Multilateralism and Institutions
Multilateralism and Institutions
Multilateralism and Institutions
Institutions in an Era
of Globalization
Edited by
Dimitris Bourantonis, Kostas Ifantis and
Panayotis Tsakonas
First published 2008
by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN
Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada
by Routledge
270 Madison Ave, New York, NY 10016
This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2007.
“To purchase your own copy of this or any of Taylor & Francis or Routledge’s
collection of thousands of eBooks please go to www.eBookstore.tandf.co.uk.”
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business
© 2008 Selection and editorial matter, Dimitris Bourantonis, Kostas Ifantis
and Panayotis Tsakonas; individual chapters, the contributors
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or
reproduced or utilized in any form or by any electronic,
mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter
invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any
information storage or retrieval system, without permission in
writing from the publishers.
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
Introduction 1
DIMITRIS BOURANTONIS, KOSTAS IFANTIS AND
PANAYOTIS TSAKONAS
PART I
Multilateralism and security: concepts, issues and strategies 19
PART II
Assessing multilateral security institutions 181
References 324
Index 359
Figures
The perception of the Cold War nuclear era in the West was of a clear and
present threat from the Soviet Union that had to be matched by the United
States and its allies. The Cold War superimposed on the international security
agenda a political and conceptual framework that simplified most issues,
while magnifying some and obscuring others. During this period, almost
every Western government defined national security in excessively narrow,
military terms. That meant there was an enduring acceptance of the need for
a balance of terror, with mutually assured destruction ensuring a stable inter-
national system. The end of the Cold War has allowed for burgeoning of the
security agenda to include a different set of threats and dangers, not really
new but previously kept outside the Cold War context. These new threats are
again global in scope, persistent in nature, and potent in their implications
(Lynn-Jones and Miller 1995: 3).
Among the new factors that transcend boundaries and threaten to erode
national cohesion, the most perilous are the “new risks”: drug trafficking,
transnational organized crime and nuclear smuggling, refugee movements,
uncontrolled and illegal immigration, environmental risks, and international
terrorism. As already noted, these are not new sources of potential conflict.
They all existed to some extent during the Cold War, but were largely sub-
sumed by the threat of military conflict between NATO and the Warsaw Pact.
A new/old issue is the proliferation of Weapons of Mass Destruction (WMD)
and Nuclear, Biological, Chemical, and Radiological (NBCR) agents. The
issue of proliferation is profoundly old, but the dimension of threat is new.
Indeed, trans-sovereign problems – problems that move beyond sovereignty
and traditional state responses – have started to fill the post-Cold War agenda
and make a mockery of state borders and unilateral state responses. The rise
of trans-sovereign problems has been made possible by changes since the end
of the Cold War: the opening of societies, economies, and technologies
(Cusimano 2000: 4).
2 Dimitris Bourantonis, Kostas Ifantis, and Panayotis Tsakonas
The spread of religious fundamentalism, the “criminalization” of state
institutions and economic transactions, the increase in cross-border narcotics
trafficking, and the potential proliferation of WMD represent an interrelated
network of transnational challenges to states and societies in regions like the
Caspian, Caucasus, Central Asia, North Africa, and (to a lesser extent) South-
east Europe, and they can serve as a potential catalyst for future conflicts.
Moreover, trans-sovereign issues present a very difficult dilemma for policy
makers: the very same policies that work to bring about open, democratic,
pluralist societies and open markets also make trans-sovereign threats pos-
sible. It is obvious that these problems can be difficult for states to address,
because effective action requires greater international co-ordination.
The same can be true for environmental problems, which are profoundly
trans-sovereign in nature: they do not respect state borders and they defy
unilateral state action. Recent times have witnessed an explosion of attention
to and concern about environmental challenges, which have become much
more salient in public discourse, more prominent in media coverage, more
visible and important in political deliberations. Indeed, the environment has
become a significant factor in international politics. Although not all
environmental problems are relevant to international security, many of them
can be a source of political conflict and can contribute to violence within and
between states. In any case, much depends on the capacity of states to adapt
and respond to the social and economic effects of environmental degradation
– for example, reduced agricultural production, declining economic perform-
ance, the displacement of populations, the disruption or even destruction of
communal relations, and the collapse of legitimate authority.
