WhatKantCanTeachUsAboutEmotionMariaBorges PDF
WhatKantCanTeachUsAboutEmotionMariaBorges PDF
WhatKantCanTeachUsAboutEmotionMariaBorges PDF
Copyright © Maria Borges 2019. You may share this work for non-commercial purposes only,
provided you give attribution to the copyright holder and the publisher.
4
What can Kant teach us
about emotions?1
It is a hard task to support my thesis that Kant can teach us something about
emotions and bring important contributions to the contemporary debate
about this issue. Kant has long been seen as the philosopher who denies any
important role to emotions. To those who read just the first section of the
Groundwork, it seems to be a clear-cut case that emotions do not possess
intrinsic moral value. For instance, Kant writes that while the sympathetic
philanthropist performs an action without moral worth, the absence of
sympathy in the heart of the insensible one makes his action morally worthy.2
This fact presumably inspired Sabini and Silver to claim in their article
“Emotions, Responsibility and Character” that “a Kantian chapter on emotion
and responsibility is easy to write and quick to read. The domain of the moral
is the domain of the will expressed in action: it is the domain of that for which
we are responsible. Emotions are beyond the will, and for this reason have no
intrinsic moral value.”3
According to these authors, emotions have no moral value because they
follow the pain model.4 Just like pain, which is a fact about us, regardless of
values or other aspects of our character, emotions, even the most complex
ones, do not fall under the command of reason. Kant, just like more recent
psychologists and physiologists, is said to embrace a model in which
emotions are precognitive,5 mere perceptions of unspecified bodily states,6
or undifferentiated states of the sympathetic nervous system. Emotions, like
pain, would be nothing more than the stimulation of nerves, disconnected
from values, character, or reason. A supporter of the pain-like conception of
emotions is Zajonc. In his paper “Feeling and Thinking, Preferences Need No
Inference” he shows that there is a direct pathway from perceptual system to
emotional responses. Accordingly, emotions are not connected with reasoning
and values. According to Sabini and Silver, Zajonc’s model is the same as Kant’s.
Both place the emotions completely out of the moral domain. Hence, we could
be held responsible for the expression of our mental states, but not for having
them. Besides this, in Sabini and Silver’s view, certain emotional states are like
the pain of withdrawal for a drug addict, in which any responsibility for action
is attenuated by the intensity of the stimuli.7
Marcia Baron, in her book Kantian Ethics Almost without Apology, criticizes
the Sabini/Silver position, objecting that the pain model is not the one Kant
uses for explaining emotion:
This [Kantian] model, with its very strong notion of agency, is diametrically
opposed to the picture drawn by Sabini and Silver, according to which
emotions function, on Kant’s view, much as pain does. It is a serious mistake
to think that Kant’s psychology even approximately fits the model of pain
and that feelings such as sympathy “move us to act without our rational
assent or assessment.” . . . Similarly, it would be more plausible to criticize
Kant for attributing to us too much responsibility for our feelings and
emotions than to attribute to him the position that we are not responsible
for them.8
Baron’s position is radically distinct from Sabini and Silver’s: we are not
passive regarding our feelings; we are responsible for the way we feel. Even if
the Critique of Practical Reason and the Groundwork could justify a negative
conception of emotions, as phenomena incapable of being controlled by
reason, Baron claims that this conception requires revision when later texts
are taken into consideration, such as Religion within the Boundaries of Mere
Reason, The Metaphysics of Morals, and Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point
of View.
I shall try to show that neither model can fully explain Kant’s view of
emotions. Baron has a point in saying that we cannot explain some emotions
through the pain model, like sympathy and gratitude, which can be cultivated.
However, Kant does describe some affects as involuntary and passive, such
as fright in battles, which overcomes the agent regardless of his will, causing
disagreeable physical effects. In this case, Baron’s claim that we are not passive
regarding our emotions does not apply to Kantian morality. I will argue that
Kant does have a robust conception of agency, in spite of our being passive
regarding some emotions. However, if emotions are not in our power, this
does not imply that they lack cognitive elements. People can feel anger without
wanting it, but they in fact feel anger because they think something unfair
or harmful has been done. Baron is right that there are some feelings like
sympathy that are not beyond rational control; however, they cannot be a
model for all feelings.
