PAPPAS - John Deweys Ethics PDF
PAPPAS - John Deweys Ethics PDF
PAPPAS - John Deweys Ethics PDF
Democracy as Experience
editorial board
Susan Bordo
Vincent Colapietro
John Lachs
Noëlle McAfee
Cheyney Ryan
Richard Shusterman
JOHN DEWEY’S
ETHICS
DEMOCRACY AS EXPERIENCE
http://iupress.indiana.edu
m a n u fa c t u r e d i n t h e u n i t e d s tat e s o f a m e r i c a
1 2 3 4 5 13 12 11 10 09 08
Para Beatriz, John, y Fema
CONTENTS
Preface xi
List of Abbreviations xv
introduction 1
PART ONE
moral theory and experience
one
Experience as Method 17
two
Moral Theory and Moral Practice 43
three
The Normative Standpoint of Pragmatism 71
contents
PART T WO
dewey’s view of moral experience
four
Morality as Experience 81
five
The ‘‘What’’ of Moral Experience 88
six
The ‘‘How’’ of Moral Experience 121
seven
Character and Conduct: Dewey and the Great Divide in Ethics 129
eight
Present Activity and the Meaning of Moral Life 146
nine
Conclusion: The Need for a Recovery of Moral Philosophy 156
viii
contents
PART THREE
the ideal moral life
ten
The Intelligent, Aesthetic, and Democratic Way of Life 165
eleven
The Ideal Moral Self 185
twelve
Democracy as the Ideal Moral Community 217
thirteen
A Philosophical Justification of Democracy 260
conclusion 300
Notes 309
Bibliography 327
Index 335
ix
PREFACE
It is one of the delights of authorship that one can publicly express one’s
gratitude to those who helped along the way. And this book is to a large
extent the product of my very fortunate interaction with many people at
di√erent stages of my inquiry. I am grateful to my dear colleague John J.
McDermott for his advice and support throughout the years, and for
stressing the importance of living aesthetically. I learned how to approach
pragmatism from my friend and mentor, Douglas Browning, to whom I
owe my deepest gratitude. As a teacher, Browning’s radical approach to the
classical American pragmatists is to try to read them as openly, honestly,
and empathetically as possible; in other words, we must try to understand
their philosophies on their own terms. A text is, of course, subject to a
plurality of reasonable interpretations, but too many philosophers cannot
help but read their own theoretical commitments into the text. In doing
so, many have missed Dewey’s radical reconstruction of philosophy. In
particular, Browning tirelessly insists that we must pay attention to what
Dewey himself tells us in regard to the proper way of engaging in philo-
sophical inquiry.
The message from Dewey is clear. The practical stance of everyday life
xi
preface
xii
preface
tion) for asking such good questions. Special thanks are owed to the late
Ralph Sleeper, Tom Alexander, my former dear colleague Larry Hickman,
Michael Eldridge, Peter Hare, Jorge Gracia, and Charlene Seigfried for
their encouragement over a long period and the example they set. I am
indebted to Ronald Chichester, who painstakingly worked through many
chapters to improve the prose. I am extremely grateful to my parents, John
and Fema, and my wife, Beatriz, for being unending sources of patience,
support, care, and advice. What good fortune to have them in my life!
I am also happy to acknowledge institutional support I received. A
Ford Foundation Postdoctoral Fellowship from the National Research
Council (Sept 1991–May 1992) allowed me to conduct the initial research
for this book. Research at the Dewey Center at Southern Illinois University
was kindly facilitated by Larry Hickman and his sta√. And a 1998–1999
Faculty Development Leave from Texas A&M University let me devote
myself fully to writing this book.
Portions of part 1 are drawn from my ‘‘Dewey’s Ethics: Morality as
Experience,’’ in Reading Dewey: Interpretive Essays for a Postmodern Gen-
eration, ed. Larry A. Hickman (Bloomington: Indiana University Press,
1998), 100–123; ‘‘New Directions and Uses in the Reconstruction of John
Dewey’s Ethics,’’ in In Dewey’s Wake: Unfinished Work of Pragmatic Recon-
struction, ed. William J. Gavin (Albany, N.Y.: State University of New York
Press, 2002), 41–62; and ‘‘Dewey’s Moral Theory: Experience as Method,’’
Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 33, no. 3 (1997): 520–556. Por-
tions of part 2 are drawn from my ‘‘To Be or To Do: John Dewey and the
Great Divide in Ethics,’’ History of Philosophy Quarterly 14, no. 4 (1997):
447–468; and ‘‘Dewey and Feminism: The A√ective and Relationships in
Dewey’s Ethics,’’ Hypatia 8, no. 2 (1993): 78–95. And portions of part 3 are
drawn from my ‘‘Open-mindedness and Courage: Complementary Vir-
tues of Pragmatism,’’ Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 32, no. 2
(1996): 316–335. I am grateful to the editors and publishers of these books
and journals for permission to reprint material here. I also gratefully
acknowledge the Banco de Mexico for permission to use Diego Rivera’s
‘‘Retrato de John Dewey’’ on the book cover.
xiii
A B B R E V I AT I O N S
xv
JOHN DEWEY’S ETHICS
Introduction
∞
john dewey’s ethics
≤
introduction
≥
john dewey’s ethics
lowing sort: ‘‘If you want to understand and verify what I am talking
about, please try to put aside for the moment all of the theories of moral
life that you know, and instead consult your everyday, gross, and crude
experience of moral decisions and problems.’’
Dewey, however, did not consolidate his ideas about moral philosophy in
any single work. The few books in which Dewey focused explicitly on ethics
were textbooks and syllabi, written primarily for classroom work and not
intended to be systematic theoretical formulations. It would have been
fitting for him to write one more revision of his 1932 edition of Ethics (with
James Hayden Tufts), not as a textbook, but as a more comprehensive and
definitive rendition of his moral thought in light of the philosophical
commitments that distinguished his philosophical outlook. The present
book is the one that Dewey should have written on his moral philosophy.
In my e√ort to bring Dewey’s scattered contributions to moral philos-
ophy into a cohesive moral vision, I borrow from all phases of his work to
find the best formulations of his theses. My presentation of Dewey’s ethics
will not be chronological. Dewey’s ideas about ethics, just as his ideas
about other subjects, underwent gradual but continual reconstruction
during the seventy-one years that constituted his public career.∏ Although
these modifications are important, they are not substantial or drastic
∂
introduction
∑
john dewey’s ethics
∏
introduction
π
john dewey’s ethics
Surely there is no more significant question before the world than this
question of the possibility and method of reconciliation of the attitudes
of practical science and contemplative aesthetic appreciation. Without
the former, man will be the sport and victim of natural forces which he
cannot use or control. Without the latter, mankind might become a race
of economic monsters, restlessly driving hard bargains with nature and
with one another, bored with leisure or capable of putting it to use only
in ostentatious display and extravagant dissipation. Like other moral
questions, this matter is social and even political. (MW 12:152–153)
In this book, I argue that the intelligent and aesthetic are mutually depen-
dent aspects or qualifications of a single normative moral vision. They are
integral aspects of Dewey’s ideal self and democratic community.
Dewey’s ethics is crucial for understanding his socio-political thought.
In spite of the fact that Dewey referred to democracy as a moral ideal,
commentators and critics often segregate Dewey’s views on democracy
from his moral thought on the assumption that his views on politics and
social thought can be understood on their own. What would happen if
instead we treated Dewey’s view of democracy as an extension of his ethics?
This is my venture in part 3. I will consider Dewey’s democratic ideal from
the standpoint of his ethics rather than from the context of the history of
American Liberalism or socio-political theory. This approach yields defi-
nite benefits worth mentioning in this introduction.
It is common today to find extensive criticisms of formalistic and
procedural visions of democracy. Cornel West, for example, has recently
argued that ‘‘to focus solely on electoral politics as the site of democratic
life is myopic. Such a focus fails to appreciate the crucial role of the
∫
introduction
Ω
john dewey’s ethics
With this, history has validated a central tenet of Dewey’s ethics: moral
amelioration or democratization must grow from within, and, while it is
∞≠
introduction
not altogether under anyone’s control, we can inquire about the indirect
conditions by which a better moral life may grow. In this book, I present
the philosophical underpinnings of this humble but positive tenet.
∞∞
john dewey’s ethics
∞≤
introduction
personal faith in experience. That is, for me, the ultimate glue of Dewey’s
vision. This insight highlights the importance of the mystical experience
in Dewey’s personal life where he felt suddenly that ‘‘everything that’s
here is here, and you can just lie back on it.’’≤∫ As Robert Westbrook
correctly points out, Dewey ‘‘would never lose touch with this feeling,
though his interpretation of its meaning and implications would change
dramatically.’’≤Ω
Dewey’s philosophy is committed to finding, articulating, and testing
the better and worse ways in which we can lie back on life. His philosophy
is saturated with hypotheses about those interactions and ways of par-
ticipating in situational, everyday life that are key to its capacity to regu-
late, ameliorate, educate, and enrich itself with meaning without the need
for something antecedent, supernatural, or external to itself. Intelligent
inquiry and the creation and appreciation of art are, for instance, two
modes in which we can find the way to guide the course of experience to
greater depth of meaning by its own resources.
I will argue that to lie back on lived experience in a way that makes the
process self-regulative requires the cultivation of a balance between virtues
typically associated with experimentation, intelligence, and democracy. I
will emphasize the importance of a pre-reflective, qualitatively felt present
situation as not only the starting point but the ultimate source of guidance
in moral life.≥≠ The pre-reflective is not only the background, but also the
normative basis of our inquiries. To dismiss the qualitative is to dismiss
context, which is for Dewey the root of all philosophical evils.
∞≥
PART ONE
Moral Theory and Experience
one
Experience as Method
∞π
moral theory and experience
∞∫
experience as method
Instead of the narrow view assumed by tenets (1) and (2), commenta-
tors and defenders of Dewey’s ethics point out that tenets (3) and (4)
better convey the sense in which Dewey’s ethics is empirical. Tenet (4)
postulates an ethics that is constantly nurtured and informed by the re-
sults of scientific inquiries. The moral philosopher is accordingly more
interdisciplinary than is typical. Compared to tenet (4), tenet (3) seems to
make a stronger claim about the relation between science and ethics. An
empirical ethics is one that adopts the general method of inquiry of the sci-
ences. For example, Dewey did not see why the conclusions of moral phi-
losophy could not be as hypothesis-driven as those of the sciences. Recent
scholars have insisted that to appreciate that this was Dewey’s view we
must first understand what he meant by science or the scientific method.
Jennifer Welchman, for example, claims that if one carefully studies Dew-
ey’s conception of the nature of science, one finds that he thought that
‘‘every scientist acts in accordance with procedural rules’’∂ that can be
experimentally confirmed. This indicates at least one respect in which
ethics can be like science. ‘‘Commitment to such rules, Dewey holds, is the
essence of science. It is in this respect that he believes ethical theory ought
to become scientific.’’∑ If ethics is to advance it should ‘‘construct pro-
cedures for inquiries analogous to those used in the physical sciences.’’∏
For James Campbell, it is the ‘‘scientific attitude’’ and the communal
(‘‘public’’) aspect of science that attracted Dewey to the notion of ‘‘ethics
as a moral science.’’π
I do not wish to question tenets (3) and (4) as Deweyan theses, or the
above claims by Dewey scholars. However, I think there are limitations to
this way of proceeding if one wants to understand both Dewey and the
notion of an empirical ethics. Although the association of empiricism
with science is not totally unwarranted, I question the fruitfulness of
ascribing tenet (3) to Dewey for a full understanding of his radical recon-
struction of moral philosophy. Dewey scholars should not assume that we
must demonstrate the respects in which ethics can be like science on the
assumption that a failure to do so will scuttle our claims to have articu-
lated an empirical ethics. This is especially so if ethics is a subject within
philosophy. Dewey had a well-developed view of what it means for an area
of philosophy to be empirical, and it is this that is appealed to in tenet (5),
a view compatible with, but not reducible to, tenet (3). Indeed, Dewey’s
thoughts about empirical philosophy are independent of how he con-
ceived the relation between philosophy and science.∫
Dewey used science as an analogy or as a paradigm, and advocated in
ethics a method analogous to scientific inquiry. At the time, the analogy
with science was important for Dewey because it served the function of
∞Ω
moral theory and experience
≤≠
experience as method
≤∞
moral theory and experience
≤≤
experience as method
cal assumptions and with certain theoretical demands and interests. Yet
the fact that many or most philosophers become trapped in their theories
does not mean that this is inevitable, and it is not su≈cient to demonstrate
that the philosophical e√ort to be truthful to experience is futile.
Dewey’s form of empiricism is not the kind that many would like.
One cannot object that although the method o√ers a way of evaluating
and testing theoretical hypothesis it cannot guarantee that they will corre-
spond to the nature of things, or in the case of moral theory to a moral
reality outside of experience. For this objection assumes a mysterious
ontological gap between experience and reality that is ruled out by Dew-
ey’s postulate. On the other hand, the complaint might be that while it
gives us an extra-theoretical check on our theories it does not provide us
with freedom from our historical circumstances. The extent to which our
primary experience is conditioned by our culture or place in history is a
source of anxiety to those who would like to have the assurance that what
they experience is unspoiled by their circumstances. Dewey did not expe-
rience this anxiety because he did not even understand what this last sense
of freedom could mean.
However, Dewey’s denial of pure experience does not mean that he
held the theory that our starting point is always inside a language, a cul-
ture, or a socioeconomic system. He would be skeptical of any theory that
claimed that our primary experience is determined (or conditioned) by
one single cohesive factor such as one’s historical period, culture, race,
class, or biological makeup. These are all reductionistic and, as such, non-
empirical theories that overlook the complexity and heterogeneity of fac-
tors and interactions that are the conditions for human experience. We do
not experience ourselves as inside (or as trapped in) our subjectivity,
language, or anything else. The notion, for example, that one’s culture or
social class solely determines moral experience is itself a theory, rather
than what we experience when we have moral experiences.
Dewey’s appeal to primary experience is not a disguised appeal to the
status quo. On the contrary, the purpose is to encourage criticism. Philos-
ophy as criticism relies on subjecting the more refined reflective products
of our inquiry to the test of primary experience. But philosophy can also
subject to criticism what, at any time, is taken as primary experience. This
is done either by arguing that it is not really primary or by unveiling
factors (e.g., historical-cultural beliefs) that condition our experience in
an unwanted way. We start where we are, in the midst of our pre-reflective
and immediate qualitative experiences. These experiences change and are
transformed by inquiry but we must return to them as our guide. If we
≤≥
moral theory and experience
Day after day we find ourselves within an integral part of those ever-
changing and always unique situations that constitute our lives and
mark out their shifting horizons. Each of us is bound within this situa-
tional stream, a stream which is never at rest, always in transit. We
cannot stop it or freeze it even for a second; we cannot view it from
without or find some external point of leverage from which we might
alter the direction of its flow. We are not mere subjects for whom our
situations are objects to be observed; we are agents in our situations, in
our arenas of action, and part of what transpires there is our own doing.
Now, this stream of situations in our lives is precisely that to which
Dewey refers by the term ‘experience’.∞≤
≤∂
experience as method
how things present themselves and not by how we want them to be. It is
‘‘accepting what is found in good faith and without discount’’ (LW 1:372),
and to settle issues by ‘‘finding and pointing to the things in the concrete
contexts in which they present themselves’’ (LW 1:377).
Dewey’s empirical method has significant implications about the re-
sources and limits of philosophical inquiry and criticism. Argumentation
and logical rigor continue to be important, but there is also the require-
ment of adequacy to experience, a requirement that introduces a way of
evaluating philosophical hypotheses that can be both a strength and lia-
bility of pragmatism. Dewey rejects commonplace assumptions in ethics
because they are not based in his everyday primary experience, and he
doubts that they are a part of the primary experience of other ethical
theorists. This is a good reason for Dewey to reject entire views, even when
they are impeccably well argued and meet all possible objections. This,
however, is a liability because it opens the pragmatist to the charge of
seeming to be shallow, dismissive, and begging questions in her confronta-
tion with alternative views.
How can anyone be certain that one is beginning with things as they
are experienced and not with reflective products or theoretical presup-
positions? There is no certainty here and Dewey provides no infallible
method by which one can guarantee success in the empirical method he
proposes. All one can do is be alert to purposes that might distort or
mislead, such as holding on to a theory too zealously. Others might also
keep us on alert. This is why the empiricist method requires that one’s
results be tested by the results and lived experience of others. One can
guide others to circumstances that would let them test one’s own results;
but suggesting that others have certain experiences is not the same as
providing a reason or an argument in their defense. It does, however, open
our hypothesis to the criticism of others.
Dewey also suggests that it would help if we keep the term ‘experience’
in philosophy as a reminder of our method. This will remind one to run a
never-ending check of one’s philosophy both with one’s day-to-day expe-
riences and with the results of other philosophers. Even more helpful is
the suggestion that we learn from the experience of other philosophers. To
study other philosophers’ mistakes might prevent one from making those
same mistakes and avoid false starts of a particular, that is, non-empirical,
kind. Dewey very helpfully summarizes the general and systematic kinds
of mistakes made by non-empirical philosophers, and it will be helpful to
consider them before continuing to disclose the proper starting point for
ethical theory.
≤∑
moral theory and experience
t h e a n a ly t i c fa l l a c y
≤∏
experience as method
t h e fa l l a c y o f u n l i m i t e d u n i v e r s a l i z at i o n
Another common way for philosophers to ignore context and elevate the
conclusions of their inquiries is to give them unlimited application. This
occurs when they ignore the fact that conclusions arise out of limiting
conditions set by the contextual situation of particular inquiries. Philoso-
phers are prone to this fallacy because they often try to formulate theories
about truth, good, reality, or the absolute writ large. In many instances,
one ‘‘converts abstraction from specific context into abstraction from all
contexts whatsoever’’ (LW 6:16). Philosophers tend to absolutize or uni-
versalize their conclusions because they ignore the fact that philosophical
inquiry always occurs against a temporal and spatial background that is
not subject as a whole to reflection.
t h e fa l l a c y o f s e l e c t i v e e m p h a s i s
The fallacy of selective emphasis occurs when the philosopher forgets or
overlooks selectivity and the purposes of selection that are part of the
context of a particular inquiry. The most common consequence and sign
of this is that non-empirical philosophers do not ascribe reality to what-
ever is left out of, or not selected in, their inquiries. Hence, whatever has
value in some specific context and for some particular purpose determines
what is real. But this is to confuse good or useful traits with ‘‘fixed traits of
real being’’ (LW 1:33). Because philosophers cherish simplicity, certainty,
and permanence, they convert these traits into real features of the world;
meanwhile, uncertainty, change, and ambiguity are taken as phenomenal,
subjective, or as lacking reality. According to Dewey, however, all that
happens is equally real though perhaps not of equal worth. If one is
empirical one recognizes that primary experience has precarious elements
as well as stable ones.
≤π
moral theory and experience
i n t e l l e c t ua l i s m
Intellectualism might be thought of as a combination of the aforemen-
tioned fallacies. But it is so pervasive in the history of non-empirical
philosophy that it should be considered a separate fallacy. Philosophers
have always favored cognitive objects. The problem arises when, as a
consequence of her cognitive bias, the philosopher deems unimportant or
unreal whatever is non-cognitive or pre-cognitive. The consequence of in-
tellectualism in philosophy has been a certain narrow view of experience,
namely, that all experience is a mode of knowing. The concept of experi-
ence that is at the heart of traditional epistemology assumes something
like an intellectualist postulate: things really are what they are known to
be. Therefore, we have to possess knowledge in order to reveal reality, and
whatever is ultimately real has to have the characteristics of an object of
knowledge.
If things are what they are experienced as, then there are many other
ways in which we experience things than as objects of knowledge. In fact,
we have a qualitative appreciation of our surroundings that precedes,
underlies, and cannot be reduced to knowledge. Our intellectual activities
always operate within the more general context of the world as encoun-
tered, lived, enjoyed, and su√ered by humans. In primary experience
‘‘things are objects to be treated, used, acted upon and with, enjoyed and
endured, even more than things to be known. They are things had before
they are things cognized’’ (LW 1:27–28). The qualitative character of expe-
rience is not something merely subjective, but rather a trait of existence.
‘‘The world in which we immediately live, that in which we strive, succeed,
and are defeated is preeminently a qualitative world’’ (LW 5:243).
Intellectualism is so predominant in moral theory that it operates in
subtle ways in accounts and debates about moral realism, moral problems,
moral relationships, and moral deliberation. For Dewey, even if the out-
come of moral deliberation might be called moral knowledge, it nonethe-
less arises out of a context of non-cognitively experienced moral subject
matter. As I will argue, even the process of moral deliberation itself is not
purely cognitive; moreover, I will even claim that for Dewey the most
important instrumentalities of moral life are not the usual cognitive pow-
ers associated with moral knowledge. This is not to deny the importance
of knowledge, for knowledge is one mode of experience that can make a
significant di√erence in primary moral experience. However, a pragmatist
is ready to argue against a reductionism of moral life to the cognitive.
Dewey knew that his philosophical views would not be understood
≤∫
experience as method
Theorists who debate each other tend to ignore the fact that in con-
crete moral experience neither the good nor the right is reducible to the
other. Ethical theorists have neglected the non-cognitive, pluralistic, and
incommensurable aspects of moral life because they are of no use in
≤Ω
moral theory and experience
≥≠
experience as method
≥∞
moral theory and experience
≥≤
experience as method
taking the theoretical point of view is something you and I often do. As
agents, i.e., as engaged, interactive participants within an immediately
experienced arena of practical, daily a√airs, we frequently find it helpful
to assume the role, take on the guise, of a disengaged and disinterested
observer who is no longer caught up in the rough and tumble of that
arena, but withdrawn from it and merely observes it or some area of
interest within it from an objectifying distance.∞π
≥≥
moral theory and experience
≥∂
experience as method
≥∑
moral theory and experience
≥∏
experience as method
become aware of the real reasons why they should care or take their
experienced obligations seriously. For instance, here is what Hare says
about the experienced moral bond (partiality) in the mother-child rela-
tion, ‘‘If we ascend to the critical level and ask why it ought to be, the
answer is fairly obvious. If mothers had the propensity to care equally for
all the people in the world, it is unlikely that children would be as well
provided for even as they are.’’≤∂ So, we are all lucky that mothers are
duped into feeling they have a special obligation to their children because
they are their children! It is only a small step from this view to the view
that all of our moral experiences are nothing but a useful fiction to propa-
gate our genes. Whether it is Platonism, cultural relativism, or scientism, a
theoretical standpoint that explains away the reality of our immediate
moral experiences is often present.
The abstraction of a thinking rational subject in a value-less world is a
common theoretical starting point implicit in a variety of ethical theories.
It is discernible in those positions that assume that our moral principles or
our desires are the sources of our moral experiences and, therefore, that
morality is a human projection upon nature. It is in views that assume
that ethical theory must provide rational reasons that would convince an
imaginary skeptic to be moral or to take morality seriously.≤∑ In such
views, it is as if to be rational (usually defined as pursuing one’s self-
interest or following the rules of logic) is primary, while all else (especially
moral value) is questionable and must be derived from this imaginary
standpoint. For Dewey, this is not to start with moral experience as it is
had because we start in a morally value-laden world. Morality is no more
in need of justification or legitimacy than the existence of the external
world. Morality is just as basic, natural, and given as rationality (in any of
its possible meanings). There is no more need to show that morality is
rational than a need to show that rationality is moral.
Another common theoretical starting point in ethical theory is to
locate morality in moral norms that are prior to, or exist across, situations.
Moral theory, according to this view, must start with the fact that agents
and communities inherit general moral principles and standards. This is
the reason why we experience moral demands and the possession of such
principles and standards determines right from wrong in a particular
situation. Moral problems are in e√ect a matter of deciding what follows
from a general criterion of right and wrong, or it is the conflict between
di√erent standards or criteria. Moral disagreement among individuals is
thus a disagreement about moral norms. The task of ethical theory is to
bring to our conscious attention the norms at work in our actions and
judgments. It must validate (i.e., seek a rational basis for) the moral stan-
≥π
moral theory and experience
dards that ordinary moral agents take for granted. This is the theoretical
view of moral experience that is assumed in debates between di√erent
forms of objectivism and relativism.
The relativist holds that moral judgments are justified only relative to
standards accepted by a person or the social group to which she belongs.≤∏
Objectivists take this as a challenge. Morality is not just a matter of our
upbringing, group mores, or desires; there must be some basic criterion of
right and wrong. There are a variety of objectivist views in ethics accord-
ing to what is proposed as the criterion. For example, what is right is
determined by:
a) what any rational person has good reason to accept or what
would be agreed upon by hypothetical contractors under ideal
conditions;
b) what is self-evident according to one’s moral sense;
c) what can be expected to produce more good than bad conse-
quences;
d) what is deducible from the commands of divine authority, a cate-
gorical imperative, the concept of the rational agent, or human
nature (or flourishing).
These are all objective standards insofar as they presuppose an objective
standpoint, that is, a standpoint outside of the historically contingent
standards of any particular individual, society, or culture. And they are
proposed as the rational basis to evaluate or criticize these relative stan-
dards. Relativism, of course, denies the existence of such a God’s-eye view
of things. Instead, we find ourselves in life with inherited and historically
contingent moral standards, and no external perspective from which we
can subject them to criticism.
From Dewey’s standpoint this debate goes on without questioning the
notion that moral norms are the locus and source of morality, and that
their application is what accounts for moral problems, deliberation, and
judgment. This is, at best, a theoretical explanation of moral life, one that
leaves out the concrete context where standards are found (an instance of
the analytic fallacy). It is only when standards are examined, imagined,
and discussed in abstracto, that is, apart from their role in morally prob-
lematic situations, that they seem to be in need of some philosophical
justification. This, Dewey would claim, is an example of how philosophers
with an a priori commitment to a particular view about our relation to
general norms are concerned with problems of their own creation. As I
will argue later, moral judgments are not derivable by applying a criterion
≥∫
experience as method
of right conduct; in fact, if there are general moral standards they receive
their normative force from particular judgments in situations.
Because of the linguistic turn in twentieth-century philosophy, the
theoretical starting point became linguistic. It is common in ethical theory
to take discrete moral terms, predicates, judgments, and propositions as
the starting point of philosophical investigations. Starting with moral
language seems more concrete and empirical than beginning with meta-
physics, understood as the postulation of the existence of mysterious and
supersensible moral values. This starting point commits the philosopher
to an attempt to derive or explain the rest of our moral experience by
‘‘expos[ing] the logic of moral concepts’’≤π or by discerning the meaning of
moral words. Ethical theories are tested by checking whether they square
‘‘with the facts of linguistic behaviour’’ or with (predictions of ) ‘‘what the
ordinary man would treat as self-contradictory.’’≤∫
Moral theories that begin with an analysis of moral terms or the
moral properties of particular actions su√er from the same problem that
the modern view of experience as a composite of atomistic simples does,
namely, that it cannot adequately account for relations. Indeed, our moral
lives seem like a disconnected series of atomistically isolated acts, and
two propositions in moral reasoning seem disconnected when the results
of ethical analysis are taken as self-su≈cient. In part 2, I will claim that
these and other problems do not arise when one takes the lived context
of our moral problems and deliberations seriously. One commits the
philosophical fallacy when one abstracts moral terms and moral judg-
ments out of their contexts and tries to acontextually set their meaning, or
when one begins with the assumption that there are some propositions
that are inherently moral.≤Ω An analysis of our ordinary moral language is
not su≈cient to account for the richness and complexity of our moral
experience.
The legalistic character of modern ethics goes hand in hand with its
linguistic bias. This bias colors or determines the descriptions of every
aspect of moral life. Moral problems are nothing but the conflict between
principles or rules that can be stated, revised or re-written. Moral judg-
ments are treated as statements or propositions that are the result of the
process of moral deliberation which has the same linear character as
reading a text. In other words, it is assumed that we ought to reach
justified moral judgments by following the same logical order of reading.
The linguistic starting point in ethics is usually accompanied by the
same intellectualist starting point of traditional epistemology. It is as-
sumed that to start with moral experience is to start with moral language
≥Ω
moral theory and experience
in the form of propositions about right and wrong (i.e., the beliefs of
common morality). As W. D. Ross says,
My starting point [is] the existence of what is commonly called the
moral consciousness; and by this I mean the existence of a large body of
beliefs and convictions to the e√ect that there are certain kinds of acts
that ought to be done.≥≠
∂≠
experience as method
leave out ‘‘that which is the controlling factor in my entire view, namely
the function of a problematic situation in regulating as well as evoking
inquiry’’ (LW 14:44).
I have been assuming that empiricism in ethics entails contextualism,
but not every contextualist position is thereby concrete and empirical.
Moral philosophers like Alasdair MacIntyre have suggested that the rele-
vant contexts for the understanding of moral terms are the moral vocabu-
laries operative in large social and historical structures and practices. But
an inquiry about moral life that begins with and comes back to shared and
cohesive ‘‘moral languages’’ or a ‘‘network of shared moral laws’’≥∑ is not
committed to an experiential starting point. For even if these refined
theoretical products explain why people experience what they experience,
they are not what agents experience in primitive experiential situations.
Cultural, historical, and sociological explanations of morality are perhaps
better theories than universalist or Platonic ones, but they remain theories
nonetheless.
For Dewey, radical empiricism in ethics entails a radical contextual-
ism, by which he meant that each situation constitutes a unique context
and while it is lived (as a process), that is all there is to moral life. Accounts
of our moral life that ignore this, and begin with the assumption of
absolutes across time and history, are adopting a God’s-eye point of view
that neglects the situational context of both our investigation and our
morality. There is no standing outside where we are.
The starting point of inquiry is the most important issue in ethical
theory because one’s understanding of moral notions and of moral expe-
rience is conditioned by one’s starting point. Dewey thought that moral
experience included virtues, rules, obligations, ends and all other notions
posited by moral theorists as exclusively moral. This inclusiveness was a
result of taking moral situations as the primary context and discerning
which notions were operative there, rather than making the moral notions
themselves primary.
Dewey wondered about ‘‘how much of distraction and dissipation in
life, and how much of its hard and narrow rigidity is the outcome of man’s
failure to realize that each situation has its own unique end and that the
whole personality should be concerned with it?’’ (MW 12:176). And he
hoped that attention to moral experience as it is experienced would lead to
a shift in ethical thought toward situations as the center of gravity of moral
endeavor. He insisted that moral philosophy must quit seeking ends or
standards that were over and above unique morally problematic situa-
tions. The resolution of each morally problematic situation was, he be-
lieved, the goal of morality. The tendency to absolutize or universalize in
∂∞
moral theory and experience
ethics by providing theories of the good was a failure to see that any
meaningful quest for the good is tied to a particular inquiry within the
unique context of a morally problematic situation. He said, ‘‘while there is
no single end, there also are not as many as there are specific situations
that require amelioration’’ (MW 12:174–175). In other words, each con-
crete morally problematic situation has its own immanent end and mean-
ing, and should not be thought of as a mere means to other, even con-
tingent or historically situated, overarching ends.
In sum, any adequate examination of Dewey’s ethical vision needs to
begin and take as central the notion of a situation. The situation’s impor-
tance has to be understood as a consequence of Dewey’s commitment to a
philosophical empiricism. Moral experience is experienced as something
that is neither subjective nor merely inter-subjective. We begin where we
are, in a situation as participants, rather than as inhabitants of a culture,
conceptual scheme, or our society’s norms. Moral situations became the
most inclusive category or concept in Dewey’s ethics. The categories and
elements that are part of moral experience (such as character, conduct,
principles, relationships, and habits) are features or traits of lived situa-
tions, not antecedent to them. Ideals are part of the means available in the
process of ameliorating a situation. Virtues are habits operative in and
integral to situations, not means to abstract notions of human flourishing.
Even Dewey’s philosophical speculations about how to live (the subject of
part 3) were nothing more than proposals about how to engage in present
situations.
Does the radical character of Dewey’s contextualism preclude the
possibility of theorizing about moral life? If philosophical inquiry is itself
embedded in situations as unique, complex, and changing pre-reflective
contexts, can moral theory perform the functions it has traditionally per-
formed? What is left of moral theory after all the methodological mistakes
are avoided? The acknowledgment of context and the abandonment of a
God’s-eye view have led contemporary skeptics to consider futile the am-
bitions of traditional ethical theory. In the next chapter, I turn to the claim
that Dewey’s skepticism about moral theory is based on a situation ethics
and on an alternative conception of the proper function of moral theory.
∂≤
two
Moral Theory and Moral Practice
∂≥
moral theory and experience
∂∂
moral theory and moral practice
But neither Dewey’s moral experience nor mine accords with (1), (2),
or (3). This is not to imply that moral experience is chaotic. There are
stabilities and uniformities in moral life, but they are not of the kind
or degree assumed by many. Moral theorists have the tendency to forget
the non-cognitive complexity, plurality, incommensurability, raggedness,
changeability, and uniqueness that characterize our primary moral expe-
rience. These are the features of moral life that almost make them re-
calcitrant to any kind of theoretical formulation. One might even claim
that in virtue of its (lack of ?) structure, moral life is anti-theoretical.
Dewey’s avoidance of intellectualism led him to the view that rules or
any propositional knowledge are only a part of the actual material of indi-
vidual moral deliberation. In fact, the qualitative, emotional, and non-
cognitive aspects are more important to moral life than any propositional
object of knowledge. Moral judgments are not deduced from rules but
are derived from an imaginative-a√ective exploration of one’s situation.
Moral agents do not distinguish right from wrong by reference to a fixed
or evolving criterion. Aside from these views about moral deliberation
(which will be considered in part 2), Dewey had serious doubts that a
morality based on a set of comprehensive and fixed rules was a workable
possibility.
Even if we could somehow come up with a substantial number of
sound moral rules, it is questionable to what extent they would be su≈-
cient to guide our lives given that it assumes that we have secured ourselves
from the flexibility of individual intelligence and sensitivity to context. For
how would we know which individual situations are cases where a par-
ticular rule applies? In discussing the rule of honesty, for example, Dewey
asks ‘‘what bell would ring, what signal would be given, to indicate that
just this case is the appropriate case for the application of the rule of
honest dealing?’’ (LW 7:276). And even if we could answer this question,
we would legitimately wonder ‘‘what course in detail the rule calls for?’’
∂∑
moral theory and experience
(LW 7:276). The notion that an ethical theory can provide a set of rules (or
even a set of virtues) by which we can automatically make the right moral
decisions is naïve. Even if we could come up with such a set, Dewey
thought that the kind of moral life that would follow or that is suggested
by this kind of ethical inquiry would be a good enough reason to reject
such a project. Instead, he thinks there are at least three dangers of this
way of conceiving our moral life,
∞) ‘‘It tends to magnify the letter of morality at the expense of its spirit’’
(LW 7:277). When what matters is mere conformity with a rule, the
moral experts are those who are able to describe a situation so that it
fits under a rule. Hence, for some, morals can become a device to
sanction their amoral pursuits.
≤) It is a formalistic and legalistic view of conduct that usually centers
on avoiding the punishment that comes from a failure to follow
rules; and, as Dewey observed, ‘‘any scheme of morals is defective
which puts the question of avoiding punishment in the foreground
of attention’’ (LW 7:278).
≥) It ‘‘tends to deprive moral life of freedom and spontaneity and to
reduce it to a more or less anxious and servile conformity to exter-
nally imposed rules’’ (LW 7:278). It ‘‘puts the center of moral gravity
outside the concrete processes of living’’ (LW 7:278).
It should be evident from these concerns that the spirit, tone, and
general quality of our moral activities are just as important to Dewey as
the content of morality. Morality is not just a matter of determining what
is right or wrong, but of how we appreciate and engage ourselves in the
moral tasks presented to us. This is a distinctive feature of his ethics that I
will stress in the remainder of this work. He was concerned that a rule-
bound morality would result in casuistries that would ‘‘destroy the grace
and play of life by making conduct mechanical’’ (EW 3:155). A rule ethics
encourages a non-aesthetic way of life; but central to Dewey’s vision is
a concern for an aesthetic moral life, a claim that I will explore at a
later point.
∂∏
moral theory and moral practice
that moral judgments that do not follow rules are thereby arbitrary; and it
a≈rms that reasonable moral judgments come from intelligently explor-
ing and assessing the situation in its qualitative uniqueness. In order to
evaluate an action or to adjudicate conflicts among possible actions or
obligations in concrete circumstances we must rely on the qualitative
context rather than on some meta-rule, criteria, or fixed procedure. Al-
though we make moral judgments and decisions on the basis of the con-
crete and unique situations that are experienced, this approach is not
usually embraced as a method, that is, as a general approach to moral
decision making. It does not have the order, definiteness and security
provided by following prefabricated rules or adopting a universal decision
procedure or criteria. Yet Dewey embraced it as a method. Instead of
trying to come up with comprehensive theories that provide answers or
decision-making procedures, he believed that we should attend to the
particular, the qualitative, and the unique equipped with the best habits of
reflection, imagination, and sensitivity available, that is, with what he
sometimes called moral intelligence. What we morally ought to do in a
situation should be determined by being true to the situation as it is
experienced. A moral judgment is a decision about what action the pres-
ent situation morally calls for, and this can only be determined by immer-
sion in the situation. He thought that this would carry into the moral
sphere the experiential way of doing philosophy more generally, that is, by
being guided by what is qualitatively found in experience. Any theory that
pretends to provide theoretical answers to moral quandaries prior to ac-
tual situations cannot be empirical, for it simply overlooks the experi-
enced uniqueness of each situation and how the moral relevance of any
feature can vary depending on the situation.
To claim that a certain sort of action is always right, or to establish
rules about what is or is not right under all conditions, is to neglect
context; for whether a feature of an action counts as a moral reason to do
it is dependent on the context. The adoption of this kind of contextualism
in morality is the same as that operative in artistic production and appre-
ciation. For instance, whether a stroke of green in a painting contributes
to the beauty of a painting depends on what other colors and lines are
present; indeed, a brushstroke of green that beautifies one painting may be
what ruins another.
