Social & Legal Studies (Forthcoming Unrevised Initial Submission)
Social & Legal Studies (Forthcoming Unrevised Initial Submission)
Social & Legal Studies (Forthcoming Unrevised Initial Submission)
INTRODUCTION
It frustrates reform-minded family scholars that some western liberal jurisdictions such as
England and Wales, while recognizing same-sex couples, have not legislated comprehensively
for unmarried cohabitants. This legislative inertia flies in the face of data demonstrating the rise
of cohabitation and of prescriptions for reform. It may also resist a particular instrumental view
of law and its relationship with the social sciences and with ‘reality’. Many of the same
recalcitrance may be something to celebrate’ (Reece 2015, 129), this comparative paper takes a
distance from literature prescribing what law should do to cohabitation in places not having
enacted reforms. Its chief inquiry is what cohabitation has already done to law in two such
This paper makes three contentions. The first is that the ‘conservative’ approach to
*
McGill University, Canada
**
Jean Monnet University, France
***
This research was funded by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada. For comments on
earlier versions, the authors are grateful to Nicholas Bala and Angela Campbell. A version of this work was
presented at the Quatrième réunion plénière du projet ANR-COMPRES (Justification et modalités des formes de
compensation économique après divorce), Université Jean Monnet et Université de Lorraine, Lyon, France.
1
In Quebec, more than one couple in three cohabits (37.8% in 2011); in France, it is nearly one in four (22.6% in
2011). In Quebec, ‘cohabitant’ or ‘de facto spouse’ refers to those living together in a conjugal couple who are
neither married nor in a civil union. In France, ‘cohabitant’ (concubin) refers to those living together in a conjugal
couple who are neither married nor ‘PACSé’ (having undertaken a pacte civil de solidarité). One might speculate
that without France’s inheritance regime, which significantly advantages those married or PACSé, the proportion of
cohabitants might be higher yet.
marriage, has failed to ‘conserve’ marriage, its legal significance, and the legal categories with
which it operates. Despite legislative abstinence from recognizing cohabitants in formal, direct
terms, ad-hoc responses to cohabitation have in effect amended marriage and surrounding law
informally and indirectly. This conclusion complicates assumptions that a legislative impasse
produces – or secures – legal stasis. The second contention concerns a cleavage. The cleavage
does not lie between law and social life; such a gap may be inevitable (see e.g. Noreau 1999,
Leckey 2011). Rather, it lies between law and its dominant justificatory discourse. The
prevailing justification for sharply differentiating cohabitants from married spouses in France
and Quebec is freedom of choice. Married spouses have freely chosen to subject themselves to
conjugal rights and obligations, runs the mantra; unmarried partners have not. Whatever one
thinks of freedom of choice as a matter of political or social theory, our brief survey of the
positive law – across family law, the general private law of property and obligations, the public
law of social security and taxation, and the supranational caselaw of fundamental rights – reveals
that it fails to convince the legislative drafters and judges whose efforts it purportedly justifies.
Theoretical resources from critical geography, queer theory, and socio-legal work on law reform
aid us in contrasting the contingent, constructed, and shifting character of legal boundaries and
categorizations with the ostensibly seamless, timeless discourse of choice. More speculatively,
the third contention bears on the mentalité or legal culture of France and Quebec. The dominant
Before proceeding, a word on the scope of our inquiry is in order. A shared language and
civil-law tradition offer reasons for comparing France and Quebec. Another is that both have
robust welfare states. This feature of political economy is relevant since approaches to
cohabitation under public programs differ from those under the private law. We hereby
underscore our capacious definition of the law pertinent to cohabitation and alertness to the
private law of the family’s embeddedness ‘in legal domains – such as social security systems and
contracts – from which it is typically divided or extruded’ (Halley and Rittich 2010, 755).
Moreover, French and Quebec enactments are subject to a fundamental law of human rights,
interpreted ultimately by a supranational or otherwise higher court. In the French case, the
European Court of Human Rights interprets the Convention and the European Court of Justice,
the treaties. Both prevail over inconsistent national law. In the Quebec case, the Supreme Court
of Canada interprets the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms and may declare invalid
inconsistent provincial law. In both, then, the jurisprudence of fundamental rights constrains the
(Woehrling 2013, 122-123, see also Flauss 2005). Although not directly germane, supplements
to family policy in France and Quebec occasionally come from above in the forms, respectively,
Three strands of theoretical work help to bring into view the character of legal boundaries
relevant to cohabitation. The first is critical research in fields such as political and human
geography on boundaries, borders, and frontiers (from within socio-legal studies, see e.g. Sarat et
al. 1998). Such work reaches beyond the territorial focus to include borders enclosing groups and
identities (Newman 2003, 22, Newman and Paasi 1998, 194). Many of the theoretical insights
apply to institutions such as marriage. They lead to taking law generally, and family law
particularly, as concretizing justifications for inclusions and exclusions – which may be more or
less convincing. This literature on borders emphasizes that the social construction of boundaries
4
defines the exercise of political and social power (Newman 2010, 774). It is necessary, then, to
ask who benefits and who loses from current enclosures and boundaries (Newman 2003, 22).
Far from being inert givens, or fixed constructs, borders arise from ongoing processes.
2006, 148, see also Brunet-Jailly 2011, 3). This process has discursive or narrative dimensions
(Newman and Paasi 1998, 195, Kolossov 2005, 624). Borders separate the ‘self’ from the
‘other’, but that act of separation may constitute the distinction it purports merely to recognize
(Newman 2003, 14-15). These processes of definition and separation are inextricably bound up
with the process of othering (van Houtum and van Naerssen 2002, 125). Eliminating borders
world has produced new group categorizations (Newman 2010, 776). Last, even as they try to
keep things separate, borders invite traversal and transgression: they ‘are equally there to be
crossed’ (Newman 2003, 14). The violent debate about same-sex marriage in France in 2013
importance, for some, of defending the border that constitutes so-called ‘traditional marriage’.