My claim is that Kant presents us with a very colorful, wide range of emotions,
which cannot be captured in one model type, be it a pain or a sympathy model.
This diversity does not allow a simple answer concerning their voluntary or
involuntary nature, or concerning the influence of physiological factors. Kant
makes room for this complex picture when he connects them to our passive,
active, or reactive self, as well as to superior and inferior faculties. My strategy
will be, first, to present the taxonomy of emotions, and then place them in what
I call a map of the self. After this first presentation of the Kantian picture, I will
address some philosophical issues and relate Kant’s theory to contemporary
discussion on emotions.
First of all, Kant does not use the term “emotion.”9 What we pre-analytically
call emotion refers to at least three different kinds of phenomena: affects,10
moral feelings, and passions. These inclinations11 can be mainly related to
two faculties: the faculty of feeling pleasure and displeasure and the faculty of
desire. Feelings of pleasure or displeasure caused by an object can be sensible
or intellectual. The former are caused by sensation or imagination; the latter
are triggered by a concept or idea (Ant, 7: 230). Pleasure and displeasure given
by sensibility alone are feelings of gratification and pain. Sensible pleasure and
displeasure admit also two other kinds of inclination, caused by imagination:
sympathy and affects. The difference between them is that sympathy can be
cultivated, while we are passive with respect to affects.12
Affects are feelings of pleasure or displeasure that hinder the reflection
through which inclinations were to be submitted to rational maxims; they are
sudden and rash, making reflection impossible (TL, 6: 408), such as water that
breaks through a dam or a stroke of apoplexy (Ant, 7: 252). They can lead the
agent to moral blindness, since they hinder deliberation, with the consolation
that this tempest easily goes away and calms itself, allowing the subject to
go back to a state where reflection is possible again. He cites the example of
someone who marries out of love and is blind to the flaws in the character of
her beloved, but regains her vision a week after marriage (Ant, 7: 253). The
Kantian paradigmatic example for affect is anger, a tempestuous feeling by
nature, and fickle like love. Sympathy, although it is a sensible feeling (TL, 6:
456), can be trained in order to help the accomplishment of moral actions,
when respect for the moral law is not a sufficient incentive.
However, pleasures and displeasures are not all sensible; we also have
the intellectual ones, caused by an idea or concept. These include feelings
that make the mind receptive to the concept of duty, such as moral feeling,
which is defined as “a susceptibility to feel pleasure or displeasure from the
consciousness that our actions are consistent or contrary to the laws of duty”
(TL, 6: 399).13 Love for human beings belongs also to the receptivity of the
mind to the concept of duty. Intellectual pleasures include love of benevolence,
but not love of satisfaction. The former but not the latter could be ordered as
a duty, since it would be contradictory to have a duty to feel pleasure. Love
of benevolence admits of something like Aristotelian cultivation, for it is a
disposition that can be awakened by habit.14
Kant’s realm of inclinations also includes passion, which is related to the
faculty of desire and refers to a strong desire for something. Passions exhibit a
contradictory nature. On the one hand, Kant says that they hinder the control
of reason to compare at a particular moment, a specific inclination against
the sum of all inclinations (Ant, 7: 265). On the other hand, they admit some
rational deliberation about the means to obtain what the agent desires. One
good case is given in the Anthropology, where Kant compares the inability
of a man who feels the affect of love to seduce someone, to the skill of one
who is taken by the passion of love. The first will not be successful, while the
second can easily trap the helpless victim (Ant, 6: 265). The difference is that
one is immersed in a full agitation of the mind, while the other keeps a cold
blood to plot the way to obtain it. This case depicts the difference Kant makes
between the meaning of affects and passion, a difference that is also illustrated
in outstanding literary works, such as Dangerous Liaisons.15 While affects are
outbursts of feelings, which cannot coexist even with a prudential rationality,
passions show their cunning. The same difference can be seen when one
compares the affect of hate with the passion of anger: while the latter is fickle,
the former is a permanent disposition, which inclines the agent to plot a cold
blood vengeance.
