Nagarjuna - Douglas Berger
Nagarjuna - Douglas Berger
Nagarjuna - Douglas Berger
250)
Table of Contents
1. Nagarjuna’s Life, Legend and Works
2. Nagarjuna’s Skeptical Method and its Targets
3. Against Worldly and Ultimate Substantialism
4. Against Proof
5. The New Buddhist Space and Mission
6. References and Further Reading
Nagarjuna was born a “Hindu,” which in his time connoted religious allegiance to the
Vedas, probably into an upper-caste Brahmin family and probably in the southern
Andhra region of India. The dates of his life are just as amorphous, but two texts
which may well have been authored by him offer some help. These are in the form of
epistles and were addressed to the historical king of the northern Satvahana dynasty
Gautamiputra Satakarni (ruled c. 166-196 CE), whose steadfast Brahminical
patronage, constant battles against powerful northern Shaka Satrap rulers and whose
ambitious but ultimately unsuccessful attempts at expansion seem to indicate that he
could not manage to follow Nagarjuna’s advice to adopt Buddhist pacifism and
maintain a peaceful realm. At any rate, the imperial correspondence would place the
significant years of Nagarjuna’s life sometime between 150 and 200 CE. Tibetan
sources then may well be basically accurate in portraying Nagarjuna’s emigration
from Andhra to study Buddhism at Nalanda in present-day Bihar, the future site of
the greatest Buddhist monastery of scholastic learning in that tradition’s proud
history in India. This emigration to the north perhaps followed the path of the Shaka
kings themselves. In the vibrant intellectual life of a not very tranquil north India
then, Nagarjuna came into his own as a philosopher.
Nagarjuna saw in the concept sunya, a concept which connoted in the early Pali
Buddhist literature the lack of a stable, inherent existence in persons, but which since
the third century BCE had also denoted the newly formulated number “zero,” the
interpretive key to the heart of Buddhist teaching, and the undoing of all the
metaphysical schools of philosophy which were at the time flourishing around him.
Indeed, Nagarjuna’s philosophy can be seen as an attempt to deconstruct all systems
of thought which analyzed the world in terms of fixed substances and essences.
Things in fact lack essence, according to Nagarjuna, they have no fixed nature, and
indeed it is only because of this lack of essential, immutable being that change is
possible, that one thing can transform into another. Each thing can only have its
existence through its lack (sunyata) of inherent, eternal essence. With this new
concept of “emptiness,” “voidness,” “lack” of essence, “zeroness,” this somewhat
unlikely prodigy was to help mold the vocabulary and character of Buddhist thought
forever.
Armed with the notion of the “emptiness” of all things, Nagarjuna built his literary
corpus. While argument still persists over which of the texts bearing his name can be
reliably attributed to Nagarjuna, a general agreement seems to have been reached in
the scholarly literature. Since it is not known in what chronological order his writings
were produced, the best that can be done is to arrange them thematically according
to works on Buddhist topics, Brahminical topics and finally ethics Addressing the
schools of what he considered metaphysically wayward Buddhism, Nagarjuna
wrote Fundamental Verses on the Middle Way (Mulamadhyamakakarika), and then, in
order to further refine his newly coined and revolutionary concept, the Seventy Verses
on Emptiness (Sunyatasaptati), followed by a treatise on Buddhist philosophical
method, the Sixty Verses on Reasoning (Yuktisastika).. Included in the works addressed
to Buddhists may have been a further treatise on the shared empirical world and its
establishment through social custom, called Proof of Convention (Vyavaharasiddhi),
though save for a few cited verses, this is lost to us, as well as an instructional book
on practice, cited by one Indian and a number of Chinese commentators,
the Preparation for Enlightenment (Bodhisambaraka). Finally is a didactic work on the
causal theory of Buddhism, the Constituents of Dependent
Arising (Pratityasumutpadahrdaya). Next came a series of works on philosophical
method, which for the most part were reactionary critiques of Brahminical
substantialist and epistemological categories, The End of Disputes (Vigrahavyavartani)
and the not-too-subtly titled Pulverizing the Categories (Vaidalyaprakarana). Finally are
a pair of religious and ethical treatises addressed to the king Gautamiputra,
entitled To a Good Friend (Suhrlekha) and Precious Garland (Ratnavali). Nagarjuna
then was a fairly active author, addressing the most pressing philosophical issues in
the Buddhism and Brahmanism of his time, and more than that, carrying his
Buddhist ideas into the fields of social, ethical and political philosophy.