The second strand is queer theory, which offers an analytically useful reminder that the
so-called ‘norm’ and the ‘outsider’ engage in mutual processes of self-constitution. If legally
defining the class of homosexuals involves constituting a class of heterosexuals (Halley 1993,
83), so defining marriage involves producing the class of those outside it. Queer theory asks
‘how certain categorizations work, what enactments they are performing and what relations they
are creating’ (Sedgwick 2008, 27). It cautions, too, that flagging a category’s inconsistency need
not undermine its force. To the contrary, ‘definitional incoherence is the very mechanism of
5
material dominance’ (Halley 1993, 98). The concern of queer critics of same-sex marriage that
new inclusions entail new exclusions echoes the reminder of border theorists that processes of
The third is work by socio-legal scholars experienced in law reform. They underscore
how changes outside a legal category, such as marriage, may affect that category. Pointing to
law’s ‘inescapable complexity’, Macdonald (2007, 1160) distinguishes explicit and implicit law
reform, as well as reform that is textual and non-textual (Macdonald and Kong 2006, 32-45). The
upshot is that social practices in family matters can effectively produce law reform – implicitly
and non-textually – despite legislative inactivity. Socio-legal discourse resonates with that of
queer scholars. For instance, for Carbonnier (2008, 262-263), reforms to the status of children
born outside marriage affect marriage’s significance and position. So would amendments that
ended marriage’s monopoly by allowing unmarried couples to adopt. Indeed, for Carbonnier,
marriage and its outside, cohabitation, sustain a reciprocal relation such that ‘the question of
marriage is the question of concubinage’ (2008, 277 [authors' translation]). An American scholar
speaks similarly about marriage’s ‘dynamic nature … and the way it is actively constructed in
nonmarital spaces’ (NeJaime 2014, 164 [footnote omitted]). These theoretical strands offer
analytical resources for contrasting legal boundaries under pressure with the overarching
discourse of choice.
Traditional family law in France and Quebec included the proposition that cohabitants form at
best a couple, not a family. Traces of this view remain and the legislative drafters have declined
to dislodge marriage from its privileged place. Cohabitation produces not a civil status, but at
6
most a factual situation. Still, the proposition by which cohabitants do not form a family has
identify the chief justification for legislative policy in their regard. This justification is freedom
obligations. Married spouses have voluntarily assumed reciprocal obligations; cohabitants have
not. The prevailing reading of a policy that withholds from de facto spouses any protections
under family law is that the legislature thereby ‘respects their will and their freedom’; by
themselves’ (Pineau and Pratte 2006, 536 para 374 [authors' translation]). It is de facto spouses’
liberty that purportedly justifies treating them as legal strangers (Nicolas-Maguin 2009, 386-392,
Hauser 2005, D.-Castelli and Goubau 2005, 1, Goubau 1995, 476, Roy 2010, for critical
analysis, see e.g. Leckey 2009a, Tremblay 2015, on 'complicating choices', see generally
Campbell 2013Ch. 1)
Orthodox sources in the civil law present marriage as the founding institution of a family.
Filiation, the legal bond between parent and child, is the institution by which a family then
reproduces itself forward in time (Marty and Raynaud 1956, 530 at para. 384). Whether or not
contemporary authors maintain this view consistently, legislative drafting implies that de facto
spouses do not form a family. For example, in Quebec the adjective ‘family’ (in French, familial)
qualifies measures restricted to de jure spouses. In France, that adjective denotes measures
regarding the support and custody of children. The legislative experience in France and Quebec
shows that the legal approach to marriage and cohabitation no longer tracks faithfully the
While cohabitants find themselves in movement across the boundary between family and
not-family, the core provisions on marriage continue to give credence to the view of cohabitants
as not-family. The Civil Codes of France and Quebec regulate in detail the relations between
spouses by marriage and by civil union. They provide for them a range of obligatory and
suppletive or default measures. Such measures address the obligation of support, the sharing of
household expenses, and the family residence. With variation in the statutory matrimonial regime
and varying scope for electing separate property via a marriage contract, the two Civil Codes
also presume a sharing of the gains during the marriage. In contrast, neither code attaches rights
and obligations to de facto spouses in virtue of their relationship. Similarly, the regime for the
legal devolution or distribution of intestate successions makes no provision for the de facto
spouse or the civil partner in the French PACS (art 653 CCQ a contrario; arts 756, 515-7 CC).
(Lefebvre 2012a).
Nevertheless, the legislative drafters have not entirely ignored de facto spouses. The
French Civil Code defines concubinage as ‘an union [sic] in fact, characterized by a life in
common offering a character of stability and continuity, between two persons, of different sexes
or of the same sex, who live in couple [sic]’ (art 515-8 CC, Legifrance, trad. by David W.
Gruning). For its part, the Civil Code of Québec includes no definition of de facto spouse.
Instead, the Interpretation Act provides one: ‘Two persons of opposite sex [sic] or the same sex
who live together and represent themselves publicly as a couple are de facto spouses …’
(
Interpretation Act, CQLR c I-16, s 61.1, para. 2).
defined concubinage or de facto spouses at the same time that they enacted a form of relationship
recognition open to same-sex couples (in France, the PACS (1999); in Quebec, the civil union
8
(2002)). It is as if, while same-sex relationships move ‘from “odious crime” to “gay marriage”’
(Cretney 2006), becoming ever more speakable, law must also speak henceforth of other types of
union. The dynamic character of the boundary between marriage and cohabitation is observable
in the fact that a challenge to marriage – or at least to its exclusivity as the sole civil status for
adult conjugal couples – produced developments in marriage’s outside, the field of cohabitation.