In order to improve our understanding of Kant’s model or models for
emotions, it is helpful to locate them in relation to a Kantian sketch of the
self.16 Kant claims there are three instances of soul17 in a generic sense,
whose reference in each case is the self. The self can be observed in a triple
we know that our actions are wrong is associated with the active self, since it
is a feeling connected with a concept: the concept of duty. Between the pure
passive and the pure active part of the self, abide the reactive feelings, which
still belong to the superior faculty of feeling, and refer to affects and sensibility.
Kant, who was a well-known hypochondriac, illustrates in his Lectures on
Anthropology the difference between passive, reactive, and active feelings with
a case of a man who suffers from gout:
I cannot prevent the pain inflicted on my body from passing into my soul.
I can only prevent that my soul reflects over this, e.g., when I have gout and
think what will become of me in the future, how I will acquire my bread
and this causes sadness over the state of my health, here animus agitates.
The sickness of the mind is also what makes me miserable. Because such
reflection never attaches to animals, they are never miserable. But finally the
highest degree of sadness arises when my spirit abstracts from all pain and
awakens in me a self-reproach, when it imagines to itself how I brought this
illness upon myself and became unhappy through my own fault. (AntPa,
25: 247–48)
We can clearly see, in this quotation, the difference between three levels of
displeasure. The first one is purely physical, beyond control, even indirectly.
Since it is purely sensible, it is independent of any cognitive content; the
subject feels a certain wound as pain. This is an example of the inferior faculty
of pleasure and displeasure, where the feeling is given through sensation alone.
The second level relates to the displeasure of an affect, sadness, and allows
a nonphysical cause: sadness is caused by the imagination that agitates the
mind when the agent worries about the future. Here we have the reactive part
of the self, which relates to the superior faculty of feeling. Sadness is aroused
by imagination, which agitates the mind. Animals, Kant argues, are never
miserable, although they can feel the pain of a wound. However, Kant claims
in another lecture, “On Philosophers’ Medicine of the Body,” that animals do
have imagination, although in cattle “this force [of imagination] is not directed
by any choice or deliberate intention of animal.” Since some animals do have
imagination, Kant can conceive that a certain illness may oppress the mind
of the animal when it is brought into captivity, “yet the black anxiety that
afflicts the miserable human race escapes the animal, which knows nothing
of worry.”18 To mention animal mind, which can be affected by sadness, ipso
facto refutes the idea that Kantian affects fit the pain model, since even animals
are supposed to have affects triggered by imagination. The very idea of being
in captivity can trigger in their minds some emotions of sadness. In human
beings, this faculty is supposed to be even stronger, giving a deeper force to
affects. Animals may feel sadness, although their weaker imagination does
not allow for deep anxiety. Their emotions, according to Kant’s account, are
not always involuntary, nor are they always precognitive. The idea of captivity
brings them the idea of a miserable future, which triggers the affect of sadness.
Thus, the pain model will not even explain the emotions Kant ascribes
to animals.
Humans have another level of emotions, the one connected with moral
judgments. This third level, the displeasure of spirit, the pure active part of the
self, is completely absent in animals, since it depends on reason that awakes
self-reproach. The moral conscience would create in the agent the feeling of
displeasure because she knows that she has not acted well. Self-reproach is,
then, an illustration of an intellectual displeasure, caused just by a concept.
As we have seen, in the classification of the faculty of pleasure and displeasure
(Ant, 7: 230), we have the division between sensuous and intellectual pleasure.
While the former can be produced by sensation or imagination, the latter is
conceived by concepts or by ideas. In the case of self-reproach, displeasure is
produced by the idea of moral law.
