Nobelprize 2002 PDF
Nobelprize 2002 PDF
Nobelprize 2002 PDF
Until recently, economics was widely regarded as a non-experimental science that had to rely
on observation of real-world economies rather than controlled laboratory experiments. Many
commentators also found restrictive the common assumption of a homo oeconomicus
motivated by self-interest and capable of making rational decisions. But research in
economics has taken off in new directions. A large and growing body of scientific work is
now devoted to the empirical testing and modification of traditional postulates in economics,
in particular those of unbounded rationality, pure self-interest, and complete self-control.
Moreover, today’s research increasingly relies on new data from laboratory experiments
rather than on more traditional field data, that is, data obtained from observations of real
economies. This recent research has its roots in two distinct, but converging, traditions:
theoretical and empirical studies of human decision-making in cognitive psychology, and tests
of predictions from economic theory by way of laboratory experiments. Today, behavioral
economics and experimental economics are among the most active fields in economics, as
measured by publications in major journals, new doctoral dissertations, seminars, workshops
and conferences. This year’s laureates are pioneers of these two fields of research.
Human decision-making deviates in one way or another from the standard assumptions of the
rationalistic paradigm in economics. If such deviations from rationality and self-interest were
small and purely idiosyncratic, they would on average cancel out, and economic theory would
not be too wide off the mark when predicting outcomes for large aggregates of agents.
Following the lead of Vernon Smith, early studies of alternative market mechanisms by
experimental economists can be viewed as tests of the hypothesis of idiosyncratic deviations
from standard economic theory. If deviations from rationality and self-interest were
systematic, however, this would call for a revision of economic theory itself. Following the
lead of Daniel Kahneman and the late Amos Tversky, early studies of human decision-making
by cognitive psychologists can be seen as testing hypotheses of systematic deviations from
rationality.
This text begins by addressing Vernon Smith’s contributions to the field of experimental
economics. It then considers Daniel Kahneman’s findings in the field now known as
behavioral economics. The final sections summarize these contributions and their
importance, and offer some suggestions for further reading.
Traditionally, economics has been viewed as a non-experimental science that had to rely
exclusively on field data:
The establishment of a growing research field called experimental economics has radically
challenged this view.1 Under controlled laboratory conditions, experimentalists study human
behavior in situations that, in simplified and pure forms, mimic those encountered in markets
2
and other forms of economic interaction. The extent to which the results of such experiments
can be generalized to market situations is still under debate. But the notion that laboratory
results concerning microeconomic behavior can crucially inform the development of
economic theory is basically the same as the notion that laboratory results concerning small-
scale phenomena in physics (such as those pertaining to elementary particles and
thermodynamics) can crucially inform the development of theoretical physics (with regard to
the universe or the weather). 2
Experimental research in economics has early predecessors. More than fifty years ago,
Chamberlin (1948) attempted to test the neoclassical theory of perfect competition by way of
experiments, and 1994 economics laureate Reinhard Selten conducted early experimental
studies of price formation in oligopoly markets, the first paper being Sauerman and Selten
(1959). There are also early studies on the predictive power of game theory in an
experimental setting, by John Nash – also a 1994 economics laureate – with colleagues
(Kalish, Milnor, Nash and Nehrig, 1954) and by Flood (1959). Furthermore Siegel and
Fouraker (1960) and Fouraker and Siegel (1963) reported experimental results on bargaining.
Without any doubt, however, the main researcher in the experimental tradition is Vernon
Smith. Smith not only made the most important early contributions, but has also remained a
key figure in the field to date. He has educated and collaborated with a large number of
younger researchers in experimental economics. The most prominent of these is Charles
Plott, who has also made important contributions to the field.
1
New panel data sets and advancements in econometrics, such as those recognized in the awards to Heckman
and Mc Fadden in 2000, have also substantially improved the potential for convincing causal inference from
observational data.
2
External validity requires that the results uncovered in the laboratory be valid across time and space. This may
be a stronger assumption in economics than in meteorology or astrophysics, but theories about the atmosphere or
the big bang that build on experimental results also have to resort to the same kind of assumption.
3
1.1. Market mechanisms
Vernon Smith’s most significant work concerns market mechanisms. He laid the groundwork
for this research area in innovative experiments with competitive markets (Smith, 1962), in
tests of different auction forms (Smith, 1965, 1976b, Coppinger, Smith and Titus, 1980), and
in the design of the so-called induced-value method (Smith, 1976a).
Smith’s first experimental article (Smith, 1962) was inspired by Chamberlin’s (1948)
classroom experiments. Chamberlin, who was Smith’s teacher at Harvard at the time, had let
participants engage in pairwise bargaining, acting as buyers and sellers of a fictitious good.
