WhatKantCanTeachUsAboutEmotionMariaBorges PDF

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 21

Borges, Maria. "What can Kant teach us about emotions?.

" Emotion, Reason, and Action in


Kant. London: Bloomsbury Academic, 2019. 85–104. Bloomsbury Collections. Web. 2 Apr. 2020.
<http://dx.doi.org/10.5040/9781350078390.0011>.

Downloaded from Bloomsbury Collections, www.bloomsburycollections.com, 2 April 2020,


20:31 UTC.

Copyright © Maria Borges 2019. You may share this work for non-commercial purposes only,
provided you give attribution to the copyright holder and the publisher.
4
What can Kant teach us
about emotions?1

The pain model

It is a hard task to support my thesis that Kant can teach us something about
emotions and bring important contributions to the contemporary debate
about this issue. Kant has long been seen as the philosopher who denies any
important role to emotions. To those who read just the first section of the
Groundwork, it seems to be a clear-cut case that emotions do not possess
intrinsic moral value. For instance, Kant writes that while the sympathetic
philanthropist performs an action without moral worth, the absence of
sympathy in the heart of the insensible one makes his action morally worthy.2
This fact presumably inspired Sabini and Silver to claim in their article
“Emotions, Responsibility and Character” that “a Kantian chapter on emotion
and responsibility is easy to write and quick to read. The domain of the moral
is the domain of the will expressed in action: it is the domain of that for which
we are responsible. Emotions are beyond the will, and for this reason have no
intrinsic moral value.”3
According to these authors, emotions have no moral value because they
follow the pain model.4 Just like pain, which is a fact about us, regardless of
values or other aspects of our character, emotions, even the most complex

Emotion, Reason and Action in Kant.indb 85 18-01-2019 13:36:39


86 EMOTION, REASON, AND ACTION IN KANT

ones, do not fall under the command of reason. Kant, just like more recent
psychologists and physiologists, is said to embrace a model in which
emotions are precognitive,5 mere perceptions of unspecified bodily states,6
or undifferentiated states of the sympathetic nervous system. Emotions, like
pain, would be nothing more than the stimulation of nerves, disconnected
from values, character, or reason. A supporter of the pain-like conception of
emotions is Zajonc. In his paper “Feeling and Thinking, Preferences Need No
Inference” he shows that there is a direct pathway from perceptual system to
emotional responses. Accordingly, emotions are not connected with reasoning
and values. According to Sabini and Silver, Zajonc’s model is the same as Kant’s.
Both place the emotions completely out of the moral domain. Hence, we could
be held responsible for the expression of our mental states, but not for having
them. Besides this, in Sabini and Silver’s view, certain emotional states are like
the pain of withdrawal for a drug addict, in which any responsibility for action
is attenuated by the intensity of the stimuli.7
Marcia Baron, in her book Kantian Ethics Almost without Apology, criticizes
the Sabini/Silver position, objecting that the pain model is not the one Kant
uses for explaining emotion:

This [Kantian] model, with its very strong notion of agency, is diametrically
opposed to the picture drawn by Sabini and Silver, according to which
emotions function, on Kant’s view, much as pain does. It is a serious mistake
to think that Kant’s psychology even approximately fits the model of pain
and that feelings such as sympathy “move us to act without our rational
assent or assessment.” . . . Similarly, it would be more plausible to criticize
Kant for attributing to us too much responsibility for our feelings and
emotions than to attribute to him the position that we are not responsible
for them.8

Baron’s position is radically distinct from Sabini and Silver’s: we are not
passive regarding our feelings; we are responsible for the way we feel. Even if

Emotion, Reason and Action in Kant.indb 86 18-01-2019 13:36:39


WHAT CAN KANT TEACH US ABOUT EMOTIONS? 87

the Critique of Practical Reason and the Groundwork could justify a negative
conception of emotions, as phenomena incapable of being controlled by
reason, Baron claims that this conception requires revision when later texts
are taken into consideration, such as Religion within the Boundaries of Mere
Reason, The Metaphysics of Morals, and Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point
of View.
I shall try to show that neither model can fully explain Kant’s view of
emotions. Baron has a point in saying that we cannot explain some emotions
through the pain model, like sympathy and gratitude, which can be cultivated.
However, Kant does describe some affects as involuntary and passive, such
as fright in battles, which overcomes the agent regardless of his will, causing
disagreeable physical effects. In this case, Baron’s claim that we are not passive
regarding our emotions does not apply to Kantian morality. I will argue that
Kant does have a robust conception of agency, in spite of our being passive
regarding some emotions. However, if emotions are not in our power, this
does not imply that they lack cognitive elements. People can feel anger without
wanting it, but they in fact feel anger because they think something unfair
or harmful has been done. Baron is right that there are some feelings like
sympathy that are not beyond rational control; however, they cannot be a
model for all feelings.
My claim is that Kant presents us with a very colorful, wide range of emotions,
which cannot be captured in one model type, be it a pain or a sympathy model.
This diversity does not allow a simple answer concerning their voluntary or
involuntary nature, or concerning the influence of physiological factors. Kant
makes room for this complex picture when he connects them to our passive,
active, or reactive self, as well as to superior and inferior faculties. My strategy
will be, first, to present the taxonomy of emotions, and then place them in what
I call a map of the self. After this first presentation of the Kantian picture, I will
address some philosophical issues and relate Kant’s theory to contemporary
discussion on emotions.