Passions, which belong to the faculty of desire, are also related to the active
self, since agents form maxims according to their passions. The thirst for
vengeance, evil as it may appear, is still a maxim of reason, developed out of an
Sympathy and affects belong to the reactive realm of the soul. They are
phenomena that are different from pain, in that they require other faculties
besides sensation, and they are different from moral feelings, in that they are
not provoked by a concept. That is why neither the pain model nor Baron’s
model can explain them.
The affects are typically reactive agitations, or reactions to something that
has affected our mind. Kant’s view of these feelings, which include anger,
joy, sadness, and fear, is usually negative: affect acts like a surprise through
sensation, suspending the composure of mind. Therefore, emotions are
precipitate and also have the unwanted property of growing to a degree of
feeling that makes reflection impossible (Ant, 7: 252).
Being like a surprise, this kind of feeling cannot be directly controlled by
the will. We can decide whether or not to perform a correct action, and hence
whether we will feel moral pleasure or displeasure resulting from such action.
But we cannot decide whether it is appropriate to feel anger in a particular
situation. Sometimes, we feel anger, even if we do not desire to feel it, other
times we can think it would be fair to feel it, although we are insensible in
the situation. Kant illustrates this possibility in the Anthropology, mentioning
Socrates, who was in doubt whether it would be good to be angry sometimes,
since it is paradoxical to have emotion so much under control that one can
cold-bloodedly deliberate whether or not one ought to be angry (Ant, 7:
253). We cannot deliberate about feeling angry, although anger does not
lack cognitive content. The affects have fewer cognitive elements than moral
feelings; however, they have more cognitive elements than pain or other mere
physical feelings. Anger involves the perception that something unfair was
done, which hurts the agent or is against her conception of justice. We do not
feel anger the way we feel pain; we feel anger when we realize that something
in a situation is offensive or unfair.
Sympathy is a sensible feeling that admits of choice. It can be cultivated,
in order to give a correct response in situations where we need practical
benevolence. It is a phenomenon of the reactive part of the soul, which can be
changed by the active part. Sympathy, as referred to by Kant in the Doctrine
If a person comes to your room in anger in order to say harsh words in great
wrath, politely ask him to be seated, and, if you succeed in this, his scolding
will already be milder because the comfort of sitting is a relaxation which
does not really conform to the menacing gesticulations and screaming
while one is standing. (Ant, 7: 252)
In this case, one should make the angry man sit down, because the comfort of
sitting is a relaxation, which does not conform to a great wrath. As for fright,
he mentions the disagreeable digestive effects that can affect soldiers before
a battle (Ant, 7: 257). Kant’s account of the incontrollable and even highly
undesirable outcomes of these emotions agrees with contemporary findings
in physiology, according to which emotions may cause effects related to the
autonomic neural system.19 These physiological components of emotions are
responsible for the difficulty to controlling them,20 since they have an inertial
component, which is not easy to handle.
For Kant, emotions do have evaluative components, but, with the exception
of passion, they are also feelings, which have physiological features. This is
why Kant recommends that we should soothe the movements of a mad man,
making him sit down and relax. The soothing of movements will help to calm
the affect of anger itself.
We can say that Kant is between the propositional attitude school and
the feeling theory.21 According to Griffiths,22 the former explains emotional
phenomena mainly by beliefs and desires,23 while the latter claims that emotions
are characterized by a quality and intensity of sensation. Kant proposes a
view of the emotions according to which they are intentional states as well
as feelings. They are intentional states24 in so far as they are about something,
or directed to something in the world beyond themselves. We are not only
mad, as we feel pain, but we are mad with someone or at something, we are
not in love without an intentional object, we are in love with someone. As
intentional states, they have a propositional content, and also bring evaluation
and cognitive elements, as feelings they present physiological arousal. In this
way, he can overcome the dichotomy of thought and feeling. Kant will not
deny that an emotion has mental content. However, it is not only a desire for,
or a judgment about something. Physiological processes also accompany it.
He would agree with the propositional attitude school, in that there is no
sense in attributing sadness without the idea that something valuable was
lost, or anger without the idea of something offensive done by someone.