Dewey’s contextualism thus entails that there is something wrong-
headed about the abortion debate if that debate is only about which value
or principle is always overriding. In other words, a moral contextualist is
neither pro-life nor pro-choice insofar as both entail a commitment to a
value, obligation, or principle that is absolute. A contextualist could make
∂π
moral theory and experience
an empirical claim that, in most situations, the life of the fetus trumps the
woman’s choice, but this is irrelevant to determining the rightness or
wrongness of each case.≤
The notion that deliberation and judgment should ultimately be
guided by context is not new. Aristotle and W. D. Ross held a similar kind
of contextualism.≥ However, the contextualism of those thinkers is only
operative at the level of making particular moral judgments since their
ethical views assume, at some other level, fixed moral truths. Dewey’s
contextualism is more radical for it is a thoroughgoing contextualism, one
where no general rule or principle can escape its relativity to context.
Dewey does not cling to any moral absolute; nor does he guarantee that
with the most able use of intelligent reflection on the facts at hand we
will succeed or be certain that we are doing the right thing. There is
no right answer that fits every situation, but neither should we assume
that every situation has one right answer. Many morally problematic sit-
uations are experienced as having several possible good or better answers.
The idea that actions such as promise-keeping, killing, lying, and adul-
tery are sometimes right and sometimes wrong depending on the situa-
tion and independent of a priori criteria or rules is uncomfortable for
those who seek a fixed ethical standard. Can an ethics be so flexible with-
out losing its credibility? Before considering this issue, we should guard
Dewey against some misinterpretations of his position.
Dewey’s situation ethics is not the narrowly individualistic view that
one must decide for oneself according to one’s own standards or feelings
of right and wrong. Communal inquiry about shared moral problems is
important, but it, too, should be sensitive to each particular context. Even
for individual decision makers, Dewey is prescribing a way of interacting
in a situation, rather than leaving decision making up to subjective moral
introspection or some faculty of moral intuition. Moreover, Dewey is not
endorsing an absolute particularism, where there is a radical discontinuity
between situations and nothing of decision making importance is carried
forward to new situations. On the contrary, lessons from previous experi-
ences are part of one’s present situational resources because we inherit and
learn the appropriate response to situations from the evolving practices
and institutions in which we participate.∂ We do this from habit and
without much conscious e√ort. Dewey, therefore, does not hold the view
that one should abandon all precedent, that we should come to a situation
empty-handed and with a neutral or impartial attitude toward what is
right or wrong. The abandonment of ready-made standards is consistent
with a strong presumption against actions such as killing and lying. For
∂∫
moral theory and moral practice
Principles
Dewey’s distinction between principles and rules is not based on a di√er-
ence in their contents but in the way we appropriate our inherited moral
knowledge. Principles, as he uses the term, are not fixed or universal
maxims that prescribe and determine what an agent ought to do. They are
instead inherited instrumentalities for analyzing individual and unique
situations. Dewey is willing to accept and adopt, say, the golden rule, but
only as part of the tools of analysis that one might draw upon to consider
what is morally relevant and to make a decision in a particular situation.
Dewey explains:
∂Ω
moral theory and experience
∑≠
moral theory and moral practice
That it, or any other rule, may be a workable tool, that it may really give
aid in a specific case, it must have life and spirit. We cannot give it life
and spirit necessary to make it other than a cramped and cramping
petrification except through the continued free play of intelligence upon
it. (EW 3:101–102)
In short, Dewey does not deny the importance of having, using, and
carrying forward our inherited moral knowledge in the form of princi-
ples, ideals, and habits. But he believes that principles, etc., will lose their
vitality and instrumental capacity the more they are absolutized, that is,
when one does not continue to reexamine them in light of present condi-
tions. Thus, the best way to show respect for a moral idea is to subject it to
continuous reflective criticism.
From this brief consideration of Dewey’s view about the status and
role of principles we have unveiled assumptions of central importance to
his moral philosophy, ones that I will further explore in this study. They
are assumptions about how we should engage ourselves as agents in moral
experience and deliberation. The notion that the non-artistic use of moral
ideas is what transforms them into useless and powerless tools in our
moral life suggests important postulates of Dewey’s moral philosophy. To
anticipate a bit, Dewey’s situational approach is inspired by, and assumes,
the possibility of a moral life that is aesthetic in its mode of engagement.
Furthermore, Dewey’s thoughts about principles give us a clue about one
important function of intelligence in his moral philosophy, namely, that
intelligence constitutes the set of habits that can keep morality from de-
generating into an unaesthetic activity that is externally imposed upon
us. This is the way in which ‘‘moral life is protected from falling into
formalism and rigid repetition. It is rendered flexible, vital, growing’’
(MW 12:180).
∑∞
moral theory and experience
perhaps I will have to admit that not all reasons are sensitive to context
in this way—that there are a privileged few, including probably the
intentional inflicting of undeserved pain, which necessarily constitute
the same sort of reason wherever they occur. If so, I will have lost a battle
but won the war. For the main aim of my particularist position is to
break the stranglehold of a certain conception of how moral reasons
function—the generalist conception under which what is a moral reason
in one situation is necessarily the same reason wherever it occurs.
∑≤
moral theory and moral practice
capable of being altered by changes in context,’’ this follows not only from
Dewey’s contextualism but also from his metaphysical stance that nothing
in the universe is immune to change. The denial of this sort of necessity
(invariance) does not mean, however, that there are no stable and per-
sistent correlations between features of an action and their valence or
rightness. Dewey would be suspicious of the options (absolute invari-
ance and variance) assumed in this debate. The more interesting issue is
whether ethical theory is capable of formulating, or should even try to
formulate, what these stable correlations (between actions and their va-
lence) are at any particular time. Dewey did not rule this out as a possible
task of ethical theory in terms of principles, but he believed that principles
were things that already function, and that perhaps function best, in the
deliberations of particular agents who have inherited a moral tradition.
This raises another noteworthy di√erence.
Principles are, for Dewey, something broader and more embedded in
our ordinary moral a√airs than the sort of intellectual or theoretical rule
that concern particularists. Their rejection or dislike of principles is based
on an overly theoretical conception of principles as propositions in a
theory that specify how non-moral features are tied to moral ones in a
situation. Since principles are, as Dewey believes, tools of analysis of an
engaged moral agent, they need not have the sort of restricted proposi-
tional form assumed by the particularist. In other words, particularists are
able to undermine the function and importance of principles simply be-
cause what they have in mind by principle is not part of anyone’s moral
experience.
The most important di√erence between Dewey and recent particular-
ists is the ultimate context that is appealed to in the grounding of moral
judgments. Dewey’s particularism starts with and takes particular situa-
tions as the ultimate contexts of our moral deliberations, rather than as a
holism of reasons. Dancy joins the ethical tradition he attacks in assuming
that ethical theory must start with the abstraction of reasons in relation to
each other in someone’s moral deliberation. His concern is with ‘‘the
nature of rationality’’ and with ‘‘holistic logic.’’Ω For Dewey, this way of
proceeding in ethics assumes a theoretical starting point that leaves out the
lived situational context that ultimately guides inquiry and in which peo-
ple’s reasons for action are found. In this Dancy is no di√erent from
traditional logicians who concern themselves with reasoning (the universe
of discourse), as if this is all there is to inquiry, and as if the context in
which reasoning occurs (universe of experience) is irrelevant to what
guides the process of reasoning. For Dewey, as I will later discuss, there is
a direct qualitative appreciation (judgment) of the situation as a whole
∑≥
moral theory and experience
that precedes and guides the survey of how reasons relate to each other
in inquiry.
In the introduction to his new book, Ethics without Principles, Dancy
acknowledges that there is more to moral life than moral thought when he
says, ‘‘The book I have written is about how to understand the way in
which reasons work, and deals largely with theories about reasons rather
than life. As you can see, I would like to have been able to write the other
book, the one about life, but this one is all I could manage.’’∞≠ This philo-
sophical bracketing of moral thinking from moral life (experience) is the
sort of starting point that Dewey was against. One cannot understand the
way in which reasons work in moral deliberation without an account of
moral experience. In isolating moral deliberation from moral experience,
Dancy leaves out the context that was so important for Dewey and that set
constraints that could help Dancy confront the charge of moral laxity
raised by generalists.
For the generalist, the particularist’s morality is lax because it fails to
propose an account of how guidance in moral deliberation is possible
without the guidance provided by principles. The particularist does well
to respond that ‘‘there can be fully particular constraints on action, and
the judgment that this action would be wrong is surely just such a thing.
Constraints do not need to be general constraints, any more than reasons
need to be general reasons.’’∞∞ From Dewey’s point of view, there is no need
to choose between the general constraints (i.e., the regulative function
provided by principles) and the more particular constraints found in a
situation. In most situations, it is precisely the interplay between princi-
ples (that represent funded experience) and the new and unique particu-
lars that makes serious thinking di≈cult. More importantly, both the
general and the particular are ultimately within and guided by something
that is more particular than the reasons appealed to by the particularist,
namely, a problematic situation. There are situations in which the weight
of precedent or the need to be consistent is such that to insist on the
particulars reflects a serious lack of sensitivity to the situation. In the end,
it is the particular situation that demands a certain response from me,
rather than the particular moral reasons or generalizations (i.e., rules).
Sometimes, morality requires that we make a similar choice in a similar
situation; but when this is so, it is because of what the particular situation
requires, not because of what morality in general requires.
Dancy questions the assumption (of generalists) that without the
moral sti√ening provided by a principle-based ethics there is a serious
danger of backsliding in ethics or of making exceptions in our own favor.
Dewey is aware of the dangers of moral laxity and moral sti√ening; and
∑∂
moral theory and moral practice
∑∑
moral theory and experience
∑∏
moral theory and moral practice
fun are anything but wrong? If it cannot, then one may argue that there is
something wrong with his view.
It does follow, according to Dewey’s view, that it is possible for there
to be a situation where torturing children for fun is morally permissible.
Openness to this possibility, however, does not mean that in a concrete
situation this action stands somehow on an equal basis with others, and
Dewey would not have condoned the torture of children. Is there any
genuine doubt that the presumption against torturing children for fun is
so strong that it is hardly ever the subject of conscious deliberation? That
does not make it immune to criticism, nor does it suggest that its stabil-
ity and validity are independent of particular situations. It can be sub-
ject to evaluation and doubt in a situation, no matter how unlikely this
may seem. Although it is hard to imagine a situation where torturing
children for fun is morally permissible, it is clear that a Deweyan, fully
committed to the openness entailed by contextualism, must bite the bullet
and take this as evidence of the limits of our imagination.∞∏ There could be
unique factors in a situation that may well change the moral quality of an
act that has always been wrong. Does biting the bullet undermine the
credibility or validity of Dewey’s ethics? This would be to assume that an
ethics without any absolute prohibitions couldn’t be valid or helpful to
moral life. Why?
This brings us to the second possible objection. If his ethics cannot
rule out certain actions as wrong (by providing a fixed criterion of right or
wrong) then one may question what good it is. If all that Dewey can tell us
is that we should take certain purported rules as principles, then this does
not help us avoid the dangers of moral absolutism and moral licentious-
ness that much. One hopes that Dewey’s moral thought proposes some-
thing more substantial than the advice to stay away from standard moral
theories and theorists. This in e√ect points to a challenge to any recon-
struction of Dewey’s ethics. The challenge is to present an ethics thin
enough not to fall into another absolutist ethical system but thick enough
to be taken seriously as an ethics that, in some indirect way, can at least
illuminate moral practice. It is di≈cult for a contextualist who abandons
the traditional pretensions of theory, as did Dewey, to make normative
suggestions without compromising its openness to context.
The apparent thinness of Dewey’s ethics has troubled both critics and
sympathizers. C. I. Lewis, Sidney Hook, and more recently, Robert West-
brook and Hilary Putnam agree with Dewey that we must abandon the
quest for some ultimate external, fixed, and absolute standard or criteria.
But they all agree that there must be some other type of standard, other-
wise Dewey’s philosophy would be in trouble.
∑π
moral theory and experience
But is it not the case that we must ourselves bring to experience the
ultimate criterion and touchstone of the good; that otherwise experience
could no more teach us what is good than it can teach the blind man
what things are red?∞π
Before one embarks upon the practical and empirical problem of realiz-
ing the valuable or constructing the good, is it not essential that one
should be able to recognize it when disclosed . . . ? . . . [C]an experience
determine the nature, essence, criteria of goodness?∞∫
Sidney Hook and Robert Westbrook are concerned that Dewey did not say
enough to meet this sort of challenge. Even if there are no fixed ends for
Dewey, what criteria do we use to evaluate the success of our ends in
view?∞Ω Even if there is no foundationalist-type of justification for democ-
racy, Dewey must have assumed a criterion that made this way of life
better than others.≤≠ Many scholars have tried to reconstruct Dewey’s
thought on the subject of criteria. These attempts strike me as either too
thin or too thick because they miss something fundamental in Dewey’s
philosophy. Those that are too thick attribute to Dewey some criterion of
goodness, even if it is not a fixed and external one. The usual candidates
here are some goal or consequence, like growth or flourishing. They are
too thick in the sense that they attribute to Dewey the sort of normative
substance that goes against the contextualist and pluralistic character of
his ethics. As I will argue, there is no criterion or standard of the good of
any kind in Dewey’s ethics.
Other e√orts have been too thin; in particular, those that have ac-
knowledged that even if there is no single standard in his philosophy,
Dewey trusted that the plural standards that we have inherited from our
previous experience and community will provide us with enough guid-
ance. In other words, the past, in the form of principles and the lessons of
previous inquiries, set present constraints. Putnam, for example, thinks
that Dewey’s answer to the question ‘‘By what criteria do we decide that
some valuations are warranted?’’ is that ‘‘we always bring a large stock of
valuations and descriptions’’ that we can rely on and ‘‘there are some good
things that we have learned from inquiry in general’’≤∞ that can be applied.
These last e√orts are in the right direction. Yet they are too thin
∑∫
moral theory and moral practice
because there is for Dewey more to say about the moral guidance that he
thinks we can discern in present experience. Even if some constraints are
set by our previous experiences, it does not help us determine how we
should guide ourselves in the use of these resources or in their criticism.
Dewey’s advice has to be more than that we follow the best principles
available. And there is more to intelligence than applying standards of
inquiry learned from experience.
Both of these interpretations or defenses of Dewey miss one of the
most important, radical, and unique aspects of his philosophy. The notion
that moral discourse depends only on its own evolving criteria or stan-
dards to guide itself misses the point that there is more to morality than
moral discourse. In particular, there is the qualitative situational context;
and far from being a mere background consideration, the context is what
ultimately guides morality. Dewey has much to say regarding how we can
best equip ourselves to rely on this guidance.
To adequately answer the charge of thinness requires that we take into
consideration how thick Dewey’s account is. As I will argue later, Dewey
o√ers normative prescriptions; there are, in other words, better and worse
ways of approaching moral problems and our moral relationships. In
moral deliberation there is more to rely on than principles in coming to
judgments about right and wrong; in particular, there is a qualitative
context that, if we are equipped with the proper dispositions, can guide us.
I will present Dewey’s ethics as committed to certain dispositions, a cer-
tain character and community. One must not, however, expect to find in
Dewey instructions that if followed will guarantee moral conduct or that
will determine who is or is not acting morally or immorally. He does not
o√er any guarantee that even if we follow his advice we will stay within the
bounds of moral decency or avoid relativism. This is not the function of
an ethical theory. What, then, is the function of an ethical theory once one
has abandoned the traditional expectations about ethical theory? Is there
any legitimate role left for an ethical theory? Let’s now consider these
questions as a prologue to my presentation of the more substantive aspects
of Dewey’s ethical theory.
∑Ω
moral theory and experience
moral decisions. On the other hand, there are philosophers who have tried
to save ethics by claiming that the mistake lies in thinking that ethical
theory has anything to do with aiding moral conduct. Ethical theory
should be done exclusively for the sake of theoretical understanding or to
solve the theoretical problems of philosophers. In other words, only meta-
ethics or general and abstract theoretical speculations for theoretical pur-
poses are possible. Dewey was sensitive to both of these extreme views but
never thought we had to choose between them. For Dewey, there is an
alternative which lies between divorcing ethical theory completely from
moral practice and the pretensions of some normative ethical theories to
dictate our moral conduct. The key to seeing this alternative lies in having
an adequate empirical conception of what a theory is.
In an early essay Dewey explains the functional relation between the-
ory and practice by using the example of an engineer building a tunnel.
No matter how many times the engineer has constructed similar tunnels,
what she is building is not a tunnel in general. ‘‘It is a tunnel having its
own special end and called for by its own set of circumstances’’ (EW 3:156).
However, because similar tunnels have been built under functionally simi-
lar circumstances one may develop theories or techniques that, because
of their generality, can function as tools of analysis for particular cases.
Hence, the general character of theories is not a limitation but the key to
their possible functional importance for practice. To be sure, not all of the
theoretical resources available to the engineer have the same kind of in-
strumental value. The most immediate ready at hand tools are principles
or rules of thumb that provide a suggestion as to what to do when one is
building this kind of tunnel. An engineer might also have a very general
theory about the nature of the materials used to make the tunnel. Even if
this theory makes no reference to the practice of building tunnels, it is not
entirely divorced from or irrelevant to that practice.
In general, Dewey claims that theory cannot be divorced from the
context of practice; for theory arises from, is informed by, and a√ects
practice. It is true that theoretical moral inquiry has its own theoreti-
cal problems, very di√erent in nature from the concrete moral conflicts
that are the origin of personal moral deliberation. However, theoretical
inquiry is not the quest for a ‘‘foundation for moral activity in something
beyond that activity itself ’’ (EW 3:94). To think otherwise is to com-
mit the philosophical fallacy. For Dewey, moral philosophy is invari-
ably and inevitably enmeshed in a particular context, that is, it is a func-
tion of and within moral life. The refined conclusions (i.e., secondary
products) of moral theory are, like the theoretical resources of the engi-
neer, instrumentalities by which we might be able to indirectly assist or
∏≠
moral theory and moral practice
t h e e m p i r i c a l - i n s t r u m e n ta l c o n c e p t i o n
o f m o r a l t h e o ry
For Dewey the view that moral theory is both in and for moral life has
important implications regarding how to evaluate ethical theories and
their most productive functions. The most straightforward of these is that
one cannot determine what an adequate ethical theory is without consid-
ering what kind of ethical theory is better for our moral lives. In other
words, the worth of a theory is determined not only in terms of its intellec-
tual consistency and coherence or its explanatory power, but also in terms
of its instrumental and ameliorative powers in the context of practice.
This allows us to propose hypotheses about when, and in what form,
moral theory helps and when it hinders moral practice. Of course, any
suggestion in this regard is ultimately an empirical claim, one that has to
be tested in the moral lives of agents, remains open for future inquiry, and
should be evaluated in light of the particular theories available at any given
∏∞
moral theory and experience
time. Dewey’s own evaluation of some of the ethical theories of his time
led him to some general hypotheses about this issue.
Dewey believed that our moral lives are better served if ethical theory
becomes empirical. As we have seen this means primarily that ethics must
take morally problematic situations in their qualitative uniqueness as the
start and end point of inquiry, and avoid the adoption of any kind of axi-
omatic first principles. No ethical theory is final. It must have a dynamic,
open, and learning relation with respect to the practice out of which it
arises and within which it is embedded. However, one might accept the
general claim that empirical theories are better than non-empirical ones
and still remain skeptical about the point of ethical theory. For it is not
clear what role there is left for ethics, once one gives up its traditional goals.
Does this mean that philosophers should redirect their concern with the-
ory to a more direct and exclusive concern with specific practical prob-
lems, as in what is today called applied ethics? This issue needs to be
considered in order to avoid saddling a Deweyan approach to ethics with a
narrow kind of instrumentalism about moral theory.
Ethical theory is not necessarily made more practical simply by hav-
ing as its direct end a desire to be practical. In philosophy, just as in
science, a constant fixation and concern with practical problems and ends
could undermine practical e√ectiveness. One might argue that productive
inquiry requires a division of labor where there are individuals who are
directly involved in doing theory for theory’s own sake. This is not to deny
that there are excesses and dangers that result when intellectuals are so
committed to their theories that they forget the place of theory within the
context of moral practice. The failure to be empirical is perhaps the result
of being seduced by one’s interest as a theorist.
If the function of moral theory is to assist our moral practice, then the
operations and selectivity of a theorist should be guided by purposes that
enhance this function. However, the temptation of the ethical theorist is to
guide her selectivity by theoretical or academic purposes that are irrele-
vant, secondary, or even counterproductive to the improvement of moral
practice. For instance, selecting only those features of moral life that can
be quantified, universalized, or made commensurable in terms of a theory
is not in the best interest of morality as a lived practice. Moral theories are
bad tools if they suggest that the complexity, uncertainty, and incommen-
surability that we experience in our moral lives are illusory. One is more
likely to direct the changes in experience intelligently if one is faithful to its
present traits.
Does ethics become more practical by limiting itself to applied ethics,
that is, if it addresses particular problems instead of the usual general ones?
∏≤
moral theory and moral practice
∏≥
moral theory and experience
lived experience. In other words, ethical theories and rules can become
bad tools when they are either too abstract or too specific. In one of his
early ethical writings, Dewey wrote,
This is a claim that can be understood in terms of both the descriptive and
the normative functions of ethical theories. A metaphysics of morals (as
an empirical description of moral experience) is undesirable when it con-
sists of excessively abstract generalities that ‘‘remain remote from contact
with actual experience’’ (EW 3:159). Yet a metaphysics that can illuminate
practice cannot be too specific. Dewey’s reference to an empirical meta-
physics as a ‘‘ground map of the province of criticism’’ provides a useful
analogy to make this point (LW 1:309). A map can be general to the point
of becoming a useless abstraction. On the other hand, a map that pretends
to capture the uniqueness of the streets we travel or that tells us where to
go becomes a bad tool. Furthermore, the fact that a map cannot have this
kind of precision is hardly a good excuse for not using or making maps.
Dewey uses this argument to support the construction and use of moral
theory.
Ethical theories can become so abstract and general that they are of no
use to moral practice; but the general character of theory is a precondition
for it to inform and be informed by practice. It makes possible a dynamic
relation between theory and practice where ‘‘the former enlarges, releases
and gives significance to the latter; while practice supplies theory with its
materials and with the test and check which keep it sincere and vital’’
(LW 2:58). Ethical theory can also be a tool for moral education. Like our
best maps, it can orient us, but we must do our own traveling and learn-
ing. In both aesthetics and ethics a philosopher should be more concerned
with a survey of the subject matter than with making judgments for
others. ‘‘Then his surveys may be of assistance in the direct experience of
others, as a survey of a country is of help to the one who travels through it,
while dicta about worth operate to limit personal experience’’ (LW 10:313).
In sum, the alternative to either an ethical theory that stands totally
aloof or one that pretends to lay down in advance fixed rules is an empiri-
cal theory concerned with the generic in moral experience, and that o√ers
only indirect assistance to moral practice. These seem, so far, to be rather
formal or methodological conditions of a theory. The type of theory that
∏∂
moral theory and moral practice
meets these conditions cannot solve moral problems. It cannot adopt the
kind of standpoint where it convinces a moral skeptic that it is rational to
be moral; and it cannot provide a rational proof that Hitler’s conduct was
wrong. Is there anything it can do? What sort of indirect assistance can be
proposed? If one wishes to confront the skeptic about the possibilities of
ethical theory once its traditional pretensions are abandoned, it is neces-
sary to suggest some specific positive functions that a Deweyan ethics can
perform. There are at least two. An ethical theory can function as a tool of
criticism, and it can propose hypotheses about the conditions for living a
better moral life.
∏∑
moral theory and experience
∏∏
moral theory and moral practice
∏π
moral theory and experience
∏∫
moral theory and moral practice
∏Ω
moral theory and experience
π≠
three
The Normative Standpoint of Pragmatism
π∞
moral theory and experience
ence the question that requires an answer is a matter of choice, rather than
idle speculation; for it needs to be answered in terms of what our present
living∞ options are, where we are, and what we can do. The issue is a
momentous and forced one because we are not subjects who can stand
outside the course of events; participation or engagement of some form or
another is unavoidable. The only choice available to us is between modes
of participation. As Dewey says, ‘‘one cannot escape the problem of how to
engage in life, since in any case he must engage in it some way or another—
or else quit and get out’’ (MW 14:58). This does not mean that we are
trapped—unless we presuppose a non-relational, non-contextual notion
of ourselves. However, it does mean that the question about how we
should live cannot be answered once and for all; there is no final rest-
ing place, and no final answer, because our options and conditions can
change. But this is not a good enough reason to neglect the question.
Therefore the pragmatic approach has to be tentative.
It might be objected that once one gives up the Archimedean stand-
point one also has to give up the normative task of being concerned with
how one should live, since there is no justifiable and non-arbitrary stand-
point from which to judge this issue. Richard Rorty claims that a pragma-
tist needs to admit that there is ‘‘no ahistorical standpoint from which to
endorse the habits of modern democracies he wishes to praise,’’ that there
is no ‘‘demonstration of the ‘objective’ superiority of our way of life over
all other alternatives.’’≤ For Rorty, the alternative to an ahistorical objective
justification is not despair, but solidarity. We need to learn to be ‘‘ethno-
centric’’ and to ‘‘privilege our own group, even though there can be no
noncircular justification for doing so.’’≥ Since it is idle to want to stand
outside our particular community and look down at it from a more
universal standpoint, we should cultivate the desire to stand by our tradi-
tional liberal habits and hopes simply because they are ours. In the end,
Rorty recommends a blind solidarity that merely justifies the status quo;
in so doing, he places us in a false dilemma.
Dewey rejects the choice between ahistorical objectivity and solidar-
ity, and thus rejects Rorty’s dilemma. We do not have to stand outside
experience or assume a God’s-eye point of view in order to assess the
options available to us. Neither is there a field of experience that provides
all the considerations relevant to the evaluation of a mode of participation
in experience. We can use past experience and our knowledge of actual
conditions in order to evaluate our options. We need to start from where
we are, but we can also learn from where we have been. The options we
have today are not strictly the same as the ones our ancestors had, but
neither are they so di√erent that learning from past experience is impos-
π≤
t h e n o r m at i v e s ta n d p o i n t o f p r a g m at i s m
π≥
moral theory and experience
most controlled environment for testing his hypotheses was the class-
room; this is why he thought that moral theory and moral education were
interdependent.
Dewey was fully committed to democracy as a moral ideal, that is, as a
tool that provides some guidance without being the normative basis of all
values, or without telling us what to do in a particular situation. Neverthe-
less, I will argue in the last part of this book that a reconsideration of
Dewey’s view on democracy in light of his ethics discloses an even thicker
description of democracy, one that goes beyond the vague commitments
of Deweyans to notions like social intelligence, communal inquiry, and
growth. Democracy is part of a general moral outlook toward the world
and others. It is not merely a type of social procedure or mode of public
deliberation; moreover, Dewey’s defense of democracy as a way of life is
not made from an Archimedean standpoint. He merely wants to win the
consent of people who are already committed to certain values and who
are challenged by certain concrete problems. Why must the only rea-
sonable justification of democracy be the one that convinces an imagi-
nary rational agent or a radical moral skeptic under ideal conditions?
This again assumes a very questionable starting point for a philosophy of
democracy.
The task of eliciting and articulating the thickness of Dewey’s ethics in
terms of the two general theoretical tasks just described will occupy us for
the remainder of this study. But to some extent I have already begun. For I
have unveiled Dewey’s methodological commitments and hinted at some
moral commitments behind his skepticism of traditional ethical theories.
I have already indicated that his anti-theoretical views and his notion of
principles cannot be understood independently of other assumptions that
are part of his moral vision, for example, the function of intelligence and
the artistic use of moral ideas. I will further explore the meaning and
implications of these assumptions and the commitments they presuppose.
But before moving into broad hypotheses about our moral lives I think it
is important to reiterate why any adequate unfolding or examination of
Dewey’s ethical vision needs to begin and take as central the notion of a
situation.
For Dewey, in our moral life we are always in a situation. His norma-
tive proposals, no matter how general or abstract they might seem, are
about how to participate in situations. Furthermore, if we wanted to
summarize most of what Dewey’s moral vision proposes, we could say that
his moral philosophy encourages us to live by and for a situation. In other
words, a concrete situation should be the means and end of morality. Let’s
begin to explore what this means.
π∂
t h e n o r m at i v e s ta n d p o i n t o f p r a g m at i s m
π∑
moral theory and experience
π∏
t h e n o r m at i v e s ta n d p o i n t o f p r a g m at i s m
Dewey was not naïve. He believed that the course of events in nature
and the quality of our moral life is not altogether under our control, but
he didn’t see this as a good reason to abandon an inquiry into what
di√erence we can make. Dewey found it childish to abandon that which is
in our power on the ground that we lack total control.
We know that though the universe slay us still we may trust, for our lot is
one with whatever is good in existence. We know that such thought and
e√ort is one condition of the coming into existence of the better. As far
as we are concerned it is the only condition, for it alone is in our power.
To ask more than this is childish; but to ask less is a recreance no less
egotistic, involving no less a cutting of ourselves from the universe than
does the expectation that it meet and satisfy our every wish. (LW 1:314)
These passages assume a very delicate balance that is key to Dewey’s vision.
Dewey presents us with a ‘‘doctrine of humility’’ but also of ‘‘direction’’
(LW 1:373). He recognizes that we can only operate in a piecemeal fashion
and from where we are. The way to rely on (lie back upon) lived experience
is to rely on what is directly experienced. This requires that we open and
trust our eyes, ears, and thoughts; but it must not be naïve, it is not a blind
trust. We are no longer naïve, for example, about how undesirable racial
or class-based prejudices can condition our immediate moral experience.
We cannot question everything at once but we must nonetheless try to
question. Dewey says, ‘‘An empirical philosophy is in any case a kind of
intellectual disrobing. . . . We cannot achieve recovery of primitive naïveté.
But there is a cultivated naïveté of eye, ear, and thought’’ (LW 1:40).
Cultivated naïveté requires both trust and criticism. As I discuss in later
chapters, the ideal is the balance between receptivity (appreciation) and
criticism. We must be ready to doubt, but we must do so for the sake of
cultivating our immediate experience. What we need to do in moral edu-
cation is to foster the set of habits by which students can acquire cultivated
naïveté instead of becoming absolutist or skeptics.
To summarize, I have suggested that Dewey’s situation ethics is unin-
telligible apart from certain positive assumptions and commitments that I
have been slowly revealing. The most important is his faith in experience
and his commitment to taking the situation as the end and means of
morality. We need to unfold Dewey’s moral vision, for not just any moral
life is consistent with these commitments. To anticipate what lies ahead:
ππ
moral theory and experience
π∫
PART TWO
Dewey’s View of Moral Experience
four
Morality as Experience
∫∞
dewey’s view of moral experience
∫≤
morality as experience
∫≥
dewey’s view of moral experience
∫∂
morality as experience
To be sure, this is a di√erent sort of realism than the typical variety where
moral properties exist independently of an agent’s participation in a moral
situation. Rather, moral qualities, such as those that we call good or right,
are experienced and judged as objective features of a situation, even if
further inquiry might change this or if there is disagreement about their
presence.
This sort of realism is consistent with Dewey’s contextualism. Moral
qualities and moral decisions are context-dependent and have their home
and meaning in a particular situation. This is true of all qualities. Color
and sound are not qualities appreciated or discriminated in isolation, or
self-su≈cient elements that can be used to explain complex cases of sense
perception. The situational context as a scene of action is what is experi-
enced, where what we are directly concerned with becomes focal and
meaningful because of that implicit field. ‘‘When objects or qualities are
cognitively apprehended, they are viewed in reference to the exigencies of
the perceived field in which they occur’’ (LW 12:153). Hence, the rightness,
goodness, or moral necessity of an act is ‘‘not one property it possesses in
and of itself, in the isolation of non-relatedness’’ (LW 14:77). It is true that
∫∑
dewey’s view of moral experience
moral qualities are not the subject matter of scientific inquiry. But the fact
that moral qualities are not quantifiable or subject to predictive control
does not imply that they are not real and important in the context of a
morally problematic situation. This is the fallacy committed by recent
naturalists who reject the notion that moral qualities are natural.≥
In philosophy, the word ‘quality’ is usually associated with either
some abstract metaphysical property or some subjective phenomena, as in
emotivism. With Dewey, however, it simply points to our pre-theoretical
and pre-cognitive experience in the world. A qualitative world of persons
and things is the most basic and inclusive context where one finds lan-
guage, knowledge, and all of our more discursive activities, philosophy
included. ‘‘A universe of experience is the precondition of a universe of
discourse’’ (LW 12:74).
The world of everyday experience also has tertiary qualities, that is,
qualities that pervade all the parts of a whole. The quality that pervades a
situation is what demarcates it as a situation. A situation is a ‘‘complex
existence that is held together in spite of its internal complexity by the fact
that it is dominated and characterized throughout by a single quality’’
(LW 5:246). To say that a quality pervades a situation is to say that the
quality runs through every aspect and detail of a situation, gives meaning
to each aspect, and binds them all together. ‘‘If the situation experienced is
that of being lost in a forest, the quality of being lost permeates and a√ects
every detail that is observed and thought of ’’ (LW 12:203). This is relevant
to the issue of designating what is moral in experience. Moral qualities
should not be limited to single acts or agents. A situation may be experi-
enced as predominantly moral, that is, as having the pervasive quality of
demanding that one find out what one morally ought to do. When a felt
moral perplexity controls and pervades the development of a situation, we
can designate the situation and its corresponding inquiry as moral.
Although morality and art have traditionally been associated with the
qualitative, serious thought and inquiry have not. This is because modern
notions of thought neglect or downplay the importance of the qualitative.
As a consequence, morality and art are disregarded as thought-less and
arbitrary. In contrast, for Dewey, all thought is qualitative thought. Situa-
tions that demand reconstruction through inquiry are situations that are
qualitatively experienced as unsettled, confused, and indeterminate. The
transformation of the pervasive quality of this sort of situation is, in e√ect,
the general function of any inquiry. This is not a subjective transforma-
tion. Situations in their qualitative immediacy and uniqueness are pri-
mary and prior to any distinction between subject and object. Dewey
explains: ‘‘according to my theory, while the initial problematic situation
∫∏
morality as experience
and the final transformed resolved situation are equally immediately qual-
itative, no situation is subjective nor involves a subject and object relation’’
(LW 5:70). More importantly, ‘‘the immediate existence of quality, and of
dominant and pervasive quality, is the background, the point of depar-
ture, and the regulative principle of all thinking’’ (LW 5:261, my emphasis).
In my general characterization of moral life as a qualitative and social
process, I have not mentioned the elements, phases, and operations that
are experienced as an integral part of this process. In the next chapter, I
turn my attention to some of the finer and functional distinctions that can
be articulated about moral experience.
∫π
five
The ‘‘What’’ of Moral Experience
One of the broadest functional distinctions that can be made about lived
experience is that between the subject matter experienced—what is expe-
rienced—and the experiencing of it—how it is experienced.∞ How we par-
ticipate in morally problematic situations is one of the key features of such
situations. In the next chapter, I will consider the function of habits and
character in moral experience, that is, the how. In other words, I will
distinguish our moral attitudes and dispositions from the moral situations
in which they are operative. But I will first consider what occurs during
the course of morally problematic situations. What are the generic traits
and phases of these kinds of processes?
For Dewey, life is neither a homogeneous flux nor a succession of
disconnected (atomistic) moments. It is ‘‘a thing of histories, each with its
own plot, its own inception and movement towards its close’’ (LW 10:43).
Each of these histories is a situation that begins with a disruption from the
fluidity provided by our habits. From this initial phase we usually move to
an intermediate phase in which we try to transform the unsettledness. In
this second phase, we might engage in inquiry as a series of doings and
undergoings with our environment. If successful, we arrive at a final phase
∫∫
t h e ‘‘w h a t’’ o f m o r a l e x p e r i e n c e
∫Ω
dewey’s view of moral experience
Ω≠
t h e ‘‘w h a t’’ o f m o r a l e x p e r i e n c e
Ω∞
dewey’s view of moral experience
Ω≤
t h e ‘‘w h a t’’ o f m o r a l e x p e r i e n c e
Ω≥
dewey’s view of moral experience
and irreducible to the other even though one of them may end up becom-
ing more pressing in the particular situation. Once moral inquiry is initi-
ated, the experienced moral tension may or may not be eased.
Dewey’s ‘‘Three Independent Factors in Morals’’ is a centerpiece of his
moral thought. In a letter to Professor Horace S. Fries, Dewey acknowl-
edged that in his early works ‘‘I followed the tradition in making ends, the
good, the basic ideal,’’ but that by 1930 it became clear to him that he had
changed his view. His tripartite division of moral experience in this essay
prefigures, among other things, his 1932 Ethics, where he placed good,
duty, and virtue in separate chapters. It is clear in this essay how radical the
situational and pluralistic thrust of his moral philosophy is.∑ His situation
ethics is based on the view that each moral problem is unique and is usu-
ally constituted by an irreconcilable complexity. All three of the factors—
good, duty, and virtue—have something to contribute, but their respective
adherents in ethical theory have all latched on to one aspect of our moral
experience. Dewey was concerned that this singularity does not encourage
a generous survey of our moral problems. A narrow view of moral prob-
lems is responsible for the tendency in normative ethics to propose a
single right way to reason in ethics. For Dewey, an appreciation of the
nature of the conflicts that are the basis for moral theory and deliberation
protects us from false pretensions about the power of single factors to
resolve them. Dewey’s faith in the instrumentalities of experience was
tempered by the honest realization that the most intense moments of our
moral life are tragic.