Emotion, Reason and Action in Kant.indb 87 18-01-2019 13:36:39


88 EMOTION, REASON, AND ACTION IN KANT

Emotions in the map of the self

First of all, Kant does not use the term “emotion.”9 What we pre-analytically
call emotion refers to at least three different kinds of phenomena: affects,10
moral feelings, and passions. These inclinations11 can be mainly related to
two faculties: the faculty of feeling pleasure and displeasure and the faculty of
desire. Feelings of pleasure or displeasure caused by an object can be sensible
or intellectual. The former are caused by sensation or imagination; the latter
are triggered by a concept or idea (Ant, 7: 230). Pleasure and displeasure given
by sensibility alone are feelings of gratification and pain. Sensible pleasure and
displeasure admit also two other kinds of inclination, caused by imagination:
sympathy and affects. The difference between them is that sympathy can be
cultivated, while we are passive with respect to affects.12
Affects are feelings of pleasure or displeasure that hinder the reflection
through which inclinations were to be submitted to rational maxims; they are
sudden and rash, making reflection impossible (TL, 6: 408), such as water that
breaks through a dam or a stroke of apoplexy (Ant, 7: 252). They can lead the
agent to moral blindness, since they hinder deliberation, with the consolation
that this tempest easily goes away and calms itself, allowing the subject to
go back to a state where reflection is possible again. He cites the example of
someone who marries out of love and is blind to the flaws in the character of
her beloved, but regains her vision a week after marriage (Ant, 7: 253). The
Kantian paradigmatic example for affect is anger, a tempestuous feeling by
nature, and fickle like love. Sympathy, although it is a sensible feeling (TL, 6:
456), can be trained in order to help the accomplishment of moral actions,
when respect for the moral law is not a sufficient incentive.
However, pleasures and displeasures are not all sensible; we also have
the intellectual ones, caused by an idea or concept. These include feelings
that make the mind receptive to the concept of duty, such as moral feeling,
which is defined as “a susceptibility to feel pleasure or displeasure from the

Emotion, Reason and Action in Kant.indb 88 18-01-2019 13:36:39


WHAT CAN KANT TEACH US ABOUT EMOTIONS? 89

consciousness that our actions are consistent or contrary to the laws of duty”
(TL, 6: 399).13 Love for human beings belongs also to the receptivity of the
mind to the concept of duty. Intellectual pleasures include love of benevolence,
but not love of satisfaction. The former but not the latter could be ordered as
a duty, since it would be contradictory to have a duty to feel pleasure. Love
of benevolence admits of something like Aristotelian cultivation, for it is a
disposition that can be awakened by habit.14
Kant’s realm of inclinations also includes passion, which is related to the
faculty of desire and refers to a strong desire for something. Passions exhibit a
contradictory nature. On the one hand, Kant says that they hinder the control
of reason to compare at a particular moment, a specific inclination against
the sum of all inclinations (Ant, 7: 265). On the other hand, they admit some
rational deliberation about the means to obtain what the agent desires. One
good case is given in the Anthropology, where Kant compares the inability
of a man who feels the affect of love to seduce someone, to the skill of one
who is taken by the passion of love. The first will not be successful, while the
second can easily trap the helpless victim (Ant, 6: 265). The difference is that
one is immersed in a full agitation of the mind, while the other keeps a cold
blood to plot the way to obtain it. This case depicts the difference Kant makes
between the meaning of affects and passion, a difference that is also illustrated
in outstanding literary works, such as Dangerous Liaisons.15 While affects are
outbursts of feelings, which cannot coexist even with a prudential rationality,
passions show their cunning. The same difference can be seen when one
compares the affect of hate with the passion of anger: while the latter is fickle,
the former is a permanent disposition, which inclines the agent to plot a cold
blood vengeance.
In order to improve our understanding of Kant’s model or models for
emotions, it is helpful to locate them in relation to a Kantian sketch of the
self.16 Kant claims there are three instances of soul17 in a generic sense,
whose reference in each case is the self. The self can be observed in a triple