That Quebec’s definition appears outside the Civil Code, which has the vocation of establishing
and defining the basic notions of private law and social life (Brierley and Macdonald 1993, 100
at para. 87), bespeaks the drafters’ ambivalence. They could no longer ignore cohabitation, but
On the front of filiation and parenthood, French and Quebec law takes account of the
parents’ relationship or civil status. In both jurisdictions, it is easier for children born into a
marriage or a civil union to establish their filiation than for children whose parents are unmarried
(presumption of paternity; power of one parent to declare parentage for the legal spouse) (arts
525, 114 CCQ; art 312 CC). In Quebec, a person may adopt the child of his or her de facto
spouse using the streamlined process of adoption by ‘special consent’ (art 555 CCQ). By
contrast, the French Civil Code restricts adoption by more than one person to married spouses
(art 346 CC). Downstream of establishing parentage or filiation, however, both the French and
Quebec Civil Codes do not distinguish unmarried from married parents regarding the exercise of
parental authority or the obligation of child support. Marriage and filiation are thus substantially
uncoupled, although the rules mentioned here imply that legal spouses have committed ex ante to
forming a family by having children in a way that de facto spouses have not.
Both Civil Codes are not wholly silent regarding de facto spouses. Ad-hoc
acknowledgement shows the instability of the boundary between family and not-family. Where
9
an incapable person of full age has not designated a person able to consent to care on his or her
behalf, the de facto spouse may do so (art 15 CCQ; art L1111-4 CSP). Within the regimes of
obligations, the rules for residential leases grant a de facto spouse certain rights vis-à-vis a
landlord (a right to maintain occupancy where the other spouse was the lessee; a right to
terminate a lease because of domestic violence) (arts 1938, 1974.1 CCQ; Law 89-462 (6 July
1989), art 14). Law protects the rented premises in which de facto spouses dwell together less
fully than married spouses’ ‘family residence’. It distinguishes such premises, however, from the
lodging shared by strangers, burdening third-party landlords’ exercise of their contractual and
property rights.
De facto spouses’ familial character appears most undeniable on the terrain of disputes
following relationship breakdown. In such settings, judges do not accept the legislative drafters’
cue that de facto spouses are not ‘family’. For instance, judges at times speak of cohabitants’
‘family residence’, although they are not strictly speaking applying rules of family law (Leckey
2009b). Procedural law frankly acknowledges de facto spouses’ familial character. Mandatory
information sessions on mediation in family matters now reach disputes between de facto
spouses regarding property division (art 417 CCP (new); art 127 CPC). The French judge for
family matters (JAF), competent regarding married spouses’ proceedings for legal separation or
divorce, is also competent for all kinds of disputes regarding former cohabitants.
Arguably, this inconsistent treatment of de facto spouses – legal strangers one to the
other, but, for some purposes, partners or family to third parties – sets them in ‘a kind of state of
liminality, betwixt and between recognition and nonrecognition’ (Cossman 2008, 156). They are
not formally family, subject to familial rights and obligations. Their disputes are, however,
family disputes. If their dwelling is not a family residence, neither is it just any rented dwelling.
10
Cohabitants do not have a civil status as spouses, but the conjugal character of their relationship
‘flickers’ (Halley 2010, 26), coming into law’s view, sometimes. Consequently, the contours of
marriage no longer track the boundaries of the legal definition of family. Indeed, if it would be
exaggerating to say that legislative drafters have lost control of the boundaries of family, the
hybrid character of de facto spouses undercuts claims that the legal boundaries of family are
natural or historically stable. Sprinkling privileges associated with marriage on the field of
cohabitation, and doing so increasingly over time, denaturalizes the concentration of such
couple’ (McGowan 2015, 2). The contingent, shifting, and ambivalent quality of legal
justification for withholding family rights and obligations from them: their freedom to choose
This part of the paper reveals a further disjuncture between the positive law applicable to
cohabitants and the justification based on their freedom of choice. Scrutiny of the boundary
between family law and the general law of property and obligations reveals that legislative
abstinence from including cohabitants in private family law’s economic protections has not
sheltered lawyers and judges from pressure to address the fallout of unmarried intimacy. The
result is acknowledgement of family dynamics as judges apply and adapt rules conceived for
commercial parties who interact at arm’s length. Political scientists who work on judicial
behaviour note the difficulty of proving causation in relation to judicial decisions (Segal 2009).
Still, it is reasonable to connect these developments with family law’s refusal to recognize
cohabitants.
11
The basic notion is that de facto spouses – like any individuals – are subject to the
general private law of property and obligations and are free to use it to fashion suitable
arrangements. In Quebec, it is 35 years since the legislature abrogated the rule declaring
unenforceable an individual’s gift to his concubine that exceeded aliments (former art 768
CCLC). In 1999, the French Cour de cassation admitted gifts or legacies to an adulterous
cohabitant (Favier 2015, 2013, 508 at para. 142.33). In principle, contracts by which de facto
sharing, are enforceable. Quebec courts do not decline to enforce agreements on the basis that
their ‘cause’ offends public order or that they are purporting to access the benefits of marriage
covertly (Couture c Gagnon). There are severe limits on the French courts’ willingness to
enforce the clauses in cohabitation contracts addressing alimony between cohabitants and
undivided co-ownership. Notably, clauses may be unenforceable on the basis that their cause is
illicit or inexistent (Favier 2013, 506 at para. 142.17). In contrast with matrimonial conventions
or the legal rules entailed by marriage, contracts between cohabitants may not threaten or
If the ideas of choice and of cohabitants’ freedom to protect themselves by deploying the
devices of the general private law convinced judges, the latter would not adapt those devices to
the cohabitation context. Instead, in departure from the neutrality implied by cohabitants’
freedom to use the general private law, judges have acknowledged de facto union’s specificity in
to an estranged de facto spouse. Making out the conditions to demonstrate the formation of a
contract of partnership is, however, difficult (Lefebvre 2012b, 25 para 37, Morin 2008). A
division of property and of gains between cohabitants – on separation or on one partner’s death –
12
will be possible only where the claimant proves a distinctive affectio societatis (on the French
‘société créée de fait’, see Civ. 1re, January 20th 2010, 08-13.200 and 08-16.105).