Moral Deliberation
Moral deliberation is not something that happens within one’s mind. It is
experienced as an intermediate phase in the process of transforming a
morally problematic situation into one that is determinate. This does not
mean that it is a discrete and independent phase. In moral inquiry the
disruption that is felt as the engrossing whole that provoked it persists and
evolves in the background; in other words, we are still su√ering the prob-
lem even if the foreground or focus of attention is concerned with such
questions as: what is the problem? What resources do I have at my disposal
to settle this? How can I gather more evidence? To set up a problem that is
not guided by some genuinely felt doubt or perplexity ‘‘is to start on a
course of dead work’’ (LW 12:112). The overarching and final aim is to
determine what I ought to do among alternative courses of action. In
other words, the aim is choice as ‘‘the emergence of a unified preference
out of competing preferences’’ (MW 14:134).
Ω∂
t h e ‘‘w h a t’’ o f m o r a l e x p e r i e n c e
Ω∑
dewey’s view of moral experience
Ω∏
t h e ‘‘w h a t’’ o f m o r a l e x p e r i e n c e
how the parts contribute to making an overall judgment. These are mutu-
ally dependent phases throughout the di√erent stages of moral inquiry.
Reaching a hypothesis about the nature of the conflict is itself an act of
synthesis from the more particular analysis of what the competing moral
demands are in a situation and what particular features of the situation
contribute to their rightness. Any tentative proposal about the nature of
the problem provokes in turn an examination (analysis) of possible solu-
tions that issues in a tentative overall judgment (synthesis) about the best
solution; this may then guide further analyses and surveys of new aspects
of the situation. The final judgment about what we ought to do is a
synthesis that results from the analysis of the situation as a whole, but it is
only the final step in a series of tentative overall judgments that have
occurred throughout the entire process of deliberation.
This same process can be also described in terms of the phases of
doing and undergoing in an experimental learning process. The conse-
quences of di√erent operations in the situation are perceived (appreci-
ated) in order to guide subsequent ones. What we take to be the right
course of action at any point in inquiry guides our survey of what we take
to be the settled features, the facts, of the case (through observation or
recollection of similar cases); this, in turn, may generate new suggestions
and revisions of our judgment, which may in turn lead us to survey
di√erent aspects of the situation. In this process principles and habits have
the function of bringing previous experience to bear. Reasoning provides
us with the inferences needed to go beyond what we have, or it helps us
elaborate our suppositions in light of other beliefs. Imagination in the
form of a dramatic rehearsal helps us survey and test our options. Let’s
consider in some more detail some of these complex and interdependent
operations and resources.
I explained the function of principles in Dewey’s ethics in chapter 2.
In the arts, cooking, or morals we often rely on principles and habits that
are informed by previous experience in order to reach judgments. Princi-
ples may even help us with the task of deciding which facts are relevant in
coming to a decision; but even in these cases, we have to ultimately rely on
the guidance provided by the particular context of inquiry. For Dewey,
even in the case of judgments reached in a court of law, where there is an
explicit reliance on rules, ‘‘the quality of the problematic situation de-
termines which rules of the total system are selected’’ (LW 12:124, my
emphasis).
Judgment is required in deciding what principles apply. ‘‘There is no
label, on any given idea or principle, that says automatically, ‘Use me in
this situation’ ’’ (LW 8:215). Judgment is required to find out what features
Ωπ
dewey’s view of moral experience
of an action are morally relevant and which ones are a distraction. Princi-
ples can help but they are no substitute for the tact and discernment of a
good judge. No rules can replace the power to seize the significant factors
in a situation and the sensitivity to the quality of the problematic situation
that is being transformed.
Moral deliberation can also rely on ‘‘reasoning’’ (LW 12:115), such as
the examination of the implications of a proposed solution in light of its
logical relations with other beliefs or meanings. This can be useful in
developing and revising suggestions and considerations in such a way that
they can be more easily tested. Moral deliberation is not, however, a
deductive process. It is experimental insofar as the results of its operations
are tentative and subject to confirmation or frustration as inquiry pro-
ceeds. Experimental thinking is not the exclusive domain of the sciences.
The notion that empirical testing is the confrontation of ideas and hy-
potheses with the direct observation by the senses is a narrow form of
empiricism. In moral life, many times it is only after one acts upon a
choice (and judgment) that one can obtain the necessary confirmation or
disconfirmation for one’s choice. In fact, a judgment reached in a morally
problematic situation is not final for it is a doing that might provoke
further undergoings. Reaching a judgment about what to do is usually
followed by experiences that either o√er no resistance (a type of confirma-
tion) or that generate a new problematic situation.
There is, however, no reason why testing needs to take the form of an
overt experiment. For Dewey, the imagination plays a crucial role in the
exploration and testing of our options in a situation. This provides an
opportunity to have a preliminary test (trial) of our options in a morally
problematic situation without su√ering the consequences of acting upon
them. In deliberation, the competing possible lines of action that are
present in a morally problematic situation are tried out in an imaginative
drama that includes the agents involved, possible consequences, and im-
plications. Thus, Dewey often referred to moral deliberation as ‘‘a dra-
matic rehearsal’’ (MW 14:132). This is why he claims that what goes on
in moral deliberation is closer to ‘‘an actor engaged in drama’’ than to
a ‘‘clerk recording debit and credit items’’ (MW 14:139). Just as an actor en-
gaged in a drama, moral deliberation may require imaginary role-playing,
as well as taking seriously the standpoint or possible reaction of others.
For example, my imagination may be provoked by the following ques-
tions: What are possible scenarios (or stories) if I support the war? How
do they compare with the one of not supporting it and with regard to my
duties? What would an impartial moral judge think? What good would be
preserved or enhanced? How does the best-case scenario (in terms of
Ω∫
t h e ‘‘w h a t’’ o f m o r a l e x p e r i e n c e
ΩΩ
dewey’s view of moral experience
∞≠≠
t h e ‘‘w h a t’’ o f m o r a l e x p e r i e n c e
∞≠∞
dewey’s view of moral experience
led him to investigate the ways in which scientific inquiry and moral
inquiry can share a way, or general method, of forming and justifying
judgments. In his later works he came to rely more on an aesthetic model.
This is most evident in his description of moral deliberation as a transfor-
mation into a unified consummatory experience and in his emphasis on
the importance of the imagination and the emotions in this process. This
is the aspect of Dewey’s view on moral deliberation that seems most
radical, considering the predominance of sterile rationalistic accounts of
moral deliberation in the history of moral philosophy. It is also the most
promising, considering the recent developments in cognitive science on
the role of metaphor, imagination, and emotion.π
For Dewey, moral deliberation is not an intermediate phase where
one moves from a conflict of qualitative material to a process of cold
reasoning where qualities are transformed into quantities and proposi-
tions. Deliberation is not an intermediate phase where we close or sus-
pend our access to the qualitative world. On the contrary, it is an oppor-
tunity to widen and enrich our qualitative experience. The access to the
qualitative-richness of a situation is not limited to sense perception or
observation. The function of imagination is to amplify perception, to
open up the situation in ways that could assist us in coming to a judgment.
Imagination ‘‘elicits the possibilities that are interwoven within the texture
of the actual’’ (LW 10:348). It ‘‘puts before us objects which are not directly
or sensibly present, so that we then may react directly to these objects’’
(MW 14:139). The capacity to deliberate signifies the ability to take an
experienced conflict of possible actions and place them in an imaginative
field so that they can be judged in light of what is qualitatively revealed in
that field. Deliberation ‘‘is an attempt to uncover the conflict in its full
scope and bearing . . . to reveal qualitative incompatibilities by detecting
the di√erent courses to which they commit us’’ (MW 14:150). And deliber-
ation is not a phase of cool, detached inactivity or indi√erence. If there is
no unified extrovert response while we deliberate it is only because dif-
ferent aspects of the situation are pushing us in di√erent directions. Since
these tendencies toward action are present, though inhibited, during de-
liberation, the resulting choice ‘‘is not the emergence of preference out of
indi√erence’’ (MW 14:134). Hence, in Dewey there is no need to postulate
the will as a separate faculty which pushes the agent in the direction
dictated by deliberation.
It is also worth noticing how Dewey’s account of how judgments are
reached reverses the order assumed in many ethical theories. In these
theories the final verdict about our ‘‘actual duty’’ (to use W. D. Ross’s
term) in a situation is something that is derived after we have first analyzed
∞≠≤
t h e ‘‘w h a t’’ o f m o r a l e x p e r i e n c e
and evaluated what are the competing prima facie principles in the situa-
tion. There is a final verdict for Dewey, but like the conclusion of any
inquiry, it is something that gradually emerges and is prior to its premises.
Dewey explains how formal conceptions of logic often give the wrong
impression about how we actually think.
In moral deliberation the search for the reasons that ground our
overall impression about what is right must involve a sincere survey of
how the relevant features that make up a situation are related, and it may
lead to assertions about what makes a particular action right or wrong.
Articulating in propositional form what traits or features of a situation
sustain one’s moral judgment is key to justifying ourselves to others and in
inviting them to consider for themselves the situation. In other words, it
facilitates a more communal inquiry. More importantly, the phase of
∞≠≥
dewey’s view of moral experience
∞≠∂
t h e ‘‘w h a t’’ o f m o r a l e x p e r i e n c e
Valuation emerges from valuing but they do not always converge. For
example, I might not immediately value recycling, although I come to
reflectively judge that it is a good practice. However, most of the situations
that Dewey has in mind when he makes the distinction between valuing
and valuation are those in which one of these judgments of value emerges,
∞≠∑
dewey’s view of moral experience
∞≠∏
t h e ‘‘w h a t’’ o f m o r a l e x p e r i e n c e
moral grounds is not just at the valuing level. As much as I have reflectively
considered the issue (i.e., engaged in valuation), I have yet to be convinced
that there is anything morally wrong with homosexuality. None of the
arguments o√ered by others or considered on my own have any validity. It
is possible that in some future reflective consideration of the issue I will
change my mind. If so, then it is also probable that I will also change my
valuing about homosexuality. A change in the contrary direction is also a
possibility. I may come to have new valuing experiences that may a√ect
significantly my valuation.
For Dewey, our valuing should be subject to constant and even in-
tense criticism, but critical reflection (inquiry) is not a contextless and
rationalistic process that can guide itself by logic and facts alone. My
critical reflections about homosexuality may end up changing my valuing,
but it starts, takes place, and is guided by whatever valuing experiences I
happen to have. In other words, valuation is not an impartial and rational
process that requires that the immediate valuings be bracketed or left
behind, perhaps because they are considered mere appearance or subjec-
tive. These valuings are not objects of knowledge (e.g., propositions) but
they function as initial data and are regulative as moral deliberation pro-
ceeds. (I discuss this further below.) And one does well to remember that
what is revealed from the valuing standpoint (from the practical engaged
point of view) is moral reality, rather than our inner moral feelings toward
actions. As Dewey says, ‘‘It is not experience which is experienced, but
nature—stones, plants, animals, diseases, health, temperature, electricity,
and so on’’ (LW 1:12). My valuing experience of an act of injustice as wrong
is about a value that I find in the same world where I also find plants and
stones. To dismiss the importance of valuing in inquiry because it is
merely subjective or a mere psychological reaction is to assume a dualism
or to presuppose the supremacy of the theoretical standpoint in revealing
what is real.
Dewey’s view on judgments of value has important implications about
the nature of moral disagreements and what resources are available to deal
with them. Suppose I am having a discussion with some who oppose
homosexuality on moral grounds. Let us assume (and this is not a small
assumption) that we are all fairly committed but open-minded individuals
infused with the Deweyan democratic spirit to genuinely learn from each
other (more about this in part 3). Each of us thinks that she is right, but we
are willing to be convinced otherwise about the moral value of homosex-
uality. My role in this communal inquiry is to try to convince others but, if
Dewey is right, the challenge takes a lot more than argumentation. I must,
of course, engage others as much as I can in serious reflective examination
∞≠π
dewey’s view of moral experience
∞≠∫
t h e ‘‘w h a t’’ o f m o r a l e x p e r i e n c e
tion to be justified, but this opens the doors to more e√ective ways of
e√ecting moral change in our society than just dialogue or reflection.
Women have come to be experienced as the moral equals of men (valu-
ing), not just as a result of philosophical arguments that prove their moral
equality (valuation), but as an indirect result of a change in social and
economic conditions. The development of new technologies, such as birth
control, has facilitated the movement of women into certain social roles
that has, in turn, a√ected the valuings of men, that is, how men experience
women. Sometimes changes in environmental conditions are more ef-
fective than the best-argued objections to provoke the sort of criticism
that is needed to change people’s valuings. It could be argued, for example,
that it was not until Louis Braille worked out his basic 6-dot system for the
blind to communicate, read, and participate more fully in society that
many people reconsidered the immediate valuing of the blind as idiots or
as not deserving of the respect and dignity as other humans.Ω
In estimating the power of valuation over valuing in changing moral
judgments it makes a di√erence how one conceives the role of reasons and
arguments in moral deliberation. In the process of reflectively considering
the moral value of homosexuality we can exchange arguments, but is the
goal and hope of such an exchange that others will reach our conclusion
by making a logical inference from certain premises? We do not change
people’s judgments by this sort of process because this is not how reflective
judgments are reached. The way we can contribute and a√ect someone’s
reflective judgments of value is not by reasoning alone but by bringing up
considerations or reasons to which they have hitherto not fully attended.
Reasons are considerations to look for in the survey of one’s situation,
rather than premises in an argument. Arguments are important but they
are just one of the resources available to make others reexamine on their
own the subject matter to be judged. It is part of the method proposed by
Dewey to extend an invitation to others and provide the conditions by
which they can have the experiences that confirm or reject our assertions.
You may also contribute to someone’s dramatic rehearsal by provoking
him or her to consider similar cases or to adopt an imaginary impartial
standpoint. None of these resources may in the end be e√ective in a
particular communal inquiry, but Dewey’s view of what it takes to be
reflective about value is more heterogeneous and resourceful than the
anemic rationalistic conceptions of moral deliberation and intelligence
that predominate in ethical theory.
Dewey held that an organic relation between valuing and valuation
can lead to the kind of integration of means and ends present in artistic
activity. This is an ideal of human conduct that I will explore later, but it is
∞≠Ω
dewey’s view of moral experience
The new value, dependent upon judgment, is, when it comes, as imme-
diate a good or bad as anything can be. But it is also an immediate value
of a plus sort. The prior judgment has a√ected the new good not merely
as its causal condition but by entering into its quality. The new good has
an added dimension of value. (MW 13:6)
∞∞≠
t h e ‘‘w h a t’’ o f m o r a l e x p e r i e n c e
Speaking literally, there are no such things as values. . . . There are things,
all sorts of things, having the unique, the experienced, but indefinable,
quality of value. Values in the plural, or a value in the singular, is merely a
convenient abbreviation for an object, event, situation, res, possessing
the quality. (MW 15:20)
∞∞∞
dewey’s view of moral experience
plains that ‘‘they may also sum up and integrate prolonged previous expe-
rience and training, and bring to a unified head the results of severe and
consecutive reflection’’ (LW 5:250). It is important to understand that in
making the distinction between valuing and valuation we are discriminat-
ing between phases of a continuous process.
The move toward a more reflective judgment and phase of inquiry is not a
jump to a separate objective domain or to receiving the guidance of a
reality independent of experience. Instead, ‘‘when it is said that a thing
cognized is di√erent from an earlier non-cognitionally experienced thing,
the saying no more implies lack of continuity between the things, than the
obvious remark that a seed is di√erent than a flower’’ (MW 3:166). Valua-
tion (the flower) emerges from within the same initial valuing situation
that provoked it (the seed). An initial conflicting or disturbed valuing
experience evokes reflection (valuation) and guides the possible solutions
to be tried out. Any eventual correction or improvement of a present
experience comes from the same experience in need of reconstruction.
Dewey’s empiricism is committed to the view that ‘‘whatever gain in
clearness, in fullness, in trueness of context is experienced must grow
out of some element in the experience of this experienced as what it is’’
(MW 3:164). This became the basis of Dewey’s faith in experience. We
need to trust the potential of any present experience to carry the seed of its
own transformation. We detect and correct illusoriness ‘‘because the thing
experienced is real, having within its experienced reality elements whose
own mutual tension e√ects its reconstruction’’ (MW 3:164). If a moral
problem has a solution, it must emerge from guiding our inquiry by its
initial direct and unique problematic character. It is untrue that without
some external criteria of right and wrong we are lost and cannot trans-
form the situation.
This early insight was later refined and elaborated as Dewey became
more interested in the logic of artistic construction and appreciation. The
initial immediate experience of a work of art as good, for example, is
‘‘relatively dumb and inarticulate yet penetrating’’ (LW 5:249). It is neither
knowledge nor a mere state of a personal feeling, but it is an initial valuing
that serves as the reliable basis (the seed) to any subsequent reflective
∞∞≤
t h e ‘‘w h a t’’ o f m o r a l e x p e r i e n c e
∞∞≥
dewey’s view of moral experience
∞∞∂
t h e ‘‘w h a t’’ o f m o r a l e x p e r i e n c e
∞∞∑
dewey’s view of moral experience
ject applies some criterion upon the more natural traits of things. In other
words, value qualities and judgments must supervene on or be derived
from the more objective traits of the world, otherwise the alternative
seems to be the sort of emotivism that makes value judgments mere
expressions of our subjective preferences.
For Dewey, of course, there is no need for an explanation. The only
thing queer about values is how anyone could question their existence, for,
insofar as ‘value’ is a term that points to what is directly and immediately
qualitative, everything is value-laden. In particular, moral judgments are
as natural and as descriptive of the objective world as any other judgment.
Moral qualities are not experienced as things added to a world that is
morally neutral.∞∑ This is, at best, a theory. To be sure, the fact that we find
ourselves in a qualitative world of moral value does not mean that, as
implied by some forms of objectivism, we can only copy what we find. As I
noted above, inquiry has the power to change what we directly perceive or
judge as valuable, but what has been transformed is the same objective
world of tables and chairs.
In general it is a favoritism toward objects of knowledge that has dis-
credited the objectivity and reality of moral experience. Contributing to
this is a particularly narrow conception of knowledge where science and
math are the models of objective discourse. This reflects deep-seated dual-
isms where science and art are polar opposites. On this view, art is clearly
subjective since it is concerned with expression and creation of values,
whereas science is the discovery of what is the case independently of human
values. Dewey explains how this picture makes moral values especially
problematic and how it generates the subjectivism versus objectivism
debate.
Between these two realms, one of intellectual objects without value and
the other of value-objects without intellect, there is an equivocal mid-
country in which moral objects are placed, with rival claimants striving
to annex them either to the region of purely immediate goods . . . or to
that of purely rational objects. (LW 1:304)
∞∞∏
t h e ‘‘w h a t’’ o f m o r a l e x p e r i e n c e
∞∞π
dewey’s view of moral experience
∞∞∫
t h e ‘‘w h a t’’ o f m o r a l e x p e r i e n c e
∞∞Ω
dewey’s view of moral experience
∞≤≠
six
The ‘‘How’’ of Moral Experience
∞≤∞
dewey’s view of moral experience
Habits
Through the process of socialization, an organism channels its impulses,
that is, it learns habits. Habits include not only one’s routine way of doing
things, but a broad spectrum of tendencies and dispositions, dominant
ways of acting, ways or modes of response, abilities, attitudes, sensitivities,
accessibilities, predilections, and aversions. ‘‘Habits are the fibre of charac-
ter, but there are habits of desire and imagination as well as of outer
action’’ (LW 9:187). Habit is a word that expresses ‘‘the kind of human
activity which is influenced by prior activity and in that sense acquired’’
(MW 14:31). However, when one develops a habit, what one has acquired
is not a possession within the confines of a self but a way of interacting
within a social and natural environment. Since some pre-existing associa-
tion is prior to any particular human being, many of our habits are com-
mon ways of feeling and believing, or what Dewey called ‘‘custom.’’∞
Habits have to be understood in terms of their function in the life-
process and in situations. They are the most basic instrumentalities of any
organism in its environment. Organisms depend on habits for sustenance,
control, and continuity. One trait common to human beings is that most
of our habits are not instinctive; they are instead acquired through our
constant interaction with an environment that is social and processive.
Our ability to acquire habits is due to the original plasticity of our nature.
Habits permit the everyday unreflective flow of action. The disruption
of a habit in meeting present conditions marks a state of crisis for an
organism. A morally problematic situation is in e√ect a disruption of the
fluid function of our habits, that is, a blockage of e√ective overt action. In
these situations, there is shock and confusion. Disruption of habits is
an occasion for deliberation, in other words, thinking or inquiry comes
about when habits no longer work. The outcome of this process is the
recovery of the same kind of stability, equilibrium, and fluidity of conduct
provided by previous habits in a stable environment. However, some
habits remain operative and stable through this process.
In a morally problematic situation, di√erent habits are operative at
di√erent levels depending on whether they are in the background or at the
foreground of our reflective awareness. The contextual background is
∞≤≤
t h e ‘‘h o w’’ o f m o r a l e x p e r i e n c e
∞≤≥
dewey’s view of moral experience
tion that habits are essentially conservative. Habits can have the tendency
to become self-perpetuating and mechanical, but not all habit is the ‘‘en-
slavement to old ruts’’ (MW 14:48). There are habits that, though per-
sistent, can adapt themselves to new conditions. Dewey referred to these
flexible habits as ‘‘intelligent’’ or ‘‘artistic’’ (MW 14:52). Moreover, the
thinking capacities that are needed to reconstruct and reform habits that
are old ruts are themselves habits. An intelligent organism is capable of
modifying and improving her habits so that they can become relevant to
this and similar situations. With time, an intelligent organism not only
learns to adapt her habits to present situations, but also learns to learn; she
can, in other words, modify her present tools, but she can also create tools
to modify tools.
Situations and habits do not constitute separated isolated compart-
ments of experience. Habits are not formed in a vacuum and we cannot
think of them as an exclusive property of a self. Just as ‘‘breathing is an
a√air of the air as truly as of the lungs’’ (MW 9:15), habits require the
cooperation (interaction) of the organism and the environment. On the
other hand, situations are what they are and have their uniqueness be-
cause they are a result of the interaction (transaction) between the habits
and attitudes of the organism and its environment. There are two sides to
the relation (interaction) between our habits and the situations in which
they operate. With the attitudes and habits we bring from previous experi-
ence to a particular situation we a√ect the quality of the resulting situa-
tion, but these same attitudes and habits are also a√ected by the situation.
This ongoing, bi-directional process provides the basis for continuity in
the development of experience. But it also forms a continuity that, in a
certain sense, is educative or cumulative. In Dewey’s words,
The fact that habits are the tools funded by previous experience makes
them one of the more dependable and stable aspects of our moral life.
∞≤∂
t h e ‘‘h o w’’ o f m o r a l e x p e r i e n c e
whole’’ (LW 7:258). The habits that constitute character are always opera-
tive, though some might be more overt than others depending on the
situation. That is, most of our conduct is an expression of the coordina-
tion of several habits, though occasionally one habit predominates.
There is continuity in conduct because of character. ‘‘Were it not for
the continued operation of all habits in every act, no such thing as charac-
ter could exist. There would be simply a bundle, an untied bundle at that,
of isolated acts’’ (MW 14:29). Character is not a fixed thing, but is in a
continuous process of transformation. ‘‘There is always in character the
possibility of change, of development.’’≤ The habits that are constitutive of
a character are not all plastic or persistent to the same degree. Those that
persist and resist change form the most stable aspects of our characters.
It is because of his organic model of character that Dewey resisted the
approach to ethics and to moral education that consists in listing and
cultivating a set of moral positive traits of character or virtues. He said,
The mere idea of a catalogue of di√erent virtues commits us to the
notion that virtues may be kept apart, pigeon-holed in water-tight com-
partments. In fact virtuous traits interpenetrate one another; this unity
is involved in the very idea of integrity of character. (LW 7:283)
∞≤∑
dewey’s view of moral experience
To call them virtues in their isolation is like taking the skeleton for the
living body. The bones are certainly important, but their importance lies
in the fact that they support other organs of the body in such a way as to
make them capable of integrated e√ective activity. And the same is true
of the qualities of character which we specifically designate virtues. Mor-
als concern nothing less than the whole character. (MW 9:367)
For Dewey, if one considers the nature of intellectual activity, then this
opens the door to challenging the separation of the intellectual virtues
from the moral virtues within character. Such activity is not something
purely mental or the exercise of reason, but a social transaction, a certain
kind of communication. Therefore, intellectual activity cannot be sepa-
rated from the virtues that are usually labeled moral. While the canons of
deductive and inductive logic are integral to intellectual communication
in philosophy and in the sciences, traits of personal and social morality
∞≤∏
t h e ‘‘h o w’’ o f m o r a l e x p e r i e n c e
that make possible a democratic and cooperative process are also impor-
tant. Dewey was aware of the inseparability of moral values from our more
intellectual activities.∂ Philosophers such as Jürgen Habermas and Alan
Gewirth have also acknowledged this inseparability. Gewirth, for example,
says that without some ‘‘moral traits of character and social interaction,
the very operation of intellectual inquiry becomes impossible.’’∑
The distinction between and separation of moral and intellectual
virtues is counterproductive in moral education. With respect to the aims
of education, Dewey maintains that ‘‘no separation can be made between
impersonal, abstract principles of logic and moral qualities of character.
What is needed is to weave them into unity’’ (LW 8:139). More important
than education by ‘‘direct moral precept’’ (MW 6:388), that is, learning
moral rules or principles, is the indirect learning that comes from engag-
ing students in open, communal, and sensitive inquiry. The openness and
tolerance that I might encourage in my students by examining together
di√erent moral systems is of more moral importance than the informa-
tion they learn.
If character is an organic whole, then this opens the possibility of
being able to evaluate habits in terms of their interactive e√ect upon other
tendencies that one cherishes or in terms of how they contribute to the
whole character. Di√erent habits of a character might reinforce each other
or they might function at cross-purposes. There are persons who lack
integration, where di√erent habits or compartments of their character are
relatively isolated from each other. A specialized habit might endure and
become more e≈cient in its area of application in virtue of its relative
seclusion from others. But this confinement does not really work in a
world where one does not have control over one’s environment or in
situations that may call for other conflicting habits. The character that
allows for the mutual modification (interaction) among its habits opens
itself to the possibility of making readjustments that might resolve con-
flicts among habits and at the same time enrich the whole character.
To be sure, the hypothesis that it is better to have an integrated charac-
ter than one that is compartmentalized is not based on the assumption
that integrity or unity are worth achieving for their own sake. Character is
one of our most reliable tools in a situation. The integrative ideal signifies
the fullest and most productive use we can make of our characters in a
situation. I will return to Dewey’s conception of an ideal character in
part 3.
So far, I have described character in terms of its constitutive habits,
but it must also be understood in its relation to conduct and social en-
vironment. The specific reactions, habits, and dispositions that make up a
∞≤π
dewey’s view of moral experience
∞≤∫
seven
Character and Conduct
Dewey and the Great Divide in Ethics
∞≤Ω
dewey’s view of moral experience
t h e au t o n o m y c l a i m
Dewey believed that both Kant and Mill based their ethical views on the
di√erences and divergences between judgments of character and judg-
ments of conduct in situations. Mill claims that one can get the same
objective good act from di√erent motives, even from bad ones. On the
other hand, Kant believes that the goodness of a good will does not de-
pend on the rightness of its actions. In general, the act theorist would
argue that, for example, an act can be judged dishonest or wrongful even if
it is performed by a person of honest character. Therefore, character has
nothing to do with morality. Meanwhile, the virtue theorist claims that
virtues, such as honesty, are independent of and cannot be reduced to
judgments or rules of good conduct.
Dewey of course acknowledged that there are times when we invert
our judgments of the doer and the deed, for example, an honest person
∞≥≠
character and conduct
can do a dishonest act. But the only way a philosopher can establish that
the moral goodness of a trait of character is somehow independent of the
assessment of the activities of that person is if she stipulates a narrow
definition of human action. For example, only if it is assumed that honesty
is a property of the inner confines of the self and not a tendency to interact
in a situation in a certain way, can one claim that the goodness of honesty
is independent of conduct. But, for Dewey, there is no basis in experience
for such a dualism and there is a good explanation for the disparities and
di√erences between judgments of character and those of conduct.
Character is a working interaction of habits. We cannot always accu-
rately assess the character of a person by assessing his or her conduct, even
after a long period of time. However, this is not because character is
something inner that may or may not cause external action, but simply
because there is no certainty about when our actions are expressions of
stable dispositions (habits) and when they are accidental reactions to an
undetermined number of contextual factors. Judging traits of character
can be di≈cult, uncertain, and complex but that does not mean that they
are other than tendencies to interact in a certain way in a situation—
habits. We cannot judge character without considering actual or possible
conduct.
But what about moral judgments of action? Are they not autonomous
from character-relevant discourse? This seems on its face more promising.
It is clear, for example, that sometimes one can judge an act to be honest
without considering the honesty of someone’s character. Moreover, many
ethical theories and moral traditions have made reference in their list of
moral precepts to acts, such as stealing and lying, regardless of who the
actor might be. Does it then follow, however, that moral judgments of
conduct as they are made in everyday moral experience can disregard the
agent and her character?
To what extent character-considerations of the agent are relevant to
the final moral judgment of an act is something that will depend on the
context, but they are a necessary part of that context. As Dewey noted,
‘‘intent is a normal part of a moral situation’’ (LW 7:167). In judging moral
conduct, one needs to consider if it is an expression of the self, that is, if it
embodies ‘‘the interest and motive of the self.’’≥ To be sure, Dewey makes
these claims not because he has or wishes to have a theory that centers on
character, but because he is a contextualist. To evaluate an act by taking
into account the actor is part of what is required in order to judge an act in
light of its concrete context. Of course, philosophers can always perform
the intellectual exercise of assessing acts in abstraction from their agents,
but there is no obvious reason why we should do this. Moreover, it is
∞≥∞
dewey’s view of moral experience
unclear why we should think that this is the way in which acts acquire their
moral cast in the concrete context of moral life.
In sum, Dewey holds that we can distinguish judgments of character
from judgments of conduct without assuming that they are about sepa-
rated domains of moral discourse or moral experience. On the contrary,
the way we make moral judgments suggests that character and conduct
are mutually dependent and inseparable facets of our moral experience.
Dewey claims that ‘‘There is no character excepting as manifested in con-
duct, there is no conduct excepting that which expresses character.’’∂
But even if the autonomy claim were true, this does not by itself pro-
vide support for making the divide issue a meaningful one. Why must one
decide which discourse represents the distinctively moral one? It seems
that only an unstated dualism would make one assume that character and
conduct cannot be brought together in an integrated view of moral life, or
that a moral agent cannot attend to both virtue and the moral goodness of
her actions without su√ering from a type of moral schizophrenia.
Perhaps aware that claims about autonomy are di≈cult to support,
recent philosophers have instead couched their centeredness claims in
terms of the primacy in morality, rather than in terms of exclusion. Let’s
briefly consider this recent way of arguing for the divide issue.
Even if one cannot judge character without conduct (and vice versa) one
might still make the claim that one of these judgments must be basic.
There are two ways to understand this issue, neither of which is sound
from the point of view of Dewey’s ethics.
The issue of basicness has sometimes been understood as being about
which kind of judgment is susceptible to theoretical explanation and re-
duction by the other. For example, if virtues are reducible to moral rules
of conduct but not vice versa, then the latter are basic.∑ But in this way
of understanding the issue, it seems that what is basic is decided by how
good one is at performing conceptual reductions. This kind of reduction-
ism is indicative that perhaps the interest in ethical theory on the divide
issue arises out of a theoretical demand for conceptual economy and
elegance, and not because it has anything to do with anyone’s actual moral
experience.
Is there any way to make sense of the issue of basicness from the point
of view of moral agents making moral decisions? Which kind of judgment
is derivative to the other in terms of its justificatory role in moral delibera-
tion? This is a loaded question. In order to engage in debates that center
∞≥≤
character and conduct
on this issue one has to assume a certain model of moral reasoning and
justification. It reduces, without an argument, all morally relevant consid-
erations and judgments to two, that is, to act- and character-centered
ones. But the content of people’s actual moral deliberation is a lot richer
and more varied than proponents of both sides of the divide issue seem to
allow. More importantly, it assumes that either the inherent goodness of
certain types of character or the moral quality of certain kinds of actions
determined by some rule is the source of all moral justification and value.
The theoretical appeal of this assumption should be obvious. But Dewey
would argue that this is an oversimplification of moral experience. Moral
philosophy ‘‘should frankly recognize the impossibility of reducing all
the elements in moral situations to a single commensurable principle’’
(LW 5:288).
In Dewey’s contextualist view of moral justification, neither character-
judgments nor act-judgments have an inherent primacy or foundational
role in moral reasoning independent of the particular context of a situa-
tion. The relative weight of each judgment in coming to a final decision of
what one ought to do will depend on considerations of the unique and
specific features of the situation under consideration.
∞≥≥
dewey’s view of moral experience
∞≥∂
character and conduct
∞≥∑
dewey’s view of moral experience
∞≥∏
character and conduct
characters, but this does not mean that they cease to be moral decisions.
There are also situations where the virtue concern is overridden by other
moral considerations, situations in which one is aware that what one
morally ought to do might adversely a√ect one’s character. For Dewey
claimed that the virtue concern is only one among many other indepen-
dent and irreducible moral demands, such as duty and good, that charac-
terize morally problematic situations. None of these demands can claim
an inherent primacy over the others.
Virtue ethics may claim to have a broader scope in moral matters
because it is concerned with seemingly larger issues, such as the nature of
human flourishing and the good life, or how one should live, but it is not
thereby a richer or more inclusive view of morality. But perhaps the claim
of a broader scope is based on the context or standpoint from which these
questions are asked. Bernard Mayo, for example, explains the context of
‘‘What I ought to be’’ as ‘‘. . . where a man’s perplexity extends not merely
to a particular situation but to his whole way of living.’’∫ The assump-
tion seems to be that certain questions entail the abandonment of the
situationalist and particularistic thrust that has characterized act theory.
But there is nothing about the content or meaning of these questions
that make them transcend the particular contexts within which questions
about what action to undertake are asked. Even such far-reaching deci-
sions as ‘‘to be brave’’ or ‘‘to be a good human being’’ are as situation-
specific for Dewey as any other decision. They arise out of a particular
problematic situation and not from some wider standpoint or context.
Virtue ethics is a reaction to the act-theorist view of moral life as a
succession of isolated situations. For the virtue ethicist, the solution to this
atomistic conception of our moral life is to posit a moral self who is
primarily concerned with her life as a whole. This concern is meaningful
to Dewey, but it always takes place in a particular situation and for a self
that is in a process of continuous formation. Virtue ethics wants to recover
the sense of continuity in our moral lives but for this we do not have to
postulate one concern that pervades all moral situations or a standpoint
from which a growing self can survey her moral life as a whole. A stand-
point that is wide but nowhere in particular might be bigger but if it has
nothing to do with our concrete experience as moral agents it has nothing
to contribute to a rich conception of morality. What these two views share,
in spite of their opposition, is the theoretical starting point (discussed in
chapter 1) of gazing at atomistic actions or moral life as a unified whole.
From within moral life things are experienced di√erently.
Virtue ethics has taken advantage of the general disillusionment with
act theories in order to support their centrality claims. The appeal or
∞≥π
dewey’s view of moral experience
∞≥∫
character and conduct
teristic of virtue ethics. For, as I noted, our moral life is not merely a
succession of isolated situations; there is continuity and the possibility of
learning in our moral development. Moral ideals and character, for exam-
ple, have a place in Dewey’s ethics. However, he is able to incorporate these
concerns in his ethics without postulating abstract notions that are ante-
cedent to concrete situations. Ideals are part of the means of a situation.
Virtues are to be examined as habits operating in the context of situations
and not as means to abstract notions of human flourishing. Dewey would
even agree with virtue ethicists that moral theorists should concern them-
selves more with providing hypotheses about the traits of character that
might be worth cultivating than trying to construct rules of action. But
this does not mean that character is central to morality or that we should
make character and its flourishing the primary conscious aim of our
moral life. From time to time we need to reflect about our moral charac-
ter. However, to make the state of our character the moral end and every-
thing else the means to improving character is to elevate character as
antecedent to the context from which it emerges and has its importance.
For Dewey this is not only a philosophical mistake, but if put into practice,
can lead to one of the worst forms of moral life. Agent-centered views
encourage what he called ‘‘spiritual egotism,’’ that is, it produces people
who ‘‘are preoccupied with the state of their character, concerned for the
purity of their motives and goodness of their souls. The exultation of
conceit which sometimes accompanies this absorption can produce a cor-
rosive inhumanity which exceeds the possibilities of any other form of
selfishness’’ (MW 14:7).
Making the goodness of our character the conscious object of our
moral concern can in fact be counterproductive. Too much concern for
our character can become a distraction or block to fruitful character-
building activity. The best way to improve our moral characters is to
attend to what we ought to do in a particular situation. Dewey thought
that just as there is a hedonistic paradox, there is a moralistic paradox:
‘‘the way to get goodness is to cease to think of it—as something separate—
and to devote ourselves to the realization of the full value of the practical
situations in which we find ourselves’’ (MW 5:318).
We need to shift the emphasis in moral philosophy away from rules of
action. However, in Dewey this is done by shifting the emphasis toward
the concrete and unique situations of our moral experience and not to-
ward virtues and notions of the good or human flourishing. Does the
claim that the locus of our moral life is in situations where one has to
decide what one ought to do commit Dewey to an act-centered view? The
answer is ‘‘no’’ for several important reasons.
∞≥Ω
dewey’s view of moral experience
First, the reason why the question What ought I to do? is primary is
because in a morally problematic situation it is always a choice about a
particular course of conduct which is being considered. This does not
imply anything about giving inherent primacy to rules, standards, or any
act-centered type of evaluative commitment in making such decisions.
Furthermore, Dewey holds that among the legitimate and irreducible
moral demands considered in trying to answer or resolve a morally prob-
lematic situation is the state of one’s character (i.e., the virtue concern).
Third, and most important, Dewey’s particularism is a contextualism that
does not share with act-centered positions the atomistic view of acts and
of moral experience. His ethics begins with situations as individualized
contexts that, though unique, are continuous with each other in an open-
ended process. Acts are not contextless events or mere external e√ects of a
self. In fact, for Dewey moral conduct is an expression of the moral self.