The developing world is particularly vulnerable to the social consequences
of eco-problems, because those states have fewer or no technical, financial,
and institutional resources to devote to containing or coping with the con-
sequences. In such cases, conflicts are easily born of scarcity, deprivation, or
ethnic, racial, or cultural strife exacerbated by scarcity and deprivation
(Homer-Dixon 1995). It is beyond doubt that environmental degradation
leads to refugee flows and violent conflicts, thus undermining state institu-
tions and authority, as occurred in Chiapas in Mexico, and in Rwanda. The
flow of refugees can cause further environmental damage, which in turn adds
more pressure on state authority and economic capacity, thus providing
fertile ground for drug trafficking and organized criminal activity.
Trans-sovereign problems tend to be mutually reinforcing.
Refugee movements, along with uncontrolled or illegal immigration, repre-
sent yet another non-traditional threat to international security and stability.
Refugees place economic and social burdens on government services, burdens
that have become substantial. In some cases they have overwhelmed and
drained the already fragile institutions and infrastructure of host states,
resulting in violent conflicts and military interventions. Former Yugoslavia is
a case in point. There are 30 to 40 million people displaced across state
boundaries or within states, and this figure is expected to rise.
Introduction 3
As a result, numerous countries in Europe are beginning to re-examine
their immigration policies and enforce more stringent standards, thus moving
towards neo-conservative, undemocratic practices. This could have a destabil-
izing effect on the less economically advanced nations in Europe and could
threaten inter-state relations. It also could lead to domestic unrest if more is
not done soon to regulate the flow of refugees and expedite safe repatriation
of those not accepted for long-term residence. Such policies will almost
inevitably result in much suffering and not a little “militant migration” as
marginalized migrants are radicalized. In the interim, Europe is experiencing
an increase in crime rates and hatred crimes, any of which could lead to
instability and thence to conflict and insecurity.
At the same time, international terrorism has become more than ever a
source of grave concern. This was true even before 11 September 2001, but
“9/11” finally answered the question of what the dominant security problem
in the post-Cold War world is: “mega-terrorism”, a non-state form of terror-
ism in which a readiness to take life knows no limits (Muller 2003: 7). Con-
straints on the use of violence are not effective. There are no bounds to the
number of fatalities a group like al-Qaeda wishes to cause. The new breed of
terrorist seems to want only to kill, create havoc and cause destruction on a
massive scale; in most cases they are not seeking to negotiate to achieve certain
objectives; they are very well organized, trained, funded, and supported; and
their worldwide networks include an excellent intelligence and communications
structure that gives them enough information about their targets to be able to
direct their operatives, often over the internet, from thousands of miles away.
The challenge has been enormous, especially for the United States.
Post-Cold War global processes have been changing the nature of threat and
forcing some adaptation of basic strategic principles, and the patterns of
allegiance associated with them. Each of these dimensions – threat, strategy,
and affiliation – is understood most readily “in terms of a sharp conceptual
distinction: the difference between a deliberate opponent and a natural pro-
cess, between strategies of prevention and strategies of reaction, and between
cooperative and confrontational alignments” (Steinbruner 2000: 195). Secur-
ity challenges become more complex when one turns to those issues that may
not directly challenge the viability of the state, in traditional terms, but may
nevertheless undermine its sovereignty, compromise its ability to control
the penetrability of its borders, and exacerbate relations – either between
groups within the polity or between states in the regional or global system.
Moreover, the 9/11 terrorist attacks by militant Muslims, the subsequent
counter-terrorist campaigns in Afghanistan and Pakistan, and the war
against Saddam’s regime in Iraq have further changed the post-Cold War
security discourse.