The doctrinal path preferred by the Quebec Court of Appeal and the French Cour de
cassation for remedying the potential injustices arising from a de facto union is unjust
enrichment. Since 2008, the Cour de cassation has contemplated compensation for a cohabitant’s
contribution to such expenses and of any support obligation. To facilitate a former de facto
spouse’s claim in unjust enrichment, the Quebec Court of Appeal has adopted presumptions
concerning the correlation between the defendant’s enrichment and the plaintiff’s
impoverishment and concerning the absence of justification for the enrichment (Baudouin, Jobin,
and Vézina 2013, 575-576 para 585). Moreover, the Court of Appeal has also departed from the
prevailing understanding by which the lesser of the claimant’s deprivation and the respondent’s
gain caps any potential award (Leckey 2012). Quebec courts occasionally take the Canadian
common law’s notion of the ‘joint family venture’ (Kerr v Baranow) as relevant to claims in
unjust enrichment under Quebec civil law (e.g. Droit de la famille—132495). The Court of
Appeal purports to tread the fine line between recognizing the potential injustice that risks
arising from cohabitation as a known social phenomenon and respecting the legislative decision
not to attach to cohabitants any regime for sharing property (compare from England adaptation
of the law of trusts to the ‘domestic consumer context’: Stack v Dowden: para. 58; Jones v
In effect, the decision to maintain a consequential boundary between the married and the
unmarried in family law has moved or rendered porous that between family law and the general
private law of property and obligations. A family textbook’s coverage of adult couples must now
13
include elements of partnership and unjust enrichment that might once have been the exclusive
domain of books on obligations (e.g. Pineau and Pratte 2006, 566-79 at para. 383). A book on
obligations may now require material dedicated to de facto spouses (e.g. Baudouin, Jobin, and
Vézina 2013, 640-644 at paras. 551, 552). In other words, a legislative decision to preserve the
coherence and formal logic of matrimonial law based on adults’ formal consent has undermined
the coherence and formal logic of regimes in the law of obligations. Views may differ on the
tradeoff’s fairness. Significantly, though, debates of elected lawmakers on family policy do not
usually foreground the prospect of such a tradeoff. The paper’s next part takes up private law and
public law. These are not wholly separate, but different policy choices articulate their
entanglement differently.
If the preceding part reported that judges seem unpersuaded that choice justifies family
law’s sharp distinctions between marriage and cohabitation, this part suggests that the same
legislative drafters responsible for family policy in the Civil Codes seem themselves half-hearted
about the distinction. Bringing together private family law and public law on the cohabitation
question leads to a better appreciation of the variable boundary between them. It shows further
the gap between the positive law and the justification based on choice.
The point of departure is cohabitants’ different treatment under private family law and
public law. As noted, in contrast with the hands-on approach to married spouses, private family
contrast, dozens of social and fiscal laws in France and Quebec assimilate de facto spouses to
spouses by marriage or by civil union (Tétrault 2010, 854). These laws provide some benefits.
They also impose disadvantages, in a form of ‘deprivative recognition’ (Aloni 2014). For
14
example, the Quebec government reduces means-tested benefits on the assumption that de facto
spouses share resources, irrespective of whether they do so. Moreover, if the government
overpays benefits to one partner, both are jointly and severally liable for repayment. The
presumption of pooled resources is irrebuttable. That is, individuals may challenge their
characterization as de facto spouses, but once recognized as such, they cannot rebut the
presumption that they pool resources. The French tax system assimilates concubins to married
spouses for taxing income and wealth. For cohabitants, such treatment is a clear disadvantage
(Favier 2013, 510 at para. 142.51, see further Douet 2013). The justification for these public
regimes recognizing cohabitants, in a way over which they have no control, cannot be that they
are free to choose to marry. It may be that the decision to live together represents a legally
significant choice, but private family law does not see conduct as such.
Public law and private family law pursue, then, distinct approaches in their treatment of
cohabitants. Under public law, cohabitants form an economic unit. Under private law, they are
individuals who potentially negotiate and contract with one another at arm’s length. This
difference need not be intrinsically problematic, although common lawyers may tolerate better
across the legal system (Legrand and Samuel 2008, 64-68). The point is not just that public law
and private law define family or spouses differently. It is that the question of marriage and
cohabitation illuminates the variable character of the boundary between public law and private
law.
It is no coincidence that the public law and private law share an approach to married
chronology, the public law’s approach followed the private law’s recognition of familial
15
obligation. The private law of the family has historically imposed economic obligations within
marriage – until fairly recently, gendered ones, centred on the husband’s duty to support his wife
and hers to submit to his authority. The welfare state’s panoply of benefits, exemptions, credits,
and deductions developed later. The legal curriculum and librarians’ catalogues separate public
from private law (Millard 1995). On marriage, though, they have a relationship of reciprocal
support. The justification for public law’s spousal benefits may be that the performance of the
private law’s spousal obligations increases overall utility. The justification for public law’s
spousal disadvantages may be the resource sharing and economies of scale under the private law
of marriage. Still, the approach of each is more compelling in the other’s light.
By contrast, on the cohabitation question, public law and private law present opposing
views. Together, public law’s recognition of de facto spouses and private law’s abstinence from
doing so potentially cause confusion and produce injustices (Belleau 2015, Leckey 2014).