This relation is so intimate and direct that, in a sense I will soon explain,
questions about what one ought to do are in e√ect also questions about
what one ought to be. But before turning to this view of moral conduct, I
must consider one more argument used by character theorists to defend
the view that one’s moral life must be centered on a concern with being.
Some recent ethicists have claimed that one’s moral theory and moral life
must be centered on character because otherwise one su√ers the con-
stricted and alienating moral life that is entailed by the act-centered con-
cern. Let’s examine the problem of alienation and consider if this warrants
the conclusion that moral philosophy should center on character and
whether Dewey’s ethics is susceptible to this problem.
∞∂≠
character and conduct
that insofar as character views presuppose the same view of the moral self
as act views, they are susceptible to the same criticism. As Dewey sees it,
the problem is a consequence of starting ethical theory with a certain
theoretical conception of what it is to be a self in moral experience,
namely, the spectator view of the moral self.
For a moral self as a subject-spectator, conduct is an external conse-
quence of its deliberation, itself an inner cognitive process. Therefore, the
relation between the self and its conduct is, at best, one of cause and e√ect.
This is troublesome because the relation between a moral self and what
she does seems in moral experience to be more intimate, that is, moral
conduct is an expression of a moral self. In e√ect the spectator view of the
self alienates the moral self from its own activities. The implications about
alienation of this view are perhaps more evident in act-centered moral
theories, for they usually assume that acts are atomistic contextless events
subject to external demands, rules, duties, or principles, which hold no
special relation to the one who e√ects them.
What agent-centered views, such as that of Williams, overlook is that
their attempt to anchor morality in the agent (or character) might not
resolve the problem of alienation between the moral self and its acts. Can
the self genuinely identify with her actions if they are merely an outward
expression of some personal moral project or a mere means to achieving
virtue? Possessive attitudes toward an activity can be as alienating as im-
personal ones. Consider, for example, how alienating is the experience of
students who think of learning merely as a way of getting good grades or
becoming a good future professional. Virtue theorists assume an account
of moral reasoning that rests on a hypothetical imperative where the
antecedent is a desire to be a certain sort of person. In other words, the
condition for engaging in moral activity (finding and doing the right
thing) is an antecedent concern for one’s character. How is this better than
rules in regard to alienation? On both views my identification with what I
ought to do in a particular situation is mediated and conditional upon a
concern that is somewhat removed from the concrete and specific issue at
hand. Moral conduct is not a direct expression but only a consequence of
caring for something else.
If the only alternative to the abstract concern to abide by rules is the
exclusive concern to become the right sort of person, then alienation
seems like an unavoidable trait or danger of living morally. The problem
seems unavoidable as long as we assume a separation between the self and
its acts, and make one a means to the other. If there is in moral experience
a more intimate relation between the moral self and its acts, then the
problem of alienation is a further reason to reject the divide and its
∞∂∞
dewey’s view of moral experience
∞∂≤
character and conduct
interest of the self, for example, the attainment or expression of virtue, the
maximization of happiness, or compliance with a universal duty. On this
assumption, self-realization and moral activity are usually conceived in
terms of getting something for the self. Hence, it is not surprising that one of
the predominant tendencies in the history of moral philosophy (e.g., that
of utilitarianism and virtue ethics) most criticized by Dewey was a pos-
sessive and acquisitive view of morality. He said whether it be pleasure or
For Dewey, ‘‘morality consists in not degrading any required act into a
mere means towards an end lying outside itself, but in doing it for its own
sake, or, again, in doing it as self ’’ (EW 4:52). The alternative to the notion
of living morally for the self is living morally as the self. This means that
the self is directly identified with what she ought to do, that morality is
‘‘finding the self in the activity called for by the situation’’ (EW 4:51).
Morality, as Dewey understands it, is thus a matter of a being that is
doing. Therefore, although concerns about what one ought to do convey
that in a morally problematic situation it is always the choice of a particu-
lar course of conduct that is being considered, this is not something
independent from what an agent ought to be in that situation. Only an
agent view of the self implies the kind of identity between the self and its
acts that avoids the problem of alienation endemic to both character-
centered and act-centered views.
The notion of the self as a passive spectator that is moved to moral
activity by something outside itself ∞≤ has also led to narrow views of moral
motivation. When the unity of the self and its acts is not recognized, it is
assumed that concern for moral activity is either for the self or it is the
impartial and impersonal motivation of act-centered views. It is as if,
apart from wanting virtue or wanting to comply with rules, the moral self
would be indi√erent to each particular moral task. This mistake is avoided
by starting with the experience of concrete moral selves as they are genu-
inely engrossed in present moral activity instead of starting with abstrac-
tions. What is ruled out is that a self can be directly interested in or
concerned with present moral activity. But this is precisely the type of
moral self and engagement that Dewey describes as the model of having a
moral experience. Once again it will be useful to draw from the similarities
with art as experience.
∞∂≥
dewey’s view of moral experience
The moral self, like the genuine artist, while engaged in the process,
defines and identifies herself with what she does; there is no distinction
between herself and the activity (process). In the absence of this kind of
engagement and direct absorption in a situation, any other special com-
mitment to a value, ideal, or purposes can be a narrow and distracting
indulgence. It is like the artist who lets personal projects and agendas, such
as fame or the desire to become a better artist, get in the way of the artistic
process.
For Dewey, this model of the self needs to be studied and fostered in
moral education. He was concerned to undermine the divide issue be-
cause of its implications for moral education. The view that moral train-
ing in schools is a matter of discipline to act according to certain pre-
established rules of conduct, and the view that what is important is that
students have a good character or a good will were dangerous and one-
sided. The former produces characters that are so rigid and mechanical
that they lack the spirit of morality; the latter encourage characters who
limit their moral tasks to meaning well and perfecting their characters. For
Dewey, these alternatives reflect not only dualisms, but also a society
unable to encourage the optimal sort of engagement from individuals to
deal with moral problems.
What virtue ethics tries to recover is what might be called the personal
character of morality. But it has assumed that the way to recover from
legalistic and impartial models of morality is to shift the focus of ethics
away from problematic situations and toward character. But Dewey pro-
vides an alternative view that recovers the personal character of morality
and gives character its due without giving up the situational thrust of our
moral experience. The moral agent who is aesthetically engaged in present
moral activity has a direct personal identification with the specific con-
duct that is morally required of her in a situation. For this kind of self,
moral activity is a matter of self-expression and not an external imposition
(of obeying rules) or a matter of ‘‘getting’’ virtue (or any moral good). In
my account of the ideal self in part 3, I will discuss the characteristics of a
self capable of this sort of engagement.
In conclusion, in spite of similarities, it would be a mistake to regard
Dewey’s ethics as a form of virtue ethics. This mistake is costly since it
precludes the appreciation of the distinctive character of Dewey’s ethics.
His ethics is an alternative that avoids the atomistic view of acts, the
legalistic form of morality, and the neglect of the self and communal
context that characterizes many modern act-centered views. Dewey would
not deny that moral agents are or can be concerned with character consid-
erations (virtues, ideals, projects) and also with act considerations (rules,
∞∂∂
character and conduct
∞∂∑
eight
Present Activity and
the Meaning of Moral Life
I n the history of moral philosophy, present moral activity has been taken
as a means to a future remote goal, virtue, happiness, a universal duty, or
the good life. Moral life has been conceived as a cumulative process where
present situations are important only to the extent that we can acquire
something from them, such as the goodness in our characters, happiness,
or compliance with a general rule. Several things can account for this
commonly shared assumption.
The view of moral life as acquisitive and product-oriented has been
supported by socio-economic practices. Dewey was alert to the close rela-
tion between, for example, utilitarianism and capitalist institutions which
subordinated ‘‘productive activity to the bare product’’ (MW 12:184).
Socio-economic conditions have contributed to the belief that satisfaction
and fulfillment are future possessions—products—that can be separated
from present productive activity. But Dewey also diagnosed how in philos-
ophy a mistaken notion of the self and of the temporal in experience
contributed to making these assumptions about moral life seem like com-
mon sense. Let’s first consider the issue of time.
The importance a philosopher might give to the present or to the
∞∂∏
present activity and the meaning of moral life
∞∂π
dewey’s view of moral experience
future and more worthwhile ones? Dewey would agree that control of the
future is a precious goal, since we live in a precarious and changing world.
But it is incorrect to believe that the best way to achieve something is to
always directly aim at it. Even if we want future improvement and control
as a result of present action, this does not mean that we should thereby
directly aim our actions at securing future improvement. On the contrary,
there are reasons to believe that reflective overconcern with future im-
provement is the surest way not to attain it, because such overconcern
results in a halfhearted ‘‘attention to the full use of present resources in the
present situation’’ (MW 14:183), which is detrimental to any future state.
Dewey claimed that the surest means to attain anything in the future is ‘‘to
attend to the full possibilities of the present’’ (MW 14:183) and that ‘‘such
enrichment of the present for its own sake is the just heritage of childhood
and the best insurer of future growth’’ (LW 8:348). Dewey says,
control of future living, such as it may turn out to be, is wholly depen-
dent upon taking his present activity, seriously and devotedly, as an end,
not as means. (MW 14:184, my emphasis)
moralists have spent time and energy in showing what happens when
appetite, impulse, is indulged without reference to consequences and
reason. But they have mostly ignored the counterpart evils of an intel-
ligence that conceive ideals and goods which do not enter into present
impulse and habits. (MW 14:188, my emphasis)
∞∂∫
present activity and the meaning of moral life
noted, Dewey’s view of the moral agent implies that the self cannot be
ontologically separated from present activity; moreover, it achieves self-
expression by being directly concerned and immersed in it.
Any consequentialist or teleological interpretation of Dewey’s ethics
ignores his attempt to shift the center of gravity of morality to concrete
present situations. Consequences and ends are, of course, important, but
they are only part of our present resources for present reconstruction. As
Dewey writes,
growth of present action in shades and scope of meaning is the only good
within our control, and the only one, accordingly, for which respon-
sibility exists. The rest is luck, fortune. And the tragedy of the moral
notions most insisted upon by the morally self-conscious is the relega-
tion of the only good which can fully engage thought, namely present
meaning of action, to the rank of an incident of a remote good, whether
that future good be defined as pleasure, or perfection, or salvation, or
attainment of virtuous character. (MW 14:194, my emphasis)
Views that have ‘‘made the present subservient to a rigid yet abstract
future’’ (MW 14:284) understand moral progress and growth in terms of
an approximation to a fixed and remote ideal or standard. One version of
this is when moral progress is conceived as a cumulative and linear pro-
gression toward a final ‘‘stable condition free from conflict and distur-
bance’’ (MW 14:285). These views interpret change and our present moral
struggles as signs of our human limitations, and as incentives to work
toward a world where these aspects of existence are diminished until we
reach moral stability, perfection, fulfillment, and completeness.
As Dewey sees it, the dogma of approximation runs counter to the
general pattern and rhythm of moral experience. Moral life does not have
this linear pattern. There is, of course, continuity and many instrumen-
talities are carried forward and improved, but moral life is ‘‘no uniform
uninterrupted march or flow. It is a thing of histories, each with its own
plot’’ (LW 10:42). Even when we talk as if our lives were a cohesive, on-
going story for us to make, we do so as a way of understanding and making
meaningful the present episode. We experience life as a continuous pro-
cess but not as a single, all-inclusive, and evolving situation. Furthermore,
it is wishful thinking to assume that moral life will become easier and
more secure with every solved moral problem and with every improve-
ment of character; this view assumes a uniform environment without the
possibility of unforeseen new problems. But every accomplishment—each
resolution of a morally problematic situation—introduces new conditions
that generate new and sometimes even more complex problems. Dewey
∞∂Ω
dewey’s view of moral experience
asks us to admit that ‘‘no matter what the present success in straightening
out di≈culties and harmonizing conflict, it is certain that problems will
recur in the future in a new form or in a di√erent plane’’ (MW 14:285).
New struggles and failures seem inevitable. The way toward a conflict-less,
trouble-free, stable, and final state of a√airs could only be achieved if it
were possible to go back to a state of primitive simplicity or to follow the
Buddhist’s renunciation of desire, action, and attainment.
It is not surprising that pessimism is one of the consequences of
conceiving of moral life as an approximation to moral stability and perfec-
tion. With such high expectations, one’s moral struggles to ameliorate
present situations seem to be in vain. For many, the only way to avoid
pessimism and to keep the dogma of approximation intact is to subscribe
to a form of transcendentalism where the desired trouble-free, stable con-
dition is found outside of space and time. That is, moral life is finite,
illusory, but perhaps a necessary evil and bridge to a transcendent moral
reality.
Dewey’s disagreement with this view is more than an empirical issue
about what moral life is or can o√er. Even if such an approximation to a
perfect and stable end were possible he would consider it almost inher-
ently unappealing, for he shared with William James the idea that an
existence without struggle lacks meaning. First, the concepts of success,
growth, and fulfillment would be unintelligible in a world completely
devoid of struggle and failure. More important, an existence without
struggle lacks meaning; it is a pointless and unbearable kind of existence.
For as James said, ‘‘need and struggle are what excite and inspire us; our
hour of triumph is what brings the void.’’≤ Dewey and James did not
understand how a trouble-free existence can be a source of moral aspira-
tion or motivation.
Even if we agree with Dewey’s criticisms of any final and future telos,
this does not mean that he has provided an alternative view that has
answered adequately all the important questions. How does his view avoid
pessimism? If all there is to moral life is the rhythmic pattern of unending
problems, then how is this any di√erent than the meaningless life of
Sisyphus repeatedly rolling the rock up the hill? What could be the point of
moral life if it is not cumulative, or if it ends up in nothing? Moreover, if
there is no final end or outcome to the present process, then how can we
judge the quality of the present process? How do we know if in the present
we are headed in the right direction? Let’s consider these issues since they
point to commitments that ground the normative vision I discuss in part 3.
Consider first how one is able to judge present experience without a
fixed and final standard. This objection is important because it suggests
∞∑≠
present activity and the meaning of moral life
that Dewey might not be able to avoid the implication that in moral
experience there is no non-arbitrary way to determine better from worse.
This implication follows if one assumes that the quality of any present
process can be judged only by the quality of its future end-product. The
future is the only standard for the present. But Dewey was critical of this
commonly held assumption in the American school system and work-
place. Outcomes, especially quantifiable ones, are important but they do
not determine the quality of the present process. Present learning can be
directly experienced and judged as a meaningful and worthwhile experi-
ence regardless of what may come from it.
The apparent need for a future and fixed end to judge the present may
well be the result of having an abstract and narrow view of the resources
that are found in the present situation. But as Dewey notes, the present is
not a ‘‘sharp narrow knife-blade in time’’ (MW 14:194) and it includes not
only what is present to observation but also a complex of working habits,
memory, and foresight. To rely on present experience to judge its own
ongoing quality means that one needs to rely on character, inherited
moral principles, and present possibilities (including goals or ends-in-
view). Moreover, the present is a qualitative context that we can syn-
chronically rely on to determine better from worse. In other words, we
experience whether we are making progress during a moral problem as a
pervasive quality of the present situation without deliberately applying
some antecedent standard or criteria. Dewey claimed that if moving into
the better ‘‘cannot be told by qualities belonging to the moment of transi-
tion it can never be judged’’ (MW 14:195). He insisted that
∞∑∞
dewey’s view of moral experience
the quality of the process was motivated by a concern that if we do not give
the present its due attention, the quality and meaningfulness of life su√ers.
Criticism of moral theories that legitimize the separation of means and
ends and products and process is needed because these dualisms keep
individuals from living more meaningful moral lives. Product-oriented
views of morality overemphasize our acquisitive capacities at the expense
of the creative ones. If the best we can do with our present moral struggles
is endure them for the sake of some remote end, then present experience is
a mere means, and moral life is experienced as unaesthetic drudgery. This
is, in fact, how many in today’s complex conditions already experience
their daily lives. For Dewey there is another possibility: moral life can have
aesthetic quality. This is the possibility that I will explore in part 3. But
before turning explicitly to Dewey’s normative proposals, I will end this
chapter with a reminder about the kind of proposals we can expect and the
broadest commitments on which they are based.
There is in Dewey a general but clear prescription to give up thinking
of ‘‘some parts of this life as merely preparatory to other later stages of it’’
(EW 4:50) and to instead aim at the ‘‘fullest utilization of present resources,
liberating and guiding capacities that are now urgent’’ (MW 14:185, my
emphasis). This does not mean that we ought to rest on previous ac-
complishments. He says that ‘‘morality is a continuing process not a
fixed achievement. Morals mean growth of conduct in meaning . . .’’
(MW 14:194). To live fully in the present means that the past should be
used as a ‘‘storehouse of resources by which to move confidently forward’’
(LW 10:23). On the other hand, the future ‘‘consists of possibilities that are
felt as a possession of what is now and here’’ (LW 10:24). In short, fore-
sight, hindsight, and present observation are all done in the present for the
present. He said,
The quest for fixed and final ends ought to be replaced by an e√ort to
attend to the needs and possibilities within a unique and present situation
to the best of our abilities. At one point Dewey summarized his moral
outlook by saying,
∞∑≤
present activity and the meaning of moral life
and study the needs and alternative possibilities lying within a unique
and localized situation. (MW 14:196, my emphasis)
∞∑≥
dewey’s view of moral experience
lems of life? For Dewey it was, but he would have to recognize that there
may be individuals who need more than the present meaningfulness of the
journey or struggle. Dewey would of course question whether the need for
more is grounded on prejudice or on a failure to give the present a chance.
But all he can do as a philosopher is argue that the faith that underlies his
moral vision is possible and reasonable. The activity of creating and re-
shaping present moral experience can be meaningful and of value without
the guarantee or hope of an independent and long-term final end. We do
not have to aspire to acquire something outside of experience in order to
make our melioristic e√orts meaningful or to engage in the creative pro-
cess of transforming existing situations. The present trouble, strife, mo-
notony, limitations, and su√ering in a situation can be su≈cient reasons
and motivation to pursue the task of reconstruction. Dewey said that
‘‘men have constructed a strange dream world when they have supposed
that without a fixed ideal of a remote good to inspire them, they have no
inducement to get relief from present troubles, no desires for liberation
from what oppresses’’ (MW 14:195). He would even argue that it is pre-
cisely the search for fixed, absolute, and final goods that is an obstacle to
e√ective amelioration. The pursuit of general fixed goods such as truth,
knowledge, health, and justice can make one overlook the specific, con-
crete, and unique situations where such goods are at stake. For ‘‘in declar-
ing that good is already realized in ultimate reality tends to make us gloss
over the evils that concretely exist’’ (MW 12:182). Dewey hoped that the
abandonment of the quest for universal and fixed rules and ends in morals
would enable us to employ all our resources and focus our ‘‘attention to
present troubles and possibilities’’ (MW 14:198). He would agree that our
e√orts to improve present conditions are and should be sometimes in-
spired and guided by ideals (e.g., the ideal of democracy). But he would
not understand why such ideals need to be fixed, final, or absolute. They
can be nothing more than present means of present amelioration.
Does this commit Dewey to meliorism as the end of moral life? I
would rather characterize it as a faith. If meliorism is an end, it would have
to be something so broad and general that it would elude a fixed determi-
nation of its content. Just as seeking health can only mean that one tries to
live healthily, so too does seeking meliorism mean living melioristically,
that is, doing our best to make things better. But what does this really come
to? If it presupposes any particular rule about what counts as making
things better, then there is not much di√erence between meliorism and any
other ethical view that presupposes a fixed standard. Consistency requires
that Dewey holds that ‘better’ is context dependent, that is, its meaning
depends on what particular problems and potentialities are present in a
∞∑∂
present activity and the meaning of moral life
∞∑∑
nine
Conclusion
The Need for a Recovery of Moral Philosophy
∞∑∏
conclusion: the need for a recovery of moral philosophy
ate the personal and human aspect of morality, especially the fact that we
qua moral agents are ourselves a condition of moral experience. But by
committing the philosophical fallacy they have portrayed morality as a
self-centered endeavor or, worse, they have reduced moral experience to
the act of experiencing or to the content of consciousness.
Contemporary moral theories appreciate the linguistic, cultural, his-
torical, biological, and communal character of morality. From the stand-
point of Dewey’s ethics, this is a welcome trend, but it is not a significant
improvement on subjectivist views if it leads one to commit the philo-
sophical fallacy. Moral experience cannot be reduced to its conditions.
The view that moral life begins and ends inside a language, a conceptual
scheme, or a culture is a theoretical presupposition that is not supported
by life as it is lived considered from a practical, engaged standpoint. Fur-
thermore, such a narrow view tends to portray moral agents as trapped in
their own creations, without the possibility to test or judge specific moral
claims without begging the question. From this perspective, it seems as if
the only way to save morality from arbitrariness is to jump ‘‘into the fire of
absolutism’’ (LW 13:241).
Dewey thought that the history of ethics was dominated by family
quarrels and by the recurrent oscillation between extreme views, each
trying to compensate for what the other had failed to emphasize. Dewey
thought that there is a need for a recovery of moral philosophy. This
recovery requires the abandonment of certain common assumptions
about moral experience that are made by non-empirical philosophies. It is
helpful to contrast some of the assumptions in non-empirical philoso-
phies with Dewey’s view of moral experience.
∞∑π
dewey’s view of moral experience
structure, that is, one with patterns, rhythms, and phases. Situa-
tions are the ultimate context of our problems, inquiries, ideals,
and resources.
≤) Moral experience is not subjective. To describe moral experience is
not to describe the content of an agent’s consciousness. Further-
more, there is more to moral experience than what, at any given
time, is cognitively discerned and at the foreground of attention.
In the context of a morally problematic situation there is the fore-
ground where moral problems and inquiries are taking place, but
there is also the temporal and spatial background upon which we
rely and that we take for granted. Moral experience per se is not
knowledge, although knowing experiences are part of it.
≥) Many of the traditional polemics in moral theory start with a
dualism, for example, between subject and object, or character
and conduct. For Dewey, we can recognize the functional basis of
these distinctions while being faithful to the integrity of moral
experience. In fact, the distinction between what is experienced
and how it is experienced in a moral situation, or between conduct
and character, is important for an e√ective ethics.
∂) Many traditional views of moral experience start with the abstrac-
tion of an antecedent subject whose conduct is merely an external
e√ect. For Dewey, the moral self is an embodied and acculturated
agent with habits, and engaged in processes; moreover, the self is
inseparable but distinguishable from its relationships and acts.
When the moral agent is engrossed in moral reconstruction, con-
duct is an expression of the self, that is, there is a unity of the moral
self and its conduct.
∑) Moral deliberation is often conceived of as an inner cognitive
search for moral truths, or as reasoning with propositional con-
tent that centers on the application of antecedent rules to current
situations. For Dewey, however, moral deliberation is a qualita-
tive, experimental, social, and imaginative process that requires
operations to transform situations which carry their own seeds of
reconstruction.
∏) For Dewey, judgments are not propositions. In ethics, it is com-
monly assumed that the normativity or reasonableness of our
specific moral judgments is derived from a general standard of
appropriate conduct. Debates center on whether these general
standards are grounded in some ahistorical, objective standpoint,
or are rather the result of communal, intersubjective agreement.
For Dewey, this gets it backward and puts the emphasis in the
∞∑∫
conclusion: the need for a recovery of moral philosophy
∞∑Ω
dewey’s view of moral experience
∞∏≠
conclusion: the need for a recovery of moral philosophy
∞∏∞
PART THREE
The Ideal Moral Life
ten
The Intelligent, Aesthetic, and
Democratic Way of Life
D ewey did not have a theory about the good life, a notion antithetical to
the pluralistic and contextualist thrust of his moral philosophy. Neverthe-
less, his ethics is unintelligible apart from some normative commitments
and hypotheses about the conditions and instrumentalities for a better
moral life. Dewey wanted us to give each moral situation the attention and
care that it deserves and to assume a positive trust in the possibilities and
instrumentalities available in a situation. The moral life that he envisioned
is one that relies on experience for direction, illumination, and motiva-
tion. He was not, however, always explicit about his ideal. I will be oc-
cupied, in the remainder of this book, with articulating in a coherent way
this normative vision. This chapter begins with the most general descrip-
tion of the kind of moral life that Dewey thought was worthwhile in light
of his preoccupation with the quality of present experience. Then, in the
last two chapters, I consider the kind of self and community that, accord-
ing to Dewey, are constitutive of such a life.
The broadest possible characterization of Dewey’s ideal is that he
advocates living a moral life that is intelligent, aesthetic, and democratic.
These three adjectives characterize mutually dependent aspects of a single
∞∏∑
the ideal moral life
moral vision, and they collectively describe a moral life that promises
to be the most meaningful and fruitful general form of engagement in
experience.
To say that a moral life has a dimension of intelligence is to say that
one who lives the moral life can educate herself (i.e., learn) and transform
morally problematic situations through her own moral resources. What
Dewey called ‘‘experimental intelligence’’ involves those habits of inquiry
by means of which hypotheses are tested and by means of which working
connections are found between old habits, customs, institutions, beliefs,
and new conditions. With respect to moral life, intelligence refers to a way
of reaching moral judgments and appropriating a moral tradition. Dewey
contrasts intelligence with the practice of guiding our lives by authority,
custom, coercive force, imitation, caprice, or drift. To live a reflective
moral life is not to live in accordance with reason but to have ‘‘the power
of using past experience to shape and transform future experience. It is
constructive and creative’’ (MW 11:346).
The aesthetic dimension of moral life refers to its qualitative aspect
and to the inherently meaningful forms of engagement exercised within it.
Moral reconstruction is undertaken in an aesthetic manner. Dewey con-
trasts the aesthetic with the mechanical, the fragmentary, the non-inte-
grated, and all other non-meaningful forms of engagement. To engage a
situation intelligently is to engage it aesthetically. It is in this way that
‘‘moral life is protected from falling into formalism and rigid repetition. It
is rendered flexible, vital, growing’’ (MW 12:180).
The democratic aspect of moral life means that living the moral life
involves a certain way of interacting with others, a certain kind of com-
munication and community. Dewey understands democracy as a form of
moral association in which a certain way of life is instituted in the relations
and interactions of its citizens. ‘‘It is primarily a mode of associated living,
of conjoint communicated experience’’ (MW 9:93). His notion of democ-
racy is an outgrowth of his ideas about moral experience, and the demo-
cratic way of life involves the intelligent and the aesthetic community.
Although an important part of my task is to show how the ideal moral
life is supported by and consistent with Dewey’s philosophical commit-
ments (e.g., his faith in experience) it would be wrong to suppose that this
ideal logically follows from them. To do this would be to neglect context
(i.e., commit the philosophical fallacy) and assume a view of ideals that is
foreign to Dewey’s philosophical outlook. Inquiry about how to live takes
place in the context of a felt discontent with present ways of living. Let’s
briefly consider the problematic context that generated and gives meaning
to Dewey’s ideal.
∞∏∏
t h e i n t e l l i g e n t, a e s t h e t i c , a n d d e m o c r at i c way o f l i f e
The result of these divisions has been the creation of a large number of
problems which in their technical aspect are the special concern of
philosophy, but which come home to every one in his actual life in the
segregation of the activities he carries on, the departmentalizing of life,
the pigeon-holing of interests. Between science’s sake, art for art’s sake,
business as usual or business for money-making, the relegation of reli-
gion to Sundays and holy-days, the turning over of politics to profes-
sional politicians, the professionalizing of sports, and so on, little room
is left for living, for the sake of living, a full, rich and free life. (LW 2:104)
∞∏π
the ideal moral life
∞∏∫
t h e i n t e l l i g e n t, a e s t h e t i c , a n d d e m o c r at i c way o f l i f e
∞∏Ω
the ideal moral life
the quality of present moral experience. This quality has su√ered in part
because of extremism in dealing with moral and social problems. To be
torn between the rigidity of absolutism and the laxity of relativism is to be
torn between qualitatively poor ways to live and conceive of moral life. By
Dewey’s lights, both alternatives reflect a general distrust in our everyday
moral experience and a failure to use the resources and potentialities of
experience.
Dewey sought to undermine the dualistic and otherwise mistaken
philosophical views that sanctioned the idea that we are stuck between
extreme options. He said, ‘‘The modern world has su√ered because in so
many matters philosophy has o√ered only an arbitrary choice between
hard and fast opposites’’ (MW 12:137). Philosophy as criticism is needed to
unearth these prejudices and to suggest better ways to live.
∞π≠
t h e i n t e l l i g e n t, a e s t h e t i c , a n d d e m o c r at i c way o f l i f e
experience.≤ For Dewey, not all of the items in columns A and B are
conceptual abstractions, for many of them designate contrary tendencies
or generic traits that have to be dealt with in nearly every dimension of
experience. In fact, many of these traits became part of the ground map
of experience that he provided in Experience and Nature.≥ I will argue
that the relation between them is important to the philosophical issue of
how to live.
Typically, the philosopher takes the opposition of A and B as prob-
lematic. Hence, the task of inquiry for such a philosopher becomes one
of finding, once and for all, a way to theoretically overcome, reconcile,
downplay, or solve the oppositions by determining which side of the
opposition is ontologically primary. For example, the monism-versus-
pluralism debate assumes that all things are either interdependent or inde-
pendent. Universalists and nominalists assume either that particulars can
be explained by or reduced to universals, or the contrary. The absolutist-
versus-relativist debate usually assumes either that moral principles are
fixed or that anything goes. Dewey was concerned to diagnose why phi-
losophers tend toward these polemical extremes.
The fundamental mistake of the traditional philosopher is that she
misconstrues the nature of the concrete problems where A and B are in
tension, thus confusing a practical tension in actual situations with a
theoretical issue about what is real. This is the philosophical fallacy.∂ We
live in world that is a mixture of A and B, where we can distinguish them
without setting them dualistically apart. However, this does not mean they
coexist in some sort of pre-established harmony. The practical problem is
that A and B are sometimes in an undesirable tension in the context of a
problematic situation. The challenge is not to get rid of the tension but ‘‘to
find the limits or balance between these two things.’’∑ For example, in our
moral life there is a recurrent experienced tension between the stability
and order of our acquired habits (and principles), and new conditions, on
the other hand. But the practical problem, if taken for what it is, is not
how we should get rid of the opposition and tension. From the point of
view of the everyday person, the concrete problem is a matter of propor-
tion, that is, of determining how much flexibility should be allowed in
specific areas of our moral practice, or deciding what has to be changed
and what does not.
Philosophers have ended with extreme views because they have con-
fused matters of proportion with an abstract ontological problem. If
there were no opposition, the sides of the tension would lack mean-
ing and, more importantly, would lead to undesirable consequences. For
instance,
∞π∞
the ideal moral life
For the ‘‘ordinary man,’’ as Dewey put it, it is of practical importance that
the balance between A and B should obtain. Dewey explained that
the ordinary man would say that you must not let one factor unduly
predominate over the other, that you get disintegration if you allow the
individualistic factor to go too far; you lose public spirit, the sense of
solidarity. . . . On the other hand, if you carry out authority too far you
get despotism, arrest of freedom of thought and action, and fossilization
of society.π
It is clear that Dewey uses the ordinary man to propose a normative thesis
that remained central to his philosophy: that we ought to seek an integra-
tive balance between A and B, and that wisdom usually lies in avoiding the
tempting simplicity of extreme philosophical views. Although even a short
acquaintance with his works would confirm this general thesis, he never
explicitly and systematically defends it. Instead, it is implicit in his treat-
ment of particular oppositions present in di√erent areas of philosophy.
Not enough attention has been given to balance as a normative notion in
Dewey. Balance is a feature of ideal activity, the ideal moral self, and the
ideal community.
∞π≤
t h e i n t e l l i g e n t, a e s t h e t i c , a n d d e m o c r at i c way o f l i f e
∞π≥
the ideal moral life
∞π∂
t h e i n t e l l i g e n t, a e s t h e t i c , a n d d e m o c r at i c way o f l i f e
She does not know beforehand how much room she has, therefore she has
to rely on experimentation. Those who take more risk in artistic produc-
tion are those willing to test the limits, that is, to try to find out how much
of one element they can get away with without falling o√ balance. Dewey
thought that being able to achieve this dynamic variation within balance is
a mark of great works of art. ‘‘The greater the variation, the more interest-
ing the e√ect, provided order is maintained’’ (LW 10:169). This is balance
that is maintained in spite of changes in rhythm. In great works of art
there might be periods of relative predominance of disorder and novelty,
but they do not lead to chaos or confusion, that is, ‘‘it does not prevent a
cumulative carrying forward from one part to another’’ (LW 10:171).
Structure and process, substance and accident, matter and energy, per-
manence and flux, one and many, continuity and discreteness, order and
progress, law and liberty, uniformity and growth, tradition and innova-
tion, rational will and impelling desires, proof and discovery, the actual
and the possible, are names given to various phases of their conjunction,
and the issue of living depends upon the art with which these things are
adjusted to each other. (LW 1:67, my emphasis)
∞π∑
the ideal moral life
∞π∏
t h e i n t e l l i g e n t, a e s t h e t i c , a n d d e m o c r at i c way o f l i f e
and pain. But Dewey would argue that this is not what they really want. A
life of too much struggle and challenges is undesirable, but so is a life
without enough challenges and struggle.
Dewey’s a≈rmation of the hypothesis that balance makes for a better
lived experience can be demonstrated by showing how balance is essential
to his descriptions of ideal activity in all of the di√erent dimensions of
human life. For example, in How We Think Dewey claims that ‘‘the best
thinking occurs when the easy and the di≈cult are duly proportioned to
each other’’ (LW 8:350). He also characterizes the extremes. ‘‘Too much
that is easy gives no ground for inquiry; too much that is hard renders
inquiry hopeless’’ (LW 8:350). However, nowhere is it clearer that the
notion of balance is ideal for Dewey than in his aesthetics and ethics. In
fact, art is his paradigm of balance. Art is the highest achievement of
experience. It represents the complete integrative balance of those tenden-
cies and generic traits of experience that philosophers have erected into
dualisms because they are in a tension-filled relation. ‘‘In art as experience,
actuality and possibility or ideality, the new and the old, objective material
and personal response . . . are integrated in an experience in which they are
all transfigured from the significance that belongs to them when isolated
in reflection’’ (LW 10:301). Moreover, Dewey holds that balance is key to
any human activity with aesthetic quality. The ideal moral life, in other
words, has aesthetic quality.
∞ππ
the ideal moral life
vidual creation. The extreme forms that our moral life can take are not
straw man philosophical positions to be dealt with only within philosophy
proper. They represent liabilities of living. For even if we might not be able
to point to any one who can be said to wholeheartedly embody these
extremes, they are two opposite tendencies our characters and community
can take if we do not attend to the di≈cult task of reflective moral life.
There is always the risk that acquired habits and any inherited or past moral
knowledge can become mechanized and rigid when they are taken as direct
guides to action. But there is also the risk that flexibility in moral matters
might descend into a lack of respect for any moral standard.
Perhaps these risks are more evident when we think about the moral
education of our children. No matter how true the moral principles are
which we wish to inculcate in our children, we should also be concerned
about how they are going to adopt and apply them to their unique circum-
stances. There is no guaranteed or simple method to prevent our children
from becoming either too flexible or too rigid and dogmatic in moral
matters. We can only hope to create the conditions which may enable
them to steer between undesirable extremes. Some of these conditions are
the habits of intelligence.
In his writings on philosophy of education Dewey describes the ideal
in terms of the balance between ‘‘the work attitude and the play attitude’’
(LW 8:347). He claims that, ‘‘To be playful and serious at the same time is
possible, and it defines the ideal mental condition’’ (LW 8:347). In morals,
just as in art and science, there should be a merging of playfulness with
seriousness. There is no intention on Dewey’s part to establish a dichot-
omy; as he says, ‘‘there is no distinction of exclusive periods of play activity
and work activity, but only one of emphasis’’ (MW 14:211). In play, one is
engaged in the present activity for its own sake, for ‘‘interest centers in
activity, without much reference to its outcome’’ (LW 8:346). Play is ‘‘free,
plastic,’’ imaginative, and requires a ‘‘serious absorption’’ in present ac-
tivity. The presence of play signifies tendencies of curiosity, flexibility, and
openness. In work, on the other hand, the direction of one’s interest is in
the product in which the activity terminates, therefore ‘‘the end holds
attention and controls the notice given to means’’ (LW 8:346).
When there is excess or deficiency of either play or work, or an isola-
tion of one from the other, the outcome is undesirable, that is, it is an
unaesthetic vice. On the side of play the vice is ‘‘fooling,’’ namely, ‘‘a series
of disconnected temporary overflows of energy dependent upon whim
and accident’’ (LW 8:346). Excessive playfulness becomes the kind of in-
dulgence that becomes an arbitrary and aimless fancy. The excessive flexi-
bility and openness in play can lead to dissipation or disintegration. On
∞π∫
t h e i n t e l l i g e n t, a e s t h e t i c , a n d d e m o c r at i c way o f l i f e
the side of work the vice is drudgery. When work becomes drudgery,
activity that was ‘‘directed by accomplishment of a definite result’’ be-
comes activity ‘‘undergone as mere means by which to secure a result’’
(LW 10:283). In drudgery, the agent is not emotionally or imaginatively
involved in present activity, and it becomes routine and mechanical. An
exclusive interest in outcomes results in ‘‘activities in which the interest in
the outcome does not su√use the process of getting the result’’ (LW 8:346).
In drudgery, the present activity is taken as if it were a necessary evil.
When ends are external to the means, the process of doing loses all value
for the doer.
The occurrence of any of the above vices is often followed by the other.
For when there is excess or isolation on the side either of play or work, the
other develops in isolation. When most of our daily activities fail to engage
our emotions and imagination, the few opportunities for play usually
degenerate into aimless amusement, that is, there is a ‘‘recourse to abnor-
mal artificial excitations and stimulations’’ (MW 14:113). Hence, for Dewey,
a society where passive entertainment and drudgery are the predominant
modes of daily engagement is a sign of a problem. He also diagnosed that
in our product-oriented and class-structured society, social and economic
conditions tend to make ‘‘play into the idle excitement for the well-to-do,
and work into uncongenial labor for the poor’’ (MW 9:214).