4 Dimitris Bourantonis, Kostas Ifantis, and Panayotis Tsakonas
Throughout the 1990s, the security debate remained rather tentative,
unfocused and vague. The formulations of threat now in use – ranging from
major regional contingencies, via lesser nationalist or fundamentalist war-
prone regimes and groups, to the eventual emergence of peer competitors –
refer to the deliberately aggressive actions of calculating enemies, who are
assumed to have conscious identity even if they are not mentioned explicitly.
Armed conflicts like the ones in Kosovo and Afghanistan have clearly dem-
onstrated the difficulty of anticipating and meeting the new problems that
have arisen from the debris of the old order.
The scope of political change and the complexities of international
security are making the new challenges much harder to understand. All the
above represent a new class of security problem, in which dispersed processes
pose dangers of potentially large magnitude and incalculable probability. In
reaction to those problems, policies seem to be shifting from contingency
reaction to anticipatory prevention, pre-emptive action and coalitional crisis
management. In that context, contemporary security discourse seems to be
aimed at taking account of security’s geographical and functional scope, its
degree of institutionalization, its strength and fragility, and its ideological
and normative elements. Also, more often than in the past, there are new and
sometimes unexpected linkages between political, security and economic
concerns, which have challenged the capacity of the state to recognize and
respond to new dangers and needs for action. They have also challenged
international institutions – the adequacy of existing bodies for action, and
the potential for multilateral co-ordination.
The 9/11 terrorist attacks truly changed the world security system. The scale
of these attacks, the destruction they caused, the relative ease with which they
were organized and executed against the most powerful country in the world,
made it very clear to everybody that no country was immune. The attacks
that followed in Madrid and London showed that no country could afford to
be complacent about terrorism any more. Like drug traffickers, nuclear
smugglers, and international crime cartels, terrorist groups take advantage of
the infrastructure that open societies, open economies, and open technologies
afford. Such groups are more easily able to move people, money, and goods
across international borders thanks to democratization, economic liberaliza-
tion, and technological advances. They rely on international telecommunica-
tions to publicize their acts and political demands. Even if propaganda is
nothing new, tools like CNN and the Internet dramatically extend the scope
of a terrorist’s reach. Terrorists also take advantage of weaker or developing
states to serve as operational bases for training and carrying out attacks
against Western targets. As the 11 September attacks indicated, counter-state
Introduction 5
and counter-society abilities have already become more available to radical
and fundamentalist groups. Overall these trends suggest that seemingly
invulnerable states, however powerful and wealthy they may be, have innate
weaknesses.
All these trends, probably as much as the proliferation of weapons of mass
destruction (nuclear, chemical, and biological) and their means of delivery as
well as human-rights abuses, pose profound challenges to efforts to build a
new global order. They contribute to terrorist groups’ capability for violence
and other forms of coercion. Contrary to other global challenges (the com-
munications revolution, water shortages, access to energy resources, financial
flows), they call directly into question the very authority of the state, and are
therefore potentially, if not openly, subversive. However, this multifaceted
conception of security entails a multifaceted approach to security. That does
not mean analysis cannot be state-centered. Rather, it means that, while a
state-centered analysis is capable of illuminating most facets of discord and
conflict in the 1990s (for example, proxy wars and irredentism), it should
acquire a multidimensional optic, beyond accounts of military power
distribution.
This multifaceted/multidimensional security concept means that there is
no rigid link between a comprehensive concept for understanding a new
situation and the quality of the response. On the contrary, a broad concept –
where military force and defense policy continue to occupy a central place
– allows a flexible, tailored policy in which force is a major element, but
only one of the means that could be employed. In the final analysis, security
is a politically defined concept. It is open to debate whether the widening
of security might be a good or a bad political choice, but security is
not intrinsically a self-contained concept, nor can it be related to military
affairs only. If political priorities change, the nature and the means of
security will inevitably follow and adapt to the different areas of political
action.
In an age of protean threats, transnational in nature, trans-sovereign in
quality, and coupled with insidious weapons of enormous destructive cap-
ability, the only way forward seems to be through co-operation, preparedness,
vigilance, and creative diplomacy. The tools to make a safer world already
exist: political fora, international law, economic levers, intelligence assets, and
(where necessary) military power. What remains to be harnessed is a collect-
ive will to succeed, a will grounded in the UN Universal Declaration of
Human Rights and the International Law.
