Richard Biernacki - Language and The Shift From Signs To Practices in Cultural Inquiry
Richard Biernacki - Language and The Shift From Signs To Practices in Cultural Inquiry
Richard Biernacki - Language and The Shift From Signs To Practices in Cultural Inquiry
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Wiley and Wesleyan University are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to History
and Theory.
http://www.jstor.org
1.
RICHARDBIERNACKI
ABSTRACT
A model of culture as a partially coherent system of signs comprised the most widely
employed instrumentfor analyzing culturalmeaning among the new culturalhistorians.
However, the model failed to account for meanings that agents produce by executing
social practicesratherthan by only "reading"contrastsamong signs. It also encouraged
some analysts to conceive the difference between sign system and concrete practice as
that between what is graspable as an intellectual form and what remains inaccessibly
material or corporeal. This essay introduces three exemplars of the ties between signs
and practicesto show how the pragmaticsof using signs comprises a structureand a gen-
eratorof meaning in its own right. In the three exemplars,which are based on the tropes
of metonymy,metaphor,and irony, I employ the analytic tools of linguistics to appreci-
ate the non-discursiveorganizationof practice. Analysis of the diverse logics for orga-
nizing practice offers promising means for investigatinghow signs come to seem expe-
rientially real for their users. Finally, this view of culture in practice suggests new
hypotheses aboutthe possible interdependenciesas well as the lack of connection among
the elements of a culturalsetting.
The new cultural history has become both preeminent and old. A quarter century
has now passed since the phrase "linguistic turn" entered our vocabulary of
inquiry. The great majority of the think pieces published in the last five years as
symposia or review essays in the American Historical Review have focused on
discursive identities, collective memory, fictional narratives, and other motifs of
cultural history. But a just-issued collection of essays on method in cultural his-
tory and historical sociology, edited by two early practitioners of cultural method
in historical inquiry, Lynn Hunt and Victoria Bonnell, suggests that some are trou-
bled by the role of culture in historical inquiry in the current phase of consolida-
tion "after the revolution." The very title of their collection, Beyond the Cultural
Turn, raises the question "What next?" Above all, Hunt and Bonnell conclude,
many analysts at the current juncture share a general unease "with a definition of
culture as entirely systematic, symbolic, or linguistic."' Recent historical works
on the embodied culture of material life and on the use of culture in practice rep-
resent efforts to rethink the constituents of culture and how culture fits into social
I. THE FORMALIZINGPREMISE
Ecstasies: Deciphering the Witches'Sabbath (New York, 1992), 23, 30; William Sewell, Jr., "The
Concept(s)of Culture,"in Beyond the CulturalTurn,ed. Bonnell and Hunt, 35-61. In culturalsociol-
ogy, perhapsthe most stringentanalysis of the syntax of symbols, drawingon Saussure,is KarenA.
Cerulo,IdentityDesigns: The Sights and Sounds of a Nation (New Brunswick,N.J., 1995).
5. Michel Foucault, The Order of Things. An Archaeology of the Human Sciences (New York,
1971).
6. Lynn Hunt, Politics, Culture,and Class in the FrenchRevolution(Berkeley, 1984), 34-39.
7. Analysts may position deviance and creativityas parts of a cohesive sign system. See the cri-
tiques by CatherineGallagherand Stephen Greenblattin Practicing the New Historicism (Chicago,
2000), 12-13 and by William M. Reddy, Money and Liberty in Modern Europe. A Critique of
Historical Understanding(Cambridge,Eng., 1987), 39.
8. Scott's notion of culturalmeaning draws, I think, on what William Sewell has termed "thin"
coherence among cultural elements. Sewell's synthetic review of changes in investigators'under-
standingsof culture,"TheConcept(s)of Culture,"convincingly demonstratescontinuedreliance on a
concept of cultureas a sign system. See Beyond the CulturalTurn,ed. Bonnell and Hunt, 35-61.
9. Sewell, "TheConcept(s) of Culture,"in Beyond the CulturalTurn,ed. Bonnell and Hunt, 51.
10. In Darnton'sthe Great Cat Massacre, for example, the analysis culminatesby showing how
Parisianjourneymenin revoltcould manipulateritualsigns as dextrouslyas poets could words.Robert
Darnton,The Great Cat Massacre and OtherEpisodes in French CulturalHistory (New York, 1984),
101.