It is again not known precisely how long Nagarjuna lived. But the legendary story of
his death once again is a tribute to his status in the Buddhist tradition. Tibetan
biographies tell us that, when Gautamiputra’s successor was about to ascend to the
throne, he was anxious to find a replacement as a spiritual advisor to better suit his
Brahmanical preferences, and unsure of how to delicately or diplomatically deal with
Nagarjuna, he forthrightly requested the sage to accommodate and show compassion
for his predicament by committing suicide. Nagarjuna assented, and was decapitated
with a blade of holy grass which he himself had some time previously accidentally
uprooted while looking for materials for his meditation cushion. The indomitable
logician could only be brought down by his own will and his own weapon. Whether
true or not, this master of skeptical method would well have appreciated the irony.
The early Buddhists were not nearly so sure about the possibility of ultimate
knowledge of the world. Indeed, the founder of the tradition, Siddhartha Gautama
Sakyamuni (the “Buddha” or “awakened one”), famously refused to answer questions
about such airy metaphysical ponderings like “Does the world have a beginning or
not?”, “Does God exist?” and “Does the soul perish after death or not?” Convinced
that human knowledge was best suited and most usefully devoted to the diagnosis
and cure of human beings’ own self-destructive psychological obsessions and
attachments, the Buddha compared a person convinced he could find the answers to
such ultimate questions to a mortally wounded soldier on a battlefield who, dying
from arrow-delivered poison, demanded to know everything about his shooter before
being taken to a doctor. Ultimate knowledge cannot be attained, at least cannot be
attained before the follies and frailties of human life bring one to despair. Unless
human beings attain self-reflective, meditative enlightenment, ignorance will always
have the upper hand over knowledge in their lives, and this is the predicament they
must solve in order to alleviate their poorly understood suffering. The early
traditional texts show how the Buddha developed a method for refusing to answer
such questions in pursuit of ultimate, metaphysical knowledge, a method which came
to be dubbed the “four error” denial (catuskoti). When asked, for example, whether
the world has a beginning or not, a Buddhist should respond by denying all the
logically alternative answers to the query; “No, the world does not have a beginning,
it does not fail to have a beginning, it does not have and not have a beginning, nor
does it neither have nor not have a beginning.” This denial is not seen to be logically
defective in the sense that it violates the law of excluded middle (A cannot have both
B and not-B), because this denial is more a principled refusal to answer than a
counter-thesis, it is more a decision than a proposition. That is to say that one cannot
object to this “four error” denial by simply saying “the world either has a beginning
or it does not” because the Buddha is recommending to his followers that they should
take no position on the matter (this is in modern propositional logic known as
illocution). This denial was recommended because wondering about such questions
was seen by the Buddha as a waste of valuable time, time that should be spent on the
much more important and doable task of psychological self-mastery. The early
Buddhists, unlike their Brahminical philosophical counterparts, were skeptics. But in
their own view, their skepticism did not make the Buddhists pessimists, but on the
contrary, optimists, for even though the human mind could not answer ultimate
questions, it could diagnose and cure its own must basic maladies, and that surely
was enough.
But in the intervening four to six centuries between the lives of Siddartha Gautama
and Nagarjuna, Buddhists, feeling a need to explain their worldview in an ever
burgeoning north Indian philosophical environment, traded in their skepticism for
theory. Basic Buddhist doctrinal commitments, such as the teaching of the
impermanence of all things, the Buddhist rejection of a persistent personal identity
and the refusal to admit natural universals such as “treeness,” “redness” and the like,
were challenged by Brahminical philosophers. How, Vedic opponents would ask,
does one defend the idea that causation governs the phenomenal world while
simultaneously holding that there is no measurable temporal transition from cause
to effect, as the Buddhists appeared to hold? How, if the Buddhists are right in
supposing that no enduring ego persists through our experienced lives, do all of my
experiences and cognitions seem to be owned by me as a unitary subject? Why, if all
things can be reduced to the Buddhist universe of an ever-changing flux of atoms, do
stable, whole objects seem to surround me in my lived environment? Faced with
these challenges, the monk-scholars enthusiastically entered into the debates in
order to make the Buddhist worldview explicable. A number of prominent schools of
Buddhist thought developed as a result of these exchanges, the two most notable of
which were the Sarvastivada (“Universal Existence”) and Sautrantika (“True
Doctrine”). In various fashions, they posited theories which depicted causal efficacy
as either present in all dimensions of time or instantaneous, of personal identity
being the psychological product of complex and interrelated mental states, and
perhaps most importantly, of the apparently stable objects of our lived experience as
being mere compounds of elementary, irreducible substances with their “own
nature” (svabhava). Through the needs these schools sought to fulfill, Buddhism
entered the world of philosophy, debate, thesis and verification, world-
representation. The Buddhist monks became not only theoreticians, but some of the
most sophisticated theoreticians in the Indian intellectual world.