Chamberlin regarded his experimental results as a falsification of the standard neoclassical
model of a market under perfect competition (that is, with price-taking and rational agents).
Smith realized that Chamberlin’s results would be more compelling if the participants were
placed in a setting more similar to a real market. He thus set up an experiment where subjects
were divided into groups of potential sellers and buyers in a so-called double oral auction, a
market mechanism used in many financial and commodity markets. Subjects were randomly
assigned the roles of seller and buyer, and each seller was given one unit of the good to be
sold, and a reservation price for this unit. If the reservation price was v for the unit, the
seller was not allowed to sell below that price, while she would earn p–v dollars by selling at
a price p>v. A seller’s reservation price v was her own private information. Similarly, each
buyer was assigned a private reservation price w, the highest price at which he was allowed to
buy a unit. Purchases at a price p<w resulted in earnings of w-p dollars. Based on the
distribution of reservation prices which he had chosen, Smith could draw a supply and a
demand schedule and locate the competitive equilibrium price as their intersection. The
subjects, by contrast, did not have this information and were thus not able to compute the
theoretical equilibrium price. Much to his surprise, Smith found that the actual trading prices
came close to the theoretical equilibrium price, hence supporting the theory that the
experiments were initially supposed to reject.
The result from one of his experiments is illustrated in Figure 1 (Smith, 1962, Chart 1, p.
113). The left-hand panel shows the demand and supply schedules induced by the given
distribution of reservation prices. The schedules intersect at p = 2.00, which is thus the
competitive equilibrium price. The right-hand panel shows the trading prices in five
4
successive trading periods, as well as the standard deviation of the price distribution in each
period, expressed as a percentage of the theoretical equilibrium price (the number α in the
diagram). As is seen in this diagram, most trading prices were close to the theoretical
prediction, and the standard deviation fell over time as the prices converged towards the
theoretical prediction.
Figure 1
Smith concluded that
“…there are strong tendencies for a … competitive equilibrium to be
attained as long as one is able to prohibit collusion and to maintain
absolute publicity of all bids, offers, and transactions. … Changes in
the conditions of supply and demand cause changes in the volume of
transaction per period and the general level of contract prices. These
latter correspond reasonably well with the predictions of competitive
price theory.” (Smith, 1962, p. 134).
Smith and other researchers subsequently carried out a series of similar experiments to check
whether this agreement with theory was a mere coincidence. Later experiments continued to
confirm Smith’s original result. In joint work, Plott and Smith (1978) obtained the same
general result, but added an important twist: market institutions do “matter.” Specifically,
5
they compared the outcomes when sellers and buyers were allowed to change prices
continuously during a trading period (Smith’s original design) with the outcomes when they
had to post a price for an entire trading period. The latter design turned out to result in a
slower convergence towards the theoretical equilibrium price. The experimental approach, as
opposed to collecting field data, was essential in driving home this result; it made it possible
to hold constant the “market environment” (in this case the distribution of reservation prices)
while varying the “market institution” (in this case the rules for price adjustment) in a
controlled fashion.
In almost any market experiment, a clear test of the hypothesis in question requires
controlling for the subjects’ preferences. This is a major difficulty, as selling and buying will
generally be influenced by the subjects’ idiosyncratic evaluations of gains and losses,
evaluations that are not directly observable to the researcher. This problem was first
addressed by Chamberlin (1948), who suggested a method for resolving it, essentially by
providing the subjects with the “right” monetary incentives. This so-called induced-value
method was developed further by Smith (1976a) 3, and has now become a standard tool in
experimental economics.
In order to illustrate this method, consider a subject assigned the role of buyer in a market for
a homogeneous good (where all units are identical). Suppose that the experimentalist wants
this subject to express a certain demand function D . That is, at any price p , the subject
should be willing to buy precisely q = D(p) units. But the experimentalist does not know the
subject’s utility of wealth, u(w). Smith’s method induces the desired demand function by
rewarding the subject with R(q) - pq dollars for any quantity q bought at price p , where R
is a suitably chosen reward function. According to economic theory, the subject will choose
the quantity q such that her marginal benefit from increasing q equals her marginal cost of
doing so, that is, such that R′(q) = p.4 As long as the unknown utility function u is
increasing and concave, her demand will coincide with the desired demand function if, for
any relevant price, the inverse derivative of the reward function R is set equal to the desired
demand function, that is, if (R′)–1(p) = D(p) for all relevant prices p. Similar methods have
been applied ever since in the experimental literature.
3
Smith had sketched this method in an earlier working paper (Smith, 1973).