11. As illustration,see Bourdieu'soft-repeatedassertionthat the logic of practice "hasnothing in
common with intellectualwork, that it consists of an activity of practicalconstruction. .. that ordi-
nary notions of thought, consciousness, knowledge preventus from adequatelythinking."In Pierre
Bourdieu and Lofc Wacquant,An Invitation to Reflexive Sociology (Chicago, 1992), 121. On the
reception of Bourdieu's divide between thought and practice, see Paul Connerton,How Societies
Remember(Cambridge,Eng., 1989), 94-95.
The second of the two majorassumptionsthat came togetherin the 1980s could
well be termedthe "essentializingpremise."By this I mean to suggest how cul-
turalinvestigatorsmistook the concepts of "sign" and "sign reading"for parts
of the naturalfurnitureof the world, ratherthan as historicallygenerated"ways
of seeing." Clifford Geertz's statement of principle in The Interpretationof
Culturesproved phenomenally influentialin legitimating this move. "As inter-
worked systems of construablesigns," Geertz wrote, "cultureis not a power,
something to which social events, behaviors, institutions, or processes can be
causally attributed;it is a context, something within which they can be intelligi-
bly-that is, thickly-described."14 Geertz disallowed any form of illumination
that would put cultureon the same plane as other elements with which it might
be compared(it "is not a power").In my view, however,there is a contradiction
here thathad to be suppressedat all cost: the formal theory of meaning focused
on sign and sign system as naturalconstituentsviolates the principlethat all con-
cepts are conjuredby convention.To call on the title of one of Geertz's books,
the paradigmof the sign system is the only exception to the rule that every prin-
ciple is "local knowledge." 15 This naturalizingmove emerges in Geertz's non-
12. William Sewell, Jr., Workand Revolution in France: The Language of Laborfrom the Old
Regimeto 1848 (Cambridge,Eng., 1980), 23-24, 71.
13. See, for illustration,Lynn Hunt, review essay of Penser la revolutionfranCaise,History and
Theory20 (1981), 320; and the treatmentof languageas a brokerof historyin GarethStedmanJones,
"RethinkingChartism,"in his Languages of Class: Studies in English WorkingClass History,
1832-1982 (Cambridge,Eng., 1983).
14. CliffordGeertz, The Interpretationof Cultures(New York, 1973), 14.
15. It is worth noting how Geertz's naturalizingof culture as a fundamentis confirmed by his
stance towardthose outside the culturalistfold. He often wrote that the ultimategoal of anthropolo-
gy was to promote dialogue between different communities in the world. Yet he rejected dialogue
between himself and those outside his own paradigm.For instance, he treatedthe metaphorsof cul-
ture-skepticsas inadmissible a priori and blacklisted the enterpriseof social explanationas "social
physics" (CliffordGeertz,Local Knowledge:FurtherEssays in InterpretiveAnthropology[New York,
1983], 3). Geertz describedthe acceptanceof the culturalparadigmas a kind of conversionprocess:
you are either inside the flock or you are lost outside of it. His illiberal stance is evident in how he
narratesthe rise of interpretivestudies. In 1972 he wrote that "Even Marxists are quoting Cassirer;
19. For a swift exposition of Saussure'sview of the use of languageto make referenceto the world,
see Benjamin Lee, "Peirce, Frege, Saussure, and Whorf: The Semiotic Mediation of Ontology,"in
Semiotic Meditation:Socioculturaland Psychological Perspectives,ed. E. Mertz and R. Parmentier
(Orlando,Fla., 1985), 113.
20. FerdinandSaussure,Course in General Linguistics(New York, 1959), 15, 18.
* 21. Bruno Latour, WeHave Never Been Modern (Cambridge,Mass., 1993), 23. MargaretJacob
shows how Latour'sequationof naturalwith humanagency rests on a naturalizedconcept of the sign
in "Science Studies after Social Construction,"in Beyond the CulturalTurn,ed. Bonnell and Hunt,
106.
The fusion of the formalist and essentializing premises licensed rich and novel
methodologicalmoves. In retrospectit is easy to quibble with their soundness,
but they enabledhistoriansto launch dazzling new genres of research.
1. Historicalinvestigatorsused the marriageof the two assumptionsto show
that the deciphermentof meaning is not the explication of subjectivemeanings
or states of consciousness locked away in the heads of individualagents. Instead
culturalinvestigatorsextracteda semiotic code (or at least a model of partialcon-
sistencies) from public symbols and conventions.The code is independentof the
ideas in the head of any individual.As Geertz always emphasized, the analyst
does not have to perceive what agents perceive, only the sharedconventionsthe
agents perceive with.23That is sufficient for the investigatorto explain how the
agents use the conventionsso as to carryon their own thoughtor performances.