Debate has raged for centuries about how to place Nagarjuna in this philosophical
context. Ought he to be seen as a conservative, traditional Buddhist, defending the
Buddha’s own council to avoid theory? Should he be understood as a “Great Vehicle”
Buddhist, settling disputes which did not exist in traditional Buddhism at all but only
comprehensible to a Mahayanist? Might he even be a radical skeptic, as his first
Brahminical readers appeared to take him, who despite his own flaunting of
philosophy espoused positions only a philosopher could appreciate? Nagarjuna
appears to have understood himself to be a reformer, primarily a Buddhist reformer
to be sure, but one suspicious that his own beloved religious tradition had been
enticed, against its founder’s own advice, into the games of metaphysics and
epistemology by old yet still seductive Brahminical intellectual habits. Theory was
not, as the Brahmins thought, the condition of practice, and neither was it, as the
Buddhists were beginning to believe, the justification of practice. Theory, in
Nagarjuna’s view, was the enemy of all forms of legitimate practice, social, ethical
and religious. Theory must be undone through the demonstration that its Buddhist
metaphysical conclusions and the Brahminical reasoning processes which lead to
them are counterfeit, of no real value to genuinely human pursuits. But in order to
demonstrate such a commitment, doubt had to be methodical, just as the philosophy
it was meant to undermine was methodical.
The method Nagarjuna suggested for carrying out the undoing of theory was,
curiously, not a method of his own invention. He held it more pragmatic to borrow
philosophical methods of reasoning, particularly those designed to expose faulty
argument, to refute the claims and assumptions of his philosophical adversaries. This
was the strategy of choice because, if one provisionally accepts the concepts and
verification rules of the opponent, the refutation of the opponent’s position will be all
the more convincing to the opponent than if one simply rejects the opponent’s
system out of hand. This provisional, temporary acceptance of the opponent’s
categories and methods of proof is demonstrated in how Nagarjuna employs
different argumentative styles and approaches depending on whether he is writing
against the Brahmins or Buddhists. However, he slightly and subtly adapts each of
their respective systems to suit his own argumentative purposes.
What are we to draw from all this abstract logical critique? Are we to infer that
Nagarjuna’s philosophy boils down to some strange paradoxical mysticism in which
there is some ambiguous sense in which things should be considered causally
interdependent but interdependent in some utterly unexplainable and inscrutable
way? Not at all! Nagarjuna has not refuted all available theories of cause and effect,
he has only rejected all substantialist theories of cause and effect. He thinks he has
shown that, if we maintain the philosophical assumption that things in the world
derive from some unique material and essential basis, then we shall come away
empty-handed in a search to explain how things could possibly relate to one another,
and so would have no way of describing how changes happen. But since both our
eminently common sense and the words of the Buddha affirm unremittingly that
changes do indeed happen, and happen constantly, we must assume that they
happen somehow, through some other fact or circumstance of existence. For his own
part, Nagarjuna concludes that, since things do not arise because phenomena relate
through fixed essences, then they must arise because phenomena lack fixed essences.
Phenomena are malleable, they are susceptible to alteration, addition and
destruction. This lack of fixed nature (nihsvabhava), this alterability of things then
means that their physical and empirical forms are built not upon essence, as both the
Universal Existence and True Doctrine schools posit, but upon the fact that nothing
(sunya) ever defines and characterizes them eternally and unconditionally. It is not
that things are in themselves nothing, nor that things possess a positive absence
(abhava) of essence. Change is possible because a radical indeterminancy (sunyata)
permeates all forms. Burning happens because conditions can arise where
temperatures become incindiary and singe flesh, just as thirst can be quenched when
the process of ingestion transforms water into body. Beings relate to one another not
because of their heterogeneous forms, but because their interaction makes them
susceptible to ongoing transformation.