But are there not things one has to do without the direct interest
characteristic of play? Of course, but ideally even in this kind of situation
work activity can be more than mere means. The alternative is that interest
in and appreciation of the value of the end su√uses and informs the
present means; in other words, a sense of its value is transferred to the
means. The process is appreciated as constitutive of the product. In ideal
work ‘‘activity is enriched by the sense that it leads somewhere’’; there is
‘‘interest in an activity as tending to a culmination’’ (LW 8:287). This is
di√erent from situations of drudgery where it is only the thought of
completion—to earn a reward or avoid punishment—that keeps you go-
ing. Artistic activity, again, is Dewey’s model: ‘‘Work which remains per-
meated with the play attitude is art—in quality if not in conventional
designation’’ (MW 9:214).
Dewey thought that moral philosophers had either conceived moral
activity as a playful, arbitrary, and subjective creation or tried to recover
the seriousness of morality at the expense of associating it with drudgery;
in other words, morality conceived of as a rigid and emotionally sterile
activity that subordinates the present, or that is based on externally im-
posed rules. He envisioned the possibility of a moral life with aesthetic
quality as one that achieves a balance between the tendencies and traits
∞πΩ
the ideal moral life
associated with play (i.e., B) and with work (i.e., A). This balance is also
the key to an intelligent moral life. Intelligence requires that the self or
community be capable of carrying forward the habits funded by previous
experience while keeping them open to modification; such is a society
capable of integrating means with ends. It must be creative but receptive,
unified but expansive, working but playful. This is our best hope for a
meaningful moral life that can maintain its own integrity without the
support or guidance of fixed and external (transcendental) foundations. A
moral life that is lived merely by finding the best means to fixed ends is
neither aesthetic nor intelligent.
∞∫≠
t h e i n t e l l i g e n t, a e s t h e t i c , a n d d e m o c r at i c way o f l i f e
tive. For one who sees the desirability of one extreme, the attempt to
introduce balance tends to lead further and further into the opposite and
undesired direction. For example, those who endorse freedom and spon-
taneity might claim that any attempt to add order or objective control to
our lives leads eventually to fixity, a clear threat to freedom. Therefore, if
we really care about freedom we need to be ready to pay the price of laxity
or anarchy, if that were to occur. In other words, there is no lasting
integration by which we can secure at the same time the values gained by
freedom and order. We live in world where we must make a tragic choice
between extremes. The quest for balance amounts to delaying or disguis-
ing the di≈cult choice that must be made; meanwhile, we are not able to
reap the full benefits of taking a one-sided, wholesale stance. Wisdom
requires that we make a practical choice regarding which of the elements
of the A-B opposition should be primordial.
We could extend this argument to the more general disputes about our
moral life. Those philosophers who describe our moral life primarily by
using A categories are perhaps concerned that allowing (or trying to
integrate) change, flexibility, and precariousness as features either of real-
ity or of our basic principles, character, morality, and society will even-
tually lead to decay, disorder, chaos, and anarchy. In other words, a de-
parture from immutable standards leads to a lack of fixity in habit and
principles. On the other hand, those who endorse B-traits are concerned
that the stability, commitment, and security characteristic of the opposite
extreme lead to conformity, stagnation, lack of creativity and spontaneity,
and all the possible evils that derive from self-righteousness. Notice that in
all of these arguments the notion of balance is undermined by a slippery
slope argument; in other words, attempts to balance opposing tendencies
eventually lead to a vice or failure. Therefore, since one cannot have the
best of both tendencies we should embrace one. In this debate, both sides
claim that any compromise or balance is deceptive or open to suspicion.
Dewey was in fact criticized from both sides. People at contrary extremes
perceived Dewey’s position as a disguised threat to their endorsed extreme.
One has to admit that each of the extremist philosophers in this
imaginary debate points to authentic concerns about the dangers of living
under their opponent’s assumptions. However, such slippery slope argu-
ments only show the risk and di≈culty involved in trying to keep a work-
able balance; they do not, however, prove that the possibility envisioned
by Dewey is unworkable. Of course, to add more flexibility to the moral
stabilities that we count on might lead to a chaotic and unprincipled
moral life, but this is not a good reason to adopt one-sidedness. On the
∞∫∞
the ideal moral life
contrary, for Dewey this is a reason to try to study the conditions by which
the kind of balanced relationship that he envisions might be achieved and
maintained.
As I have explained, balance is not something achieved for all time or
something antecedent to human e√ort and experimentation. Dewey can-
not claim to know that there will always be a workable and lasting balance
by which we can secure at any time the values gained by A and B respec-
tively. Moreover, there are many situations in which, even with our best
e√orts, we will fail to achieve balance and will have to embrace an extreme.
Dewey was not naïve. He was aware that his proposals were di≈cult to
implement. But he was not ready to assert that it was impossible or that we
must resign ourselves to a life of extremes.
One could argue that it is too much to ask that we make balance the
aim of all of our conduct. But making balance an ideal does not entail this.
The only kind of activity where balance is usually a conscious aim is art.
Art serves as a paradigm because in it we are concerned with balance and
rhythm for their own sake and enjoyment. The artist takes as her subject
matter and concern something that is implicitly present in all ideal ac-
tivity. But the fact that the achievement of balance outside the realm of art
is relegated to the background does not make it less important in those
activities. Most of moral life is directly concerned with unique, morally
problematic situations and there may well be situations where extreme
solutions are called for. To hold balance as an ideal is not to set it up as a
criterion, standard, or end of morally correct action. That is determined
by the particular context. Dewey only claims that a balance between our
doings and undergoings, means and ends, etc., is the optimal condition
for confronting morally problematic situations. Balance is key to a more
meaningful and enriching moral life, but it is not morality’s explicit end.
In fact, a moral agent who makes balance the direct conscious aim of all
her situations will likely preclude the sort of balance that Dewey thinks is
needed in attending wholeheartedly and intelligently to moral problems.
Indeed, even in art the artist usually achieves balance by attending directly
to materials and their relation, rather than by making balance the con-
scious end. A moral agent might make balance her conscious concern but
this is only when a serious imbalance is experienced and one is concerned
with improving one’s method or character (i.e., the ‘‘how’’ of experience),
such as when one has become too rigid in dealing with moral problems
and one wants to re-balance oneself. Similarly, in social and political
inquiry one is typically concerned with very specific social and political
problems. Balance becomes a direct and conscious issue only when, for
example, one experiences problems that indicate that one’s society is be-
∞∫≤
t h e i n t e l l i g e n t, a e s t h e t i c , a n d d e m o c r at i c way o f l i f e
∞∫≥
the ideal moral life
periods of deficiency (or vice versa). We tend to fall into this pattern
because while experiencing one excess its contrary seems desirable. The
desired excess might represent the direction toward which we should aim,
but we must not confuse direction with final aim. It is true that a life lived
as the alternation between extremes has rhythm and therefore might be
better than the monotony of living under one extreme. But Dewey hoped
we could do better. We can try to maintain a balance where there is
significant variation and rhythm, aware of the risk we are taking. Extrem-
ism is appealing because extremes are easily noticed and they seem to
represent a position of strength. But Dewey argued otherwise. It is when
we live within an extreme that we are the most vulnerable because we are
more likely to compensate by shifting to the opposite extreme.
In sum, Dewey’s view about balance is important to his philosophical
outlook. It sheds new light on the importance of undermining philosoph-
ical dualisms. Dualisms, more than just roadblocks to inquiry, are ob-
stacles to rehearsing in practice a more beneficial relation between oppos-
ing elements in experience. The consequences of dualisms are usually
seclusion, isolation, suppression, one-sidedness, excesses, and deficien-
cies. His task as a philosopher was to keep our options alive and open. As
long as we continue to believe that extremes exhaust our options we will
fail to try what he thought deserved to be tried.
Dewey’s ability to stand somewhere between apparent oppositions on
almost every issue has led to the view that he was the great American
unifier and reconciliator. Alan Ryan, for example, has recently claimed
that Dewey’s ‘‘views gratify a familiar American longing to unify op-
posites.’’∞∞ Although there is some truth to this, we must be clear about the
nature of Dewey’s solution or proposal regarding the oppositions that are
present in philosophy and experience. It is a simplification and misunder-
standing to suggest that he only sought to remove dualisms or that he
unified by dissolving tensions. Rather, he sought a more balanced relation
that relies on and a≈rms the tensions found in everyday experience.
Thus far, my characterization of Dewey’s ideal is too general for our
purposes. What in particular needs to be in balance in a moral life that is
aesthetic, intelligent, and democratic? What kind of self and community is
required? What specific habits are required in order to achieve the bal-
anced integration between doing and undergoing, play and work, needed
in morality? In the remainder of this book, I will provide a sketch of the
kind of moral self, virtues, relationships, and community that were con-
stitutive of Dewey’s moral ideal.
∞∫∂
eleven
The Ideal Moral Self
∞∫∑
the ideal moral life
∞∫∏
the ideal moral self
openness
Open-mindedness is a neglected virtue in moral philosophy. A probable
reason for this neglect is that too many epistemologists have kidnapped the
notion of open-mindedness and claimed it as a merely epistemic virtue.∞
This is a misconception that can prevent one from appreciating the moral
and social importance of this virtue for pragmatism. How specific can we
get in determining what open-mindedness is? It is uncontroversial to say
that it is the tendency or disposition to act open-mindedly. But how do we
determine if an act is of the open-minded kind? We cannot say without
circularity that such an act is just one which is performed by an open-
∞∫π
the ideal moral life
minded person. As a contextualist Dewey must claim that what does and
does not count as acting open-mindedly is ultimately determined by the
contextual features of a situation that cannot be specified by a set of
definite rules. Nevertheless, a contextualist approach does not preclude a
philosopher from delineating some general marks of paradigm cases. In
such an analysis, however, vagueness should be expected to rear its head.
For example, basic to open-mindedness is a willingness to revise or recon-
sider one’s views and commitments if necessary. But there is no exact
answer to the question of when we should expect an open-minded person
to revise her views or to retain them. Another reason why precision tends
to elude us is that openness seems to be a matter of degree. There is a
di√erence of openness between one who looks at objections only if they
arise and another who actively looks for weaknesses in his view; this is the
di√erence between one who welcomes new ideas when they arise, and
another who actively seeks new experiences.
Given the variety of forms open-mindedness takes, and since it is not
merely an intellectual trait, it is more appropriate to describe this virtue in
terms of a general attitude, one Dewey describes as an attitude of hospi-
tality toward the new. To be open is to be free from rigidity and fixity, but
‘‘it is something more active and positive than these words suggest. It is
very di√erent than empty-mindedness’’ (LW 8:136). It is a receptivity and
plasticity that comes from an active accessibility, from ‘‘alert curiosity and
spontaneous outreaching for the new’’ (LW 8:136).
Open-mindedness means a capacity to interact. It is to welcome new
experiences, but in the strong sense of a willingness to be a√ected by par-
ticipation with the new. As Dewey says, it is a ‘‘willingness to let experi-
ences accumulate and sink in and ripen’’ (MW 9:183). Openness is not just
letting the other person have her say but actively listening to her. Openness
is almost the contrary of a defensive attitude. In being open we become
exposed, susceptible, sensitive, and therefore vulnerable. Because open-
mindedness constitutes the lived rejection of absolutism, there is a pecu-
liar humility to the open-minded character, an implicit recognition of
one’s limitations and vulnerability. For a pragmatist, it points to a recogni-
tion of the precarious and open-ended character of experience.
Dewey had reasons to consider openness and courage habits worth
cultivating. They are virtues because (1) they are part of intelligence, un-
derstood as the concrete set of habits which make possible the ameliora-
tion of experience through its own means, and (2) a balance between these
dispositions is required for an aesthetic moral life, one that avoids the
extremes of moral absolutism and moral anarchy.
Recall that Dewey’s faith is that betterment might result if we do what
∞∫∫
the ideal moral self
is in our power. The power to improve the habits which interact with the
demands, possibilities, and enjoyments of present experience is under our
control. An intelligent organism has the capability to modify and improve
a disrupted habit so that it can become relevant to this and all similar
situations. With time, an intelligent organism not only learns to adapt her
habits to present situations but learns to learn; in other words, not only
can she modify her present tools, but she can create tools to modify tools.
However, the habits involved in the e√ort to readjust disturbed habits are
general and second-order habits of habits. Whereas first-order habits op-
erate and are applicable only at the level of the particular situation (they
are specialized tools), second-order habits are general in the sense that
they operate with respect to many kinds of situations.
A general name for the operation of second-order tools is intelligence.
When a pragmatist like Dewey refers to intelligence or experimental re-
flection, he is pointing to the workings of a very complex but concrete set
of habits and attitudes which make possible the ability to learn from and
reconstruct experience. Some of these habits are wholeheartedness, per-
sistence, sensitivity, single-mindedness, sympathetic curiosity, unbiased
responsiveness, sincerity, breadth of outlook, and balance of interest.≤ But
I want to claim that openness and courage are two of the most important
second-order dispositions of this ideal character.
The most important learning a person accomplishes in a situation is
not amassing information, but the cultivation of habits which are going to
a√ect the quality of future situations. A present experience can, for exam-
ple, promote the formation of secondary habits and attitudes that prevent
the enrichment of future experiences; for example, it might engender
callousness or a lack of sensitivity and responsiveness. Hence, as far as
moral education is concerned, the cultivation of secondary dispositions to
improve old habits is more important than teaching information or a set
of rules. But which dispositions are worth cultivating?
If the very existence of habit signifies a tendency toward recurrence
and self-preservation, then the ability to modify and improve old habits
requires, first of all, an openness, plasticity, or flexibility in the face of new
experiences. Without plasticity there would be a non-pedagogical fixity, a
self-imposed stability, which is not faithful to the precarious and changing
character of experience. But without an active, stable determination noth-
ing can be carried over to guide us and to be tested in subsequent experi-
ence; continuity and learning would be impossible. In terms of an ideal
character, it means that both open-mindedness and courage are comple-
mentary virtues. Openness makes a character flexible and adaptable when
a change of direction or modification in our beliefs and habits is called for.
∞∫Ω
the ideal moral life
∞Ω≠
the ideal moral self
∞Ω∞
the ideal moral life
∞Ω≤
the ideal moral self
moral demands of situations and to give direction to our moral life. Let’s
consider each of these virtues separately.
s e n s i t i v i t y a n d c u lt i vat e d a p p r e c i at i o n
In our initial confrontation with a morally problematic situation the emo-
tional direct and spontaneous response to situations is indispensable for
moral inquiry. The development of sensitivity to the felt problem that
evokes inquiry, as well as to the pervasive quality of the context of inquiry
as it is transformed, is our best preparation for obtaining qualitative guid-
ance from experience. Dewey wrote,
∞Ω≥
the ideal moral life
∞Ω∂
the ideal moral self
man are more to be trusted than many of the elaborately reasoned out
estimates of the inexperienced’’ (LW 7:266). But this also means that there
are some characters for whom ‘‘the warped and distorted might seem
natural’’ (LW 7:267). Moreover, even the best among us (i.e., the morally
good person) is fallible and subject to the unavoidable elements of novelty
and complexity in moral situations. Intuitive moral appraisals are ‘‘depen-
dable in the degree in which conditions and objects are fairly uniform and
recurrent. They do not work with equal sureness in the cases in which the
new and unfamiliar enters in’’ (LW 7:267). We cannot then rely exclusively
on our acquired sensitivity to meet the demands of morality.
Moreover, too much reliance upon our moral sensibilities can lead to
an unaesthetic moral life in which our habits do not change. Exclusive
trust in our immediate appreciation does not let us grow and learn from
new situations. As Dewey puts it, ‘‘extreme intuitionalism and extreme
conservatism often go together’’ (LW 7:267). In a world of change and
novelty, in which each situation is unique, our direct appreciations are
fallible even if they have a ‘‘presumption of correctness’’ (LW 7:267).
The limitations of the good and sensitive character can only be ame-
liorated by supplementing its immediate appreciations with a disposition
to engage in reflective valuations. ‘‘The direct valuing which accompanies
immediate sensitive responsiveness to acts has its complement and expan-
sion in valuations which are deliberate, reflective’’ (LW 7:271). In terms of
moral character this means that sensitivity should operate in a balanced
relation with ‘‘conscientiousness’’ (LW 7:271).
va l uat i o n a n d c o n s c i e n t i o u s n e s s
∞Ω∑
the ideal moral life
∞Ω∏
the ideal moral self
one can only see from a certain standpoint, but this fact does not make
all standpoints of equal value. A standpoint which is nowhere in particu-
lar is an absurdity. But one may have an a√ection for a standpoint which
gives a rich and ordered landscape rather than for one from which things
are seen confusedly and meagerly. (LW 6:14–15, my emphasis)
∞Ωπ
the ideal moral life
with a rich, broad, and wide landscape upon which to deliberate and act,
and there are others that in comparison are constraining, one-sided, and
narrow. Dewey prescribes ‘‘the fostering of those habits and impulses
which lead to a broad, just, sympathetic survey of situations’’ (MW 14:144).
Thinking is the capacity to consider an act in its bearings and rela-
tions. But there is more to moral deliberation than reasoning or exploring
logical relations between abstract propositions. Recall that for Dewey one
does not fully examine the relations of an act unless one engages in inquiry
as an imaginative process of constructing and testing hypotheses. In this
process, relations with past experience, present events, and possible con-
sequences are explored. One can do this better or worse according to
whether one has a vivid imagination, but a more important determinant
of one’s success in inquiry is the breadth, width, and flexibility of one’s
imaginative field. At one extreme is the agent who only considers the
consequences of a single proposed act with respect to one person (usually
him or herself ), without considering other possible acts and their conse-
quences. Equally narrow from Dewey’s perspective is the experience of
someone—a utilitarian, for example—who in deliberation can only con-
sider the relation between alternative actions and one predetermined fixed
end. Moral agents can do better. They can develop the kind of habits that
allow them to have a wider experience in that they open themselves in
deliberation to several sometimes incommensurable ends and their rela-
tions, and thereby entertain a rich field of considerations. Sympathetic
imagination and openness are thus two valuable undergoing habits.
I have already considered how openness expands or welcomes our
reach toward new experiences. But whether our experience is wide or nar-
row depends also on the extent and depth of our sympathies. ‘‘Every wid-
ening of contacts with others, every deepening of the level of sympathetic
acquaintance, magnifies in so much vision of the good’’ (MW 5:379).
What Dewey meant by sympathy is closer to what feminist writers today
have identified as empathy.∑ To understand sympathy we must distinguish
it from other more casual and ordinary considerations. It is one thing to
consider how a possible course of conduct will a√ect others, quite another
to consider how those a√ected others would look at it from their stand-
point independently of our own. Of course, this capacity is a matter of
degree and will likely vary as a function of the level of acquaintance, the
nature of the relationship, and one’s powers of imagination. But this
ability does not presuppose the existence of some mysterious or indepen-
dent faculty. For Dewey and George Herbert Mead alike, the natural basis
of sympathy is the way we acquire a sense of a self as an individual. The self
is not given; it emerges out of ‘‘taking on the attitude of the other.’’∏ With
∞Ω∫
the ideal moral self
∞ΩΩ
the ideal moral life
The defect of his statement is that the rational process as such has never
treated and so far as can be foreseen never will treat human beings as
ends. To treat a human being as end it is necessary to put oneself into his
place in his whole nature and not simply in his universalizing, and
legislative aspects.Ω
There is no prima facie reason why humans can be the only objects of
sympathy. Although Tufts and Dewey do not address this issue, it is a lack
of sympathy, rather than a failure to cognitively acknowledge rights, that
may be the reason why many humans fail to treat other animals as ends. A
Deweyan ethics, with a more global or ecological scope than Dewey him-
self acknowledged, would encourage humans today to deliberatively con-
sider other creatures in a sympathetic way and not merely from the point
of view of human needs.
Dewey warned us that ‘‘when a legal type of morality is current’’
(LW 7:373), justice is ‘‘the working of some fixed and abstract law’’
(LW 7:373) and is separated from sympathy or care. But justice ceases to be a
virtue if it is not fused with sympathy. It is through sympathy that one can
appreciate what justice demands because it makes us understand what
each person needs in a vivid and more reliable fashion. Hence Dewey
claims that ‘‘to put ourselves in the place of another, to see things from the
standpoint of his aims and values . . . is the surest way to appreciate what
justice demands in concrete cases’’ (LW 7:251).
For Dewey, moral thought that is sympathetic is integral to the con-
siderate and just character. Sympathy ‘‘is the surest guarantee for the
exercise of consideration, for examination of a proposed line of conduct
in all of its bearings. And such complete interest is the only way in which
justice can be assured’’ (LW 7:259).
I should anticipate the important role of sympathy in Dewey’s ideal
democratic community. He claims that ‘‘the political action of citizens of
an organized community will not be morally satisfactory unless they have,
individually, sympathetic dispositions’’ (LW 7:300). Sympathy makes pos-
≤≠≠
the ideal moral self
sible the kind of moral life and community where the interests, demands,
and needs of others are vital and moving realities in one’s moral delibera-
tion, rather than abstract variables in a cold utilitarian calculation or in
the application of a formal law. When sympathy becomes fused with other
virtues, such as openness, it becomes part of the democratic readiness to
listen to others and look at things from their point of view whether we
agree or not. The morally reasonable person in Dewey’s moral vision is
not someone who listens to reason, but one who sympathetically listens to
others. The ideal moral community is one where agents treat each other as
ends in the sense that each has the willingness and imagination to take
account of others from the point of view of their needs, desires, and
circumstances.
Moral education should aim at developing in students the habits that
make them capable of examining for themselves the nature of the practical
situations they will face. Foremost is ‘‘the formation of a sympathetic
imagination for human relations in action; this is the ideal which is sub-
stituted for training in moral rules’’ (EW 4:57). The cultivation of charac-
ter is not an easy task, for sympathy can only grow out of having certain
communal experiences. This is why Dewey thought that the most impor-
tant kind of moral education in the school is the creation of the conditions
for a certain kind of community. He objected to the emphasis in schools
on absorption of information and competition because it goes against the
required social spirit needed to cultivate the ‘‘habits of social imagination’’
(MW 4:284). The presence of these habits is a prerequisite for any sig-
nificant moral lessons to be conveyed in the classroom. These lessons
‘‘amount to something only in the degree in which pupils happen to be
already animated by a sympathetic and dignified regard for the sentiments
of others. Without such a regard, it has no more influence on character
than the information about the mountains of Asia’’ (MW 9:364).
I have distinguished sensitivity, conscientiousness, courage, open-
mindedness, and sympathy as some of the virtues required in an intel-
ligent, aesthetic, and democratic moral life. But they are not virtues unless
they are integrated into a certain unity of character.
≤≠∞
the ideal moral life
tional distinctions help one appreciate how the elements of character that
Dewey stressed at di√erent times, including the few virtues I have consid-
ered, form part of an integral whole.
t h e i n t e l l e c t ua l
Commenting on the intellectual aspects of character, Dewey wrote that ‘‘it
has been the fortune of this element to su√er from both over-appreciation
and extreme depreciation’’ (MW 6:383). In modern moral philosophy, the
intellectual has been overappreciated at the expense of the active and
emotional phases simply because experience has been conceived of as a
primarily cognitive a√air. For Dewey, intellectual habits are tools of reflec-
tion needed for general learning and to estimate in particular situations
what one ought to do, that is, to reach judgment. In education Dewey
stressed that the mere passing down of information or knowledge does
not a√ect character in a way needed to a√ect good judgment.∞≠ Judgment
is the ‘‘power to perceive the bearings of what is known’’ (MW 6:382), it ‘‘is
equivalent to valuation, appraisal, estimation’’ (MW 6:383). To reach judg-
ment one must engage in a process of inquiry. To adequately engage in this
process requires all the habits that can make a character critical, experi-
mental, and able to follow the leads of experience wherever they may go.
When one develops the disposition to apply these thinking tools to moral
experience, it becomes conscientiousness.
The importance of cultivating the more intellectual constituents of
our character is that they make possible a relative control of changes based
on the relations or grain found in experience. The habits of critical reflec-
tion make it possible for us to deliberate over the means to achieve our
ends, as well as the ability to assess our ends in light of our means. The
disposition to think and judge signifies the ability to reconsider and re-
shape present habits—that is, to engage in criticism—thereby preventing
us from resting on our oars and living an unaesthetic moral life. Dewey
explains that ‘‘through judging, we get above the mere routine of habit;
through judging, we get above being mere imitators, copiers, and fol-
lowers of others; through judging we get above caprice, above random
activity’’ (LW 17:338).
the executive
For Dewey, the executive is not like the will, that is, a faculty that moves
the self into action after deliberation. If the self is an agent in process (and
not a spectator), then the will developed in our character cannot simply be
≤≠≤
the ideal moral self
≤≠≥
the ideal moral life
t h e a f f e c t i v e a n d i m a g i n at i v e
The a√ective and imaginative are the areas of moral experience that have
been most devalued and neglected in traditional Western ethics. Dewey
would have agreed with many of today’s feminist writers in ethics who are
reclaiming for the a√ective and imaginative their proper place in our
moral life.∞∞ The a√ective is central to an adequate account of moral
inquiry and of a good moral character. This is evident in the previous
account of sensitivity, openness, and sympathetic imagination as modes of
direct and emotional undergoing in experience. These dispositions under-
lie the function of the a√ective in providing the necessary qualitative
material in inquiry.
The dualism between reason and the emotional or the imaginative, as
well as a narrow view of the latter, have led to views in moral education
and ethics that take emotion and impulse as sources of vices because they
do not allow us to ‘‘look far enough ahead’’ (MW 14:137). But for Dewey,
blindness and narrowness result from a lack of the a√ective and imagina-
tive. To have an a√ective relation with someone or some situation signifies
access and sensitivity to a landscape that would not be available otherwise.
Dewey explains,
We cannot know the varied elements of value in the lives of others and in
the possibilities of our own save as our a√ections are strong. Every
narrowing of love, every encroachment of egoism, means just so much
blindness to the good. (MW 5:379)
≤≠∂
the ideal moral self
guides the entire process of deliberation. Recall that this process relies on
making qualitative judgments, rather than on making deductive infer-
ences from moral axioms or on calculating future pleasures and pains.
Any actual experience of reflection upon conduct will show that every
foreseen result at once stirs our present a√ections. . . . There is developed
a running commentary which stamps objects at once as good or evil. It is
this direct sense of value, not the consciousness of general rules or
ultimate goals, which finally determines the worth of the act to the
agent. (LW 7:275)
Good moral deliberation is one that comes from a good character, and a
good character is one that even in imagination responds with the ‘‘right
emotional stamp’’ (MW 5:255).
What Dewey admired in Greek philosophers is how they stressed
‘‘direct emotional susceptibility to values presented in experience,’’ and
how aesthetic qualities, like rhythm, grace, and balance, were considered
the ‘‘chief instruments’’ to ‘‘create a direct feeling of the beauty of the
good’’ (MW 6:386). All this is lost in most modern educational practices
and theories.
The modern mind has been much less sensitive to aesthetic values in
general and to these values in conduct in particular. Much has been lost
in direct responsiveness to right. The bleakness and harshness often
associated with morals is a sign of this loss. (LW 7:271)
The imaginative is not necessarily the imaginary; that is, the unreal. The
proper function of imagination is vision of realities and possibilities that
cannot be exhibited under existing conditions of sense-perception. Clear
insight into the remote, the absent, the obscure is its aim. (MW 6:355)
≤≠∑
the ideal moral life
its moral worth. Moreover, to be able to reach beyond one’s narrow view
of things and understand others through sympathetic communication
requires imagination, rather than the mere manipulation of information.
Without the development of our imaginative capacities deliberation is
reduced to calculation and a drudgery-filled task. ‘‘The imagination is the
medium of appreciation in every field. The engagement of the imagina-
tion is the only thing that makes any activity more than mechanical’’
(MW 9:244).
The functional classification into constituents of character allows us
to formulate the following thesis found in Dewey: the ideal state is for
these constituents to be in a certain organic relation to one another and as
parts of character in an integral whole. It is only then that the virtues we
have distinguished can in fact function as virtues.
the conclusion is not that the emotional, passionate phase of action can
be or should be eliminated in behalf of a bloodless reason. More ‘‘pas-
sions,’’ not fewer, is the answer. To check the influence of hate there must
≤≠∏
the ideal moral self
≤≠π
the ideal moral life
It is di≈cult to put the quality into words, but we all know the di√erence
between the character which is somewhat hard and formal, and that
which is sympathetic, flexible, and open. In the abstract the former may
be as sincerely devoted to moral ideas as the latter, but as a practical
matter we prefer to live with the latter, and we count upon it to ac-
complish more in the end by tact, by instinctive recognition of the
claims of others, by skill in adjusting, than the former can accomplish by
mere attachment to rules and principles which are intellectually justi-
fied. (EW 5:80)
One final observation about the ideal character is in order. There is hardly
any reference in Dewey’s ethics to many of the dispositions that are usually
considered moral virtues in ethics textbooks, for example, honesty, truth-
fulness, compassion, etc. Instead, one finds a strong and almost exclusive
emphasis on the complex array of habits that allow one to sense, explore,
and find the right course of action in a situation. To be sure, Dewey does
≤≠∫
the ideal moral self
not wish to exclude the usual moral virtues from his account of a good
character. They are not emphasized in his texts because he wanted to
discourage a certain view about moral character. It is often assumed in
moral theory that there is a defined number of virtues that are exclusively
moral, such as honesty and truthfulness, and that the habits that allow us
to explore situations are only intellectual means and therefore non-moral
and external to morality. But this dualism between moral and intellectual
virtue is for Dewey unacceptable. The reason why we tend to associate
moral virtues with such virtues as honesty and truthfulness is because they
play a crucial role in our everyday moral relationships. But, as Dewey said,
to treat these virtues as the moral virtues is ‘‘taking the skeleton for the
living body . . . morals concern nothing less than the whole character’’
(MW 9:367). Furthermore, to take the virtue of intelligence as a mere
external means to a core of moral virtues assumes a primacy and self-
su≈ciency of the latter not warranted by our moral experience. If one has
acquired the habit of honesty, it is because of honest acts. But what counts
as an honest act and when or where it is called for requires the context-
sensitive reflection provided by the habits that Dewey identifies with intel-
ligence. Without the habits required to sense and figure out what I ought to
do in particular moral situations there cannot be the development of mor-
ally well-formed characters. This is why they are the most important in-
strumentalities in moral life. The cardinal virtues are the traits of character
that make it possible to determine what morality requires here and now.
Let me summarize my progression up to this point. My presentation
of Dewey’s ideal began in the previous chapter with a very broad charac-
terization in terms of a way of life. In this chapter I have specified what
sort of character is involved and some of the virtues that it requires. But
Dewey occasionally expresses his normative vision in terms of a certain
kind of self. I now consider that characterization of the self.
≤≠Ω
the ideal moral life
≤∞≠
the ideal moral self
≤∞∞
the ideal moral life
≤∞≤
the ideal moral self
≤∞≥
the ideal moral life
≤∞∂
the ideal moral self
≤∞∑
the ideal moral life
≤∞∏
t w e lv e
Democracy as the Ideal Moral Community
≤∞π
the ideal moral life
Dewey’s concern with character is thus a means and end to the task of
enriching the quality of associations, and both are integral to the more
inclusive goal of ameliorating the quality of present experience. Whereas
in the previous chapter I articulated some of the traits of character needed
for an ideal moral community, in this chapter I am concerned with the
kind of community and communication that is required for an ideal
character to flourish.
Democracy as Experience
It is well known that Dewey objected to the customary but narrow view of
democracy as a political mechanism, and preferred that we shift our atten-
tion to democracy as a way of life or as a form of moral association. But
what does this shift really mean? Most commentators are content to add a
moral dimension to Dewey’s ideal, but ignore the importance of experi-
ence, and in particular, his views of moral experience. My claim is that if
one takes Dewey’s views on democracy as integral to his ethical thought,
then one has to attribute to him a more radical and richer view of democ-
racy than is usually done.
The impoverished quality of present moral experience was the under-
lying concern behind Dewey’s democratic vision. This is the context that
gives Dewey’s ideal its plausibility and function. In fact, the relevance of
Dewey’s ideal today can be attributed to the fact that our society still
su√ers from the same generic ailments that prevent us from having a
better quality of shared experience. When Dewey is read today he sounds
prophetic, for he mentions fragmentation, a lack of unity and variety, a
heterogeneity that leads to isolation, a homogeneity that stifles, polariza-
tion, absolutism, drudgery, relativism, drifting, suppression, consumer-
ism, triviality, superficiality, blind impulse, and impersonality as present
threats to the spirit of democracy. Dewey was a philosopher concerned
more with the problems of a society that is democratic in form, but not in
spirit, rather than with the theoretical problems of democratic theory.
A complete diagnosis of why the current ways of living, even in a soci-
ety that calls itself democratic, are unfulfilling must be pursued on many
fronts. Dewey addressed multiple fronts, including the economic, socio-
logical, and political dimensions of the problems of his era. He warned us
that the hope of a democratic culture could be corrupted by a growing
money culture that subordinates the quality of the present process of living
to some future quantifiable product or end. This is a culture in which the
emphasized value is market value, the only freedom it procures is an
economic one, and the only virtues it encourages are those associated with
≤∞∫
democracy as the ideal moral community
≤∞Ω
the ideal moral life
≤≤≠
democracy as the ideal moral community
positive freedom
≤≤∞
the ideal moral life
This problem is not resolved simply by getting rid of the few that
control opinion. A useful way to understand this condition today is by
≤≤≤
democracy as the ideal moral community
≤≤≥
the ideal moral life
the online world is the freest community in American life. Its members
can do things considered unacceptable elsewhere in our culture. They
can curse freely, challenge the existence of god, explore their sexuality
nearly at will, talk to radical thinkers from all over the world. They can
even commit verbal treason.∑
e q ua l i t y
There are quantitative and legalistic notions of equality that Dewey criti-
cizes as formal or narrow. They are a consequence of the same assumptions
made by visions of democracy centered only on negative freedom. If a
community was composed of atomistic individuals, each with inherent
potentialities requiring the same obstruction-free conditions for develop-
ment, then equality of opportunity would only require the removal of
these same external conditions. On this view, equality also means that at
the very core of every self, in spite of our di√erences, we are all made up of
the same substance. For utilitarians and for those who hold views that cen-
ter on human rights as an original possession, equality means sameness.
Historically, these views are reactions to aristocratic ones that claimed that
some individuals are inherently superior to others. In Dewey’s alternative
view, equality negates fixed hierarchical inequalities while maintaining the
reality of irreducible di√erences among actual individuals.
Dewey’s understanding of equality is based on the uniqueness of each
≤≤∂
democracy as the ideal moral community
person and means that every one in a community can appreciate every
other one beyond a comparative and quantitative scale–type judgment. So
understood, equality does not mean that beyond our classifications and
plurality of identities everyone is alike. Instead, it means that beyond them
there is something irreducible and incommensurable about everyone.
Equality means ‘‘e√ective regard for whatever is distinctive and unique in
each, irrespective of physical and psychological inequalities’’ (MW 12:329–
30). And further: ‘‘Moral equality means incommensurability, the inap-
plicability of common and quantitative standards’’ (MW 13:299).
A community with Dewey’s ideal of equality does not homogenize,
since it takes di√erences as unavoidable and irreducible. Diversity is cele-
brated not just at the level of social groups but at the level of individuals.
Pluralism in Dewey goes all the way down. This appreciation of individu-
ality is a social good. It tends to improve the quality of communications
and relationships. Equality is more than an empty slogan when it operates
as the assumption that no one has an inherent privilege in communica-
tion or can be reduced to the group, class, or culture he or she represents.
Each participant has something unique to contribute and to gain from
participation. William James and John Dewey hoped that the denial of a
privileged universal standpoint by anyone would lead to an appreciation
of the particular and unique location each of us inhabits in experience.
James said: ‘‘Hands o√: neither the whole of truth nor the whole of good is
revealed to any single observer, although each observer gains a partial
superiority of insight from the peculiar position in which he stands. Even
prisons and sick-rooms have their special revelations.’’∏ And equality as
uniqueness must not only be recognized, it must be fostered. A commu-
nity nurtures its own means of improvement when it makes it possible for
everyone to develop their own unique voice. This is more than allowing
everyone to speak.
The shift from democracy as a political system to democracy as experi-
ence means that there is more to equality than legal and institutional
guarantees. It has to go beyond judging others according to some impartial
standard. Equality is an abstract name for something that can be qualita-
tively and directly experienced in our relations with others. We must
appreciate others as individuals who have grown out of unique conditions
and transactions, and also as having unique possibilities for future growth
and development. Democratic respect is not only about how we treat
others (a doing) but also about how we experience them (an undergoing).
It is, in e√ect, the most generous experience we can have of others. In our
deliberations and judgments of others we must be as sensitive as possible to
their unique circumstances. This is the key to democratic generosity.
≤≤∑
the ideal moral life
≤≤∏
democracy as the ideal moral community
f r at e r n i t y
James Gouinlock is not exaggerating when he makes the following claim
about Dewey: ‘‘It would be hard to find a philosopher (I think, in fact, that
there is none) who identified a more profound value in the experience of
intimately associated life.’’∫ This may lead some today to label Dewey a
communitarian, but that word fails to capture the uniqueness of his vi-
≤≤π
the ideal moral life
≤≤∫
democracy as the ideal moral community
tion for the ‘‘Great Community’’ (LW 2:327). Does this mean that he
conceived of local communities as a means to a great one? Furthermore,
how can society on a mass scale ever be a community in any meaningful
sense of the word? The United States, for instance, is simply too big and
diverse to create the sort of community that Dewey hoped for. What is
possible on a small scale may not be on a larger one. These are important
challenges, but they misconstrue what Dewey meant.