Emotion, Reason and Action in Kant.indb 89 18-01-2019 13:36:39


90 EMOTION, REASON, AND ACTION IN KANT

perspective: as passive, reactive, or purely active. This tripartite division of the


self is connected with the superior and inferior faculties. The inferior faculty
corresponds to the passive part; the superior faculty, as active, corresponds to
the perspective of both a purely active self and a reactive one.
The superior/inferior distinction applies to all three faculties: the cognitive
faculty, the faculty of desire, and the feeling of pleasure and displeasure. As
regards the faculty of feeling, we have pleasure or displeasure of sensibility
alone through the inferior faculty, while the pleasures, given by imagination
and understanding, belong to the superior faculty. This difference can be
illustrated when one contrasts pain, which belongs to the inferior faculty of
feeling, to the feelings of pleasure and displeasure in the superior faculty, such
as moral feeling. Physical pain seems not to allow a rational control, because
it is displeasure of the animal or appetitive soul. Pain is defined as “displeasure
of sensation,” and is explained by the effect produced in the mind by the
sensation of one’s physical condition. Totally opposed to physical pain, we have
the pleasure or displeasure due to a concept, such as the moral feeling of The
Metaphysics of Morals. This feeling is an effect of the concept of duty: the moral
feeling “is the susceptibility to feel pleasure or displeasure merely from being
aware that our actions are consistent with or contrary to the law of duty” (MS,
6: 399). Hence, there is a big contrast between pain and moral sentiments,
even though they could both be classified as feelings: the first one is related
to the inferior faculty of feeling, connected with sensibility; the second one is
related to the superior one, connected with reason. While physical pain is an
involuntary, precognitive feeling, moral feeling includes the concept of a right
action. We cannot decide whether we will feel pain or not, while we can decide
whether we will feel a moral pleasure, because this requires just that we act
according to the moral law.
The inferior faculty of pleasure is responsible for purely sensible phenomena
such as pain, hunger, and thirst. The superior faculty of pleasure relates to
the reactive and active self. The sensation of displeasure that we feel when

Emotion, Reason and Action in Kant.indb 90 18-01-2019 13:36:39


WHAT CAN KANT TEACH US ABOUT EMOTIONS? 91

we know that our actions are wrong is associated with the active self, since it
is a feeling connected with a concept: the concept of duty. Between the pure
passive and the pure active part of the self, abide the reactive feelings, which
still belong to the superior faculty of feeling, and refer to affects and sensibility.
Kant, who was a well-known hypochondriac, illustrates in his Lectures on
Anthropology the difference between passive, reactive, and active feelings with
a case of a man who suffers from gout:

I cannot prevent the pain inflicted on my body from passing into my soul.
I can only prevent that my soul reflects over this, e.g., when I have gout and
think what will become of me in the future, how I will acquire my bread
and this causes sadness over the state of my health, here animus agitates.
The sickness of the mind is also what makes me miserable. Because such
reflection never attaches to animals, they are never miserable. But finally the
highest degree of sadness arises when my spirit abstracts from all pain and
awakens in me a self-reproach, when it imagines to itself how I brought this
illness upon myself and became unhappy through my own fault. (AntPa,
25: 247–48)

We can clearly see, in this quotation, the difference between three levels of
displeasure. The first one is purely physical, beyond control, even indirectly.
Since it is purely sensible, it is independent of any cognitive content; the
subject feels a certain wound as pain. This is an example of the inferior faculty
of pleasure and displeasure, where the feeling is given through sensation alone.
The second level relates to the displeasure of an affect, sadness, and allows
a nonphysical cause: sadness is caused by the imagination that agitates the
mind when the agent worries about the future. Here we have the reactive part
of the self, which relates to the superior faculty of feeling. Sadness is aroused
by imagination, which agitates the mind. Animals, Kant argues, are never
miserable, although they can feel the pain of a wound. However, Kant claims
in another lecture, “On Philosophers’ Medicine of the Body,” that animals do