The Fundamental Verses on the Middle Way is a tour de force through the entire
categorical system of the Buddhist metaphysical analysis (abhidharma) which had
given birth to its scholastic movements. Nagarjuna attacks all the concepts of these
traditions which were thematized according to substantialist, essentialist
metaphysics, using at every turn the logically revised “four errors” method. But
perhaps most revolutionary was Nagarjuna’s extension of this doctrine of the
“emptiness” of all phenomena to the discussion of the relationship between the
Buddha and the world, between the cycle of pain-inflicted rebirth (samsara) and
contented, desire-less freedom (nirvana). The Buddha, colloquially known as “the one
who came and went” (Tathagata), cannot properly be thought of for Nagarjuna in the
way the Buddhist scholastics have, that is, as the eternally pure seed of the true
teachings of peace which puts to rest the delusions of the otherwise defiled world.
The name and person of “Buddha” should not serve as the theoretical basis and
justification of distinguishing between the ordinary, ignorant world and perfected
enlightenment. After all, Nagarjuna reminds his readers, all change in the world,
including the transformations which lead to enlightenment, are only possible
because of interdependent causality (pratityasamutpada), and interdependent
causality in turn is only possible because things, phenomena, lack any fixed nature
and so are open (sunya) to being transformed. The Buddha himself was only
transformed because of interdependence and emptiness, and so, Nagarjuna infers,
“the nature of Tathagata is the very nature of the world/” It stands to reason then that
no essential delimitations can be made between the world of suffering and the
practices which can lead to peace, for both are merely alternative outcomes in the
nexus of worldly interdependence. The words and labels which attach to both the
world and the experience of nirvana are not the means of separating the wheat of life
from its chaff, nor true cultivators of the soil of experience from the over-ambitious
“everyday” rabble. Rather, samsara and nirvana signify nothing but the lack of
guarantees in a life of desire and the possibility of change and hope. “We assert,”
Nagarjuna proffers to say on behalf of the Buddhists, “that whatever arises
dependently is as such empty. This manner of designating things is exactly the
middle path.” A Buddhist oath to avoid suffering cannot be taken as a denunciation
of the world, but only as a commitment to harness the possibilities which already are
entailed within it for peace. Talk about the Buddha and practices inspired by the
Buddha are not tantamount to the raising of a religious or ideological flag which
marks off one country from another; rather, the world of suffering and the world of
peace have the same extension and boundary, and talk about suffering and the
Buddha is only there to make us aware of the possibilities of the world, and how our
realization of these possibilities depends precisely on what we do and how we
interact.
4. Against Proof
The apparently anti-theoretical stance occupied by Nagarjuna did not win him many
philosophical friends either among his contemporary Buddhist readers or the circles
of Brahminical thought. While it was certainly the case that, over the next seven
centuries of Buddhist scholastic thought, the concept of emptiness was more
forcefully articulated, it was also hermeneutically appropriated into other systems in
ways of which Nagarjuna would not necessarily have approved. Sunyata was soon
made to carry theoretical meanings unrelated to causal theory in various Buddhists
sects, serving as the support of a philosophy of consciousness for the later illustrious
Vijnanavada or Cognition School and as the explication of the nature of both
epistemology and ontology in the precise school of Buddhist Logic (Yogacara-
Sautrantika). These schools, deriding Nagarjuna’s skepticism, retained their
commitment to a style of philosophizing in India which allowed intellectual stands to
be taken only on the basis of commitments to thesis, counter-thesis, rules of
argument and standards of proof, that is, schools which equated philosophical
reflection with competing doctrines of knowledge and metaphysics. This is all the
more ironic given the overt attempt Nagarjuna made to head off the possibility that
the idea of emptiness would be refuted or co-opted by this style of philosophizing, an
attempt still preserved in the pages of his work The End of
Disputes (Vigrahavyavartani).
The End of Disputes was in large measure a reactionary work, written only when
philosophical objections were brought against Nagarjuna’s non-essentialist, anti-
metaphysical approach to philosophy. The work was addressed to a relatively new
school of Brahminical thought, the school of Logic (Nyaya) Philosophical debate,
conducted in formalized fashions in generally court settings, had persisted in India
for perhaps as much as eight hundred years before the time of the first literary
systematizer of the school of logic, Gautama Aksapada. Several attempts had been
made by Buddhist and Jaina schools before Nyaya to compose handbooks for formal
debate. But Nyaya brought to the Indian philosophical scene a full-blown doctrine
not only of the rules and etiquette of the debate process, but also an entire system of
inference which distinguished between logically acceptable and unacceptable forms
of argument. Finally, undergirding all forms of valid argument was a system of
epistemology, a theory of proof (pramanasastra), which distinguished between various
kinds of mental events which could be considered truth-revealing, or corresponding
to real states of affairs and those which could not be relied upon as mediators of
objective reality. Direct sensory perception, valid logical argument, tenable analogy
and authoritative testimony were held by the Logicians to be the only kinds of
cognitions which could correspond to real things or events in the world. They could
serve as proofs to the claims we make to know. With some modifications, the
approach of Nyaya came to be accepted as philosophical “first principles” by almost
all the other schools of thought in India for centuries, both Vedic and non-Vedic.
