Agriculture, 1521-1630: Transformation o f the Mode o f
Production. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981.
Freeland, Anne. ‘Gramsci in Latin America: Reconstitutions of the State’.
PhD dissertation, Department of Latin American and Iberian Cultures,
Columbia University, New York, 2017.
Garavaglia, Juan Carlos. ‘Un modo de producción subsidiario: la organi
zación económica de las comunidades guaranizadas durante los siglos
XVII-XVIII en la formación regional altoperuana-rioplatense [A Sub
sidiary Mode of Production: The Economic Organization o f the
Guaranized Communities during the Seventeenth and Eighteenth C en
turies in the Regional Formation of Upper Peru and the River Plate] in
Carlos Sempat Assadourian, Ciro Flamarión S. Cardoso, Horacio Cia-
fardini, Juan Carlos Garavaglia and Ernesto Laclau, Modos de producción
en América Latina [Modes of Production in Latin America]. Buenos
Aires: Siglo XXI, 1973, pp. 161-92.
García Linera, Alvaro. El retorno de la Bolivia plebeya [The Return of Ple
beian Bolivia]. La Paz: Muela del Diablo, 2000.
Gates Jr., Henry Louis. ‘The Black Letters on the Sign: W. E. B. Du Bois and
the Canon in The Oxford W. E. B. Du Bois, Volume 8: Black Folk Then
and Now: An Essay in the History and Sociology o f the Negro Race. New
York: Oxford University Press, 2007, pp. xi-xxiv.
Genovese, Eugene D. The Political Economy o f Slavery: Studies in the Econ
omy and Society o f the Slave South. New York: Pantheon Books, 1965.
G old, David A., Clarence Y. H. Lo and Erik Olin Wright. ‘Recientes desar
rollos en la teoría marxista del Estado capitalista [Recent Developments
in the Marxist Theory of the Capitalist State] in Heinz Rudolf Sonntag
BIBLIOGRAPHY • 305
Kula, Witold. Teoría económica del sistema feudal. Mexico City: Siglo XXI,
1979. Available in English as: An Economic Theory o f the Feudal System:
Towards a Model o f the Polish Economy, 1500-1800. New York: Verso,
1987.