Emotion, Reason and Action in Kant.indb 91 18-01-2019 13:36:39


92 EMOTION, REASON, AND ACTION IN KANT

have imagination, although in cattle “this force [of imagination] is not directed
by any choice or deliberate intention of animal.” Since some animals do have
imagination, Kant can conceive that a certain illness may oppress the mind
of the animal when it is brought into captivity, “yet the black anxiety that
afflicts the miserable human race escapes the animal, which knows nothing
of worry.”18 To mention animal mind, which can be affected by sadness, ipso
facto refutes the idea that Kantian affects fit the pain model, since even animals
are supposed to have affects triggered by imagination. The very idea of being
in captivity can trigger in their minds some emotions of sadness. In human
beings, this faculty is supposed to be even stronger, giving a deeper force to
affects. Animals may feel sadness, although their weaker imagination does
not allow for deep anxiety. Their emotions, according to Kant’s account, are
not always involuntary, nor are they always precognitive. The idea of captivity
brings them the idea of a miserable future, which triggers the affect of sadness.
Thus, the pain model will not even explain the emotions Kant ascribes
to animals.
Humans have another level of emotions, the one connected with moral
judgments. This third level, the displeasure of spirit, the pure active part of the
self, is completely absent in animals, since it depends on reason that awakes
self-reproach. The moral conscience would create in the agent the feeling of
displeasure because she knows that she has not acted well. Self-reproach is,
then, an illustration of an intellectual displeasure, caused just by a concept.
As we have seen, in the classification of the faculty of pleasure and displeasure
(Ant, 7: 230), we have the division between sensuous and intellectual pleasure.
While the former can be produced by sensation or imagination, the latter is
conceived by concepts or by ideas. In the case of self-reproach, displeasure is
produced by the idea of moral law.
Passions, which belong to the faculty of desire, are also related to the active
self, since agents form maxims according to their passions. The thirst for
vengeance, evil as it may appear, is still a maxim of reason, developed out of an

Emotion, Reason and Action in Kant.indb 92 18-01-2019 13:36:39


WHAT CAN KANT TEACH US ABOUT EMOTIONS? 93

injustice suffered. History gives many illustrations of plotted murders based on


hatred, sometimes based on the ambition and lust of power. Such passions lead
the mind to accept evil maxims, in order to accomplish its ends. That is why
Kant claims that passions manifest certain characteristics of reason (Ant, 7: 270).
What should we conclude from this taxonomy of emotions? Since the pain
model is obviously ruled out, should we assume that Baron is right? Are we,
according to Kant, responsible for our emotions? Since Kant supposes that
humans can have moral feelings of displeasure according to the rightness or
wrongness of our actions, is it the case that we do have control over all emotions?
The answer is negative, moral feelings are but one part of the wide range of
emotions. The nature of moral feelings, as something produced by the concept
of moral correctness, hence controllable, arises from its belonging to the active
part of the self. Nevertheless, between the purely passive part, where the feeling
of pleasure depends on the form through which the object affects sensibility, and
the purely active part, in which the satisfaction should relate directly to a concept,
we have a variety of intermediary phenomena, such as sympathy and affects.
This reconstruction gives us the following table, where emotions are in
bold letters:

Faculty of feeling pleasure or displeasure Faculty of desire

Inferior faculty Superior faculty of feeling Propensity Instinct Inclinations Passions


of feeling (hate, greed, lust
of power,
ambition)

Passive self: Reactive self: Active self:


soul, anima, Seele mind, animus, spirit, mens,
Gemüth Geist

Pain, hunger Affects (anger, Moral


sadness, joy) feelings

Sympathy and affects belong to the reactive realm of the soul. They are
phenomena that are different from pain, in that they require other faculties

Emotion, Reason and Action in Kant.indb 93 18-01-2019 13:36:39


94 EMOTION, REASON, AND ACTION IN KANT

besides sensation, and they are different from moral feelings, in that they are
not provoked by a concept. That is why neither the pain model nor Baron’s
model can explain them.
The affects are typically reactive agitations, or reactions to something that
has affected our mind. Kant’s view of these feelings, which include anger,
joy, sadness, and fear, is usually negative: affect acts like a surprise through
sensation, suspending the composure of mind. Therefore, emotions are
precipitate and also have the unwanted property of growing to a degree of
feeling that makes reflection impossible (Ant, 7: 252).
Being like a surprise, this kind of feeling cannot be directly controlled by
the will. We can decide whether or not to perform a correct action, and hence
whether we will feel moral pleasure or displeasure resulting from such action.
But we cannot decide whether it is appropriate to feel anger in a particular
situation. Sometimes, we feel anger, even if we do not desire to feel it, other
times we can think it would be fair to feel it, although we are insensible in
the situation. Kant illustrates this possibility in the Anthropology, mentioning
Socrates, who was in doubt whether it would be good to be angry sometimes,
since it is paradoxical to have emotion so much under control that one can
cold-bloodedly deliberate whether or not one ought to be angry (Ant, 7:
253). We cannot deliberate about feeling angry, although anger does not
lack cognitive content. The affects have fewer cognitive elements than moral
feelings; however, they have more cognitive elements than pain or other mere
physical feelings. Anger involves the perception that something unfair was
done, which hurts the agent or is against her conception of justice. We do not
feel anger the way we feel pain; we feel anger when we realize that something
in a situation is offensive or unfair.
Sympathy is a sensible feeling that admits of choice. It can be cultivated,
in order to give a correct response in situations where we need practical
benevolence. It is a phenomenon of the reactive part of the soul, which can be
changed by the active part. Sympathy, as referred to by Kant in the Doctrine