4
If the quantity q maximizes the subject’s utility of wealth, u(R(q)-pq), then the first-order condition
6
1.2. Tests of auction theory
Auction theory has emerged as one of the most successful developments in microeconomic
theory and game theory since the early 1960s. A number of precise theoretical results for a
variety of auction forms were developed by the late economics laureate William Vickrey,
followed by a number of younger researchers (see Krishna, 2002, for an overview). Smith
initiated the experimental testing of many of these propositions, and has published extensively
on the subject (see, for example, Smith, 1976b, Coppinger, Smith and Titus, 1980, and Cox,
Robertson and Smith, 1982). Moreover, he pioneered the use of controlled laboratory
experiments as “wind tunnel” tests of new auction designs – for which precise theoretical
predictions are hard to obtain – before they are used in practice (see section 1.3).
As the term is commonly understood, auctions may seem of little importance for real-world
economies. However, by proceeding from simpler to more complex auction forms, theory has
deepened our understanding of the functioning of many real-world markets. Even some of the
simpler auction forms studied in theory are widely used in practice, particularly in the context
of deregulation and privatization of natural monopolies, public procurement, the sale of
government bonds, etc.
Central to Smith’s experimental work on auctions are the established theoretical predictions
for certain auction forms used in the sale of a single object. Such auctions are traditionally
classified into four types. In an English or ascending auction, buyers announce their bids
sequentially and in an increasing order, until no higher bid is submitted. In a Dutch or
descending auction, a high initial bid by the seller is gradually lowered in fixed steps at fixed
times regulated by a clock, until some buyer shouts “buy,” whereupon the clock stops. Both
of these auctions are usually oral, and the trading price is the last (first) bidder’s bid. In the
other two auction forms, all bidders instead simultaneously submit their bids in sealed
envelopes and the unit for sale is allocated to the highest bidder. In the first-price sealed-bid
auction, this bidder pays his or her bid to the seller; while in the second-price sealed-bid
auction, this bidder pays only the second highest bid.
Microeconomic theory also distinguishes between auctions with private and common values.
In both cases, the value to each buyer is treated as a random variable. In the case of private
7
values, these valuations are statistically independent across the population of potential bidders
– the value to a buyer is his or her purely idiosyncratic valuation of the object. In common-
value auctions, by contrast, the value to the buyers also has a common component, such as a
resale market value or the conditions in some related market (examples include spectrum
auctions and telecommunication markets).
Economic theory makes the following three predictions in the case of private values: (1)
English and second-price auctions are equivalent, in terms of who will (probabilistically)
obtain the item and the expected revenue to the seller. This result follows from individual
rationality (more precisely, from assuming that bidders do not use weakly dominated
strategies). (2) Dutch and first-price auctions are equivalent, a result which follows from the
more restrictive assumption of Nash equilibrium behavior, that is, individual rationality
combined with interpersonally consistent expectations. (3) All four auction forms are
equivalent if all buyers are risk neutral (that is, if they are indifferent between participating in
an actuarially fair lottery and obtaining the expected lottery prize for sure; see also section 2).
Smith carried out many experiments – once more, controlling for demand and supply
conditions, while varying the market institution – in order to empirically test these and other
theoretical predictions.5 In order to generate private values, each bidder was given a
randomly and independently drawn number, v, which was kept private to the bidder. If the
bidder won the auction and paid the price p, this subject would earn the monetary amount p–
v. In regard to prediction (1) above, Smith discovered that English and sealed-bid second-
price auctions indeed produce similar experimental outcomes, just as theory says. As for (2),
Dutch and sealed-price first-price auctions did not give rise to equivalent outcomes, in
contrast with theory. In the case of (3), he found that models which presume that buyers have
identical attitudes toward risk could be rejected. Furthermore, he found that the average sale
price was higher in English and sealed-bid second-price auctions than in sealed-bid first-price
auctions, and that the latter yielded higher average selling prices than Dutch auctions.
Of these results, one of the most unexpected was that Dutch and sealed-bid first-price auctions
turned out to be unequivalent. Two theoretical explanations have been suggested. One is that
utility depends not only on the monetary outcome but also on the “suspense of waiting” in the
8
Dutch auction, the other that bidders underestimate the increased risk associated with waiting
in the Dutch auction. These and other possible reasons for the observed non-equivalence
between the two auctions are explored in Smith (1991b).
The experimental method developed by Smith deviates from the experimental approach used
in psychology (cf. section 2). It emphasizes the importance of providing subjects with
sufficient monetary incentives, in order to outweigh the distorting effects of decision costs.
5
Smith (1976b) is a seminal paper on this topic. See also Coppinger, Smith and Titus (1980), who seem to have
been the first to test these propositions in a comparison of all four types of auction, and Cox, Roberson and
Smith (1982).
9
Smith’s method also emphasizes the importance of designing experiments as repeated trials,
so that the subjects can become familiar with and understand the experimental situation.