We are angry with a specific person or at a determinate situation; anger
consequently has an intentional object. However, he seems to acknowledge
that for some strong emotions, such as anger, a physiological arousal seems
to be a necessary condition for emotion. In the case of anger, the man has
to sit in order to calm himself, because anger is accompanied by a strong
do it for him. Reason will tell him this is not the right thing to do. Anger
could inform us that someone did us some harm and trigger the desire of
vengeance. Yet reason will tell that vengeance is not the right thing to do. As
Michael Moore correctly remarks, for Kantian morality “the emotions that
generate a moral belief are irrelevant to the truth of that belief.”26 In that sense,
good emotions could give rise to false as well as to true moral beliefs. This
does not imply that emotions are not connected with beliefs. In the end, what
Kant offers us is the more subtle idea that emotions are connected with moral
assessment, yet a moral command based solely on emotion cannot be validated
without further rational considerations. Our compassion for a murderer who
has had an awful childhood could let us forgive his crimes; our sympathy for a
friend who suffers could lead us to not telling her a sad truth. Yet these are not
morally right courses of action.
If we take into account that passions can also be put under the label of
emotions, then here we have a different relation between emotions and
morality. While affects hinder momentarily the sound use of reason, passions
are always evil. They also have a different relation with physiological arousal,
and seem not to exhibit them just like feelings do. Thirst of vengeance,
greed, lust of power, ambition can be accompanied by no physiological
arousal, since they have characteristics of a cold-blooded reason. They are
more desires than feelings, having a salient intentional object and lacking
physiological disturbances.
We can still say that the majority of emotions usually have both intentional
object and physiological arousal, since for the most part they are feelings.
However, passions lack physiological arousal and can be conceived rather
as a strong desire of something, being then defined more specifically as
propositional attitudes than as internal feelings. Kant shows sophistication
in dividing what we usually call emotions into two kinds of events: feelings
of pleasure and displeasure and passions, both of which are composed by
different components.
Emotions have cognitive and evaluative content; however, they are not
trustworthy in showing us what to do. Is the cognitive content of emotions
therefore useless for morality? I don’t think this is Kant’s answer, since he
recommends, for instance, that one should visit places where people suffer
in order to awake our natural sympathy. He presents a more sophisticated
approach, where the content of our emotions should be scrutinized by reason.
What does the Kantian account of emotions teach us about the relations
between feelings and morality? First, emotions do not constitute a radically
different realm from cognition and morality. For Sabini and Silver, on the
other hand, morality and emotions constitute two different realms, and for
Baron they are concurrent domains. Radical difference, supported by Sabini
and Silver, would make emotions irrational feelings; the total coincidence
(Baron) would imply both that we can be considered responsible for what
we feel, and that emotions can be easily controlled by reason. The former
conception is wrong because texts such as the Doctrine of Virtue explicitly
show how we could and should cultivate some emotions in order to accomplish
benevolent actions, when respect for the moral law is not a sufficient incentive.
But Baron’s statement that we are responsible for the way we feel is also not
true, because there are some emotions like fright and anger, that arise in our
self without permission and do not permit easy control. Hence, the relations
Kant establishes between morality and emotion are more complex than total
distinction or total similarity.
There is no unique answer regarding the role of emotions in morality,
since they have a multiple reference to a continuum ranging from reactive
phenomena to active phenomena of the self. An example of the latter is moral
feeling, which is generated by the consciousness of the moral value of an
action. Most of what we call emotions, however, lies in the reactive part of
the soul. But here also we have a continuum: from affects, which are the most
Can we be held responsible for our emotions? It is true that some emotions of
the reactive self, such as joy, sadness, and longing, are intimately connected
with imagination and this faculty does have the power to modulate affects.
However, the power of imagination cannot deny the evidence for my belief
in a bad or good future. Although we can modulate some affects through
imagination, we cannot decide not to have them or to have them at ease.
Imagination of a future state of pleasure or displeasure should be connected
with a possible state of affairs. If the sick man could not work in the future
because of his gout, he cannot prevent the feeling of sadness for the bad future
he imagines. Or, he can even trigger for some moments the affect of joy when