Dewey was keenly aware of the limitations posed by size and distance
in relationships. He said, ‘‘The Great Community, in the sense of free
and full communication, is conceivable. But it can never possess all the
qualities that mark a local community. . . . Vital and thorough attachments
are bred only in the intimacy of an intercourse which is of necessity
restricted in range’’ (LW 2:367). Nevertheless, he believed that we are
capable of extending our selves beyond our immediate and intimate rela-
tionships, as in his notion of the wider self, but he never addressed the
issue of how far. But is this a problem for his view? Why must he specify in
advance how far the precious qualities found in the local can be extended
beyond its boundaries? Why is it not su≈cient to say that we must extend
ourselves as far as we possibly can?
Even if Dewey’s Great Community is only conceivable, this is hardly
an excuse for failing to try to extend to whatever degree possible at least a
generic sense of ‘‘we’’, that is, of social unity or communal experience.
Indeed, this seems necessary to have even the weakest form of community
needed for democracy. In order for a pluralistic, scattered, and mobile
public to take charge by regulating the indirect consequences of local
interactions, individuals must extend the reach of their sense of ‘‘we’’
beyond their local group; in other words, one must first experience their
identity as that of the people. This does not mean, however, that we should
expect the Great Community to have the same depth in its a√ective ties as
the local ones; rather, the distinct ‘‘we-ness’’ of the local is irreplaceable.
A further problem with this last objection is that it assumes that the
democratic task is an approximation to a certain ultimate or grandiose
state of a√airs—for example, the Great Community—and that a failure to
obtain it means a failure of the overall task. In Dewey’s ethics, the em-
phasis is, however, on the process. There are no promises about ultimate
outcomes. Whether or not there will ever be such a society is not the
ultimate concern. We must keep striving for it, understanding that a final
realization of that goal is not the point. If it were, we’d surely give up. Our
ideals are nothing more than ends-in-view that can help us improve pres-
ent experience.
A rebuttal to the objection may be that we cannot even speak mean-
≤≤Ω
the ideal moral life
ingfully of a wider sense of ‘‘we’’ in any degree beyond the local. But
whether it can or cannot be done is an empirical issue, that is, of having or
not having the ‘‘we’’ experience. It is clear that Dewey thought that a sense
of ‘‘we’’ could be expanded well beyond our immediate community. In
fact, he even makes reference to the possibility of experiencing oneself as a
citizen of nature. Works of art and our communal bonds can elicit the
religious feeling or quality of belonging to the ‘‘larger, all-inclusive, whole
which is the universe in which we live. . . . This whole is then felt as an
expansion of ourselves [that] we are citizens of this vast world beyond
ourselves’’ (LW 10:199). To become aware of our continuities not only with
others but also with nature had, for Dewey, religious quality. But experi-
encing this sort of natural piety does not require an equal intimacy or
concern for everyone in a Great Community, or that this bigger associa-
tion should be our sole end. It may well be that instead of seeking these
experiences in what is remote and bigger they ‘‘can be found only in the
vital, steady, and deep relationships which are present only in immediate
community’’ (LW 2:368–69). In other words, it is through and by the local
that I can acquire this sense of connection with what is beyond it.
Democracy, just as with the experimental method, must grow out of
but continue to return to what is local. The consequences of e√ective
social reform at the broadest level should be measured ultimately by the
e√ects upon the quality of the experience of individual, concrete relation-
ships. Social institutions should be judged according to the degree to
which they do or do not foster exploitative relationships, and whether
they contributed to the development and qualitative enhancement of as-
sociated living.
Democracy must grow from within, that is, from what is local, spon-
taneous, voluntary, and direct. This includes the neighborhood, family,
classroom, workplace, and grass-roots movements. We may not know
beforehand if the process of democratization can reach as far as the pres-
ent and impersonal political, economic, and intellectual relations of the
wider society, but we must avoid sacrificing the quality of what is had
locally merely for the sake of reach. Our previous discussion about the
ideal wider self made it clear that Dewey is not one to make this sort of
compromise, at least as part of the ideal. The di≈cult balancing task is to
improve our present experience with further depth and intimacy, while
enhancing variety and reach without sacrificing one for the other. This is a
di√erent ideal than that of trying to achieve community on a broad na-
tional scale by any means.
Dewey’s emphasis on the local is not without di≈culties. He often
referred to this as ‘‘face to face intercourse’’ (LW 2:367), but this seems
≤≥≠
democracy as the ideal moral community
outdated and nostalgic today, when people form friendships over the
Internet. The notion of the local needs to be reconstructed in a way that
preserves Dewey’s insight. The functional distinction that Dewey stresses
is between local versus non-local relationships. From a methodological
and metaphysical perspective, the pivotal point of reference of what is
local in Dewey’s philosophy should be clear. The location in which and
from which I live is always a situation. From this shifting place, I philoso-
phize and eat cereal, but it is also where I have di√erent relationships.
Some of them are closer or more distant than others, but there is an
ambiguity about how this is understood. Even if one could make the case
that physical approximation and bodily interaction make relationships
closer and in some ways better, there is no necessary correlation. The dif-
ficulties with using face-to-face interactions as the paradigm are avoided if
we instead contrast our personal relations with our more impersonal and
formal ones.
Dewey’s point is that democracy as a political system stresses these
latter relationships too often, and therefore narrows the time and the
places where democracy is relevant. It puts the emphasis on political
activity performed only every four years (by voting) instead of something
that needs to be worked at every day through our everyday interaction
with each other in contexts such as the classroom, the workplace, and the
living room. Dewey believes that ultimately the most important relation-
ships in our lives are the personal ones.
More has to be done to clear up these conceptual distinctions. Dewey
can be criticized for failing to make some subtle distinctions in his demo-
cratic vision. It is not clear, for example, that the word community is
helpful. Between family and friends, which are usually the most local and
intimate, and our relations with remote groups and institutions, there are
many voluntary groups that vary in size. Today we speak of community of
interest, communities of professionals, and Internet communities. Are
these all communities? Where are we supposed to locate them in the
continuum between friends and the society at large?
Is Dewey guilty of underemphasizing the importance of the wider,
more indirect impersonal associations that we form as membership of a
larger society? Dewey knew that too much emphasis on personal associa-
tions is an excess to be avoided, for it could result in neglect of the wider
social relations and political decisions which might then eventually a√ect
our most personal and direct associations. He was not especially con-
cerned about this possibility simply because he did not perceive this as the
most present danger to American society. However, it is the responsibility
of followers of Dewey to ponder whether things have changed enough to
≤≥∞
the ideal moral life
≤≥≤
democracy as the ideal moral community
≤≥≥
the ideal moral life
≤≥∂
democracy as the ideal moral community
Whatever social and political reforms we need for free and full com-
munication, it is clear that we also require wider selves with the comple-
mentary virtues presented in previous chapters. To rely on some explicitly
formulated rules may sometimes be necessary, but this is a sign of a failure
to habitually experience each other in a more significant way. Communi-
cation is free when tolerance is a central virtue among individuals, but it is
not full unless there are also the receptive dispositions of openness and
sympathy. This last virtue plays an important function.
Sympathy is responsible for the sort of deliberation where partici-
pants take the roles of speaker and listener. It is only when individuals in
communication are able to emotionally and imaginatively take the role of
the other, and be willing to be a√ected by it, that significant learning and
shared experience occurs. What is precious and distinctive about demo-
cratic communication, as George Herbert Mead and Dewey conceived it,
is that the common experience is not based on sameness. As Mead put it:
‘‘A di√erence of functions does not preclude a common experience; it is
possible for the individual to put himself in the place of the other although
his function is di√erent.’’∞≥ The idea that we cannot understand or com-
municate with each other at a deeper level unless we are the same, or that
communication is better when di√erence is removed, is simply false. As an
ideal, democracy is the possibility that individuality and di√erence can
flourish and meet in common experience.
The role of openness in a democratic communication should be ob-
vious. A community of people who are merely tolerant but not open-
minded has built up internal barriers to the fullness of discussion. They
may be able to compromise and bargain, but will not learn from each
other. Democracy requires more than letting others have their say; it also
requires a certain kind of vulnerable but committed participation in a
constant dialogue. Genuine undergoing requires the kind of openness and
receptivity that may a√ect who we are. This is not easy. ‘‘It involves recon-
struction which may be painful’’ (LW 10:48). It takes courage to have a
willingness to be a√ected in this way. This is very di√erent from paying lip
service to others doing their own thing when we are already convinced
that there is nothing important to be learned from them. One must habit-
ually listen with care to the concerns of even those who oppose one’s
views. This is a standard by which we may judge today’s cyberspace com-
munications. Insofar as the Internet as a medium gives the power to
individuals to communicate with like-minded individuals, it is a tool that
can be used against democracy. Communication between parties where
each has as the primordial goal the validation of what they already believe
is superficial (i.e., not full), unfruitful, and dull.
≤≥∑
the ideal moral life
This is not the view that there is a pre-established harmony between these
values, but it does presuppose that there is no dualism that precludes
possible degrees of harmonization. It is based on the possibility that the
values that are associated with individuality can co-exist in a tensive bal-
ance with those associated with community.
≤≥∏
democracy as the ideal moral community
≤≥π
the ideal moral life
mean that they are arbitrary or artificial, but only that they are not radical
or fixed. The pluralist-separatist has chosen to select—exaggerate, in fact—
the di√erences between groups and ignore their continuities. This is an
instance of the fallacy of selective emphasis. However, the obliteration or
denial of such di√erences is not the only alternative to their overemphasis.
Both overemphasis and denial are extreme stances toward di√erence, and
both are mistaken. The mistaken denial of di√erence, for example, is
evident in the sort of universalism that denies di√erences by postulating a
human essence, or in the ideal of melting all of our di√erences together.
When di√erences are exaggerated and not conceived as a matter of de-
gree they contribute to isolation, exclusivity, and (possibly) racism.∞∂
The democratic ideal entails that we should transform di√erences from
sources of friction to sources of enrichment. And for this we need to
develop characters with suitable dispositions (e.g., open-mindedness and
sympathy) that welcome and are nurtured by what is experienced as new
and di√erent.
Di√erences and continuities each have di√erent functions in an ideal
community. Individuals and groups should be encouraged to be di√erent
because this contributes to the whole. It adds the variety needed to work
against both boredom and an atmosphere of suppression. General unifor-
mity or homogeneity produces stability but one that leads to fixity and
mechanical interaction. On the other hand, a celebration of diversity that
forbids interaction, sympathy, the making of connections, and the explo-
ration of commonalities seems to rule out any basis for a sense of ‘‘we.’’ It
is also a waste of resources since only in interaction are potentialities
discovered and developed. We can avoid separatism and homogeneity by
maintaining a balance between emphasizing our di√erences and our con-
tinuities. A pluralistic community that incorporates this in its daily com-
munication nurtures itself with di√erences and change, and at the same
time experiences a common life. The stability procured is rhythmic and
developing. It has the dynamic variation within balance that for Dewey
characterizes great works of art.
In general, one of the most di≈cult balancing acts in a democracy is
to know when and in what proportion di√erences among individuals or
groups obstruct democratic communication. Deficiency and excess in, for
example, social di√erences such as economic class and knowledge tend to
a√ect the quality of communication. Insu≈cient variety often results in
stagnation, homogeneity, and a lack of creative tension in the relation-
ships. But too much variety or too many di√erences can also undermine
the possibility of having mutually enriching democratic communication.
It may result in an undesirable power relation where it is impossible to
≤≥∫
democracy as the ideal moral community
≤≥Ω
the ideal moral life
≤∂≠
democracy as the ideal moral community
≤∂∞
the ideal moral life
≤∂≤
democracy as the ideal moral community
≤∂≥
the ideal moral life
≤∂∂
democracy as the ideal moral community
imagines is one who genuinely cares about morality and has the virtues
integral to communal inquiry and learning. In other words, he must be
open and willing to accept that the burden of proof is upon him. Dewey
explains,
On the other hand, Dewey is fully aware that one of the problems with
developing a democracy is that ‘‘the majority is always hostile to permit-
ting a minority to develop ideas which are opposed to its own’’ (LW 7:362);
therefore, ‘‘If patience, cheerfulness, freedom from conceit, self-display
and self-pity are demanded of the moral non-conformist, there is a cor-
relative duty imposed upon conformists: namely the duty of toleration’’
(LW 7:231). For Dewey, the continued vitality of communal inquiry re-
quires a ‘‘creative tension’’∞∫ between its participants, rather than the har-
mony that comes from the consensus of homogeneity. This tension may
require a diversification of the functions or roles among the participants.
The function of the conservative is to stand on precedent or on what
is generally accepted, whereas the radical is more critical and open to
change; but what brings everyone together is the ‘‘positive willingness to
permit reflection and inquiry, to go in the faith that the truly right will
be rendered more secure through questioning and discussion’’ (LW 7:231).
Moreover, one could generalize and claim that the important function of
the individual in communal inquiry is usually to provide the novelty
and experimentation, while communal bonds provide the needed stabil-
ity. As James once said: ‘‘The community stagnates without the impulse
of the individual. The impulse dies away without the sympathy of the
community.’’∞Ω
The rigidity and solidity of a community that is not open to change
usually results either in maintaining the stability by repression and con-
finement that ultimately does not work, or it leads eventually to such a
violent enthusiasm for the new as to encourage complete rupture from
previous experience. To maintain a community that is both faithful to
tradition and experimentation is a never-ending challenge. For new expe-
riences that result from open and wide communication are often per-
ceived as a threat to the traditional beliefs and accepted code that form the
≤∂∑
the ideal moral life
≤∂∏
democracy as the ideal moral community
Democracy as a Task
If believing in democracy is just a matter of accepting some theory, then it
seems as if the inherent tensions projected in the ideal of democracy
present a serious challenge to its reasonableness. John Patrick Diggins
observes that ‘‘democracy is too full of tensions and contradictions to be
subsumed under logical formulas . . . if there is a logic to democracy, it is
the logic of contradiction.’’≤≠ But Dewey stressed that part of what is meant
by calling democracy a moral ideal is that it is an endeavor, part of a
program of work, rather than a theory or something already given and
ready-made.
Democracy as a way of life means that one takes on the task of work-
ing out and ameliorating actual tensions that are integral to democracy’s
ideal in concrete and particular situations; it is not a matter of proving its
coherence or validity at the abstract level of ideas. In a democracy we want
things that, although necessary for meaning and quality of life, do not
automatically reinforce each other. History does not prove the futility of
our democratic hopes, but it does teach us that the built-in values of
democracy contain tensions that are not easily reconciled. Dewey ex-
plains, for example,
≤∂π
the ideal moral life
The di≈culty of the democratic endeavor lies in the fact that the risk
of imbalances is constant as new conditions require adjustments. Balance
is not guaranteed by the simple addition or subtraction of the elements in
tension. Moreover, the values that are supposed to be balanced are not
antecedently given. We have seen that freedom and equality, for instance,
require appropriate conditions and concerted e√ort for their emergence.
Democracy as a task also means that, beyond merely theorizing about
the coherence or philosophical foundations of the ideal, intellectual work
is needed to spell out what contemporary problems it entails in light of
present conditions. This is why Dewey insists that democracy as an ideal
‘‘poses, rather than solves’’ (LW 7:350) problems. For example, what con-
ditions are needed at a particular time to sustain a stable community
capable of readjusting or reexamining the habits and principles inherited
from previous experience? Although this must be left to a specific inquiry
of the particular case, one can speculate about some general conditions. It
seems necessary to have in the community the proper means to pass along
and reinforce the valuable habits, traditions, and lessons of experience.
Hence, communal bonds and rituals must be strong. On the other hand,
for a community to remain experimental and self-corrective, it must not
take any policy as final nor exclude anyone’s interest from continued
consideration. It would be the kind of community that secures a flexible
readjustment of its institutions and rituals, not for change’s own sake, but
because change is inevitable and the demand for remaking old habits and
institutions is recurrent. This presupposes the operation of some of the
virtues I have outlined.
Another problem posed by democracy as an ideal is how we achieve,
in light of present conditions, a way of life where there is an organic and
nurturing relation between all individuals and the social wholes (relation-
ships, institutions) to which they belong. Dewey describes this as ‘‘a postu-
late in the sense of a demand to be realized: That each individual shall have
the opportunity for release, expression, fulfillment, of his distinctive ca-
pacities, and that the outcome shall further the establishment of a fund of
shared values’’ (LW 7:350). There are no easy formulas or guarantees that
we can get close to the balance described. Neither is this something to be
achieved once and for all, nor is this the point of the endeavor. Working
for balance requires the constant meeting and solving of new and unfore-
seen problems in particular situations. Even if all goes well in a democracy,
we cannot rely solely on our past accomplishments because ‘‘the condi-
tions and the concrete significance of liberty, of equality, of mutual re-
spect, and reciprocal service, change from generation to generation, in
some degree from year to year’’ (LW 7:350).
≤∂∫
democracy as the ideal moral community
≤∂Ω
the ideal moral life
universal and fixed ideal. By making community values the only and final
aim, we may fall into the opposite extreme. We tend to fall easily into
this pattern of compensation (i.e. alternating between extremes) because,
under the experience of an extreme, the contrary excess seems desirable.
Dewey hoped we could do better. We can try instead to maintain rhythmic
variation within a balanced relation to a particular context, where the
danger of extremes (because of tensions) is always present. This requires
that we become sensitive to imbalances and that we be willing to experi-
ment in trying to reconcile tendencies that seem to lead us in di√erent
directions. More importantly, even if we succeed in our endeavor, we must
be humble and accept the vulnerability of the balance to the contingencies
of experience. The easiest task and temptation is to take an extreme.
Extremes are appealing because they seem simple and final solutions to
problems that require persistence and context-sensitive reflection. Since
they are easily noticed, they seem to represent a position of strength. But
Dewey argues otherwise. It is when we live under an extreme that we are
the most vulnerable and when we are more likely to compensate by shift-
ing to the opposite extreme.
For the democratic task, we are going to need a lot of imagination,
especially since we are living in a time of cynicism with much ‘‘disillusion-
ment about all comprehensive and positive ideas’’ (LW 5:277). In order to
be able to envision the goals of freedom and equality in balance with
fraternity, we need to give up not only dualisms but also the competi-
tive market metaphors that underlie political rhetoric about freedom and
equality. One of these is the notion that the ideal society takes place in a
field where everyone has the same capacities and freedom to run a com-
petitive race. Westbrook has suggested that we should instead think of a
basketball team as the appropriate metaphor of the type of communal
association needed for democracy. For ‘‘the game calls upon players to
develop some common skills and virtues while at the same time specializ-
ing in some of each in accordance with individual talents and desires and
to coordinate these talents with other members of the team to advance
common goals.’’≤≤ I would suggest that an even better metaphor is jazz.
This is usually the sort of music where an organic relation between inter-
action, common goals, and individuality is cherished. It is the type of
music that often achieves a balance between stable elements (perhaps in
melody, harmonies, or rhythm) and more precarious ones (in experimen-
tation or improvisation). Here is how jazz pianist Brad Mehldau describes
what should happen in a jazz trio setting: ‘‘Improvisation takes place
not only in performance but in the way the band develops. There is a
≤∑≠
democracy as the ideal moral community
d e w e y a n d d e l i b e r at i v e d e m o c r a c y
In recent years, political theory and socio-political philosophy has experi-
enced what has been called a deliberative turn. Many of the members of
this movement have proclaimed John Dewey as a predecessor, an influ-
ence, or as a founding father of deliberative democracy.≤∂ There is no
doubt that deliberative democratic thinkers share with Dewey the concern
that the quality of deliberation in political democracies continues to dete-
riorate. Moreover, they share the concern that traditional liberal theory
has neglected the importance of public deliberation. Democracy is in need
of rehabilitation through an emphasis on a more robust notion of demo-
cratic deliberation. Communal deliberation and judgment can be more
than the aggregation of private preferences, or the competition among
fixed preferences and standpoints. Deliberative political theorists have
argued, as Dewey did, for the power of dialogue to transform the prefer-
ences and views of participants. However, in examining the recent deliber-
≤∑∞
the ideal moral life
≤∑≤
democracy as the ideal moral community
≤∑≥
the ideal moral life
≤∑∂
democracy as the ideal moral community
d e w e y a n d t h e ‘‘o n e - v e r s u s - m a n y’’ d e b at e s
i n p o l i t i c a l t h e o ry
A fair and productive use of Dewey today must also keep a critical eye
on how many of the debates in political theory are centered on the same
false dichotomies that he criticized in his ethics. One such debate is that
between forms of individualism and collectivism, but there is also the
one-versus-many debate that has made its way into democratic theory
around two interdependent issues: how much unity do we actually find in
moral life? And, how much unity and pluralism can one be justified in
prescribing?
Ever since John Rawls’s A Theory of Justice it has become common to
adopt, as the starting point of democratic theory, the existence of compet-
ing visions of the good life. Many thinkers take this pluralism about the
good as a fact and as the starting point of democratic theory. As delibera-
tivists see it, the only normative task or challenge for democratic theory is
how to bring more unity in the form of a unified conception of public
reason, or an impartial standpoint upon which we can build some con-
sensus about legitimate reasons or rules. From the standpoint of these
pluralistic philosophers the concept of deliberation advanced by commu-
nitarians is suspect because the communitarians tend to assume a wide-
spread moral agreement or shared moral vision about the good that does
not exist. Communitarians take that kind of unity in moral life as a fact,
but for other philosophers what needs to be taken as a fact is a radical
pluralism among conceptions of the good. From Dewey’s perspective this
debate is based on serious misconceptions about moral life.
First, why is morality reduced to either a unified conception of the
good life or a homogenizing conception of right? Dewey would question
the tendency in political theory to oversimplify our moral life by sub-
suming or unifying it under one simple category. Just as in ethics, the
≤∑∑
the ideal moral life
≤∑∏
democracy as the ideal moral community
≤∑π
the ideal moral life
≤∑∫
democracy as the ideal moral community
supreme. In other words, the discussion is among thinkers who, at the end
of the day, believe in the same ideal. Unity and plurality, and their corre-
sponding values, are key to democracy. Community, cooperation, iden-
tity, loyalty, and solidarity are among the things that provide unity to
democracy. Individuality, di√erence, tolerance, and independence pro-
vide plurality to democracy. There is no pre-established harmony between
these values, and whether one side should be emphasized over the other is
a context-based issue. The tension between the values of democracy makes
it something fragile and in need of our intelligence, but not in need of a
final theoretical answer or resolution. Contemporary political theorists
could better spend their energies if they would recognize the context-
bound nature of their prescriptions toward either more unity or plurality.
Their disagreements may be more about the present state of a√airs than
about the ideal. There are those who believe that the present lack of
community is the problem of our democracy, whereas others believe that
the problem lies elsewhere. The calls for more unity and for more plurality
are integral parts of democracy, but one call in a particular situation may
be more important than the other based on the conditions at that particu-
lar time.
More work needs to be done in order to fairly and fully engage Dew-
ey’s views with those of contemporary political theorists. My goal here is
simply to suggest that such a dialogue is not possible, or is impoverished,
if it does not confront the most basic assumptions about moral life. I
claimed earlier that in trying to place Dewey in the context of the contem-
porary debates in ethical theory, one runs the risk of making him com-
plicit in assumptions he sought to override. This is also true in regard to
political theory. What is most promising about Dewey’s political philoso-
phy is that it proposes a way to move beyond the family quarrels between
democratic theories because of a di√erent starting point and metaphysics
of ethics. Dewey’s political theory may in the end prove inadequate, but
unless we try to understand it from the point of view of his entire philoso-
phy, and in particular his ethics, we may fail to consider how radical is his
view in comparison to many democratic political theorists.
≤∑Ω
thirteen
A Philosophical Justification of Democracy
≤∏≠
a p h i l o s o p h i c a l j u s t i f i c at i o n o f d e m o c r a c y
matist must abandon, once and for all, the notion that she can provide a
philosophical justification for democracy or any other particular way of
life. ‘‘There is no ahistorical standpoint from which to endorse the habits
of modern democracies he wishes to praise,’’∞ Rorty claims, and there is no
‘‘demonstration of the ‘objective’ superiority of our way of life over all
other alternatives.’’≤
Unwillingness to accept Rorty’s resolution has recently sparked an
interest in reformulating Dewey’s intellectual warrant for democracy. The
problem with these attempts is that they often seem more eager to answer
Rorty than to understand Dewey’s philosophy on its own terms. It is not
surprising, then, that in many of these reformulations Dewey ends up
begging the question or o√ering an embarrassingly circular justification.
According to David Fott, for example, Dewey runs into the di≈culty of
justifying science or the assumed historical relativism without going in
circles. He finds in Dewey ‘‘an odd defense of democracy,’’≥ for there is no
‘‘clear final point for his defense of democracy.’’∂ Fott is puzzled about the
validity of Dewey’s metaphysical and normative claims because he makes a
common mistake among scholars: he wants to believe that at the heart of
Dewey’s philosophy there is some truth, proposition, or theoretical thesis
from which we can derive, explain, and examine the rest of his thought.
And, of course, once one has presumably identified that first thesis for
Dewey, one is faced with a dogma or finds oneself unable to defend him
against the charge of begging the question. Meanwhile, Dewey’s remarks
about doing philosophy by starting with experience and making the entire
enterprise hypothetical are either ignored or reduced to the ludicrous
claim that philosophy must bow to science or to its truths. Dewey did not
presuppose what he set out to prove simply because he did not set out to
prove anything, at least in the traditional sense of searching for premises
by which anyone may be able to deductively derive a conclusion. This is a
view of justification sharply at odds with Dewey’s philosophy.
Even more sympathetic scholars, like Matthew Festenstein, are dis-
appointed by the incomplete character of Dewey’s justification of democ-
racy.∑ According to him, Dewey may have an adequate answer to the
skeptical threat against democracy, but it is not clear that Dewey has a
response to the relativist challenge that confronts neopragmatists today.
Festenstein is right only if it is assumed that any reasonable justification
must answer the challenges of an imaginary radical skeptic or relativist.
But this requirement for justification, like those which require an appeal
to certain first axioms or an ahistorical objective standpoint, presumes a
starting point of philosophical investigation that is not Dewey’s.
Philosophical inquiry is invariably and inevitably enmeshed in a par-
≤∏∞
the ideal moral life
I take the so-called ‘‘linguistic turn’’ in recent philosophy and the lin-
guistic and cultural relativism which has lately been spawned by certain
so-called ‘‘Post-Modernists’’ to be in fact the last and dying gasp of
≤∏≤
a p h i l o s o p h i c a l j u s t i f i c at i o n o f d e m o c r a c y
≤∏≥
the ideal moral life
a precarious and changing world that we form and rely on ideals. If all
experiences were of equal worth or if there were not a need to try to secure
and reproduce the best of our experiences, then ideals would not have a
function. ‘‘Because of this mixture of the regular and that which cuts
across stability, a good object once experienced acquires ideal quality and
attracts demand and e√ort to itself ’’ (LW 1:57). Ideals are experienced as
imaginative projections of possibilities based on goods actually experi-
enced. Democracy is not only based on but goes beyond the goods of
associated life in the sense that it is an appreciation of its richest possibili-
ties. These possibilities are not subjective or fictitious. In Dewey’s ethics
discovery and imagination, inquiry into actual conditions, and the explo-
ration of possibilities are mutually dependent phases of inquiry about
betterment. He explains this process:
We know that some methods of inquiry are better than others in just the
same way in which we know that some methods of surgery, farming,
road-making, navigating or what-not are better than others. It does not
follow in any of these cases that the ‘‘better’’ methods are ideally perfect,
≤∏∂
a p h i l o s o p h i c a l j u s t i f i c at i o n o f d e m o c r a c y
≤∏∑
the ideal moral life
≤∏∏
a p h i l o s o p h i c a l j u s t i f i c at i o n o f d e m o c r a c y
≤∏π
the ideal moral life
ence in all its uncertainty, mystery, doubt, and half-knowledge and turns
that experience upon itself to deepen and intensify its own qualities’’
(LW 10:41). Pluralism of beliefs, religions, cultures, and social groups is
increasingly an unquestionable trait of present experience. In a world
where interaction is becoming unavoidable and even necessary, isolation
and segregation are no longer ways to successfully cope with pluralism. We
can respond to pluralism by trying to remove it, either by force, indoc-
trination, or by constructing a philosophical theory that explains the
unfortunate pluralism as mere appearance or a result of human limita-
tions. These responses assume that a pluralism of beliefs is merely an early
stage on the way to later convergence or, perhaps, a fall from grace. For
pragmatists, on the other hand, the plurality of views that are deeply
believed is a positive characteristic of the human condition, rather than
something to lament. For pluralism is not only the irreducible charac-
ter of reality but a source of possible enrichment. Participation, com-
munication, and sharing in a pluralistic environment can make life rich
and varied in meanings. ‘‘To cooperate by giving di√erences a chance to
show themselves because of the belief that the expression of di√erence is
not only a right of the other persons but is a means of enriching one’s
own life-experience, is inherent in the democratic personal way of life’’
(LW 14:228).
Dewey believes that the ideals of liberty, equality, and freedom are
more meaningful or congenial to the pragmatist conception of experience
than to traditional metaphysics. Our liberty is more meaningful if we are
participants (instead of spectators) in a universe that is a genuine field of
experimentation, novelty, and constantly in the making.
≤∏∫
a p h i l o s o p h i c a l j u s t i f i c at i o n o f d e m o c r a c y
for itself and demands consideration on its own behalf ’’ (MW 11:53). A
metaphysics of democracy based on the notion of everyone having the
same rights cannot elicit the same democratic respect for one another that
comes from recognizing that there is something irreplaceable about each
one of us in every new moment in the flow of experience.
However, individuality is not something that develops or that can be
appreciated independently of association and interaction. Hence, an indi-
vidualism that is not atomistic is the metaphysical basis for fraternity as an
ideal of democracy.
To say that what is specific and unique can be exhibited and become
forceful or actual only in relationship with other like beings is merely, I
take it, to give a metaphysical version to the fact that democracy is
concerned not with freaks or geniuses or heroes or divine leaders but
with associated individuals in which each by intercourse with others
somehow makes the life of each more distinctive. (MW 11:53)
≤∏Ω
the ideal moral life
to function as an ideal. This explains why Dewey can say that democracy
‘‘is not a fact and never will be’’ (LW 2:328).
Ideals are experienced as ends-in-view that interact with the world
and have a practical function. We could thus ask about any ideal: Is it
constructive or is it counterproductive and self-defeating? Does it provide
orientation, inspiration, and carry us through tough times? Does it guide
action or make our individual struggles more meaningful? Does it posi-
tively provoke our imaginations in the sense of eliciting possibilities that
may not be appreciated or explored otherwise? These are all important
questions that would have to be considered in a full evaluation of democ-
racy as an ideal. For now I would like to focus on one important aspect of a
useful ideal according to Dewey’s ethics.
A constructive ideal must assist in transforming, guiding, and inspir-
ing but it must itself be open to improvement in light of present experi-
ence. This requires that an ideal be ‘‘su≈ciently definite to be usable and
su≈ciently flexible to lead to its own reinterpretation as experience pro-
gresses’’ (LW 7:344). Dewey was aware that both excess generality and
specificity in the formulation of an ideal tend to be counterproductive. He
was, on the one hand, concerned that the ideal of a democratic way of life
not remain an idle tool by becoming a vague abstraction. We must do
better than regurgitate the political slogans associated with democracy.
The ideal ‘‘must not remain vague and general. It must be translated into
the concrete details of what it means in every walk of life’’ (LW 11:237). On
the other hand, he was keenly aware that too much specificity can work
against the e√ectiveness of an ideal. As we saw earlier, Dewey thought that
ethical theory can betray its practical function if it abandons its generic
character and pretends to provide specific instructions. In order to serve
as an e√ective instrument of criticism without undermining context-sen-
sitive reflection, democracy as an ideal must be ‘‘stated in such a way that it
will apply to changed conditions of the present and the future’’ (LW 7:343).
This last point is relevant to evaluating an objection to Dewey that has
been reconsidered by Robert Westbrook and Michael Eldridge. They find
it problematic that, as Eldridge puts it, Dewey did not specify ‘‘ ‘in the
concrete’ the political means to e√ect the democratic ends.’’∞≤ He failed to
flesh out the details of his democratic vision. But how much more thick-
ness could be added to his ideal before it becomes counterproductive? I
am suggesting that the generality and vagueness of Dewey’s views about
democracy are strengths not weaknesses of his position. Dewey was a
committed contextualist and the lack of a more detailed vision is what
allows us today to develop the specifics as they pertain to our present
experience without abandoning Dewey’s vision. Had he, for example,
≤π≠
a p h i l o s o p h i c a l j u s t i f i c at i o n o f d e m o c r a c y
≤π∞
the ideal moral life
To foster conditions that widen the horizon of others and give them
command of their own powers, so that they can find their own happi-
ness in their own fashion, is the way of ‘‘social’’ action. Otherwise the
prayer of a freeman would be to be left alone, and to be delivered, above
all, from ‘‘reformers’’ and ‘‘kind’’ people. (MW 14:203)
≤π≤
a p h i l o s o p h i c a l j u s t i f i c at i o n o f d e m o c r a c y
does not foster the positive freedom needed for democratic interaction.
It takes great e√ort and communal resources to foster individuals and
communities capable of working out the problems they experience for
themselves.
Although we cannot export or impose democracy, we can provide or
prepare the soil in which the flower of democracy may gradually emerge.
There are some interesting implications and complications of this impor-
tant insight. First, there is the question of who is the ‘‘we’’ that fosters the
conditions for the emergence of democracy. Can it ever be someone from
outside the community in question? Furthermore, at what point can the
control over indirect conditions ruin the spontaneous emergence of what
is wanted? This is especially troublesome when one aims to restore or
revitalize the sort of relationships and genuine communities for which
Dewey hoped. They cannot be engineered or created the way one con-
structs a bridge or fixes a pipe. Since community is usually associated with
stability in experience it is easy to overlook the importance of contingency,
novelty, and spontaneity in the creation, sustenance, and quality of a
community. This becomes clear in examining the recent attempt to build
gated communities. The gates, rules, and homogeneity of these commu-
nities provide the comfort of a controlled, secured, predictable, and safe
environment but at the cost of sterility, boredom, and the unaesthetic. The
retreat into gated communities is a flight from chance. The price for
security is an environment with no surprises, where an unplanned and
enriching conversation with a person unlike oneself is ruled out. Dewey, of
course, would be opposed to this sort of community, but it is not clear
how a more intelligent and flexible Deweyan e√ort to create community is
not vulnerable to the same sort of problem. A Deweyan project to in-
directly control the conditions for the emergence of a community may
run into the problem of determining when its intervention is spoiling the
needed chance and spontaneity for a community to emerge. This being
said, it does not mean that the way of intelligence is to leave things alone. I
can think of no solution to this di≈culty except to hope that, equipped
with the habits of intelligence, we will be able to determine in a particular
case when we have reached that critical point where even indirect control
is too much. The emergence of a genuine community is in some ways a
more delicate matter than that of a flower. But just as with the flower, even
if we do what is in our power we must come to terms with the fact that it
many never blossom. This is all Deweyan in spirit.
Perhaps a more promising way of inquiring about conditions in the
name of democracy can take the negative form of answering the ques-
tion: What feature of present conditions is an obstacle to having more
≤π≥
the ideal moral life
≤π∂
a p h i l o s o p h i c a l j u s t i f i c at i o n o f d e m o c r a c y
≤π∑
the ideal moral life
And yet what was my own astonishment, on emerging into the dark and
wicked world again, to catch myself quite unexpectedly and involun-
tarily saying: ‘‘Ouf ! What a relief ! Now for something primordial and
savage, even though it were as bad as an Armenian massacre, to set the
balance straight again. This order is too tame, this culture too second-
rate, this goodness too uninspiring . . . this city simmering in the tepid
lakeside sun; this atrocious harmlessness of all things,—I cannot abide
with them. Let me take my chances again in the big outside worldly
wilderness with all its sins and su√erings . . .’’∞∏
≤π∏
a p h i l o s o p h i c a l j u s t i f i c at i o n o f d e m o c r a c y
≤ππ
the ideal moral life
≤π∫
a p h i l o s o p h i c a l j u s t i f i c at i o n o f d e m o c r a c y
≤πΩ
the ideal moral life
≤∫≠
a p h i l o s o p h i c a l j u s t i f i c at i o n o f d e m o c r a c y
there will always be a lesson or that the lessons are already there in some
sense. Rather, it presupposes that we may learn while acknowledging that
‘‘control or power is never complete; luck or fortune, the propitious sup-
port of circumstances not foreseeable is always involved’’ (LW 3:105).
A di√erent charge of naïveté can be raised against Dewey. He was not
naïve about our limitations but rather about the dangers of the drive to
control and ameliorate present conditions. Even if Dewey was sensitive to
the tragic, his meliorism is an intellectual justification for the drive to
improve that can go against certain more passive but important attitudes
toward people and events. Dewey’s faith in the instrumentalities of experi-
ence should have been tempered by recognition of what positive value
there is to accepting things as they come. There is in life a time to amelio-
rate our contingent circumstances, but there is also a time to accept them,
not in a grudgingly or stoical way, but in a loving way.
This is an issue that has come up in regard to technology in its
seemingly endless capacity to improve our lives. In a recent article, Mi-
chael Sandel argues that what is troubling about designer children, bionic
athletes, and genetic engineering is that this kind of meliorism represents
‘‘a kind of hyperagency—a Promethean aspiration to remake nature, in-
cluding human nature, to serve our purposes and satisfy our desires. The
problem is not the drift to mechanism but the drive to mastery. And what
the drive to mastery misses and may even destroy is an appreciation of the
gifted character of human powers and achievements.’’≤∏ The ethics of en-
hancement raises ‘‘questions about the moral status of nature, and about
the proper stance of human beings toward the given world.’’≤π
If we can become better human beings and communities by genetic
engineering, should we? Is that what Dewey’s melioristic ethics implies? Is
there in Dewey an acknowledgment of the attitude Sandel thinks is threat-
ened by the new developments in technology?