Crucially, the boundary between public law and private law does not keep them separate. As the
geographic literature presaged, this boundary or process of bordering is a political one involving
marriage and cohabitation differently. Public law’s recognition of de facto spouses undermines
the persuasiveness of private law’s justification for refusing to do so. Furthermore, public law’s
recognition dilutes the distinctiveness of marriage as the locus of legally cognizable economic
interdependence and solidarity. Next, we turn to the boundary between law and politics in the
Given the prominence of critical approaches by which law and politics are inseparable
and the project of human rights is inevitably a political enterprise, it is necessary to clarify our
contention. Despite litigants’ efforts, principles of human rights have not invalidated the sharp
16
difference in treatment of married and unmarried couples under the family law of France and
legislature’s policy on cohabitation. The judgments hint at sensitivity to this question’s political
stakes. It is not simply that politics infuses the process of rights adjudication. Rather, at the
crossroads of changing social practice and attitudes, family policy, and fundamental rights,
and same-sex couples. The justificatory factor of choice mediates this difference – and here
The Supreme Court of Canada’s treatment of the cohabitation question from Quebec
foregrounds the thorny matter of choice. Quebec (Attorney General) v A was a challenge to the
exclusion of de facto spouses from the provisions applicable to spouses by marriage and civil
union. The claim arose under the equality guarantee in section 15(1) of the Canadian Charter of
Rights and Freedoms. Nearly two decades earlier, the Supreme Court of Canada had recognized
marital status as a suspect ground ‘analogous’ to those listed in the equality guarantee, on the
basis that individuals will not always have effective control over their marital status. The Court
found unjustifiable discrimination where legislation imposing the terms of standard insurance
contracts withheld indemnities from unmarried partners (Miron v Trudel). In the 2013 judgment,
a narrow majority upheld the restrictive reach of Quebec’s matrimonial law. Four judges found
no discrimination. Five judges concluded that all the elements of the marriage regime were
discriminatory, excluding cohabitants who might not meaningfully have chosen their marital
status. Of those five, however, only one judge viewed all the discrimination as unjustifiable.
Three others thought it justifiable to exclude de facto spouses from the division of matrimonial
property, but not from the support obligation. The fifth judge saw the discrimination as
17
justifiable, on the basis that a legislature might validly promote autonomy and choice. She
referred to the values of federalism and the exclusive legislative competence of the province,
political matters not normally relevant to the proportionality of limits on rights. Her discussion
nodded to Quebec’s distinctiveness within the Canadian federation. In the background hovered
In the case of France, the Court of Justice of the EU and the European Court of Human
Rights (ECtHR) have shown the same hesitation when considering whether discrimination based
on marital status is unjustifiable. For European judges, the legislature may confer a special status
on marriage or registration and withhold that status from de facto types of cohabitation. The
basis is that marriage confers a special status on those who enter into it and Article 12 of the
European Convention on Human Rights protects the right to marry. Accordingly, marriage ‘gives
rise to social, personal and legal consequences’, as said about spousal testimonial privilege (Van
der Heijden v. Netherlands: para. 69). Both French appellate courts and the ECtHR have
France).2 In general, the European jurisprudence grants states a wide ‘margin of appreciation’
regarding the question of the equality of treatment of married and unmarried couples and the
right to protection of one’s private and family life. That is, the courts tolerate a range of
legislative policies that distinguish unmarried from married couples, preserving legal
‘differences in otherwise similar situations’ (Schalk and Kopf v. Austria: para. 96).
2
For French higher courts, see Cour de cassation Civ. 2ème, 5 mars 2008, pourvoi n° 08-60.232 and Conseil
constitutionnel DC n° 2011-155 QPC du 29 juill. 2011; Conseil d’État déc. 6th 2006, 06-12-2006, rec. 262096. The
position of the European (EU’s) Court of Justice is more nuanced: see 10 May 2011, Römer c/ Freie und hansestadt
hamburg, C- 147/08, D. 2011. 1485; 1 April 2008, n° C-267/06, Versorgungsanstalt der deutschen Bühnen cases.
18
The contrast that makes this hesitation to override legislative policy so interesting arises
from the rights challenges raised by same-sex couples. Canadian courts concluded in the early
2000s that denying same-sex couples access to marriage was unjustifiably discriminatory. Gay
men and lesbians are not gay by choice – we are ventriloquizing, not endorsing this argument
(Halley 1994) – and thus they, unlike unmarried cohabitants, did not have the ‘choice’ and
‘freedom’ to marry (compare Osterlund 2009). The Grand Chamber of the European Court of
Human Rights has concluded that Greece’s domestic civil partnership, restricted to different-sex
disproportionately limited gay men and lesbians’ enjoyment of the right to personal and family
life (Vallianatos and Others v Greece) (Trispiotis 2014, Johnson 2015). More recently, the
European Court of Human Rights has concluded that Italy must adopt some kind of law allowing
same-sex couples to register their relationships. Doing nothing is no longer an option (Oliari &
Others v Italy). The Court has not found a positive state duty to recognize same-sex marriage,
although it has enlarged its concept of ‘family’ (for careful critique, see Ammaturo 2014). Still,
the conclusions on same-sex couples challenge national legislative policy on marriage more
cohabitation question than the marriage question. The courts are not, then, deferring to
(Krause 2006, 1101). Granted, as judicial upshots, deferring more and deferring less may be
equally ‘political’. Nevertheless, they gesture towards differently located boundaries between
human rights and legislative policy. A mediating factor is choice: absent judicial or legislative
action, same-sex couples had no ‘choice’ to attain a formal relationship status. Unmarried
19
cohabitants – so the reasoning goes – may marry if they (both) so choose. These differing
approaches to the fundamental rights of cohabitants and same-sex couples make evident the
shifting boundary between law and politics. Furthermore, the finding of discrimination in the
choice.
evidence of the constructed character of major organizing boundaries for law and of indirect,
informal changes to marriage’s position as sole authorized form of legitimate conjugal life. We
have also highlighted the gap between legislative and judicial acknowledgements of cohabitation
and the private law’s justification for not doing so, namely, cohabitants’ choice to marry and
their freedom to make law for themselves. In this part, deepening the paper’s interest for
comparatists, we focus on the civil law tradition (Glenn 2014), specifically on the narrow
interpretation of its resources that underwrites legal discourse on cohabitation in France and
Quebec.