Perhaps only the marriageof the formalist and essentializing premises could
have so naturallylegitimatedthe pursuitof the putativecode, not of individuals'
fluid consciousness and thoughts, as the grasping of the tenable foundationto
historicalprocess. The abstractedcode for studying meaning became more sub-
stantial than the agents' thinking itself. Historians were relieved of the inter-
minable evidentiarygame of guessing the inwardintentions in agents' sayings.
They had a rationalefor limiting themselves to the accessible conventions by
which those sayings were structured-or, more exactly, to examples sufficientto
supportthe inventionof a putativelysharedmodel of their meanings. Likewise
sociologists who had been influenced by the Weberianand Parsonianviews of
culturewere now fortunatethey no longer had to stake inquiriesinto cultureon
the agents' "ultimatevalues."Those final commitmentshad not only proven dif-
ficult to documentand measure;worse yet, since the constraintsand ethical con-
tradictionsof actualsocial settings skewed the agents'pursuitof ultimatevalues,
these values had begun to appearto be related only tangentiallyto the agents'
observeddecision-makingand courses of action.24
2. The new combinationof premises gave investigatorsa license to relate any
piece of cultureto another.If meaningis generatedby an approximatecoherence
in a sign system thatreaches across local sites of practice,then investigatorscan
startwith any fragmentand move with it to a perspectiveon a largerculturalsys-
22. Geertz,Available Light, 12.
23. As Geertz famously put it, "Cultureis public because meaning is." Geertz, The Interpretation
of Cultures,12. For his most recent formulation,see Available Light, 16.
24. Ann Swidler, "Culturein Action: Symbols and Strategies,"AmericanSociological Review 51
(April, 1986), 275, 280.
25. Stephen Greenblatt,"TheTouch of the Real,"in The Fate of Culture:Geertzand Beyond, ed.
SherryOrtner(Berkeley, 1999).
26. Darnton,The Great Cat Massacre, 64.
27. I try to develop this point from a differentperspectivein "Methodand Metaphorafterthe New
CulturalHistory,"in Beyond the CulturalTurn,ed. Bonnell and Hunt, 70-71.
28. Carlo Ginzburg, The Cheese and the Worms:The Cosmos of a Sixteenth-CenturyMiller
(Baltimore, 1980).
29. See, illustratively,RobertNisbet, Social Change and History (Oxford, 1969), 264ff.
The second broad difficulty concealed in the culturalturn is that its principal,
Saussurean-affiliated model of sign systems as a distinctand irreduciblerealm is
untenableas an accountof how culturalmeaningis generated.Of course,linguists
such as R. Rommetveitand V. N. Voloshinov had made this point long ago by
offering more pragmatic,context-dependentanalyses of how language conveys
meaning.42But their philosophies have not dislodged the Saussureanaccount
because it is all too easy for historiansto see the critiquesas calling only for sup-
plements to the fashionableway of doing culturalanalysis. If the meanings of
signs also dependon how they areused in the momentin a particular,often unpre-
dictable social context, researcherscan take this as suggesting only that the sign
system is inflected by "history"and "politics" to produce specific meanings.
Historical investigatorsretain the notion that the synchronically and formally
defined sign system provides an adequategeneral structurefor culturalmeaning
in a community,and they view the particularsof practicein context as historical
instantiationsof thatstructure.43
Ratherthantry to arguehere thatanotherphilosophyof culturalmeaningmore
"accurately"capturesthe way significationworks, it is simplerto accept the for-
malist model on its termsand to reason abouthow it breaksdown by its own pro-
cedures. Once we develop formal models of the generationof culturalmeaning
out of contrasts among signs, we inauguratea divide between statements and
theirsignificance:meaning,as is often said, is no longer immanentin expression.
The divide in place, a verbal disclosure cannot contain a meaning, it can only
standat a distancefor something.This shifts the agenda of questions we pursue
to grasphow cultureworks. If meaningis at a remove from form, a model of cul-
ture has to acknowledge as a separateorder of logic the principles that agents
employ for bridging that deferralin major types of practice or types of social
41. Carlo Ginzburg,"Titian,Ovid, and Sixteenth-CenturyCodes for Erotic Illustration,"in Myths,
Emblems,Clues, transl.John and Anne C. Tedeschi (London, 1990), 93.