Emotion, Reason and Action in Kant.indb 94 18-01-2019 13:36:39


WHAT CAN KANT TEACH US ABOUT EMOTIONS? 95

of Virtue, fits the conception of sensitivity mentioned in the Anthropology. It


is a natural feeling, which should be cultivated and used when the respect for
moral law is not sufficient to trigger moral actions.
Feelings from the animal (or passive) part of the self are involuntary, and
cannot have their sensation controlled. This is the case with pain, thirst,
hunger, and so on. In the other extreme, we have the pleasure and displeasure
of the active self, such as moral feelings and the feeling of respect, which are
controllable through our actions, since they are outcomes of good or evil
actions. In between lies affect, a phenomenon of the reactive part of the self,
which is connected with the imagination.
When we mention reactive feelings, such as affects, we should consider
also that some strong affects have involuntary outcomes, which involve strong
physiological arousal. Kant cites two highly illustrative cases in this connection,
related to anger and fright. About anger, he mentions the situation of a man
who enters one’s room in anger in order to say harsh words:

If a person comes to your room in anger in order to say harsh words in great
wrath, politely ask him to be seated, and, if you succeed in this, his scolding
will already be milder because the comfort of sitting is a relaxation which
does not really conform to the menacing gesticulations and screaming
while one is standing. (Ant, 7: 252)

In this case, one should make the angry man sit down, because the comfort of
sitting is a relaxation, which does not conform to a great wrath. As for fright,
he mentions the disagreeable digestive effects that can affect soldiers before
a battle (Ant, 7: 257). Kant’s account of the incontrollable and even highly
undesirable outcomes of these emotions agrees with contemporary findings
in physiology, according to which emotions may cause effects related to the
autonomic neural system.19 These physiological components of emotions are
responsible for the difficulty to controlling them,20 since they have an inertial
component, which is not easy to handle.

Emotion, Reason and Action in Kant.indb 95 18-01-2019 13:36:39


96 EMOTION, REASON, AND ACTION IN KANT

Between the propositional attitude


school and the feeling theory

For Kant, emotions do have evaluative components, but, with the exception
of passion, they are also feelings, which have physiological features. This is
why Kant recommends that we should soothe the movements of a mad man,
making him sit down and relax. The soothing of movements will help to calm
the affect of anger itself.
We can say that Kant is between the propositional attitude school and
the feeling theory.21 According to Griffiths,22 the former explains emotional
phenomena mainly by beliefs and desires,23 while the latter claims that emotions
are characterized by a quality and intensity of sensation. Kant proposes a
view of the emotions according to which they are intentional states as well
as feelings. They are intentional states24 in so far as they are about something,
or directed to something in the world beyond themselves. We are not only
mad, as we feel pain, but we are mad with someone or at something, we are
not in love without an intentional object, we are in love with someone. As
intentional states, they have a propositional content, and also bring evaluation
and cognitive elements, as feelings they present physiological arousal. In this
way, he can overcome the dichotomy of thought and feeling. Kant will not
deny that an emotion has mental content. However, it is not only a desire for,
or a judgment about something. Physiological processes also accompany it.
He would agree with the propositional attitude school, in that there is no
sense in attributing sadness without the idea that something valuable was
lost, or anger without the idea of something offensive done by someone.
We are angry with a specific person or at a determinate situation; anger
consequently has an intentional object. However, he seems to acknowledge
that for some strong emotions, such as anger, a physiological arousal seems
to be a necessary condition for emotion. In the case of anger, the man has
to sit in order to calm himself, because anger is accompanied by a strong