The focus on cohabitants’ freedom to devise a regime for themselves using contract is
resilient. In France, from the mid-1980s through the 1990s, proposals circulated for variably
named and structured contracts that would regulate cohabitants’ private relations, producing no
third-party effects (Mayaux 1986) (Granet Juris-classeur code civil art 515-8 (2010), §2.).
However, this purely private-law contract seemed not to respond to a genuine social demand. It
is another type of contract – a partnership contract producing a genuine couple status, with third-
party effects, with default content so that parties need not negotiate from scratch – that has found
significant uptake. We refer to the PACS, created with same-sex couples in mind, but which
20
different-sex couples have taken up to the point that it is giving marriage a run for its money.
Thirty years after proposals for cohabitant contracts in France, a committee mandated by the
protecting the couple as a space for autonomy of the will and contractual freedom and an
facto union, including mention of the possibility of opting into elements of marriage law, would
Our primary aim is not to criticize the repeated emphasis on cohabitation contracts as
policy. There are certainly bases for doing so. In Quebec, Moore has observed that on the
cohabitation question it is odd to rely on a vision of autonomy that ‘everywhere in the law of
contract, is today seen as archaic and fantastic’ (2010, 109 [authors’ translation]). France and
Quebec seem similar enough that, without good reason to expect different results, the reform
committee’s proposal in 2015 looks more aspirational than realistic. The idea that adding
cohabitation contracts to the Civil Code will radically alter social practice might exemplify civil
lawyers’ reverence for the Civil Code as ‘sacred Text’ (Legrand 1995, 333). The whimsical
particular interpretation of the civil-law tradition. This approach stitches together three elements
3
Space constraints preclude doing justice to the subtlety of the committee’s 800-page report, which proposes a
mandatory parental regime for a child’s legal parents (Comité consultatif sur le droit de la famille 2015, 93-136).
The committee recommended extending to cohabitants the current marriage law’s compensatory allowance, a
discretionary mechanism based on principles of unjust enrichment. Doing so would relieve judges from the pressure
of unjust enrichment claims from cohabitants under the law of obligations. The committee indicates that such a
reform would be consistent with the committee’s principle of respecting adult autonomy and contractual freedom,
on the basis that this equitable remedial measure, unlike other mechanisms of family law, does not depend on
mutual consent (Comité consultatif sur le droit de la famille 2015, 151-152).
21
around the idea of cohabitants as legal strangers. One, philosophical, is a robust emphasis on
freedom of choice, which takes the absence of legal impediment as the guarantee of genuine
freedom. Another, instrumental, is a reliance on contract as the device par excellence by which
free legal subjects modify their legal situation. This element draws force from a cultural
touchstone of French civil law, the Civil Code’s declaration that ‘[a]greements lawfully entered
into take the place of the law for those who have made them’ (art 1134 CC, Legifrance, trad. by
undertaking is knowable solely by formal means. That is, only the formal ‘juridical acts’ – in the
civil law, manifestations of intention in a manner and form designed to legal effects (Quebec
Research Centre of Private & Comparative Law 2003, 162) – of marriage and contract signal
This focus on formal means as the legally relevant expressions of choice and consent
interprets cohabitation as an affirmative choice not to marry and, thus, to remain outside marital
rights and obligations. From the facts of an ongoing cohabitation union without a contract, it
highlights the potentially weaker partner’s choice to remain in the relationship despite a
precarious position. It erases the potentially stronger partner’s tacit choice to stay in the
partner’s part. The key point is not, then, the focus on consent to obligation. It is the decision to
take only a narrow set of formal actions as signalling choices and consent, thus precluding
attention to ‘juridical facts’, occurrences that produce legal consequences (Quebec Research
Centre of Private & Comparative Law 2003, 162). This cramped approach limits the thinkable
possibilities, including the ways of characterizing cohabitants and options for modifying the law.
Cohabitation is not the only question on which the confines of rigid reliance on binary categories
22
and a repudiation of grey zones are discernible (see e.g., on the boundary between French
In some jurisdictions where scholars reiterate it, this tripartite approach is unconvincing
in the light of the positive law. The legislative drafters who detect in cohabitation a legally
legible relational commitment relevant to social security and taxation do not hold to this
approach. Nor do those who assimilate cohabitants’ rented dwellings to those of married spouses
or characterize cohabitants’ disputes as familial for procedural purposes. Nor, again, do judges
who have eased cohabitants’ path to claims in unjust enrichment. Admittedly, conservative
civilians toeing the hardest line might fall back on the distinction between public law and private
law to reject the pertinence of these examples involving legislative drafters. They might also
The approach combining choice, contract, and formal expressions of commitment results
from a reading of the civil-law tradition that is partial in both senses. A subtler reading of the
resources of the civil tradition nuances the picture. The twentieth century saw the adoption of
freedom of contract. Moreover, devices – in the law of obligations, good faith in extra-
contractual dealings, the undeclared partnership, and implied mandate; in family law,
relations beyond formal acts. Expunging such complicating elements violently simplifies the
civil tradition. In a comparatist’s trenchant words, ‘[e]legance, far from being a mere ornament
that would be superimposed on legal reasoning, is that reasoning itself’; indeed, he continues, it