Indeed, in many philosophical quarters, before entering into the subtleties and
agonism of advanced philosophical debate, a student was expected to pass through
the prerequisites of studying Sanskrit grammar and logic. All thought, and so all
positive sciences, from agriculture to Vedic study to statecraft, were at times even
said to be fundamentally based on and entirely specious without basic training in
“critical analysis” (anviksiki), which, according to Gautama Aksapada, was precisely
what Nyaya was.
The Logicians, upon becoming aware very early of Nagarjuna’s thought, brought
against his position of emptiness (sunyata) a sharp criticism. Certainly no claim, they
insisted, should compel us to give it assent unless it can be known to be true. Now
Nagarjuna has told us that emptiness is the lack of a fixed, essential nature which all
things exhibit. But if all things are empty of a fixed nature, then that would include,
would it not, Nagarjuna’s own claim that all things are empty? For one to say that all
things lack a fixed nature would be also to say that no assertion, no thesis like
Nagarjuna’s that all things are empty, could claim hold on a fixed reference. And if
such a basic and all-encompassing thesis must admit of having itself neither a fixed
meaning nor reference, then why should we believe it? Does not rather the thesis “all
things lack a fixed essence, and are thus empty,” since it is a universal quantifier and
so covers all things including theses, refute itself? The Logicians are not so much
making the claim here that skepticism necessarily opts out of its own position, as
when a person in saying “I know nothing” witnesses unwittingly to at least a
knowledge of two things, namely how to use language and his own ignorance, as in
the cases of the Socratic Irony and the Liar’s Paradox. It is more the direct charge
that a philosophy which refuses to admit universal essences must be flatly self-
contradictory, since a universal denial must itself be essentially true of all things.
Should we not consider Nagarjuna as a person who, setting out on what would
otherwise be an ingenious and promising philosophical journey, in a bit too much of
a rush, tripped over his own feet on his way out the front door?
Nagarjuna, in The End of Disputes, responds in two ways. The first is an attempt to
show the haughty Logicians that, if they really critically examine this fundamental
concept of proof which grounds their theory of knowledge, they will find themselves
in no better position than they claim Nagarjuna is in. How, Nagarjuna asks in an
extended argument, can anything be proven to a fixed certainty in the way the
Naiyayikas posit? When you get right down to it, a putative fact can be proven in only
two ways; it is either self-evident or it is shown to be true by something else, by some
other fact or piece of knowledge already assumed to be true. But if we assent to the
very rules of logic and valid argument the Vedic Logicians espouse, we shall find,
Nagarjuna thinks, that both of these suppositions are flawed. Let us take the claim
that something can be proven to be true on the basis of other facts known to be true.
Suppose, to use a favorite example from the Logician Gautama, I want to know how
much an object weighs. I put it on a scale to measure its weight. The scale gives me a
result, and for a moment that satisfies me; I can rely on the measurement because
scales can measure weight. But hold on, Nagarjuna flags, your reliance on the
trustworthiness of the scale is itself an assumption, not a piece of knowledge.
Shouldn’t the scale be tested too? I measure the object on a second scale to test the
accuracy of the first scale, and the measurement agrees with the first scale. But how
can I just assume, once again, that the second scale is accurate? Both scales might be
wrong. And the exercise goes on, there is nothing in principle which would justify me
in assuming that any one test I use to verify a piece of knowledge is itself reliable
beyond doubt. So, Nagarjuna concludes, the supposition that something can be
proven through reference to some other putative fact runs into the problem that the
series of proofs will never reach an end, and leaves us with an infinite regress. Should
we commit ourselves to the opposite justification and propound that we know things
to be true which are self-evident, then Nagarjuna would counter that we would be
making a vacuous claim. The whole point of epistemology is to discover reliable
methods of knowing, which implies that on the side of the world there are facts and
on the side of the knower there are proofs which make those facts transparent to
human consciousness. Were things just self-evident, proof would be superfluous, we
should just know straightaway whether something is such and such or not. The claim
of self-evidence destroys, in an ironic fashion which always pleased Nagarjuna, the
very need for a theory of knowledge!