42. R. Rommetveit, On Message Structure: A Frameworkfor the Study of Language and
Communication(New York, 1974); V. N. Voloshinov, Marxism and the Philosophy of Language
[1929] (Cambridge,Mass., 1986).
43. Sonya 0. Rose, "CulturalAnalysis and Moral Discourses,"in Beyond the CulturalTurn,ed.
Bonnell and Hunt, 223. For a brilliantcritiqueof this method of haphazardlypatchingup the model
of language,see Michael Silverstein,"LanguageStructureand Linguistic Ideology,"in TheElements:
A Parasession on Linguistic Units and Levels, ed. Paul Clyne et al. (Chicago Linguistic Society,
1979).
48. Slavoj Zizek, The Sublime Object of Ideology (London, 1989), 31. Zizek shows Marx should
be considered a theoristof culturalpracticeratherthan a socioeconomic determinist.
49. Karl Marx, Das Kapital (Berlin, 1980), 88.
50. For a recent work that in my view analogously uses the trope of metaphorto figure the gener-
ation of representationsthrough"materialaction,"see Mukerji,TerritorialAmbitionsand the Gardens
of Versailles,especially 326, 332.
51. Biernacki, The Fabricationof Labor, chaptertwo.
52. The mathematicsof the two systems of payment were indeed distinct:in the Germansystem
thereis a linearincrease in paymentas the density of the cloth into which one thousandweft threads
are inserteddeclines; whereas in Britainthere was a linear increase in paymentwith increases in the
density of cloth.
53. For an analysis of representationsthat are complete for practicalexperiencebut partialas the-
ories, see JohnTorrance,Karl Marx's Theoty of Ideas (Cambridge,Eng., 1995), 158, 165.
ommended.7 Even as workers' beliefs about religion, politics, and the family
underwentsubstantialchange in each countryin the course of the nineteenthcen-
tury,these assumptionsabout the metric of abstractlabor,reproducedas a prag-
matic assumption,remaineduncannily stable until the shock of the First World
War.58Similarly,in Anderson'saccount,the unspokenassumptionsabouta com-
munity of anonymous readers moving incrementallythrough calendrical time
become the experientialbasis for sacralizing the nation as the frameworkfor
humanexistence; and in Marx's story,the fetishism of commodities is a central
mystificationanchoringother conceits of our culture.
Furthermore,in each of the three typifying examples, the pragmaticassump-
tions thatbecome so influentialarenot necessarily seen as "sacred,"because they
are anchoredby the execution of practice ratherthan by their cognitive or nor-
mativeimport.In consequence,the stabilityof culturalelements does not depend
on the iteration or resonance of signs across multiple domains of conduct.
Conversely,deep culturalchanges in one domain may not echo across others.
The coherence of culturehas to be tested ratherthan assumed. In Germanyand
Britain, state regulatorsin the First WorldWar intervenedwithout ado to dra-
matically modify payment systems for textile workers.In each countrythe con-
stellationof industrialtechniquesand laborrelationsthat revolved arounda par-
ticularmetric of abstractlabor suddenlycame apartwithout an amplifyingsense
of crisis in other locales. Similarly,in Anderson's model, the rituals of reading
that structuredthe experienceof the nation seem to be a relativelyincidentalfea-
tureof commercialsociety. With rapidchanges in the distributionof media, they
may undergo independentand fateful change. Finally, Marx emphasized that
practicesof commodityexchangereproducethe perceptionthatcommodities are
independentcarriersof value no matterwhetherproducersdrawon wider cogni-
tive fields to deconstructthose exchanges from a cynical scientific perspective.59
Investigatorswho seek to analyze a culture's contingent fixity and coherence
must focus initially on the connections between representationsand practice in
situ, ratherthan only on global associations among representations.
Just as the new culturalhistory drew on analogies with languageto appreciate
semanticrelations,so a rethinkingof culturein operationcan drawon models of
languagein use to appreciatehow practicenaturalizesculturalcategories.In fact,
we can takethe case of languageas an object of popularreflectionto contrastdis-
belief about the realism of signs with the experiencedrealism of the principles
used to put the signs to work. It is now almost folk knowledge to claim that any
language is an arbitraryconstruct,not a faithful telescope of the structureof the
world. Despite that "fictive"status,however,the users of a language still experi-
ence as foundationalthe implicit principles by which they use the signs of that
languageto referencethe world.Recall BenjaminWhorf's famous accountof the
generation of natural or metaphysical categories out of the process of using