is the ‘visible side of the logical rigour that is understood by civilians to define legal rationality’
(Legrand 1995, 336 [footnote omitted]). In a dazzling example of the phenomenon, Quebec’s
23
reform committee arrived at policy recommendations on cohabitation – autonomy of the will and
contract – which are the very premises that framed its inquiry. A number of policy outcomes are
presenting as policy a set of factors that, ‘at the level of mentalité … mould the structures of
thought legal actors use to interpret and understand the social world around them and their own
location within it’ (Legrand 1995, 311). Perhaps cohabitation in France and Quebec offers,
CONCLUSION
Insights from critical literature on boundaries and law reform highlight the contingency
and permeability of several major boundaries around marriage and cohabitation. Categories and
their legal significance shift even in the face of ostensible legislative inaction. Thus a
‘conservative’ approach to marriage and cohabitation has not wholly ‘conserved’ marriage in
Quebec and France. Even if obvious to a stripe of critical reader, our reminder of the facticity of
legal boundaries has political valence. Conservative scholars, especially in the civil tradition,
continue to take boundaries as ‘closure’ and justifications for the status quo (Bourdieu 1987,
834), rather than as contestable distributions of power and privilege. Thus the institutional
character of marriage is its own justification. For them, it self-evidently justifies the intense,
undertaking or obligation on the part of those in the mere factual situation of cohabitation. But
the prevailing justification based on choice fails to discipline the ensemble of legal measures
affecting cohabitants. Even as it undergoes repetition, it is plain that the faith of some legal
This paper diagnoses legal discourse in France and Quebec as symptomatic of a reductive
view of the civil tradition, one that emphasizes the role of choice, contract, and formal
causes must await another day. Even if Quebec’s minority location and the links often posited
between an ostensibly distinctive culture and the civil tradition (and the French language) might
predictably foment monolithic simplifications in the service of easier preservation, such factors
ought not to apply in France. It is obvious that legislatures may recognize cohabitants differently
from jurisdiction to jurisdiction (compare Sutherland 2013, Tobin 2013). What is less obvious is
the call, modelled by this paper, to understand legislative inaction as a site for fruitful
comparative inquiry. In other jurisdictions where reform has stalled, such as England and Wales,
culturally minded legal scholars should not hesitate, then, to take the baton from their
disappointed and more instrumental, policy-oriented colleagues. They might then draw out the
CASES CITED
Oliari & Others v Italy Applications Nos 18766/11 & 36030/11, 21 July 2015.
Schalk and Kopf v. Austria, App. No. 30141/04, Merits, 24 June 2010, ECtHR.
Vallianatos and Others v Greece, Application Nos 29381/09 32684/09, Merits, 7 November
2013.
Van der Heijden v. Netherlands, App. No. 42857/05, Apr. 3, 2012, ECtHR (G. Ch.).
REFERENCES
Favier, Yann. 2015. Rupture du couple: effets patrimoniaux: divorce et séparation, rupture de
PACS et de concubinage. Paris: Ellipses.
Flauss, Jean-François. 2005. "La présence de la jurisprudence de la Cour suprême des Etats-Unis
d'Amérique dans le contentieux européen des droits de l'homme." Revue trimestrielle des
droits de l'homme 62:313-331.
Glenn, H. Patrick. 2014. Legal traditions of the world: sustainable diversity in law. 5th ed.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Goubau, Dominique. 1995. "Le Code Civil du Quebec et les concubins: un mariage discret."
Canadian Bar Review 74 (3):474-483.
Halley, Janet. 2010. "Behind the Law of Marriage (I): From status/contract to the marriage
system." Unbound: Harvard Journal of the Legal Left 6 (1):1-58.
Halley, Janet E. 1993. "The Construction of Heterosexuality." In Fear of a Queer Planet: Queer
Politics and Social Theory, edited by Michael Warner, 82-102. Minneapolis: University
of Minnesota Press.
Halley, Janet E. 1994. "Sexual Orientation and the Politics of Biology: A Critique of the
Argument from Immutability." Stanford Law Review 46 (3):503-568. doi:
10.2307/1229101.
Halley, Janet, and Kerry Rittich. 2010. "Critical Directions in Comparative Family Law:
Genealogies and Contemporary Studies of Family Law Exceptionalism." American
Journal of Comparative Law 58 (4):753-776.
Hauser, Jean. 2005. "Les principes constitutionnels et le couple en droit français." In La
Constitution et les valeurs: Mélanges en l'honneur de Dmitri Georges Lavroff, 203-217.
Paris: Dalloz.
Johnson, Paul. 2015. "Marriage, Heteronormativity, and the European Court of Human Rights: A
Reappraisal." International Journal of Law, Policy and the Family 29 (1):56-77.
Kolossov, Vladimir. 2005. "Border Studies: Changing Perspectives and Theoretical
Approaches." Geopolitics 10 (4):606-632.
Krause, Harry D. 2006. "Comparative Family Law: Past Traditions Battle Future Trends - and
Vice Versa." In The Oxford Handbook of Comparative Law, edited by Mathias Reimann
and Reinhard Zimmermann, 1099-1129. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Leckey, Robert. 2009a. "Cohabitation and comparative method." Modern Law Review 72
(1):48-72.
Leckey, Robert. 2009b. "Family outside the book on the family." Canadian Bar Review 88
(3):545-578.
Leckey, Robert. 2011. "Law Reform, Lesbian Parenting, and the Reflective Claim." Social &
Legal Studies 20 (3):331-348.
Leckey, Robert. 2012. "Unjust enrichment and de facto spouses." Revue du Notariat 112
(3):475-500.
Leckey, Robert. 2014. "Strange Bedfellows." University of Toronto Law Journal 64 (5):641-
668.
Lefebvre, Brigitte. 2012a. "L'union de fait: enjeux de l'encadrement dans un contexte
successoral." In Conjugalités et discriminations, edited by Alain-Charles Van Gysel, 105-
117. Place Albert: Anthemis.
Lefebvre, Brigitte. 2012b. "Union de fait." In JurisClasseur Québec: Personnes et famille, edited
by Pierre-Claude Lafond. LexisNexis.
27
Legrand, Pierre. 1995. "Antiqui juris civilis fabulas." University of Toronto Law Journal 45
(3):311-362.
Legrand, Pierre, and Geoffrey Samuel. 2008. Introduction au common law. Paris: La
Découverte.