Having tested both criteria of evidence and come up short, the Logician might, and in
fact historically did, try an alternative theory of mutual corroboration. We may not
know for certain that a block of stone weighs too much to fit into a temple I am
building, and we may not be certain that the scale being used to measure the stones
is one hundred percent accurate, but if as a result of testing the stones with the scale
I put the stones in the building and find that they work well, I have reason to rely on
the knowledge I gain through the mutual corroborations of measurement and
practical success. This process, for Nagarjuna, however, should not pass for an
epistemologist who claims to be as strict as the Brahminical Logicians. In fact, this
process should not even be considered mutual corroboration; it is actually circular. I
assume stones have a certain measurable mass, so I design an instrument to confirm
my assumption, and I assume scales measure weight so I assess objects by them, but
in terms of strict logic, I am only assuming that this corroborative process proves my
suppositions, but it in fact does nothing more than feed my preconceived
assumptions rather than give me information about the nature of objects. We may
say that a certain person is a son because he has a father, Nagarjuna quips, and we
may say another person is a father because he has a son, but apart from this mutual
definition, how do we know which particular person is which? By extension,
Nagarjuna claims, this is the problem with the project of building a theory of
knowledge as such. Epistemology and ontology are parasitic on one another.
Epistemologies are conveniently formulated to justify preferred views of the world,
and ontologies are presumed to be justified through systematic theories of proof, but
apart from these projects being mutually theoretically necessary, we really have no
honest way of knowing whether they in fact lend credence to our beliefs. Again,
Nagarjuna has used tools from the bag of the logician, in this case, standard
argumentational fallacies, to show that it is Brahminical Logic, and not his
philosophy of emptiness, which has tripped itself up before having a chance to make
a run in the world.
This, as said above, was Nagarjuna’s first response to the Logicians’ accusation that a
philosophy of emptiness is fundamentally incoherent. There is however, Nagarjuna
famously asserts, another pettito principii in the Nyaya charge that the thesis “all
things are empty and lack a fixed nature” is incoherent. The statement “all things are
empty” is actually, Nagarjuna says, not a formal philosophical thesis in the first
place! According to the Nyaya rules of viable logical argument, the first step in
proving an assertion true is the declared statement of the putative fact as a thesis in
the argument (pratijna). Now in order for something to qualify as a formal
philosophical thesis, a statement must be a fact about a particular object or state of
knowable affairs in the world, and it is a matter of doctrine for Nyaya that all
particular objects or states of affairs are classifiable into their categories of
substances, qualities, and activities. Nagarjuna however does not buy into this set of
ontological categories in the first place, and so the Logician is being disingenuous in
trying to covertly pull him into the ontological game with this charge that the idea of
emptiness is metaphysically unintelligible. The Brahminical Logician is insisting that
no person can engage in a philosophical discussion without buying, at least
minimally, into a theory of essences and issues surrounding how to categorize
essences. It is exactly this very point, Nagarjuna demurs, that is eminently debatable!
But since the Logician will not pay Nagarjuna the courtesy of discussion on
Nagarjuna’s terms, the Buddhist replies to them on their terms: “If my statement
(about emptiness) were a philosophical thesis, then it would indeed be flawed; but I
assert no thesis, and so the flaw is not mine.”
With the exception of his two major commentators four centuries later, this stance of
Nagarjuna satisfied no one in the Indian philosophical tradition, neither Brahmanas
nor fellow Buddhists. It was the stance of the kind of debater who styled himself
a vaitandika, a person who refutes rival philosophical positions while advocating no
thesis themselves. Despite all their other disagreements, Brahmanas and Buddhists
in following centuries did not consider such a stance to be truly philosophical, for
while a person who occupied it may be able to expose dubious theories, one could
never hope to learn the truth about the world and life from them. Such a person, it
was suspected is more likely a charlatan than a sage. Despite the title of his work
then, Nagarjuna’s attempt to call into “first question” theories of proof fell far short
of ending all disputes. However, Nagarjuna closes this controversial and much-
discussed work by reminding his readers of who he is. Paying reverence to the
Buddha, the teacher, he says, of interdependent causality and emptiness, Nagarjuna
tells his audience that “nothing will prevail for those in whom emptiness will not
prevail, while everything will prevail for whom emptiness prevails.” This is a
reiteration of Nagarjuna’s commitment that theory and praxis are not a partnership
in which only through the former’s justification is the latter redeemed. The goal of
practice is after all transformation, not fixity, and so if one insists on marrying
philosophy to practice, philosophical reflection cannot be beholden to the
unchanging, eternal essences of customary epistemology and metaphysics