Dewey has been called an instrumentalist but he was aware of the
dangers of too much mastery or excessive doing.≤∫ I have argued that for
him activity with aesthetic quality (as a balanced relation between doing
and undergoing) is the paradigmatic form of activity. Beholding, savor-
ing, accepting, and celebrating the given world does not have to be incom-
patible with molding, transforming, and perfecting it, even if there is a
tension and risks corresponding to doing each of these things in isolation
or to the extreme. The di≈cult balance between a transforming love and
an accepting love, between molding our children and accepting their indi-
viduality, is true of all democratic relationships. The parents to be ad-
mired are not those who are willing to improve their children by whatever
means and to whatever the extent. Dewey addressed these issues with
≤∫∞
the ideal moral life
≤∫≤
a p h i l o s o p h i c a l j u s t i f i c at i o n o f d e m o c r a c y
In sum, there is in Dewey’s ethics some basis to warn us about the dangers
of technological enhancement as a general practice. It can erode an atti-
tude toward the world that is part of the sort of balanced engagement that
I have articulated in this book. The road toward perfectionism is the road
to the sort of stability and harmony that is non-aesthetic. The contingency
of our talents, fortunes, as well as of our bad circumstances are for Dewey
the grounds of democratic solidarity. I said earlier that the ultimate glue in
Dewey’s view is a faith in experience or nature, one that is felt as the
notion that ‘‘everything that’s here is here, and you can just lie back on
it.’’≤Ω There is an active and a more passive side to this faith. You can lie
back on experience by trusting its potentialities that may be released with
≤∫≥
the ideal moral life
our intervention, but it is also important to lie back in the sense of accept-
ing the grain of experience and a≈rming what it brings even if it is not in
line with our wishes.
Of course, this does not answer the di≈cult questions. At what point
does our capacity for mastery with the developments of new enhancement
technology lead to the sort of unbalanced control where we have removed
too much contingency, novelty, surprise, gifts, and uniqueness from our
everyday lives? Dewey does not say, and given his contextualism, he would
be skeptical of any philosophical attempt to fix this line a priori. Fur-
thermore, slippery-slope-type arguments would not convince Dewey to
set absolute limits to enhancement technologies; rather, he would likely
eschew line drawing and assume the risks of such technologies in the
name of trying to maintain a context-sensitive balance. Nevertheless, the
danger is there and if it is true that today we are on the verge of too much
mastery, then Deweyans today should be more resistant or watchful about
the e√ects of technology in this regard than Dewey was.
≤∫∂
a p h i l o s o p h i c a l j u s t i f i c at i o n o f d e m o c r a c y
≤∫∑
the ideal moral life
is it not the reason for our preference that we believe that mutual con-
sultation and convictions reached through persuasion, make possible a
better quality of experience than can otherwise be provided on any wide
scale? . . . I do not see how we can justify our preference for democracy
and humanity on any other ground. (LW 13:18)
≤∫∏
a p h i l o s o p h i c a l j u s t i f i c at i o n o f d e m o c r a c y
≤∫π
the ideal moral life
≤∫∫
a p h i l o s o p h i c a l j u s t i f i c at i o n o f d e m o c r a c y
that knowledge (in the form of rules or criteria) is prior to experience; this
is an instance of the intellectualist fallacy.
The empirical attitude that certain interactions are better because
they are experienced as such is not an appeal to intuition or to the view
that it is good simply because one says so. Recall that Dewey’s method is
one of trusting immediate experience without closing the door to further
inquiry. The need for criticism and communal inquiry about value is
recurrent in a changing world where we are aware of the possible narrow-
ness and limitations of our own experiences. What may be experienced
initially as good may not be experienced that way upon further dialogue,
reflection, judgment, and experience. About our most direct personal
experiences, Dewey admits that they can be restricted, one-sided, and
perverted but the ‘‘remedy, however, is not divorce of thought from the
intimacies of the direct contacts and intercourses of life, but a supplemen-
tation of limitations and a correction of biases through acquaintance with
the experience of others’’ (LW 6:21).
Dewey denied that there is a single universal standard or criterion of
value, but he did not think that it follows that there is no basis for criticism
or reasonableness, nor that one must abandon the need to provide reasons
or support for our judgments. Reasons and arguments are important for
reasonableness; they are arrived at in the process of critically reexamining
judgments and commitments, and they play a role in further inquiry. But
their mere formulation is no substitute for personal judgment based on
experience. The variety of reasons presented in favor of democracy may
lead others, who hold similar commitments, to test certain hypotheses
and to reach similar judgments about the value and promise of democ-
racy. You can guide but not reason someone into having the experiences
that can validate democracy. And even in the best of circumstances, there
is ‘‘no assurance that any one will so act as to have the experience. The
horse led to water is not forced to drink’’ (LW 14:31). According to Dewey’s
denotative method, the empirical philosopher must provide arguments,
but she should also guide others (through descriptions and other means)
to have the experiences that may confirm their hypotheses.
Dewey’s critics and sympathizers, however, continue to presuppose
that Dewey’s politics is grounded in Dewey’s ethics because in the lat-
ter one finds the ultimate criterion of all value judgments. They presup-
pose that for Dewey self-realization, human fulfillment, or growth are the
goods ultimately served by democracy.≥∑ It is hard to deny that Dewey was
to some extent concerned with all of these goods, but to assume that any of
them is the underlying and final telos is to fail to do justice to the radically
pluralistic and contextualist view of Dewey’s mature ethical thought and
≤∫Ω
the ideal moral life
≤Ω≠
a p h i l o s o p h i c a l j u s t i f i c at i o n o f d e m o c r a c y
means, but neither are goals or ideals taken as mere ends. Mastery over
means of execution and enthusiasm for wider aims and ideals should
supplement each other. In other words, the democrat needs to adopt the
‘‘genuine interest’’ in an ideal typical of the artist. The ideal democrat
experiences each e√ort on behalf of democracy in the same way that the
sculptor experiences each stroke of the chisel.
Each molding of the clay . . . is at the time the whole end in process of
realization. Whatever interest or value attaches to the end attaches to
each of these steps. He is as much absorbed in one as in the other. . . . A
genuine interest in the ideal indicates of necessity an equal interest in all
the conditions of its expression. (EW 5:128)
≤Ω∞
the ideal moral life
as we do with our clothes, but just because we cannot stand outside our
ways of life to make side-by-side comparisons does not mean that we can
never know whether we are improving or whether changes are needed in
our lives. About growth or progress Dewey says, ‘‘. . . if it cannot be told by
qualities belonging to the moment of transition it can never be judged’’
(MW 14:195).
Dewey turns the fact that we cannot stand outside of our situatedness
into a positive resource, rather than a reason to abandon all objectivity. If
we were to appreciate the guiding force of reflection based on a unique
and pervasive quality of each problematic situation, we would find absurd
the need for antecedent knowledge of the good life or some outside stand-
point to know whether or not we are doing well. As Dewey said,
It is in and because of the felt intolerance and the superficial and mechani-
cal aspects of our relations and discussions that we seek to democratize
our experience. In the process of transforming these situations of conflict,
entanglement, and obscurity, we need to rely on the sense of relevance and
guidance found in the concrete situations where these problems are felt.
We do in fact judge better from worse when guided by the same qualitative
context that raises the issue, and we do this without the need for a God’s-
eye point of view. If Dewey’s view seems like an invitation to anarchy, it is
because, as opposed to most philosophies, it holds that what ultimately
guides judgment cannot be articulated in terms of any sort of proposi-
tional knowledge. What can save us from nihilism in a world without
foundations is qualitative, unique, and pre-conceptual.
Dewey’s emphasis on primary qualitative and situated experience
does not rule out the possibility of formulating general principles of dem-
ocratic discourse or interaction. It may be useful in certain circumstances
to lay out some rules of proper deliberation in a democracy in order to
criticize present institutions. What must be avoided is overlooking the fact
that these rules are only tools derived from, not prior to, having a certain
quality of communication. Democracy as experience means that it arises
and is ultimately justified by having certain experiences in particular sit-
uations. This is a bottom-up justification of democracy.
Have we succeeded in avoiding the charge of circularity in justifica-
tion? We could play the skeptic and push the objection one more time. To
≤Ω≤
a p h i l o s o p h i c a l j u s t i f i c at i o n o f d e m o c r a c y
≤Ω≥
the ideal moral life
≤Ω∂
a p h i l o s o p h i c a l j u s t i f i c at i o n o f d e m o c r a c y
≤Ω∑
the ideal moral life
The clearer and more organized vision of the contents of beliefs may
have as an immediate outcome an enhanced sense of their worth and
greater loyalty to them. But nevertheless the set of beliefs undergoes
more than a sea-change in the process. (LW 6:19)
What is it about democracy that makes it the way of life most consistent
with the pragmatist faith in experience? In social and moral matters we
are accustomed to assume that amelioration and solutions must come
from the top down, especially from means that are beyond or above
experience. ‘‘Men have not been able to trust either the world or them-
selves to realize the values and qualities which are the possibilities of na-
ture’’ (LW 4:240). For Dewey, this general distrust in nature is intimately
tied to a distrust of those who serve as the backbone of most aristocratic
ideals. Democracy’s faith in the people is understood by Dewey as a faith
in the potentialities and self-su≈ciency of the everyday transactions of
individuals if the proper conditions are provided. ‘‘Every other form of
≤Ω∏
a p h i l o s o p h i c a l j u s t i f i c at i o n o f d e m o c r a c y
moral and social faith rest upon the idea that experience must be subjected
at some point or other to some form of external control; to some ‘author-
ity’ alleged to exist outside the process of experience’’ (LW 14:229).
For Dewey, formal and political notions of democracy are not su≈-
ciently robust to counteract the need for some aristocratic scheme to
regulate our everyday a√airs. On the other hand, if democracy is under-
stood as merely following the conversations and wishes of the people, then
this seems like the abandonment of any standards. Only a robust notion of
democracy that requires communal inquiry (with all that this implies) can
be supportive of the faith that experience can provide the standards to
which further experience may submit. Aristocracy and the need to look
outside our direct qualitative world and communications for guidance
will continue to appeal and flourish so long as democracy is devoid of its
most promising possibilities. For Dewey, the alternative to the disillusion-
ment with formal democratic societies where people are merely drifting,
are apathetic, or are mere consumers of entertainment is more democ-
racy; it is not the search for the guidance of a wise and benevolent dictator.
Again, to take this stand requires a lot of faith in the people.
The connection between Dewey’s faiths in experience and democracy
is made even stronger when the latter is understood from the point of view
of his ethics. Democracy fits his conception of an ideal moral life because
it has in its generic features, phases, and dynamics all of the features of an
intelligent and aesthetic moral life. Democratic inquiry embraces, a≈rms,
and relies on everyday life in all of its contingency and qualitative richness
to settle disagreements or to come to decisions. It so trusts the grain of
experience that it tries to turn even error, conflict, incompleteness, plural-
ism, uncertainty, and tragedy into sources of instruction. This makes
possible a moral life that can be self-educational and capable of ameliorat-
ing its problems through its own resources.
Experience cannot become educational and grow in ordered richness
when our relationships are not democratic. Certain ways of interacting are
cumulatively enriching and meaningful,∂∂ whereas others are not. It is in
democratic communication that the conditions for experience to educate,
enlarge, and enrich itself are maximized. These conditions consist of the
predominance of the traits already mentioned: full and free communica-
tion and cooperation, generous give-and-take (reciprocity and sharing),
and the exchange of experiences and ideas in an environment of sympa-
thetic intercommunication where everyone contributes and corrects her
individual limitations. The truth of this claim may be intuitively obvious
to those who have had the opportunity to be part of this kind of inter-
action. But I think there are more general and basic assumptions that are
≤Ωπ
the ideal moral life
≤Ω∫
a p h i l o s o p h i c a l j u s t i f i c at i o n o f d e m o c r a c y
enriched’’ (LW 14:229–30). The ideal is for generosity, openness, and in-
clusivity not to undermine fullness of interaction. The democratic com-
munity is wide and open, both vertically and horizontally, without losing
its integrity. The features that provide its ability to widen experience are
also responsible for its freedom and flexibility; and the ones that make
depth and fullness possible contribute to its stability and order. As with
any work of art there is a very delicate balance between the stable and the
precarious, as well as between its centripetal and centrifugal values.
The intelligent and aesthetic characters of democracies are mutually
dependent. The community most capable of learning from experience is
also the one that has all the features that define aesthetic activity, which
for Dewey is the most inherently meaningful type of activity in experi-
ence. The democratic way of life is able to maintain the kind of balance
and rhythm in its everyday doings and undergoings that, for Dewey,
characterize aesthetic experience: a balance of tensions with rhythmic
variety. Ideal activity is a merging of playfulness with seriousness that
allows richness and flexibility without sacrificing stability. Democracy
signifies for Dewey this possibility at a social level. The democratic com-
munity is also the aesthetic community because it is constituted by rela-
tionships that are neither fixed, routine, or mechanical, nor anarchical,
capricious, or arbitrary.
The democratic community falls between the extremes of a commu-
nity that is disintegrated and one that is kept stable only because of some
imposed external authority. In other words, it is capable of preserving
its own integrity without the need of external foundations. A stability
achieved through full interaction and openness and not through force or
repression is required to procure its ordered richness. Since it can steer
safely between complete radicalism and complete conservatism, it can rely
on what is stable without falling into drudgery. But it can also be play-
ful and welcome change without degenerating into chaos. The non-
democratic ways of dealing with moral and social problems represent for
Dewey a failure to use the resources and potentialities of experience. For
example, in dealing with change, uncertainty, ambivalence, and pluralism,
it is ine√ective to deny their reality (as is often the strategies of authori-
tarian, dualistic, and rule-guided views). The best way to preserve order is
not by trying to get rid of participation or of the diversity present in
human experience.
≤ΩΩ
Conclusion
≥≠≠
conclusion
≥≠∞
john dewey’s ethics
≥≠≤
conclusion
≥≠≥
john dewey’s ethics
≥≠∂
conclusion
≥≠∑
john dewey’s ethics
≥≠∏
conclusion
virtue cannot be taught, but we can provide the conditions for their
emergence. We can only prepare the soil, and reconstruction must come
from within everyday interactions. Continuous inquiry about indirect
means and present conditions is the key to finding the way we can democ-
ratize experience.
In the end, what Dewey is proposing is a program for more work, a
never-ending task that requires of those who have not lost their faith in
democracy a commitment that is balanced with criticism, and infused
with a humility that comes from the awareness of how tension-filled and
precarious is that which we seek. Of all the problems of democracy, the
one that strikes me as most urgent today is simply that democracy is not
experienced as a task or problem. This happens when it is taken for
granted, or worse, when many people have no ideal or sense of how things
could be better. Without awareness that there is a crisis of democracy,
there is not the felt, problematic situation that can lead to inquiry about
how to ameliorate present conditions.
Finally, I have claimed that one also finds in Dewey’s ethics the philo-
sophical resources to provide an alternative justification of democracy
that, while not foundational, is not problematic. What, for Dewey, is the
ultimate court of appeal in ethical matters and the grounds for the prag-
matist’s commitment to democracy? There is no absolute authority, nor is
there an Archimedean standpoint that we can take. Instead, Dewey’s ulti-
mate grounding is a historical and contextual one that he does not think is
arbitrary. Dewey shares with Richard Rorty his criticism of the quest for
some transcendental non-human authority, but Dewey’s appeal to context
is not a bald appeal to us humans, that is, our communication, consensus,
tradition, discourse, or beliefs. Instead, Dewey appeals to a faith in our
transactions within nature, that is, within a situation that can guide our
plans, purposes, and judgments. We can look outside of the human com-
munity, discourse, or consensus for guidance and test our hypotheses
without presupposing any problematic dualism. Rorty, however, contin-
ues to claim that ‘‘as Dewey saw it, whole-hearted pursuit of the demo-
cratic ideal requires us to set aside any authority save that of consensus of
our fellow humans.’’∂
What I provided in the last chapter was neither an ahistorical objec-
tive justification of democracy, nor the only plausible one. Instead, I pre-
sented philosophical reasons why Dewey thought the commitment to
democracy was reasonable and worth trying. These reasons to commit to
democracy will not convince the imaginary radical skeptic who is presup-
posed throughout much of philosophy. These are reasons, however, that
have a chance of winning the consent of people who are already com-
≥≠π
john dewey’s ethics
≥≠∫
NOTES
introduction
1. Compared to this book, the three previous books devoted to Dewey’s
ethics, while important, are more circumspect in scope and focus. The first, James
Gouinlock’s John Dewey’s Philosophy of Value (New York, N.Y.: Humanities Press,
1972), articulates Dewey’s theory of value in light of his views on experience and
nature. The second, Jennifer Welchman’s Dewey’s Ethical Thought (Ithaca, N.Y.:
Cornell University Press, 1995), focuses on the evolution of Dewey’s early ethical
thought. And the third, Steven Fesmire’s John Dewey and the Moral Imagina-
tion: Pragmatism in Ethics (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2003), ex-
plores Dewey’s views on moral deliberation and imagination from a contempo-
rary perspective.
2. The most common mistake is to attribute to Dewey some form of conse-
quentialism or teleology. I argue against this interpretation throughout this book.
But there have been recent e√orts to classify Dewey as a virtue ethicist. See, e.g.,
John Teehan, ‘‘Character, Integrity and Dewey’s Virtue Ethics,’’ Transactions of the
Charles S. Peirce Society 31, no. 4 (1995):841–63.
3. G. E. M. Anscombe, ‘‘Modern Moral Philosophy,’’ in Virtue Ethics, ed.
Roger Crisp and Michael Slote (New York, N.Y.: Oxford University Press, 2002),
26. Anscombe’s article was originally published in Philosophy 33 (1958):1–19.
≥≠Ω
notes to pages 2 – 7
≥∞≠
notes to pages 7 – 9
≥∞∞
notes to pages 10 – 18
1. experience as method
1. See Ralph W. Sleeper, ‘‘Dewey’s Metaphysical Perspective: A Note on
White, Geiger, and the Problem of Obligation,’’ Journal of Philosophy 57, no. 3
(1960):100–15; James Gouinlock, ‘‘Dewey’s Theory of Moral Deliberation,’’ Ethics
≥∞≤
notes to pages 18 – 30
88, no. 3 (1978):218–28; and Robert L. Holmes, ‘‘The Development of John Dew-
ey’s Ethical Thought,’’ The Monist 48 (1964):392–406.
2. See, e.g., Hugh LaFollette, ‘‘Pragmatic Ethics,’’ in The Blackwell Guide to
Ethical Theory, ed. Hugh LaFollette (Oxford, U.K.: Blackwell, 2000), 400–19; and
Elizabeth Anderson, ‘‘Dewey’s Moral Philosophy,’’ in The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta (Spring 2005 Edition), http://plato.stanford.edu/
archives/spr2005/entries/dewey-moral/ (accessed September 17, 2007).
3. It is therefore perfectly understandable why in Human Nature and Con-
duct (MW 12), a book that Dewey explicitly regarded as an introduction to social
psychology, there is no reference to moral qualities. From a scientific point of
view, one cannot usefully talk about moral qualities; thus, Dewey refers instead to
‘‘impulses’’ and ‘‘instincts.’’
4. Jennifer Welchman, Dewey’s Ethical Thought (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell Uni-
versity Press, 1995), 143.
5. Ibid.
6. Ibid.
7. James Campbell, Understanding John Dewey (Chicago, Ill.: Open Court
Publishing, 1995), 110.
8. If one tracks the historical development of Dewey’s philosophy, there
might be support for understanding his ethics by reference to his views on science.
This is what Jennifer Welchman has accomplished in Dewey’s Ethical Thought. But
even if Dewey came to adopt an empirical view of ethics after he reexamined his
own views about the nature of science, this does not mean that his views on
science are the key to his ethics. My intention here is not to discredit but to
supplement Welchman’s work, since we are concerned about di√erent things. She
is concerned with Dewey’s e√orts to bring science and ethics closer together
(‘‘reconcile’’), but this can be distinguished from his e√ort to show how to proceed
in an empirical philosophical inquiry about morality. I am in this book concerned
with the latter and not with the former.
9. See William T. Myers’s review of John Dewey and Moral Imagination in the
Journal of Aesthetic Education 39, no. 2 (2005):107–14.
10. Alasdair MacIntyre, ‘‘Moral Dilemmas,’’ Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research 50, Suppl. (1990):371.
11. See LW 1:40.
12. Douglas Browning, ‘‘Understanding Dewey: Starting at the Starting Point’’
(paper presented at the XIV Congreso Interamericano de Filosofía, Puebla, Mex-
ico, August 19, 1999), 4.
13. This is the fallacy of taking what is eventual as given, the ‘‘conversion of
eventual functions into antecedent existence’’ (LW 1:34).
14. Dale Jamieson, ‘‘Method and Moral Theory,’’ in A Companion to Ethics,
ed. Peter Singer (Oxford, U.K.: Blackwell, 1993), 477.
15. See MW 5:313.
16. James Gouinlock, Rediscovering the Moral Life: Philosophy and Human
Practice (Bu√alo, N.Y.: Prometheus Books, 1993), 267–68.
≥∞≥
notes to pages 33 – 48
2 . m o r a l t h e o ry a n d m o r a l p r a c t i c e
1. The term ‘situation ethics’ was already used by Joseph Fletcher in Situation
Ethics (Philadelphia, Pa.: Westminster Press, 1966), but it fits Dewey’s view better.
2. I am here considering the issue of abortion as a moral decision and not as
≥∞∂
notes to pages 48 – 58
a legal issue. On the legal issue, I suppose the contextualist would be in favor of the
legal arrangement that would in practice allow the necessary flexibility to be
contextualist about abortion. This raises some interesting questions. Does our
system of jurisprudence work against the contextualist, and toward some simple,
measurable standard? China has the concept of degrees of guilt and degrees of
liability whereas in the United States and the United Kingdom, guilt or liability is
an either/or standard.
3. For a recent formulation of contextualism in ethics, see Mark Timmons,
‘‘Moral Justification in Context,’’ The Monist 76, no. 3 (1993):360–78.
4. For an excellent account of this capacity and habits from a Deweyan
ethical standpoint, see Todd Lekan, Making Morality: Pragmatist Reconstruction in
Ethical Theory (Nashville, Tenn.: Vanderbilt University Press, 2003).
5. See MW 14:169.
6. Jonathan Dancy, Ethics without Principles (New York, N.Y.: Oxford Uni-
versity Press, 2004), 7.
7. Jonathan Dancy, ‘‘The Particularist’s Progress,’’ in Moral Particularism, ed.
Brad Hooker and Margaret Olivia Little (New York, N.Y.: Oxford University Press,
2001), 130.
8. Ibid., 131.
9. Dancy, Ethics without Principles, 77.
10. Ibid., 2.
11. Jonathan Dancy, ‘‘Moral Particularism,’’ in The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta (Summer 2005 Edition), http://plato.stanford.edu/
archives/sum2005/entries/moral-particularism/ (assessed September 17, 2007).
12. Ibid.
13. Dancy, Ethics without Principles, 2.
14. Brad Hooker and Margaret Olivia Little, ‘‘Introduction,’’ in Moral Par-
ticularism, vii.
15. Margaret Olivia Little, ‘‘Moral Generalities Revisited,’’ in Moral Particular-
ism, 304.
16. Testing our intuitions by comparing possible cases of ‘‘torturing children
for fun’’ leaves out much of the contextual background that may or may not make
a moral di√erence. Our inability to imagine one of these cases with enough
contextual details so as to make it seem morally permissible may well reflect our
lack of imagination and not the discovery of some self-evident truth. The com-
mon approach in ethics of testing theories by appealing to our intuitions in
imaginary cases has limitations that have not been su≈ciently acknowledged.
17. C. I. Lewis, ‘‘Review of The Quest for Certainty,’’ Journal of Philosophy 27,
no. 1 (1930):14–25; reprinted in Dewey and His Critics: Essays from the Journal of
Philosophy, ed. Sidney Morgenbesser (New York, N.Y.: Journal of Philosophy, Inc.,
1977), 263.
18. Ibid.
19. This is the question raised by Robert Westbrook in ‘‘Pragmatism and
Democracy: Reconstructing the Logic of John Dewey’s Faith,’’ in The Revival of
≥∞∑
notes to pages 58 – 86
Pragmatism: New Essays on Social Thought, Law, and Culture, ed. Morris Dickstein
(Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press, 1998), 133.
20. Sidney Hook regrets that Dewey did not devote enough pages to this issue.
See Sidney Hook, ‘‘Introduction,’’ in MW 9, xi–xii.
21. Hilary Putnam, The Collapse of the Fact/Value Dichotomy and Other Essays
(Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2002), 104.
22. Bernard Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard University Press, 1985), 17.
23. Ibid., 29.
24. Susan Wolf, ‘‘The Deflation of Moral Philosophy,’’ review of Ethics and the
Limits of Philosophy, by Bernard Williams, Ethics 97, no. 4 (1987):827.
25. Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, 93.
26. Williams’s deflation of theories has been received with both enthusiasm
and disappointment by the philosophical community. The source of disappoint-
ment is that Williams and other contemporary skeptics do not have much to say
about the direction (if any) that moral theory should take. See, e.g., Samuel
ScheΔer, ‘‘Morality Through Thick and Thin: A Critical Notice of Ethics and the
Limits of Philosophy, by Bernard Williams,’’ The Philosophical Review 96, no. 3
(1987):411–34.
27. Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, 116.
28. William James, The Letters of William James, ed. Henry James (Boston,
Mass.: Atlanta Monthly Press, 1920), 270.
3 . t h e n o r m at i v e s ta n d p o i n t o f p r a g m at i s m
1. I am using the terms ‘living’, ‘momentous’, and ‘forced’ in the same sense
that William James used them in The Will to Believe and Other Popular Essays
(Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1979), 14.
2. Richard Rorty, ‘‘Solidarity or Objectivity?’’ in his Objectivity, Relativism,
and Truth (New York, N.Y.: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 29, 34.
3. Ibid., 29.
4. I could have instead said that Dewey had a faith in nature or that this is
what makes Dewey a naturalist. For Dewey experience is continuous with and of
nature, and any claim about experience is a claim about nature. For the pragmatic
view of faith assumed here, see my ‘‘William James and the Logic of Faith,’’
Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 28, no. 4 (1992):781–808.
4. morality as experience
1. J. B. Schneewind, ‘‘Modern Moral Philosophy,’’ in A Companion to Ethics,
ed. Peter Singer (Oxford, U.K.: Blackwell, 1993), 147.
2. Todd Lekan, Making Morality: Pragmatist Reconstruction in Ethical Theory
(Nashville, Tenn.: Vanderbilt University Press, 2003), 30.
3. For an account of who is a naturalist in ethical theory today, see Charles R.
Pigden, ‘‘Naturalism,’’ in A Companion to Ethics, ed. Peter Singer (Oxford, U.K.:
Blackwell, 1993), 421–31.
≥∞∏
notes to pages 88 – 115
5 . t h e ‘‘w h a t’’ o f m o r a l e x p e r i e n c e
1. See MW 9:172–74. This is what James referred to as the double-barreled
aspect of experience. Double-barreled in that ‘‘it recognizes in its primary integ-
rity no division between act and material, subject and object, but contains them
both in an unanalyzed totality’’ (LW 1:18).
2. For recent skepticism about whether there can be a pre-theoretical desig-
nation of moral problems, see Alasdair MacIntyre, ‘‘Moral Dilemmas,’’ Philosophy
and Phenomenological Research 50, Suppl. (1990):382.
3. Dewey makes this same point, though using a di√erent example, in ‘‘The
Postulate of Immediate Empiricism’’ (MW 3:158–67). Contrast this, for example,
with R. M. Hare, who in Moral Thinking claims ‘‘If I am su√ering, I know that I am
su√ering,’’ 92.
4. This example is from Dewey’s ‘‘The Postulate of Immediate Empiricism’’
(MW 3:158–67).
5. This pluralism is not evident in Dewey’s discussions about value in gen-
eral, for example, in his ‘‘Theory of Valuation’’ (LW 13:189–254).
6. For more on this important aspect of Dewey’s thought, see Tom Burke,
Dewey’s New Logic: A Reply to Russell (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1994).
7. For Dewey and cognitive science, see Mark Johnson, Moral Imagination:
Implications of Cognitive Science for Ethics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1993).
8. There are some interesting questions that I cannot address here about the
nature of my own or anyone else’s non-moral negative valuing of homosexual
acts. Do I really find homosexual acts repugnant? Or is it that I find the thought of
my engaging in such acts as repugnant? Is it really repugnance or merely an
aversion to my engaging in a homosexual relationship, just as homosexuals expe-
rience an aversion to a heterosexual relationship? In any case, the important point
is that none of these possibilities has anything to do with immediate moral dis-
value.
9. See Russell Freeman, Out of Darkness: The Story of Louis Braille (Boston,
Mass.: Houghton MiΔin Company, 1999).
10. Just as with the term ‘experience’, Dewey wrestled with the ambiguities
and associations of value as a philosophical term. See, for example, ‘‘The Meaning
of Value’’ (LW 2:69–77). In The Quest for Certainty (LW 4:207) he restricted the
term ‘value’ to what results from valuation, perhaps hoping to avoid misunder-
standing of his view for subjectivism: the identification of enjoyment with value.
The same thing happened with his use of ‘judgment’. In some of his writings
‘judgment’ was a term he used only for valuation and not valuing.
11. In his Theory of Valuation and Quest for Certainty, Dewey attacks subjec-
tive/emotive and transcendental/objective views of morality and art in one stroke.
12. Dewey claims that ‘‘to grasp this aspect of empiricism is to see what the
empiricist means by objectivity’’ (MW 3:163).
13. For a recent article defending this Deweyan naturalism and distinguishing
≥∞π
notes to pages 115 – 136
it from other contemporary versions, see John Teehan, ‘‘In Defense of a Natural-
ism,’’ Journal of Speculative Philosophy 10, no. 2 (1996):79–91.
14. Mackie, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, 5.
15. For example, see Gilbert Harman’s Explaining Value and Other Essays in
Moral Philosophy (New York, N.Y.: Oxford University Press, 2000).
16. Sidney Hook, The Quest for Being (Bu√alo, N.Y.: Prometheus Books,
1961), 206.
17. Joseph Margolis, Moral Philosophy after 9/11 (University Park: Pennsyl-
vania State University Press, 2004), vii.
18. Ibid., xvi.
19. See Richard Rorty, ‘‘Putnam and the Relativist Menace,’’ Journal of Philos-
ophy 90, no. 9 (1993):453.
20. David Hildebrand, Beyond Realism and Antirealism (Nashville, Tenn.:
Vanderbilt University Press, 2003), 154.
6 . t h e ‘‘ho w’’ o f m o r a l e x p e r i e n c e
1. For Dewey on custom, see MW 14:43–60.
2. John Dewey, Lectures on Psychological and Political Ethics, 1898, ed. Daniel
Koch (New York, N.Y.: Hafner Press, 1976), 80.
3. See LW 7:235.
4. See MW 3:20.
5. Alan Gewirth, ‘‘The Implicit Teaching of Ethics,’’ APA Newsletter 90
(1990):34.
≥∞∫
notes to pages 137 – 171
1 0 . t h e i n t e l l i g e n t, a e s t h e t i c , a n d d e m o c r at i c way o f l i f e
1. John Dewey, Lectures on Ethics, 1900–1901, ed. Donald F. Koch (Carbon-
dale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1991), 331.
2. Items listed in column A are about generic traits of experience that are of
utmost importance from the standpoint of work and control, while those in
≥∞Ω
notes to pages 171 – 198
column B are traits of experience from the standpoint of play, immediate enjoy-
ment, and consummation. One could also argue that A and B can be identified,
respectively, with the Enlightenment and romantic modernity.
3. In his early lectures Dewey claimed that ‘‘the more subjects we took up the
more we would be convinced that they show up everywhere and that they show
themselves in a practical, working opposition to each other,’’ Lectures on Ethics,
1900–1901, 331.
4. It is an instance of what Dewey called the ‘‘fallacy of selective emphasis.’’
For Dewey the above oppositions do not place us in an ontological either/or
dilemma; rather, opposing generic traits of experience are all equally real.
5. Dewey, Lectures on Ethics, 1900–1901, 329, my emphasis.
6. Ibid.
7. Ibid.
8. The extent to which Dewey’s notion of balance is similar to Aristotle’s no-
tion of the mean depends on one’s interpretation of Aristotle. There are recent neo-
Aristotelian views that, insofar as they entertain a particular and context-relative
notion of a mean and the interdependence of the virtues, are similar to Dewey’s
view. See, e.g., Martha Nussbaum, Poetic Justice (Boston, Mass.: Beacon, 1995); and
Barry Schwartz and Kenneth E. Sharpe, ‘‘Practical Wisdom: Aristotle Meets Posi-
tive Psychology,’’ Journal of Happiness Studies 7, no. 3 (2006):377–95. Di√erences
between Dewey and these neo-Aristotelians may be worth further inquiry.
9. Dewey can hold that the biological is the ‘‘roots of the esthetic in experi-
ence’’ (LW 10:20) without committing himself to a reduction of one to the other
because of the ‘‘postulate of continuity’’ and ‘‘emergence.’’ Dewey shared these
postulates with George Herbert Mead; see LW 12:30.
10. Dewey, Lectures on Ethics, 1900–1901, 342.
11. Alan Ryan, John Dewey and the High Tide of American Liberalism (New
York, N.Y.: W. W. Norton, 1995), 329.
≥≤≠
notes to pages 199 – 224
≥≤∞
notes to pages 225 – 249
≥≤≤
notes to pages 250 – 258
and Will Friedman, ‘‘Deliberative Democracy and the Problem of Power,’’ Journal
of Public Deliberation 3, no. 1 (2007):article 8, http://services.bepress.com/jpd/
vol3/iss1/art8 (accessed September 17, 2007); and, for a defense of Dewey’s demo-
cratic vision from radical democratic theorists who claim that extant democratic
deliberation is blind to power relations and ill-prepared to combat such relations,
see Alison Kadlec’s Dewey’s Critical Pragmatism (Lanham, Md.: Lexington Books,
2007).
22. Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy, 166.
23. From liner notes by Brad Mehldau in his music CD Elegiac Cycles (Warner
Brothers, 1999).
24. John Dryzek claims that ‘‘an emphasis on deliberation is not entirely new.
Antecedents can be found in . . . theorists of the early twentieth century such as
John Dewey,’’ John S. Dryzek, Deliberative Democracy and Beyond (New York,
N.Y.: Oxford University Press, 2000), 2. Richard Posner also considers Dewey a de-
liberative democrat; see his Law, Pragmatism, and Democracy (Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard University Press, 2003), 50.
25. See Iris Marion Young, ‘‘Communication and the Other: Beyond Deliber-
ative Democracy,’’ in Democracy and Di√erence: Contesting the Boundaries of the
Political, ed. Seyla Benhabib (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1996),
120–36.
26. Frank Cunningham, Theories of Democracy: A Critical Introduction (New
York, N.Y.: Routledge, 2001), 180.
27. This is at least one most common understanding of Habermas. See Cun-
ningham, Theories of Democracy, 176.
28. Robert B. Talisse, Democracy after Liberalism: Pragmatism and Delibera-
tive Politics (New York, N.Y.: Routledge, 2005), 314.
29. Hilary Putnam, ‘‘A Reconsideration of Deweyan Democracy,’’ in Pragma-
tism in Law and Society, ed. Michael Brint (Boulder, Colo.: Westview, 1991); and
Cheryl Misak, Truth, Politics, and Morality: Pragmatism and Deliberation (New
York, N.Y.: Routledge, 2000).
30. Tallisse, Democracy after Liberalism, 62.
31. Jorge Valadez, Deliberative Democracy, Political Legitimacy, and Self-Deter-
mination in Multicultural Societies (Boulder, Colo.: Westview, 2001), 89.
32. According to Andrew G. Fiala, Dewey, Rawls, and other pragmatists share
the same view about tolerance: ‘‘Toleration is a pragmatic response to the practical
need to coexist with others who have di√erent conceptions of the good.’’ Andrew
G. Fiala, ‘‘Toleration and Pragmatism,’’ Journal of Speculative Philosophy 16, no. 2
(2002):103. Needless to say, I disagree with Fiala.
33. For Rorty’s view on Sandel, see his ‘‘A Defense of Minimalist Liberalism,’’
in Debating Democracy’s Discontent: Essays on American Politics, Law, and Public
Philosophy, ed. Anita L. Allen and Milton Regan (New York, N.Y.: Oxford Univer-
sity Press, 1999), 117–25. Chantal Mou√e criticizes liberals, like Rorty, for not being
pluralistic enough in her ‘‘Democracy, Power and the ‘Political’,’’ in Democracy and
Di√erence, ed. Benhabib, 245–56.
≥≤≥
notes to pages 261 – 276
1 3 . a p h i l o s o p h i c a l j u s t i f i c at i o n o f d e m o c r a c y
1. Richard Rorty, ‘‘Solidarity or Objectivity?’’ in Post-Analytic Philosophy, ed.
John Rajchman and Cornel West (New York, N.Y.: Columbia University Press,
1985), 12.
2. Ibid., 16.
3. David Fott, John Dewey: America’s Philosopher of Democracy (Lanham,
Md.: Rowman & Littlefield, 1998), 82.
4. Ibid.
5. Matthew Festenstein, for example, argues in his Pragmatism and Political
Theory: From Dewey to Rorty (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1997) that
Dewey o√ers a plausible, but incomplete, philosophical justification for his nor-
mative ethical and political theory.
6. This is a quote from Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., that Dewey uses in
LW 1:313.
7. Doug Browning, ‘‘Remarks on Rorty’s criticism of Dewey’s Metaphysics’’
(unpublished paper, May 1990).
8. Rogene A. Buchholz and Sandra B. Rosenthal, Business Ethics: The Prag-
matic Path Beyond Principles to Process (Upper Saddle River, N.J.: Prentice Hall,
1997), 63.
9. For more about comparing Dewey with Habermas’s discourse ethics, see
Matthew Festenstein, Pragmatism and Political Theory, 146–61; and Scott R. Bart-
lett, ‘‘Discursive Democracy and a Democratic Way of Life,’’ in Perspectives on
Habermas, ed. Lewis Edwin Hahn (Chicago, Ill.: Open Court Publishing, 2000),
367–86.