Macdonald, Roderick A. 2007. "Unitary law re-form, pluralistic law re-substance: illuminating
legal change." Louisiana Law Review 67 (4):1113-1160.
Macdonald, Roderick A., and Hoi Kong. 2006. "Patchwork law reform: your idea is good in
practice, but it won't work in theory." Osgoode Hall Law Journal 44 (1):11-52.
Marty, Gabriel, and Pierre Raynaud. 1956. Droit civil. Vol. I. Paris: Sirey.
Mayaux, Luc. 1986. "Les contrats des concubins." In Les concubinages: Approche socio-
juridique, edited by Jacqueline Rubellin-Devichi, 25-54. Paris: Editions du CNRS.
McGowan, Deirdre. 2015. "Governed by marriage law: An Irish genealogy." Social & Legal
Studies.
Millard, Eric. 1995. Famille et droit public: recherches sur la construction d'un objet juridique.
Paris: L.G.D.J.
Moore, Benoît. 2010. "Variations chromatiques: l’union de fait entre noir et blanc." In Mélanges
Adrian Popovici: Les couleurs du droit, edited by Générosa Bras Miranda and Benoît
Moore, 97-124. Montreal: Thémis.
Moréteau, Olivier. 2011. "France." In European Tort Law 2010, edited by Helmut Koziol and
Barbara C. Steininger, 179-199. Berlin: De Gruyter.
Morin, Christine. 2008. "La société tacite: quand les affaires se conjuguent avec l’amour."
Revue du Notariat 110 (3):825-839.
NeJaime, Douglas. 2014. "Before marriage: the unexplored history of nonmarital recognition and
its relationship to marriage." California Law Review 102 (1):87-172.
Newman, David. 2003. "On borders and power: A theoretical framework." Journal of
Borderlands Studies 18 (1):13-25.
Newman, David. 2006. "The lines that continue to separate us: Borders in our "borderless"
world." Progress in Human Geography 30 (2):143-161.
Newman, David. 2010. "Territory, Compartments and Borders: Avoiding the Trap of the
Territorial Trap." Geopolitics 15 (4):773-778.
Newman, David, and Anssi Paasi. 1998. "Fences and neighbours in the postmodern world:
Boundary narratives in political geography." Progress in Human Geography 22 (2):186-
207.
Nicolas-Maguin, Marie-France. 2009. "La formation du couple: entre libertés et contraintes." In
Mélanges en l'honneur du Professeur Gilles Goubeaux, edited by Olivier Cachard and
Xavier Henry, 385-396. Paris: Dalloz & L.G.D.J.
Noreau, Pierre. 1999. "Notions juridiques et réalité sociale: un éternel divorce ou un divorce
nécessaire? - le cas du droit de la famille." Revue Juridique Themis 33 (2):307-325.
Osterlund, Katherine. 2009. "Love, Freedom And Governance: Same-Sex Marriage In Canada."
Social & Legal Studies 18 (1):93-109.
Pineau, Jean, and Marie Pratte. 2006. La famille. Montreal: Thémis.
Probert, Rebecca. 2007. "Equality in the family home?" Feminist Legal Studies 15 (3):341-353.
Quebec Research Centre of Private and Comparative Law. 2003. Private law dictionary and
bilingual lexicons: obligations. Cowansville, QC: Yvon Blais.
Reece, Helen. 2015. "Leaping without Looking." In After Legal Equality: Family, Sex, Kinship,
edited by Robert Leckey, 115-133. Abingdon, UK: Routledge.
28
Roy, Alain. 2010. "L'union de fait en droit français et belge: une politique législative aux
antipodes du droit québécois." In Mélanges Adrian Popovici. Les couleurs du droit,
edited by Benoît Moore and Générosa Bras Miranda, 143-170. Montreal: Thémis.
Sarat, Austin, Marianne Constable, David Engel, Valerie Hans, and Susan Lawrence, eds. 1998.
Crossing boundaries: traditions and transformations in law and society research.
Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.
Sedgwick, Eve Kosofsky. 2008. Epistemology of the Closet. Revised ed. Berkeley: University of
California Press.
Segal, Jeffrey A. 2009. "Judicial Behavior." In The Oxford Handbook of Political Science, edited
by Robert E. Goodin, 275-288. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sutherland, Elaine E. 2013. "From ‘Bidie-in’ to ‘Cohabitant’ in Scotland: The Perils of
Legislative Compromise." International Journal of Law, Policy and the Family 27
(2):143-175.
Tétrault, Michel. 2010. Droit de la famille: Le mariage, l'union civile et les conjoints de fait:
Droits, obligations et conséquences pour la rupture. 4th ed. 4 vols. Vol. 1. Cowansville,
QC: Yvon Blais.
Tobin, Brian. 2013. "The regulation of cohabitation in Ireland: achieving equilibrium between
protection and paternalism?" Journal of Social Welfare and Family Law 35 (3):279-289.
Tremblay, Régine. 2015. "Sans foi ni loi: Appearances of conjugality and lawless love." In Les
apparences en droit civil, edited by Anne-Sophie Hulin, Robert Leckey and Lionel
Smith, 155-191. Cowansville, QC: Yvon Blais.
Trispiotis, Ilias. 2014. "Discrimination and civil partnerships: taking 'legal' out of the legal
recognition." Human Rights Law Review 14 (2):343-358.
van Houtum, Henk, and Ton van Naerssen. 2002. "Bordering, ordering and othering."
Tijdschrift voor Economische en Sociale Geografie 93 (2):125-136.
Warner, Michael. 2000. The trouble with normal: sex, politics, and the ethics of queer life.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Woehrling, José. 2013. "La Charte canadienne des droits et libertés et ses répercussions sur la
vie politique." In Le parlementarisme canadien, edited by Réjean Pelletier and Manon
Tremblay, 89-126. Québec: Presses de l'Université Laval.