In many respects, the differences vis-à-vis psychologically oriented methods are a matter of
focus. Whereas psychologists have been predominantly interested in individual behavior,
Smith designed his original experiments mainly to analyze market outcomes. Genuine
differences of opinion about the appropriate methodology have not subsided, however. To
some extent, they reflect two different approaches to understanding human behavior, as
further discussed in section 2 (see Smith, 1991a, and Loewenstein, 1999, for different sides of
the debate).6
Nearly half a century ago, Edwards (1954) introduced decision-making as a research topic for
psychologists, outlining an agenda for future research. Allais (1953a,b) outlined a
psychology-based positive theory of choice under uncertainty, while Simon (1956) proposed
an approach to information processing and decision-making based on bounded rationality. But
research in cognitive psychology did not come into its own until Daniel Kahneman and Amos
Tversky (deceased in 1996) published their findings on judgment and decision-making.
Although adhering to the tradition of cognitive psychology, Kahneman’s research has equally
well been directed towards economists. Many of his articles have been published in
economics journals; one article, Kahneman and Tversky (1979), even has the highest citation
count of all articles published in Econometrica, by many considered the most prestigious
journal in economics. Given the barriers to communicating across traditional disciplines,
considerable effort has gone into building a bridge between research in economics and
psychology. Nowadays, there are in fact two bridges between these disciplines – one built
6
The importance of monetary incentives or repetition obviously depends on the hypothesis that the experiment is
supposed to test. Incentives may also affect different cognitive functions in distinct ways (Nilsson, 1987).
10
around experimental methods and the other around theoretical modeling. Both serve as the
basis for the current wave of work in behavioral economics. Before discussing Kahneman’s
specific contributions, the next section outlines some differences between conceptions of
decision-making in economics and psychology.
11
the statistically expected value of this “utility function” u is greater under a than under b.7
Formally, the criterion for choosing a is thus
Hence, given existing market conditions, which define the choice set available to the decision-
maker, the cognitive process is reduced to a problem of expectation formation and
maximization. The decision-maker is thus assumed to behave as if she correctly assigned
probabilities to relevant random events and chose an action that maximized the expected
value of her resulting utility.
By contrast, cognitive psychologists consider an interactive process where several factors may
influence a decision in a non-trivial way. These components include perception, which
follows its own laws, as well as beliefs or mental models for interpreting situations as they
arise. Intrinsic motives, such as emotions – the state of mind of the decision-maker – and
attitudes – stable psychological tendencies to relate to a given phenomenon in one’s
environment – may influence a decision. Moreover, the memory of previous decisions and
their consequences serves as a critical cognitive function that also has a strong influence on
current decision-making. Given this complex view, human behavior is regarded as locally
conditioned to a given situation. Typically, behavior is adaptive; it is dependent on the
context and transitory perceptual conditions.
These differences between psychology and traditional economics also show up in research
methodology. While experiments in economics often emphasize the generality of a situation
and comprise monetary rewards and repeated trials, psychologists try to capture intrinsic
motivations and the mental processes at work in a particular decision situation, what has been
termed the framing of a decision problem.
Extensive behavioral evidence, collected by Kahneman and others through surveys and
experiments, calls the assumption of economic rationality into question, at least in complex
decision situations. A number of studies have uncovered a non-trivial amount of deviations
from the traditional model of rational economic behavior. For example, real-world decision-
makers do not always evaluate uncertain prospects according to the laws of probability, and
7
To be exact, the function u is not a utility function: such functions map decision alternatives (here actions) into
12
sometimes make decisions that violate the principles of expected-utility maximization
outlined above. Kahneman’s major contributions concerning judgment and decisions under
uncertainty are discussed in the following.
One fundamental bias is that individuals appear to use a law of small numbers, attributing the
same probability distribution to the empirical mean value from small and large samples,
thereby violating the law of large numbers in probability theory (Tversky and Kahneman,
1971). For example, in a well-known experiment it was found that subjects thought it equally
likely that more than 60 percent of births on a given day would be boys in a small hospital as
in a large hospital. In general, people do not appear to realize how fast the variance of the
sample mean of a random variable decreases with sample size.
More precisely, according to the statistical laws of large numbers, the probability distribution
of the mean from a large sample of independent observations of a random variable is
concentrated at the expected value of the random variable, and the variance of the sample
mean goes to zero as the sample size increases.8 According to the psychological law of small
numbers, by contrast, people believe that the mean value from a small sample also has a
distribution concentrated at the expected value of the random variable. This leads to “over-
inference” from short sequences of independent observations.