Emotion, Reason and Action in Kant.indb 96 18-01-2019 13:36:39


WHAT CAN KANT TEACH US ABOUT EMOTIONS? 97

physiological arousal, which cannot be instantly overcome by the sole


reasoning about the emotion.
Will this physiological arousal also accompany emotions related to the
active part of the self, such as moral feelings? The answer is yes. Although
moral feelings are ultimately caused by an idea, the idea of moral correction
of an action, they are still feelings of pleasure and displeasure. Although
here the physiological arousal is not as strong as in anger, the idea of feelings
brings with it pleasure and displeasure, which is impossible without any
physiological component.
All emotions that are feelings of pleasure and displeasure have both
components: evaluative contents and physiological arousal. Emotions express
beliefs. In the case of the man who suffers from gout, his sadness is related to
the belief that a gloomy future is waiting for him. His feeling guilty is related
to the belief that he has contributed to his actual misery. The pain model does
not apply to the Kantian account of emotions, because beliefs and desires are
constitutive of these mental states. However, Baron’s picture is not accurate
either, since emotions are also composed by physiological components, which
are scarcely under our control.
What kind of cognition is involved in emotions? Kant will certainly deny
that emotions are mere reflexes, like pain, without any moral evaluation of
a state of affairs. Some affects involve moral assessment, and they can be
valuable in giving us information about the moral salience of a situation.25
Sympathy can give us information about someone in distress. However, to
ascribe cognitive value to emotions is not to say they have normative value.
Emotions cannot tell us what to do; this is the task only of reason. Sympathy
could inform us about the existence of someone in need, but only reason
can tell if it is morally correct to help this person in that situation. Sympathy
is connected with the belief that someone needs our help. Yet this emotion
cannot validate for itself that it is right to help that person. A student can feel
sympathy for a colleague who cannot do his own assignment, and want to

Emotion, Reason and Action in Kant.indb 97 18-01-2019 13:36:40


98 EMOTION, REASON, AND ACTION IN KANT

do it for him. Reason will tell him this is not the right thing to do. Anger
could inform us that someone did us some harm and trigger the desire of
vengeance. Yet reason will tell that vengeance is not the right thing to do. As
Michael Moore correctly remarks, for Kantian morality “the emotions that
generate a moral belief are irrelevant to the truth of that belief.”26 In that sense,
good emotions could give rise to false as well as to true moral beliefs. This
does not imply that emotions are not connected with beliefs. In the end, what
Kant offers us is the more subtle idea that emotions are connected with moral
assessment, yet a moral command based solely on emotion cannot be validated
without further rational considerations. Our compassion for a murderer who
has had an awful childhood could let us forgive his crimes; our sympathy for a
friend who suffers could lead us to not telling her a sad truth. Yet these are not
morally right courses of action.
If we take into account that passions can also be put under the label of
emotions, then here we have a different relation between emotions and
morality. While affects hinder momentarily the sound use of reason, passions
are always evil. They also have a different relation with physiological arousal,
and seem not to exhibit them just like feelings do. Thirst of vengeance,
greed, lust of power, ambition can be accompanied by no physiological
arousal, since they have characteristics of a cold-blooded reason. They are
more desires than feelings, having a salient intentional object and lacking
physiological disturbances.
We can still say that the majority of emotions usually have both intentional
object and physiological arousal, since for the most part they are feelings.
However, passions lack physiological arousal and can be conceived rather
as a strong desire of something, being then defined more specifically as
propositional attitudes than as internal feelings. Kant shows sophistication
in dividing what we usually call emotions into two kinds of events: feelings
of pleasure and displeasure and passions, both of which are composed by
different components.

Emotion, Reason and Action in Kant.indb 98 18-01-2019 13:36:40


WHAT CAN KANT TEACH US ABOUT EMOTIONS? 99

Are emotions useless for Kantian morality?

Emotions have cognitive and evaluative content; however, they are not
trustworthy in showing us what to do. Is the cognitive content of emotions
therefore useless for morality? I don’t think this is Kant’s answer, since he
recommends, for instance, that one should visit places where people suffer
in order to awake our natural sympathy. He presents a more sophisticated
approach, where the content of our emotions should be scrutinized by reason.
What does the Kantian account of emotions teach us about the relations
between feelings and morality? First, emotions do not constitute a radically
different realm from cognition and morality. For Sabini and Silver, on the
other hand, morality and emotions constitute two different realms, and for
Baron they are concurrent domains. Radical difference, supported by Sabini
and Silver, would make emotions irrational feelings; the total coincidence
(Baron) would imply both that we can be considered responsible for what
we feel, and that emotions can be easily controlled by reason. The former
conception is wrong because texts such as the Doctrine of Virtue explicitly
show how we could and should cultivate some emotions in order to accomplish
benevolent actions, when respect for the moral law is not a sufficient incentive.
But Baron’s statement that we are responsible for the way we feel is also not
true, because there are some emotions like fright and anger, that arise in our
self without permission and do not permit easy control. Hence, the relations
Kant establishes between morality and emotion are more complex than total
distinction or total similarity.
There is no unique answer regarding the role of emotions in morality,
since they have a multiple reference to a continuum ranging from reactive
phenomena to active phenomena of the self. An example of the latter is moral
feeling, which is generated by the consciousness of the moral value of an
action. Most of what we call emotions, however, lies in the reactive part of
the soul. But here also we have a continuum: from affects, which are the most