10. Recall that, for Dewey, nature (i.e., reality) is not something apart, out-
side, or behind experience.
11. Giovanni Sartori, The Theory of Democracy Revisited (Chatham, N.J.:
Chatham House, 1987), 69.
12. Michael Eldridge, Transforming Experience (Nashville, Tenn.: Vanderbilt
University Press, 1998), 83. Eldridge traces the history of this objection to Dewey
(see pp. 70–84). Eldridge defends Dewey against Walter Lippmann, John Herman
Randall, Jr., and Robert Westbrook by providing some Deweyan guidelines that
could be part of a ‘‘Deweyan manual to political action’’ (113). My defense of
Dewey consists, instead, in raising doubts about what is assumed by the objection.
13. This way of expressing the objection is Alan Ryan’s. See Alan Ryan, ‘‘Prag-
matism Rides Again,’’ review of The Promise of Pragmatism, by John P. Diggins,
The New York Review of Books, February 16, 1995, 33.
14. For more on the Dewey-Lippmann debate, see Robert Westbrook, John
Dewey and American Democracy (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1991),
293–300.
15. For a recent book on this issue from a pragmatic standpoint, see Erin
McKenna, The Task of Utopia (Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Littlefield, 2002).
16. William James, ‘‘What Makes a Life Significant,’’ in his Talks to Teachers on
≥≤∂
notes to pages 277 – 287
Psychology: And to Students on Some of Life’s Ideals (New York, N.Y.: Henry Holt
and Company, 1899), 270.
17. Reinhold Niebuhr was the most persistent critic of Dewey on the issue of
naïveté. For the history of this criticism of Dewey, see Westbrook, John Dewey and
American Democracy, 523–36; and Eldridge, Transforming Experience, 52–62.
18. Eldridge, Transforming Experience, 54.
19. For instance, in The Public and its Problems, Dewey says, ‘‘As long as
interests of pecuniary profit are powerful, and a public has not located and identi-
fied itself, those who have this interest will have an unresisted motive for tamper-
ing with the spring of political action in all that a√ects them’’ (LW 2:348).
20. He was aware of ‘‘the influence of private interests in procuring suppres-
sion, secrecy and misrepresentation,’’ and of ‘‘the triviality and ‘sensational’ qual-
ity of so much of what passes as news’’ (LW 2:347).
21. John Patrick Diggins, ‘‘Pragmatism and Its Limits,’’ in The Revival of
Pragmatism: New Essays on Social Thought, Law, and Culture, ed. Morris Dickstein
(Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press, 1998), 213.
22. Ibid., 212.
23. Richard J. Bernstein, ‘‘Community in the Pragmatic Tradition,’’ in The
Revival of Pragmatism, ed. Dickstein, 149.
24. See Raymond D. Boisvert, ‘‘The Nemesis of Necessity: Tragedy’s Challenge
to Deweyan Pragmatism,’’ in Dewey Reconfigured: Essays on Deweyan Pragmatism,
ed. Casey Haskins and David I. Seiple (Albany: State University of New York Press,
1999), 151–68; James T. Kloppenberg, ‘‘Pragmatism: An Old Name for Some New
Ways of Thinking?’’ in The Revival of Pragmatism, ed. Dickstein, 83–127; West-
brook, John Dewey and American Democracy, 163, 416–17; and Hilary Putnam,
‘‘Reconsideration of Deweyan Democracy,’’ in Renewing Philosophy (Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1992), 190–99.
25. Kloppenberg, ‘‘Pragmatism: An Old Name for Some New Ways of Think-
ing?’’ 114.
26. Michael Sandel, ‘‘The Case Against Perfection,’’ Atlantic Monthly, April
2004, 54.
27. Ibid., 51.
28. See LW 10:54.
29. John Dewey, quoted in Max Eastman, ‘‘John Dewey,’’ Atlantic Monthly,
December 1941, 673.
30. As Michael Eldridge has argued in Transforming Experience, there is more
to inquiry than having a rational discussion; see pp. 24–42.
31. George Herbert Mead, Selected Writings, ed. Andrew J. Reck (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1964), 5.
32. Sidney Hook, ‘‘Introduction,’’ in MW 9, xi–xii.
33. Ibid.
34. Robert Westbrook, ‘‘Pragmatism and Democracy: Reconstructing the
Logic of John Dewey’s Faith,’’ in The Revival of Pragmatism: New Essays on Social
≥≤∑
notes to pages 289 – 307
Thought, Law, and Culture, ed. Morris Dickstein (Durham, N.C.: Duke University
Press, 1998), 133.
35. For textual support of this claim, see endnote #19 in this book’s intro-
duction.
36. This seems to be Richard Shusterman’s view in his ‘‘Putnam and Cavell on
the Ethics of Democracy,’’ Political Theory 25, no. 2 (1997):193–214.
37. This is the view of Hilary Putnam in ‘‘A Reconsideration of Deweyan
Democracy,’’ Renewing Philosophy, 180–200.
38. See my ‘‘William James and the Logic of Faith,’’ Transactions of the Charles
S. Peirce Society 28, no. 4 (1992):781–808.
39. William James, The Meaning of Truth (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Uni-
versity Press, 1975), 139.
40. Eldridge, Transforming Experience, 145.
41. William James, The Will to Believe and Other Popular Essays (Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1979), 53.
42. Ibid., 7.
43. Dewey’s metaphysics, as Westbrook correctly suggests, is a metaphysics
that supports democracy; it is a ‘‘metaphysics for the common man.’’ Westbrook,
John Dewey and American Democracy, 361.
44. James Gouinlock argues this same point eloquently in ‘‘The Moral Value
of a Philosophic Education,’’ Teaching Philosophy 3, no. 1 (1979):37–50.
conclusion
1. Dewey’s views on moral education and his moral philosophy are closely
intertwined and perhaps inseparable. Nevertheless, these are di√erent inquiries
initiated by a di√erent problem. We must not confuse the standpoint of an educa-
tor concerned to provide the best tools or prepare others for moral life with the
standpoint of a philosopher concerned with ethics as an inquiry of morality as it is
experienced. Interpretations of Dewey that take his emphasis on growth and the
cultivation of our characters as central to his ethics sometimes confuse these two
standpoints.
2. William T. Myers, review of John Dewey and Moral Imagination, by Steven
Fesmire, Journal of Aesthetic Education 39, no. 2 (2005):113.
3. I owe this way of articulating this point to Steven Fesmire.
4. Richard Rorty, ‘‘Pragmatism as Anti-authoritarianism,’’ in A Companion
To Pragmatism, ed. John R. Shook and Joseph Margolis (Malden, Mass.: Blackwell,
2006), 257.
≥≤∏
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Alexander, Thomas. 1987. John Dewey’s Theory of Art, Experience, and Nature.
Albany: State University of New York Press.
———. 2002. ‘‘The Aesthetics of Reality: The Development of Dewey’s Ecological
Theory of Experience.’’ In Dewey’s Logical Theory, ed. Thomas Burke, Micah
Hester, and Robert B. Talisse, 3–26. Nashville, Tenn.: Vanderbilt University
Press.
Altman, Andrew. 1982. ‘‘John Dewey and Contemporary Normative Ethics.’’ Met-
aphilosophy 13:149–160.
Anderson, Elizabeth. 2005. ‘‘Dewey’s Moral Philosophy.’’ In The Stanford En-
cyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta. Spring 2005 Edition, http://
plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2005/entries/dewey-moral/ (accessed Septem-
ber 17, 2007).
Anscombe, G. E. M. 2002. ‘‘Modern Moral Philosophy.’’ In Virtue Ethics, ed. Roger
Crisp and Michael Slote, 24–44. Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press.
Barber, Benjamin. 1984. Strong Democracy. Berkeley: University of California
Press.
Bartlett, Scott R. 2000. ‘‘Discursive Democracy and a Democratic Way of Life.’’ In
Perspectives on Habermas, ed. Lewis Edwin Hahn, 367–386. Chicago: Open
Court Publishing.
≥≤π
bibliography
≥≤∫
bibliography
———. 1991. Lectures on Ethics 1900–1901. Ed. Donald F. Koch. Carbondale: South-
ern Illinois University Press.
Diggins, John Patrick. 1998. ‘‘Pragmatism and Its Limits.’’ In The Revival of Pragma-
tism, ed. Morris Dickstein, 207–234. Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press.
Drysek, John S. 2000. Deliberative Democracy and Beyond. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Dykhuizen, George. 1973. The Life and Mind of John Dewey. Carbondale: Southern
Illinois University Press.
Eastman, Max. 1941. ‘‘John Dewey.’’ Atlantic Monthly, December.
Edel, Abraham. 2001. Ethical Theory and Social Change: The Evolution of John
Dewey’s Ethics, 1908–1932. New Brunswick, N.J.: Transaction.
Eldridge, Michael. 1998. Transforming Experience. Nashville, Tenn.: Vanderbilt
University Press.
Erlanger, Steven. 2004. ‘‘Why Democracy Defies the Urge to Implant It.’’ New York
Times, February 15, 2004, Week in Review Desk.
Fesmire, Steven. 2003. John Dewey and the Moral Imagination: Pragmatism in
Ethics. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Festenstein, Matthew. 1997. Pragmatism and Political Theory: From Dewey to Rorty.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Fiala, Andrew G. 2002. ‘‘Toleration and Pragmatism.’’ Journal of Speculative Philos-
ophy 16:103–116.
Fletcher, Joseph. 1966. Situation Ethics. Philadelphia: Westminster Press.
Fott, David. 1998. John Dewey: America’s Philosopher of Democracy. New York:
Rowman & Littlefield.
Frankena, William. 1995. ‘‘A Critique of Virtue-Based Ethical Systems.’’ In Ethical
Theory, 2nd ed., ed. Louis P. Pojman, 334–345. Belmont, Wash.: Wadsworth.
Freeman, Russell. 1999. Out of Darkness: The Story of Louis Braille. Boston: Hough-
ton MiΔin.
Gauthier, David.1986. Morals by Agreement. New York: Oxford University Press.
Gewirth, Alan. 1990. ‘‘The Implicit Teaching of Ethics.’’ APA Newsletter 90:34–37.
Gouinlock, James. 1972. John Dewey’s Philosophy of Value. New York: Humanities
Press.
———. 1978. ‘‘Dewey’s Theory of Moral Deliberation.’’ Ethics 88:218–228.
———. 1979. ‘‘The Moral Value of a Philosophic Education.’’ Teaching Philosophy
3:37–50.
———. 1993. Rediscovering the Moral Life: Philosophy and Human Practice. Bu√alo,
N.Y.: Prometheus Books.
Green, Joshua, and Jonathan Haidt. 2002. ‘‘How (and Where) Does Moral Judg-
ment Work?’’ Trends in Cognitive Science 6:517–523.
Haidt, Jonathan. 2001. ‘‘The Emotional Dog and Its Rational Tail: A Social Intu-
itionist Approach to Moral Judgment.’’ Psychological Review 108:814–834.
Hare, R. M. 1981. Moral Thinking: Its Levels, Method and Point. Oxford: Clarendon
Press.
≥≤Ω
bibliography
Harman, Gilbert. 1977. The Nature of Morality. New York: Oxford University Press.
———. 2000. Explaining Value and Other Essays in Moral Philosophy. New York:
Oxford University Press.
Hickman, Larry A. 1990. John Dewey’s Pragmatic Technology. Bloomington: Indi-
ana University Press.
Hildebrand, David. 2003. Beyond Realism and Antirealism. Nashville, Tenn.: Van-
derbilt University Press.
Holmes, Robert L. 1964. ‘‘The Development of John Dewey’s Ethical Thought.’’
The Monist 48:392–406.
Honneth, Axel. 1998. ‘‘Between Proceduralism and Teleology: An Unresolved
Conflict in Dewey’s Moral Theory.’’ Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce So-
ciety 34:689–709.
Hooker, Brad, and Margaret Olivia Little. 2001. ‘‘Introduction.’’ In Moral Par-
ticularism, ed. Brad Hooker and Margaret Olivia Little, vii–xi. New York:
Oxford University Press.
Hook, Sidney. 1961. The Quest for Being. Bu√alo, N.Y.: Prometheus Books.
James, William. 1899. Talks to Teachers on Psychology: And to Students on Some of
Life’s Ideals. New York: Henry Holt and Company.
———. 1920. The Letters of William James. Ed. Henry James. Boston: Atlanta
Monthly Press.
———. 1975. The Meaning of Truth. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
———. 1979. The Will to Believe and Other Popular Essays. Cambridge, Mass.: Har-
vard University Press.
Jamieson, Dale. 1993. ‘‘Method and Moral Theory.’’ In A Companion to Ethics, ed.
Peter Singer, 476–490. Oxford: Blackwell.
Johnson, Mark. 1993. Moral Imagination: Implications of Cognitive Science for
Ethics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Kadlec, Alison. 2007. Dewey’s Critical Pragmatism. Lanham, Md.: Lexington Books.
———, and Will Friedman. 2007. ‘‘Deliberative Democracy and the Problem of
Power.’’ Journal of Public Deliberation 3:article 8, http://services.bepress.com/
jpd/vol3/iss1/art8 (accessed September 17, 2007).
Katz, John. 1997. ‘‘A Birth of a Digital Nation.’’ Wired Magazine, April, http://
www.wired.com/wired/archive/5.04/netizen — pr.html (accessed September 17,
2007).
King, Martin Luther, Jr. 1967. Where Do We Go From Here: Chaos or Community?
Boston: Beacon.
———. 2000. ‘‘Letter from Birmingham Jail.’’ In his Why We Can’t Wait, 64–84. New
York: Signet Classic.
Kloppenberg, James T. 1998. ‘‘Pragmatism: An Old Name for Some New Ways of
Thinking?’’ In The Revival of Pragmatism, ed. Morris Dickstein, 83–127. Dur-
ham, N.C.: Duke University Press.
Kupfer, Joseph. 1983. Experience as Art. Albany: State University of New York Press.
LaFollette, Hugh. 2000. ‘‘Pragmatic Ethics.’’ In The Blackwell Guide to Ethical
Theory, ed. Hugh LaFollette, 400–419. Oxford: Blackwell.
≥≥≠
bibliography
≥≥∞
bibliography
Noddings, Nel. 1984. Caring: A Feminine Approach to Ethics and Moral Education.
Berkeley: University of California Press.
Pappas, Gregory. 1992. ‘‘William James and the Logic of Faith.’’ Transactions of the
Charles S. Peirce Society 28:781–808.
———. 1993. ‘‘Dewey and Feminism: The A√ective and Relationships in Dewey’s
Ethics.’’ Hypatia 8:88–95.
———. 1996. ‘‘Dewey’s Philosophical Approach to Racial Prejudice.’’ Social Theory
and Practice 22:47–66.
———. 1996. ‘‘Open-mindedness and Courage: Complementary Virtues of Pragma-
tism.’’ Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 32:316–335.
Pigden, Charles R. ‘‘Naturalism.’’ In A Companion to Ethics, ed. Peter Singer, 421–
431. Oxford: Blackwell.
Pinco√s, Edmund L. 1986. Quandaries and Virtues. Lawrence: University Press of
Kansas.
Posner, Richard. 2003. Law, Pragmatism, and Democracy. Cambridge, Mass.: Har-
vard University Press.
Putnam, Hilary. 1991.’’A Reconsideration of Deweyan Democracy.’’ In Pragmatism
in Law and Society, ed. Michael Brint, 217–246. Boulder, Colo.: Westview.
———. 1992. Renewing Philosophy. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
———. 2002. The Collapse of the Fact/Value Dichotomy and Other Essays. Cam-
bridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
———. 2004. Ethics without Ontology. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Rorty, Richard. 1985. ‘‘Solidarity or Objectivity?’’ In Post-Analytic Philosophy, ed.
John Rajchman and Cornel West, 3–19. New York: Columbia University
Press.
———. 1990. Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth. New York: Cambridge University
Press.
———. 1993. ‘‘Putnam and the Relativist Menace.’’ Journal of Philosophy 90:443–461.
———. 1999. ‘‘A Defense of Minimalist Liberalism.’’ In Debating Democracy’s Discon-
tent: Essays on American Politics, Law, and Public Philosophy, ed. Anita L.
Allen and Milton Regan, 117–125. New York: Oxford University Press.
———. 2006. ‘‘Pragmatism as Anti-authoritarianism.’’ In A Companion to Prag-
matism, ed. John R. Shook and Joseph Margolis, 257–266. Malden, Mass.:
Blackwell.
Ross, W. D. 1939. Foundations of Ethics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Rucker, Darnell, and Herbert W. Schneider. 1970. ‘‘Dewey’s Ethics.’’ In Guide to the
Works of John Dewey, ed. Jo Ann Boydston, 99–130. Carbondale: Southern
Illinois University Press.
Ryan, Alan. 1995. John Dewey and the High Tide of American Liberalism. New York:
W. W. Norton & Company.
———. 1995. ‘‘Pragmatism Rides Again.’’ The New York Review of Books, February 16.
Sandel, Michael. 2004. ‘‘The Case Against Perfection.’’ Atlantic Monthly, April.
Sartori, Giovanni. 1987. The Theory of Democracy Revisited. Chatham, N.J.: Chat-
ham House.
≥≥≤
bibliography
Savage, Daniel M. 2002. John Dewey’s Liberalism: Individual, Community, and Self-
Development. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.
ScheΔer, Samuel. 1987. ‘‘Morality Through Thick and Thin: A Critical Notice of
Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, by Bernard Williams.’’ The Philosophical
Review 96:411–434.
Schneewind, J. B. ‘‘Modern Moral Philosophy.’’ In A Companion to Ethics, ed. Peter
Singer, 147–157. Oxford: Blackwell.
Sen, Amartya. 1999. ‘‘A Decade of Human Development.’’ Paper presented at The
First Global Forum On Human Development, United Nations, New York,
July.
Shusterman, Richard. 1997. ‘‘Putnam and Cavell on the Ethics of Democracy.’’
Political Theory 25:193–214.
Siegel, Lee. 2001. ‘‘Cold Verities: The Chilly Ethics of American Pragmatism.’’
Review of The Metaphysical Club, by Louis Menand. Harper’s Magazine,
October.
Singer, Beth. 1999. Pragmatism, Rights, and Democracy. New York: Fordham Uni-
versity Press.
Sleeper, Ralph W. 1960. ‘‘Dewey’s Metaphysical Perspective: A Note on White,
Geiger, and the Problem of Obligation.’’ Journal of Philosophy 57:100–115.
Slote, Michael. 1992. ‘‘Teleological Ethics.’’ In Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Law-
rence C. Becker, 1235–1238. New York: Garland.
Sterba, James. 2001. Three Challenges to Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.
Stocker, Michael. 1976. ‘‘The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories.’’ Journal
of Philosophy 73:453–466.
Stout, Je√rey. 1988. Ethics after Babel: The Languages of Morals and their Discon-
tents. Boston: Beacon.
Talisse, Robert B. 2005. Democracy after Liberalism. New York: Routledge.
Teehan, John. 1995. ‘‘Character, Integrity and Dewey’s Virtue Ethics.’’ Transactions
of the Charles S. Peirce Society 31:841–863.
———. 1996. ‘‘In Defense of a Naturalism.’’ Journal of Speculative Philosophy 10:79–89.
Tiles, J. E. 1990. Dewey. New York: Routledge.
Timmons, Mark. 1993. ‘‘Moral Justification in Context.’’ The Monist 76:360–378.
Valadez, Jorge. 2001. Deliberative Democracy, Political Legitimacy, and Self-Deter-
mination in Multicultural Societies. Boulder, Colo.: Westview.
Varela, Francisco. 1999. Ethical Know-How: Action, Wisdom, and Cognition. Stan-
ford, Calif.: Stanford University Press.
Welchman, Jennifer. 1995. Dewey’s Ethical Thought. Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell Univer-
sity Press.
Westbrook, Robert. 1991. John Dewey and American Democracy. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cor-
nell University Press.
———. 1998. ‘‘Pragmatism and Democracy: Reconstructing the Logic of John Dew-
ey’s Faith.’’ In The Revival of Pragmatism: New Essays on Social Thought, Law,
and Culture, ed. Morris Dickstein, 128–140. Durham, N.C.: Duke University
Press.
≥≥≥
bibliography
———. 2005. Democratic Hope: Pragmatism and the Politics of Truth. Ithaca, N.Y.:
Cornell University Press.
West, Cornel. 2004. Democracy Matters: Winning the Fight Against Imperialism.
New York: Penguin.
Williams, Bernard. 1985. Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard University Press.
Williams, Bernard, and J. J. C. Smart. 1973. Utilitarianism: For and Against. New
York: Cambridge University Press.
Wolf, Susan. 1987. ‘‘The Deflation of Moral Philosophy.’’ Review of Ethics and the
Limits of Philosophy, by Bernard Williams. Ethics 97:821–833.
Wright, Jen. 2005. ‘‘Dewey and Dreyfus on Mature Moral Agency.’’ Paper pre-
sented at the 2005 Society for the Advancement of American Philosophy
Conference, Bakersfield, California.
Young, Iris Marion. 1996. ‘‘Communication and the Other: Beyond Deliberative
Democracy.’’ In Democracy and Di√erence: Contesting the Boundaries of the
Political, ed. Seyla Benhabib, 120–135. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University
Press.
≥≥∂
INDEX
absolutism, 7, 10, 12, 48, 56–57, 77, 118, 157, and balance, 173–75, 177, 182, 238, 299;
170–71, 188, 254, 285, 304 music, 241, 250; and science, 8, 12, 116
act-centered ethics, 129–41, 144, 156, authority: divine, 38; external, 75, 166, 308
318n1:7. See also being; doing
Alexander, Thomas, 11, 12 balance, 172–77, 179–84, 205, 210, 220, 247–
alienation, 140–41 49, 276, 305
Altman, Andrew, 311n19 being, 140; and doing, 129, 134–36, 196, 213
altruism, 35, 211–15. See also egoism beliefs, 22, 40, 90, 120, 123, 166, 191, 268
analysis, 26, 49, 60, 96–97, 103 Bernstein, Richard, 279
analytic fallacy, 26, 314n29 bottom-up theory, 266, 292. See also top-
anarchy, 10, 56, 70, 188, 266, 292, 302, 304, down theory
308 Braille, Louis, 109
Anscombe, G. E. M., 2 Brown, Mark Malloch, 10
Archimedean standpoint, 61, 71–72, 74, 76, Browning, Douglas, 11, 24, 33, 34, 262, 310n9
117, 307. See also God’s-eye point of Buddhism, 150
view
aristocracy, 246, 272, 297 Campbell, James, 19, 311n19
Aristotle, 4, 69, 194, 320n8 censorship, 222, 285
Art as Experience (Dewey), 8, 173 certainty, 50, 76, 134, 167
art, 82, 83, 86, 101, 109, 113, 118, 143–44, 167, change, 53, 56, 73, 117, 169, 177, 191, 220, 248;
178–79, 211–12, 230, 234, 264, 291, 302; openness to, 245–46
≥≥∑
index
chaos, 50, 70, 302 165, 186, 237, 249, 262, 265, 285, 301, 302,
character, 34, 55, 66, 69–70, 83, 88, 115, 127– 306, 315n2
28, 136–42, 144, 146, 151, 160, 178, 182, control, 77, 110, 118, 191, 279, 284
185, 187, 193, 196, 201, 204, 206, 217–18, courage, 187–91, 203, 235
236, 267, 301, 326n1; character-centered criteria, 56–58, 113, 151, 159, 287–89, 301–
theory, 130–33, 136–38, 140–41, 156, 302; universal, 68
318n1:7; and conduct, 130–35, 304; and criticism, 22, 29, 65, 66, 77, 118–19; reflec-
habits, 122, 124–26, 186; ideal, 68, 189– tive, 24, 51, 65, 110, 302
90, 208, 216, 253; intellectual, 201–202; Cunningham, Frank, 254
and moral deliberation, 205; traits of, custom, 122, 191
186, 209, 271. See also self cynicism, 276–77, 280, 295
Chautauqua community. See James,
William Dancy, Jonathan, 52, 54, 55
choice, 93, 94, 98, 128, 142, 160. See also Darwin, Charles, 18
judgments decisions, moral, 46, 60, 137, 240
collectivism, 241–42, 255, 258, 304. See also deliberation, 28, 30, 38, 45, 48, 51–54, 59, 66,
individualism 89–90, 94–95, 98–104, 109, 111, 121–22,
Collins, Ronald, 223 132, 136, 158, 192, 234, 252, 279, 301,
communication, 126, 166, 190, 206, 216, 323n24; and a√ective, 204–205; and rea-
222–23, 235, 241, 252, 254, 265, 288, 292; soning, 108, 198; and sympathy, 199, 201
in community, 238; democratic, 242–43, deliberativists, 252, 254, 255, 258
249; ideal, 68, 232–33, 236 Democracy and Education (Dewey), 5
communitarianism, 228, 242, 249, 255, 258, democracy, 224, 226, 240, 255, 259, 260–99,
304 308; as experience, 225, 252, 292; as ideal,
community, 10, 84, 119, 166, 178, 180, 184, 67, 74, 154, 200, 219, 238, 248, 263, 270,
201, 211, 213, 216, 225, 228–31, 236, 250, 276–77, 286, 290; conditions for, 222,
259, 273, 298; characteristics of, 222, 267; 259; justification of, 58, 262, 287; obsta-
‘‘Great Community,’’ 229–30; ideal, 68, cles to, 167, 244, 249, 285, 287; as politi-
172, 217, 221, 240, 276, 298; and indi- cal system, 218–19, 225; and starting
viduality, 220, 242. See also relations, point, 74, 257; values of, 10, 13, 70, 304;
social as way of life, 218, 244, 247, 290, 293
conduct, 44, 59–60, 70, 119, 125–28, 130–33, deontology, 2, 29, 33, 93, 129, 303, 314n21
140–42, 144, 158, 182, 203, 211, 213, 301, Descartes, René, 24; Cartesian philosophy,
303–304 123, 213, 262–63, 312n25
conflict, 45, 90, 92, 94–95, 120, 233, 276, 277, designation, 30–32
279, 284 determinism, 282
conscientiousness, 187, 192, 195–97, 202, Dewey, John: Art as Experience, 8, 173;
208, 302, 320n3:11 Ethics, 5, 17, 94, 310n8, 320n3:11; ‘‘The
consciousness, 21, 32, 157; social, 232 Ethics of Democracy,’’ 272; Experience
consequences, 145, 149, 198 and Education, 286; Experience and
consequentialism, 2, 9, 33, 93, 100, 129, 149, Nature, 11, 17, 31, 76, 83, 104, 111, 171;
291, 302–303, 309n2, 311n19, 314n21 How We Think, 177; Human Nature and
conservatism, 65, 245, 299 Conduct, 5, 123, 313n3; Lectures on Ethics,
constraints, 54, 58–59 1900–1901, 170; Logic: The Theory of
context, 7, 13, 45, 48, 53, 60, 66, 122–23, 302; Inquiry, 8, 75, 111, 240, 264; ‘‘The Postu-
situational, 32, 40–41, 66, 118 late of Immediate Empiricism,’’ 11; The
contextualism, 7, 11, 41–42, 46, 47, 51–53, Quest for Certainty, 111; Reconstruction
56–58, 69, 75, 83, 85, 106, 131, 133, 140, in Philosophy, 5; Theory of Valuation, 111;
≥≥∏
index
≥≥π
index
God’s-eye point of view, 41, 42, 72, 119, 147, instrumentalism, 8, 62, 186, 263
160, 292, 304. See also Archimedean intellectualism, 28–29, 39, 45, 85, 90, 168
standpoint intellectualist fallacy, 101, 289
good, 2, 33, 42, 93, 94, 99, 137, 138–39, 159, intelligence, 9, 12, 13, 47, 50–51, 59, 66, 75,
210, 256, 266, 303 82, 109, 148, 165–66, 178, 189, 195–96,
Gouinlock, James, 30, 227 208–209, 211, 241, 253, 273, 302, 310n10;
social, 74, 239
Habermas, Jürgen, 127, 254, 267 interactions, 124, 127, 166, 298–99, 306, 308
habits, 22, 69, 72, 75, 88, 96, 97, 118, 121–24, Internet, 224, 231, 235
127, 151, 155, 158–61, 166, 168, 171, 178, intuition, 289, 315n16
193, 195, 244, 248, 253, 291, 302–303; and intuitionism, 40, 99
character, 131, 134, 136, 139, 142, 254; as
tools, 191, 306; and virtues, 187, 209, James, William, 2, 11, 67, 150, 225, 245, 279,
240. See also experience 294–95, 312n25, 316n1:3, 317n1; and
happiness, 143, 146, 217 Chautauqua community, 275–76
Hare, R. M., 34, 36–37, 317n3 Jamieson, Dale, 29
harmony, 113, 283 Johnson, Mark, 3
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 30 judgments, 9, 38–39, 45, 47, 48, 52–53, 59,
heterogeneity, 218 89, 93, 95–96, 98–99, 101–102, 104, 108,
Hickman, Larry, 12 115–19, 130, 158, 159, 166, 202, 205; and
Hildebrand, David, 120 valuation, 110, 111, 113. See also synthesis;
Hitler, Adolf, 65, 73, 284 valuation; valuing
Hobbes, Thomas, 257 justice, 199–200, 207, 266
homogeneity, 218, 238, 256–57, 298
homosexuality, 106–109, 317n8 Kadlec, Alison, and Public Agenda, 249
Honneth, Axel, 311n19 Kant, Immanuel, 2, 4, 30, 49, 130, 134, 200,
Hook, Sydney, 57–58, 117, 287, 316n20 203, 211
How We Think (Dewey), 177 Katz, Jon, 223
human nature, 9, 38 King, Martin Luther, Jr., 322n18
Human Nature and Conduct (Dewey), 5, Kloppenberg, James, 279
123, 313n3 knowledge, 28, 76, 86, 90–91, 107, 112, 116,
humanism, naturalistic, 117 177, 194, 199, 202, 253, 264, 289
humility, 77, 246, 282, 307
Huxley, Aldous, 223 language, moral, 34, 39
Lectures on Ethics, 1900–1901 (Dewey), 170
ideals, 42, 66–69, 73, 75, 144, 154, 166, 177, Lekan, Todd, 84
263, 270, 275–77, 291, 293, 302; as crit- Lenz, Gabriel, 232
icism, 67–68, 274 Lewis, C. I., 57–58, 63
imagination, 67, 97–99, 102, 123, 198, 205– liberalism, 8, 119, 221, 226, 242, 251, 258, 305
206, 264 licentiousness, moral, 57, 155
immanence, 272 life, moral, 45, 54, 87, 214; aesthetic, 51, 78,
individualism, 183, 213, 220, 226, 237, 241–42, 152, 165–66, 177, 180, 184, 187–88, 192,
249, 255, 267, 304. See also collectivism 201, 207, 211, 297, 305–306, 308; demo-
individuality, 84, 220–21, 232, 235–36, 244, cratic, 165–66, 184, 187, 192, 201, 211,
259, 268–69, 271, 274 305–306; ideal, 207, 297; intelligent, 180,
inquiry, 25–26, 69, 75, 86, 91, 94, 112–13, 117, 184, 187, 192, 201, 297, 305–306, 308;
119, 126–27, 155, 198, 204, 261; commu- unaesthetic, 46, 195, 202, 215, 219
nal, 243, 245 linguistics, 35, 39–40, 101, 115, 262
≥≥∫
index
≥≥Ω
index
racism, 234, 238 274, 278; and art, 8, 12, 116; and ethics,
Randall, John Herman, Jr., 324n12 17–19, 82, 83, 86, 101–102, 304; scientific
rationalism, 99, 199, 253 inquiry, 117–19, 240; and standpoint,
rationality, 37, 53, 206 34–35
Rawls, John, 30, 255, 258, 323n32 scientism, 37
realism, 28, 85, 91–92, 107, 114 selectivity, 21–22, 27, 62
reality, 27, 91–92, 107, 160, 243, 266 self, 3, 83, 114, 121, 124, 131, 137, 140–43, 146,
reason, 53, 90, 97–98, 103, 108, 133, 148, 166, 148–49, 158, 180, 184, 198–99, 202, 213,
169, 199–201, 204, 206 298, 301, 304; and acts, 143, 209; ideal,
reasonableness, 262, 289, 301 10, 172, 185, 298; self-centeredness, 214;
reasons, 36, 53, 109, 159, 289 self-control, 203; self-interest, 267; self-
receptivity, 77, 116 realization, 9, 143, 302, 311n19
Reconstruction in Philosophy (Dewey), 5 sense perception, 22
reductionism, 23, 28, 30, 83, 132, 138, 168 sensitivity, 32, 55, 183, 187, 192–93, 194–97,
reflection, 59, 65, 69, 95, 100, 107–10, 112, 199, 204, 208, 226, 271, 288, 302, 320n3:11;
117, 196, 206, 292. See also inquiry; to context, 241–42, 249, 257, 271, 277,
valuation 284
relations, 39, 68, 104–105, 128, 160, 215–18, separatism, 238
220, 228, 230–31, 248, 254, 264, 271, 273, sexism, 234
298; local, 231–32, 274–75; personal, Sisyphus, 150, 153
231–32, 306; social, 84, 275 situations, 41–42, 48–49, 53, 55–56, 59, 69,
relativism, 7, 38, 59, 115, 120, 169–71, 192, 86–87, 118–20, 123–24, 131, 134; present,
243, 258, 261, 262, 285, 304; cultural, 37, 157–58; situation ethics, 48, 50–51, 74–
119 75, 77, 159, 314n1; uniqueness of, 44, 47,
religion, 83, 167–68, 240, 268, 294 49, 62
representationalism, 263 skepticism, 6–7, 59, 61, 65, 77, 192, 262, 295,
republicanism, civic, 258 307–308, 316n26
responsibility, 155; civic, 232, 249 Skover, David, 223
rhythm, 173, 175, 182, 184, 205, 299. See also social psychology, 3, 17–18, 159, 313n3
balance solidarity, 72, 259; democratic, 282–83
right and wrong, 34, 37–38, 40, 43, 45–47, spectator view, 33, 147–48, 206, 268
56–57, 59, 61, 112, 177, 208, 256 stability, 57, 122, 149, 176–77, 191, 220, 232,
Rorty, Richard, 9, 65, 72, 258, 260–62, 307, 238, 244, 246, 273, 283, 299. See also
312n19 order
Ross, W. D., 40, 52, 102 Stocker, Michael, 36, 314n21
rules, 35, 45–51, 54, 56, 64, 68, 70, 73, 75, 90, Stout, Je√rey, 6
92, 96, 97–98, 118, 134, 136, 145, 151, 153– subjectivism, 12, 35, 42, 69, 82, 115–19, 121,
54, 159–60, 177, 179, 188, 194–95, 224, 156–57, 317n10. See also objectivism
235, 254, 277, 280, 289, 302–303, 306, survey, 103, 106, 109
308; and principles, 52, 57, 127, 140–41, sympathy, 187, 198–201, 204, 207–208, 216,
156 227, 235, 238, 265, 302
Russell, Bertrand, 29 synthesis, 96–97
Ryan, Alan, 184
Talisse, Robert, 254, 256
Sandel, Michael, 258, 281–82 technology, 12, 82, 219, 274, 278, 281–82,
Sartori, Giovanni, 269 284, 306
Schneewind, Jerome, 82 teleology, 9, 33, 93, 149, 186, 309n2, 311n19
science, 19, 116, 118, 126, 167, 169, 178, 261, tension, 276, 304, 322n18
≥∂≠
index
theoretical standpoint, 33–36 values, 45, 90, 93, 104, 110–11, 114–15, 118,
Theory of Valuation (Dewey), 111 127, 144, 159, 317n10
thought, qualitative, 86, 101 valuing, 95, 104–105, 107–13, 117–19, 192,
‘‘Three Independent Factors in Morals’’ 282, 317n10. See also valuation
(Dewey), 5, 33, 92, 94, 111 vice, 125, 187
Tiles, J. E., 311n19 violence, 284–86
Tocqueville, Alexis de, 244 virtue ethics, 33, 93, 129–30, 135–44, 185,
tolerance, 10, 235, 257, 259, 265, 284–85, 291, 256, 303, 314n21, 318n5:7
305, 323n32 virtues, 2, 33, 42, 55, 93, 94, 99, 125–27, 133–
top-down theory, 256, 266–67, 296, 306. See 35, 138–39, 141, 143–44, 146, 159, 187, 190,
also bottom-up theory 192, 206, 208–10, 253, 266, 303, 305; as
tradition, 67, 82, 123, 166, 169, 211, 244, 247, habits, 254. See also character
249 vulnerability, 191
transcendentalism, 150
trust, 77, 239 Welchman, Jennifer, 19, 311n19, 313n8
Tufts, James Hayden, 199–200 West, Cornel, 8, 223
Westbrook, Robert, 9, 12, 13, 57–58, 270,
uncertainty, 30, 95–96, 190, 220 287, 324n12, 326n43
undergoing, 235; and doing, 96, 104, 113 wholeheartedness, 210–12
unity, 127, 173, 220, 237, 249, 255, 257–59 will, 102, 134, 144, 202
universalism, 41, 171, 177, 220 Williams, Bernard, 40, 59, 61, 63, 65, 140–
universalization, 27, 314n29 41, 316n26
utilitarianism, 29, 30, 99–101, 134, 140, 143, wisdom, 68, 176, 180–81, 183, 249
146, 198–99, 201, 213, 224 Wolf, Susan, 61
utopia objection, 275–76 work, 178–80
Wright, Jennifer, 159
Valadez, Jorge, 256
valuation, 95, 104–13, 117–18, 192–93, 195, Young, Iris Marion, 252, 258
288, 317n10. See also valuing
≥∂∞
Gregory Fernando Pappas is Associate Professor of Philosophy at
Texas A&M University. He is the author of numerous articles on the
philosophy of William James and John Dewey. He has been the recipient
of a Ford Foundation Postdoctoral Fellowship as well as the William
James and the Latin American Thought prizes by the American
Philosophical Association.