13
An example of the law of small numbers is when an investor observes a fund manager
performing above average two years in a row and concludes that the fund manager is much
better than average, while the true statistical implication is very weak. A related example is
the so-called gambler’s fallacy: many individuals expect the second draw of a random
mechanism to be negatively correlated with the first, even if the draws are statistically
independent. If a few early tosses of a fair coin give disproportionately many heads, many
individuals believe that the next flip is more likely to be tails. Recent work, such as Rabin
(2002), describes the importance of the law of small numbers for economic decisions.
The law of small numbers is related to representativeness, a heuristic which Kahneman and
Tversky discovered to be an important ingredient in human judgment. Tversky and
Kahneman (1973, 1974, 1982) illustrated the function of this heuristic in several elegant
experiments. Subjects were asked to categorize persons, e.g., as a “salesman” or a “member
of parliament,” on the basis of given descriptions. Confronted with a description of an
individual – randomly drawn from a given population – as “interested in politics, likes to
participate in debates, and is eager to appear in the media,” most subjects would say that the
person is a member of parliament, even though the higher proportion of salespersons in the
population makes it more likely that the person is a salesman. This observed heuristic way of
thinking was examined further by Tversky and Kahneman (1973), who report an experiment
where some subjects received explicit information about the true proportions in the
population. One design stated that the person to be categorized was drawn from a pool of 30
percent engineers and 70 percent lawyers, while another design reversed these proportions.
The results revealed that this difference had virtually no effect on subjects’ judgment.
The same heuristic can also prompt people to believe that the joint probability of two events is
larger than the probability of one of the constituent events, in contradiction to a fundamental
principle of probability (the so-called conjunction rule). For instance, some subjects in an
experiment thought that if Björn Borg reached the Wimbledon final, he would be less likely to
lose the first set than to lose the first set and win the match.
In an overview of behavioral finance, Shleifer (2000) argues that the law of small numbers
and representativeness may explain certain anomalies in financial markets. For example, the
excess sensitivity of stock prices (Shiller, 1981) may be a result of investors’ overreacting to
short strings of good news.
14
Another bias common in probabilistic judgment is availability, whereby people judge
probabilities by the ease of conjuring up examples. The result is that disproportionately high
weight is assigned to salient or easily remembered information (Tversky and Kahneman,
1973). People thus overstate, say, the probability of violent crimes in a city if they personally
know someone who has been assaulted, even if they have access to more relevant aggregate
statistics. A general finding in cognitive psychology is that, compared to unfamiliar
information, familiar information is more easily accessible from memory and is believed to be
more real or relevant. Familiarity and availability may thus serve as cues for accuracy and
relevance. Therefore, mere repetition of certain information in the media, regardless of its
accuracy, makes it more easily available and therefore falsely perceived as more accurate.
Such evidence on human judgment demonstrates that people’s reasoning violates basic laws
of probability in a systematic way. By demonstrating this, Kahneman's research has seriously
questioned the empirical validity of one of the fundamentals of traditional economic theory.
9
By this axiom, if a decision-maker prefers lottery A to B, he should also prefer a probability mixture pA + (1-
p)C to the probability mixture pB + (1-p)C , for all lotteries C.
15
Kahneman and Tversky, 1979, Tversky and Kahneman, 1991, 1992, Kahneman and Lovallo,
1993, and Kahneman, Knetsch and Thaler, 1990).
One striking finding is that people are often much more sensitive to the way an outcome
differs from some non-constant reference level (such as the status quo) than to the outcome
measured in absolute terms. This focus on changes rather than levels may be related to well-
established psychophysical laws of cognition, whereby humans are more sensitive to changes
than to levels of outside conditions, such as temperature or light.
Moreover, people appear to be more adverse to losses, relative to their reference level, than
attracted by gains of the same size. Tversky and Kahneman (1992) estimated that the value
attached to a moderate loss is about twice the value attached to an equally large gain. That is,
people’s preferences seem to be characterized by (local) loss aversion. With small stakes,
they generally prefer the status quo to a fifty-fifty chance of winning, say, 12 dollars or losing
10 dollars. This renders counterfactual the implied preferences over large gains and losses,
according to conventional economic analysis; see Rabin (2000). The common finding of
apparently risk-loving behavior with respect to large losses is inconsistent with the traditional
assumption of risk aversion.10 For example, Kahneman and Tversky (1979) found that seven
out of ten people prefer a 25% probability of losing 6,000 dollars, to a 50% probability of
losing either 4,000 or 2,000 dollars, with equal probability (25%) for each. Since the
expected monetary value of the two lotteries is the same, the first lottery is a mean-preserving
spread of the second, and should thus not be preferred under conventional risk aversion.