Emotion, Reason and Action in Kant.indb 99 18-01-2019 13:36:40


100 EMOTION, REASON, AND ACTION IN KANT

uncontrollable, such as anger or fright, to sympathy, which can be modulated


by the will in order to help the accomplishment of moral actions. At one
extreme, we have anger and fright, at the other, sympathy and moral feelings.
The mistake of commentators is to consider that emotions in Kant have
only one model and refer to only one kind of event, when, in fact, they
refer to a multiplicity of different phenomena, which demand different
explanations. These mistakes in defining a correct concept of emotion result
in a misunderstanding of its role in morality. Anger can bring with it moral
assessment about the unfairness of a situation; however, since it is an affect, it
will make deliberation more difficult and will be a hindrance to moral action.
Sympathy, although sharing with affects some features, because it is still a
feeling of the reactive self, can be shaped by the will in order to help morality.
Moral feeling, as a feeling of the active self, is directly connected with morality
and with the moral evaluation of a situation.
Passions have a special relation with morality: they are, with no exception,
evil. They are not, like affects, only agitations of the soul, which hinder
reflection and moral deliberation. Moreover, some affects can give us moral
information about the situation, although they are immoderate and difficult
to control. Passions, however, are quite the opposite: they are immoral desires
for something. Thirst for vengeance and power, greed and ambition present a
perversion of moral goodness, since they are related to an evil deliberation of
a mind that is not disturbed by affections.

The role of imagination

One of the problems regarding the propositional attitude theory is that it


cannot fully acknowledge the role imagination plays in the production of
emotions. Kant makes room for imagination in his account. Emotions are not
feelings without any cognitive content; therefore, they do not belong to the

Emotion, Reason and Action in Kant.indb 100 18-01-2019 13:36:40


WHAT CAN KANT TEACH US ABOUT EMOTIONS? 101

realm of total involuntariness. They are feelings that can be awakened in us


through imagination or reason, produced by the reactive or active self.
Imagination plays an important role in the arousal of reactive affects. Sadness,
as we saw, results from the imagination of a future unwanted occurrence. It
is related, like joy, to the reproduction or anticipation of events. Kant cites
the homesickness of the Swiss as an illustration of the role of imagination:
the Swiss, when transferred to other lands, have the feeling of homesickness,
which is aroused by the recollection of places where they enjoyed the very
simple pleasures of life (Ant, 7: 178). Here, the recollection of good moments
in the past can produce this feeling. In the case of the sick man, he becomes
sad when he imagines a bad future and worries how he will make a living.
Imagination can intensify the feeling of sadness, as the example of animals that
are sad, but never miserable, shows, because they don’t have the intensity of
imagination human beings have.
In the text “On the Philosophers’ Medicine of the Body,” Kant ascribes to
imagination an even stronger force: the power of imagination can heal or
produce a disease. On the one hand, the confidence sick people put in their
doctors helps them through the imagination that they will be healed. On the
other hand, imagination could spread diseases like epilepsy, since it is able to
alter bodily movements.27 Since affects are movements of the mind that agitate
the body (Rek, 15: 940) and imagination can alter bodily movements, it can
also interfere with affects. However, this alteration should not be considered as
an effect of the direct power of the will.
Imagination can modify affects by bringing images to mind that cause
agreeable or disagreeable sensations. The role of imagination is clear in the
case of fear: just like sadness, which is caused by the anticipation of a bad
future, fear is caused by the anticipation of danger. These feelings, even though
they belong to the reactive part of the soul, have some cognitive elements that
go into the evaluation of images that come before the mind. The idea that
affects are blind and completely precognitive is wrong. Feelings of sadness,

Emotion, Reason and Action in Kant.indb 101 18-01-2019 13:36:40


102 EMOTION, REASON, AND ACTION IN KANT

joy, anger, and fear depend upon an appraisal of a situation reproduced or


anticipated by imagination.
However, from the fact that there is a cognitive judgment of images, we
cannot infer that they are easily controllable, which is a mistake of other
commentators who take sympathy as a model for all affects. Taking again the
case of the Lectures on Anthropology: I could decide that a state of sadness is
bad for my disease, even though, each time I think about my future, I become
sad, against my will. However, if the sick man suddenly remembers that he has
a million dollars in health insurance for gout, his future would suddenly appear
to him as a nicer one, and these images of a good and nice future will arouse
in him the feeling of relief. Moral feelings, like the pleasure or displeasure in
the rightness or wrongness of our conduct, can be more related to judgment
than to imagination. If the sick man were to reproach himself for his situation
in the former case, now that he remembers he has health insurance, he could
feel pleasure and self-satisfaction in being prudent and wise.