Kahneman and Tversky moved beyond criticism, however, and suggested an alternative
modeling framework in their seminal article, “Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decisions
under Risk” (1979). While expected-utility theory is axiomatic, their prospect theory is
descriptive. It was thus developed in an inductive way from empirical observations, rather
than deductively from a set of logically appealing axioms. Later, Tversky and Kahneman
(1986) argued that two theories are in fact required: expected-utility theory to characterize
rational behavior and something like prospect theory to describe actual behavior. Although
expected-utility theory provides an accurate representation of actual choices in some
10
As explained in Section 1, a decision-maker is called risk neutral if she is indifferent between participating in
any actuarially fair lottery and obtaining the expected prize for sure. A decision-maker who prefers the expected
prize for sure is called risk averse, while she is called risk loving if she prefers the lottery.
16
transparent and simple decision problems, most real-life decision problems are complex and
call for behaviorally richer models.
What, then, are the differences between the two theories? In the case of monetary gains and
losses, the decision criterion in expected-utility theory, equation (1) above, presumes the
existence of a real-valued function u of wealth w, for the decision-maker in the current
situation. If action a induces probabilities pi over the different levels wi of wealth, and
action b induces probabilities qi, then the decision-maker (strictly) prefers a to b if and
only if
By contrast, prospect theory postulates the existence of two functions, v and π , such that the
decision-maker (strictly) prefers action a over action b if and only if
where ∆wi=wi-wo is the deviation in wealth from some reference level wo (which may be
initial or aspired wealth, see below).
There are three differences between the two models. First, in prospect theory, the decision-
maker is not concerned with final values of wealth per se, but with changes in wealth, ∆w,
relative to some reference point. This reference point is often the decision-maker’s current
level of wealth, so that gains and losses are defined relative to the status quo. But the
reference level can also be some aspiration level: a wealth level the subject strives to acquire,
given his or her current wealth and expectations. Kahneman and Tversky argued that a
decision problem has two stages. It is “edited”, so as to establish an appropriate reference
point for the decision at hand. The outcome of such a choice is then “coded” as a gain when it
exceeds this point and as a loss when the outcome falls short of it. This editing stage is
followed by an evaluation stage, which is based on the criterion in (3).
The second difference relative to expected-utility theory concerns the value function v . In
addition to being defined over changes in wealth, this function is S-shaped. Thus it is concave
for gains and convex for losses, displaying diminishing sensitivity to change in both
directions. Furthermore, it has a kink at zero, being steeper for small losses than for small
17
gains. The function u in expected-utility theory, by contrast, is usually taken to be smooth
and concave everywhere. The form of the value function is illustrated in Figure 2 (Figure 3
in Kahneman and Tversky, 1979).
Figure 2 Figure 3
These differences make prospect theory consistent with the experimental evidence mentioned
earlier in thissection. Since people evaluate risky prospects on the basis of changes in wealth
relative to some reference level, appropriate assumptions about the editing stage would make
the model consistent with the common observation that people choose differently depending
on how a problem is framed. The kink on the value function at the reference point – making
the function much steeper for small losses than for small gains – implies that choices are
consistent with loss aversion. As a consequence of the diminishing marginal sensitivity to
change in the v function, decision-makers become risk averse towards gains (they value large
gains less than proportionally) and risk loving towards losses (they value large losses less than
proportionally), in line with the evidence. Moreover, the fact that the decision-weight
function overweighs small probabilities and underweighs large probabilities can explain the
Allais paradox.
18
Already Allais (1953 a,b) outlined foundations for a psychologically based theory of
preferences over uncertain prospects with monetary outcomes. Unlike prospect theory, Allais
attached (cardinal) utilities to final wealth levels, but like prospect theory, he made a
distinction between objective probabilities and the decision-maker's perception of these.
Allais suggested that objective probabilities be transformed differently for gains and losses, in
such a way that the perceived probabilities sum to one.
Prospect theory may also capture several regularities that appear as anomalies from the
perspective of traditional economic theory: the propensity for people to take out expensive
small-scale insurance when buying appliances; their willingness to drive to a distant store to
save a few dollars on a small purchase, but reluctance to make the same trip for an equally
large discount on an expensive item; or their resistance to lowering consumption in response
to bad news about lifetime income.
In sum, the empirical work conducted by Kahneman and others indicates several regularities
in choice under uncertainty, and the ideas incorporated in prospect theory go a long way
towards explaining these regularities. Kahneman’s results have provided researchers in
economics with new insights and have been instrumental in subsequent model building by
alerting decision analysts to the errors commonly committed by real-life decision-makers. A
further extension of prospect theory, known as cumulative prospect theory (Tversky and
Kahneman, 1992) addresses some weaknesses of the original version. In particular,
cumulative prospect theory allows for prospects with a large number of outcomes, and it is
consistent with stochastic dominance.11
Prospect theory and its extensions have taken important steps towards a more accurate
description of individual behavior under risk than expected-utility theory. It now forms the
basis for much of the applied empirical work in this field.
11
Cumulative prospect theory combines prospect theory with a cumulative approach developed by Quiggin
(1982), Schmeidler (1989) and Luce and Fishburn (1991).
19
3. Summary
Daniel Kahneman has used insights from cognitive psychology regarding the mental
processes of answering questions, forming judgments, and making choices, to help us better
understand how people make economic decisions. Other psychologists have also made
important contributions along the same lines. But Kahneman’s work with Tversky on
decision-making under uncertainty clearly stands out as the most influential. Kahneman also
made early contributions to other areas of behavioral economics. One example is his joint
work with Knetsch and Thaler (Kahneman, Knetsch and Thaler, 1986) on the importance of
fairness considerations. This has become a lively field of research, and many experimental
studies have subsequently been carried out by other researchers, showing that a variety of
market behaviors can be derived from considerations of fairness and reciprocity (see e.g. Fehr
and Falk, 2002 for a recent review). Through this and other work, Kahneman has been a
major source of inspiration behind the recent boom of research in behavioral economics and
finance. His research has also had a substantial impact in other fields. It is widely quoted in
other social sciences as well as within the natural sciences, the humanities and medicine.
12
Since experimentation with human subjects had been a well-established method in psychology for almost a
century, it was more important for Smith than for Kahneman to develop experimental methodology.
20
A current wave of research draws on the combined traditions of psychology and experimental
economics. This new research is potentially significant for all areas of economics and
finance. Experimental evidence indicates that certain psychological phenomena – such as
bounded rationality, limited self-interest, and imperfect self-control – are important factors
behind a range of market outcomes. To the extent parsimonious behavioral theories,
consistent with this evidence, can be developed, they may eventually replace elements of
traditional economic theory. A challenging task in financial economics is to consider the
extent to which the effects of systematic irrationality on asset prices will be weeded out by
market arbitrage.
Although Kahneman's and Smith's research agendas differ in many respects, their combined
scientific contributions have already changed the direction of economic science. Economics
used to be limited to theorizing by way of a relatively simple rationalistic model of human
decision-making, homo oeconomicus, and to empirical work on field data. When they
appeared, Kahneman’s and Smith’s initial works were received with skepticism by the
scientific community in economics. It took considerable time and much further research
before their main ideas seriously began to penetrate the profession. It is their achievement
that many – perhaps most – economists today view psychological insights and experimental
methods as essential ingredients in modern economics.
Smith (1962) and Kahneman and Tversky (1979) are two classical articles by this year’s
laureates. For collections of papers we refer to Smith (2000) and Kahneman and Tversky,
eds. (2000). Overviews of the fields are given in Kagel and Roth, eds. (1995), and in Rabin
(1998).
21
References
Allais M. (1953a), “Le comportement de l’homme rationnel devant le risque: Critique des
postulats et axiomes de l’école americaine”, Econometrica 21, 503-546.
Allais M. (1953b), “Fondements d'une Théorie Positive des Choix Comportant un Risque et
Critique des Postulats et Axiomes de l’Ecole Americaine”, in Econometrie, Colloques
Internationaux du Centre de la Recherche Scientifique, Volume XL, 257-332, Paris.
(Translated into English in M. Allais and O. Hagen (eds.): Expected Utility Hypotheses
and the Allais Paradox, D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dortrecht, Holland, 1979.)
Bulfin R.L., S.J. Rasenti, and V.L. Smith (1982), “A combinatorial auction mechanism for
airport time slot allocation”, Bell Journal of Economics 13, 402-417.
Chamberlin E.H. (1948), “An experimental imperfect market”, Journal of Political Economy
56, 95-108.
Coppinger V.M., V.L Smith, and J.A. Titus (1980), “Incentives and behavior in English,
Dutch, and sealed-bid auctions”, Economic Inquiry 18, 1-22.
Coursey D.L. and V.L. Smith (1984), “Experimental tests of an allocation method for public,
private, or externality goods”, Scandinavian Journal of Economics 86, 468-484.
Cox J.L., B. Roberson, and V.L Smith (1982), “Theory and behavior of single object
auctions”, in V.L. Smith (ed.) Research in Experimental Economics, JAI Press,
Greenwich CT.
Edwards W. (1954), “Behavioral decision theory”, Annual Review of Psychology 12, 473-98.
Ellsberg D. (1961), “Risk, ambiguity, and the Savage axioms”, Quarterly Journal of
Economics 75, 643-669.
Fiorina M. and C. Plott (1978), “Committee decisions under majority rule: An experimental
study”, American Political Science Review 72, 575-98.