Can we be held responsible for


our emotions and actions?

Can we be held responsible for our emotions? It is true that some emotions of
the reactive self, such as joy, sadness, and longing, are intimately connected
with imagination and this faculty does have the power to modulate affects.
However, the power of imagination cannot deny the evidence for my belief
in a bad or good future. Although we can modulate some affects through
imagination, we cannot decide not to have them or to have them at ease.
Imagination of a future state of pleasure or displeasure should be connected
with a possible state of affairs. If the sick man could not work in the future
because of his gout, he cannot prevent the feeling of sadness for the bad future
he imagines. Or, he can even trigger for some moments the affect of joy when

Emotion, Reason and Action in Kant.indb 102 18-01-2019 13:36:40


WHAT CAN KANT TEACH US ABOUT EMOTIONS? 103

he remembers his past moments, but as soon as he focuses on his future


situation, this joy will be quickly turned into sadness.
If we are not responsible for our emotions, can we be responsible for our
actions? Emotions are said to be an obstacle to moral deliberation, and Kant
uses phrases such as water that breaks a dam in order to show the irrational
force of these feelings. However, he also draws on a strong picture of freedom,
which does not allow for pathological compulsion.28 We have strong emotions,
difficult to control, but we have means to tame them in order to act the way
we want. Virtue is one of these means. We are not responsible for emotions,
although we can be held responsible for actions, since the strength of emotions
cannot be equated to compulsion, such as the compulsion for drugs. Recently,
some philosophers have tried to establish this kind of parallel between strong
emotions and addiction.29 Kant would not accept this picture, because as
strong as emotions can be, and as much of a problem for morality they can
portray, the very idea of practical reason presupposes that agents can decide
how to act. In fact, the Kantian picture here is more likely to be accepted by
moral common sense, since a strong emotion can never be taken as a total
excuse for a bad action. Agents can mention strong anger to explain their
violent acts, yet not to forgive them. People are held responsible for wrong
actions due to strong emotions, because it is presupposed that they could have
acted otherwise.

What can Kant really teach us about emotions?

In order to explain emotions, philosophers have tried, with few exceptions,30


to build a single model for something that they supposed was a single kind of
mental event. But perhaps the key to the understanding of emotions is to grasp
their complexity and the different weight of rational and irrational components
each one has. Although Kant did not write one specific book on emotion, I

Emotion, Reason and Action in Kant.indb 103 18-01-2019 13:36:40


104 EMOTION, REASON, AND ACTION IN KANT

think he was very attentive to this variety of emotional events, particularly in


his anthropological works.
In this brief reconstruction of what could be a Kantian theory of emotion
and its relation to the passive, reactive, and active self, I have showed that this
kind of feeling presents different relations with our passive and active self.
Emotions cannot be explained by the pain model, because they are not outside
the rational domain, since they are also composed of evaluative beliefs and
judgments. They are not involuntary, nor are we responsible for feeling them.
They are phenomena of the reactive and active self, which can be modulated
by imagination or by reason, but we cannot provoke or extirpate them by the
sole power of the will. We can be held responsible for our acts, but not for our
emotions, which is what makes Baron’s model mistaken.
Kant’s model accepts features of both the propositional attitude model
and the feeling model. From the first, it takes the idea that emotions have an
intentional object, and from the feeling model, it takes the idea that emotions
are accompanied by physiological arousal. Emotions involve evaluative beliefs
and also physiological disturbances. The degree of physiological arousal
depends on whether emotions belong to the active or reactive self. And among
the later ones, there are emotions whose physiological arousals are stronger
than others. This is the case with anger, if compared to the mild affect of
longing or sadness.
Kant’s theory is more likely to be accepted by our common moral sense,
because it explains emotions as people actually feel them. It is a very sophisticated
theory that confirms the complexity of its object and does not allow for
unrefined explanations. And perhaps he shows his cunning in not using the
word emotion, but instead, other terms such as “affects,” “sympathy,” “moral
feelings,” and “passions,” in order to show that what we pre-analytically call
emotions refer to a wide variety of states, which call for different philosophical
categories. This insight agrees with some contemporary philosophers who
have recently challenged the idea that emotions form a unique class of events.

Emotion, Reason and Action in Kant.indb 104 18-01-2019 13:36:40

You might also like