Fouraker L.E. and S.Siegel (1963), Bargaining Behavior, McGraw Hill, New York.
Kahneman D., J. Knetsch, and R. Thaler (1986), “Fairness and the assumptions of
economics”, Journal of Business 59, S285-S300.
22
Kahneman D., J. Knetsch, and R. Thaler (1990), “Experimental tests of the endowment effect
and the Coase theorem”, Journal of Political Economy 98, 1325-1348.
Kahneman D. and D. Lovallo (1993), “Timid choices and bold forecasts: A cognitive
perspective on risk taking”, Management Science 39, 17-31.
Kahneman D. and A. Tversky (1979), ”Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk”,
Econometrica 47, 263-291.
Kahneman, D, and A. Tversky, eds. (2000), Choices, values and frames, Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge.
Kalish G.K., J.W. Milnor, J. Nash, and E.D. Nehrig (1954), “Some experimental n-person
games”, in R.M. Thrall, C.H. Coombs, and R.L. Davis (eds.), Decision Processes,
Wiley, New York.
Luce, R. D. and P. C. Fishburn (1991), "Rank-and sign-dependent linear utility models for
finite first-order gambles", Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 4, 29-59.
McCabe K.A., S.J. Rasenti, and V.L. Smith (1989), “Designing 'smart' computer-assisted
markets”, European Journal of Political Economy 5, 259-283.
von Neumann J. and O. Morgenstern (1944), Theory of Games and Economic Behavior (3rd
ed.), Princeton University Press, Princeton.
Nilsson L-G. (1987), “Motivated memory: Dissociations between performance data and
subjective reports”, Psychological Research 46, 183-188.
Plott C. and V.L. Smith (1978), “An experimental examination of two exchange institutions”,
Review of Economic Studies 45, 133-153.
Quiggin, J. (1982), "A theory of anticipated utility", Journal of Economic Behavior and
Organization 3, 323-343.
Rabin, M. (1998), “Psychology and Economics," Journal of Economic Literature 35, 11-46.
23
Rabin M. (2002), “Inference by believers in the law of small numbers”, Quarterly Journal of
Economics 117, 775-816.
Rasenti S.J., V.L. Smith, and B.J. Wilson (2001), “Controlling market power and price spikes
in electricity networks: Demand-side bidding”, mimeo, George Mason University.
Sauerman, H., and R. Selten (1959), “Ein Oligopolexperiment”, Zeitschrift für die gesamte
Staatswissenschaft 115, 427-471.
Savage L. (1953), The Foundations of Statistics, John Wiley and Sons, New York.
Shiller R. (1981), “Do stock prices move too much to be justified by subsequent changes in
dividends?”, American Economic Review 71, 421-436.
Siegel S. and L.E. Fouraker (1960), Bargaining and Group Decision Making, McGraw Hill,
New York.
Simon H.A. (1956), “Rational choice and the structure of the environment”, Psychological
Review 63, 129-138.
Smith V.L. (1962), “An experimental study of competitive market behavior”, Journal of
Political Economy 70, 111-137.
Smith V.L. (1965), “Experimental auction markets and the Walrasian hypothesis”, Journal of
Political Economy 73, 387-393.
Smith V.L. (1973), “Notes on some literature in experimental economics”, Social Sciences
working paper No. 21, California Institute of Technology.
Smith V.L. (1976a), “Experimental economics: Induced value theory”, American Economic
Review, Papers and Proceedings, 274-279.
Smith V.L. (1979a), “An experimental comparison of three public good decision
mechanisms”, Scandinavian Journal of Economics 81, 198-215.
Smith V.L. (1979b), “Incentive compatible experimental processes for the provision of public
goods”, in V.L. Smith (ed.), Research in Experimental Economics, JAI Press.
Greenwich, CT.
24
Smith V.L. (1979c), “Indirect revelation of the demand for public goods: An overview and
critique”, Scottish Journal of Political Economy 26, 183-189.
Smith V.L. (1980), “Experiments with a decentralized mechanism for public good decisions”,
American Economic Review 70, 584-599.
Smith V.L. (1991a), “Rational choice – the contrast between economics and psychology”,
Journal of Political Economy 99, 877-897.
Smith, V.L. (2000), Bargaining and Market Behavior : Essays in Experimental Economics,
Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Tversky A. and D. Kahneman (1971), “Belief in the law of small numbers”, Psychological
Bulletin 76, 105-110.
Tversky A. and D. Kahneman (1973), “Availability: A heursistic for judging frequency and
probability”, Cognitive Psychology 5, 207-232.
Tversky, A. and D. Kahneman (1974), “Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases”,
Science 185, 1124-1131.
Tversky A. and D. Kahneman (1986), “Rational choice and framing of decisions”, Journal of
Business 59, S252-278.
25