Moreover, the deepening of global interdependence has bred multiple
transnational problems that no country can resolve on its own, from humani-
tarian catastrophes to financial instability, from environmental degradation
to terrorism and weapons of mass destruction. By implication, and given the
spread of liberal principles and the rise of a new global agenda, multilateral-
ism would seem to offer the USA the obvious way to advance its national
interests, pursue common objectives, and exercise leadership. Yet, the United
6 Dimitris Bourantonis, Kostas Ifantis, and Panayotis Tsakonas
States has been deeply ambivalent about multilateral engagement (Patrick
2002: 2).
In fact, instead of viewing multilateralism as a tool for expanding – rather
than limiting – US options, the G. W. Bush Jr. administration clearly indicated
from the outset its intention to pursue unilateral strategies. Based on a state-
centric world view in the most traditional sense – formed by a concern with
traditional conceptions of security, such as great powers, rogue states, and
proliferation of WMD – and equipped with unmatched military capacity and
the world’s largest national economy, Washington has found multilateral co-
operation constraining. This is not surprising, because multilateralism
implies a relationship based on rules rather than power, with states agreeing
that behavior on a certain issue should be governed by shared principles, rules
and norms, regardless of individual interests and circumstances (Caporaso
1993: 53–4). US policy makers have also been sensitive to potential patholo-
gies of multilateral institutions, such as “free-riding” and “buck-passing”, while
viewing the institutions as constraints that could slow decisions, dilute object-
ives, and even entangle the United States in foreign adventures on behalf of
global agendas.
By implication, multilateralism was seen as carrying certain costs for a
dominant power like the United States and did not appear to be a very
attractive grand strategy or/and foreign-policy option. Instead, the com-
bination of unprecedented military might and the most vibrant single
national economy drove the political and military strategy of “engagement
and enlargement” that has become the lynchpin of US foreign and
national security policy. Indeed, the 1991 Gulf war, the 1995 and 1999
Balkan campaigns, and most of all the 2001 Afghanistan intervention and
the spring 2003 war against Iraq have been impressive US exhibitions of
its capacity to go to war. They have demonstrated that military power is
not obsolete.
Indeed, the most profound effect of 9/11 has been the reordering of Ameri-
ca’s international engagement, coupled with reinforcement of the administra-
tion’s strident unilateralism. America’s attempt to make its own international
rules is the most vivid example of unilateralism. Washington pushes a mili-
tary agenda that aims self-confidently to master the “contested zones”
because it believes that primacy depends only on vast, omni-capable military
power. It also believes that the USA need not tolerate plausible threats to its
safety from outside American territory. These threats are to be eliminated.
Insofar as pre-emptive war is perceived negatively abroad, this strategy
requires a unilateral, global, offensive military capability. The effort to
achieve such a capability will further alienate America’s traditional allies, it
will definitely produce balancing tendencies, it will drive the costs of sustain-
ing US military pre-eminence to unacceptable levels, and it will thus create
great difficulties in sustaining, improving, and expanding the global network
of US military bases (Posen 2003: 45). Most importantly, with its pre-emptive
strategies and tendency to treat different global challenges as being all in the
Introduction 7
same category, the Bush doctrine is seen as damaging the fabric of inter-
national law and the world multilateral acquis.
In that context, the Iraq war has been a crisis for the United States,
because UN members saw a prospect of unchecked American power being
tested. For many around the world the Iraq war is viewed as a step towards
seizing global energy control, or hegemonic world economic and trade dom-
ination, or to assure Israel’s ambitions. They have seen the United States as
being unable to provide a rationale for its Iraq policy that can convince the
majority of the democracies, its natural supporters. They have seen it
intemperately denounce those who criticize it. In short, they have seen Wash-
ington demand submission and take steps to obtain it by force. To the rest of
the world, this is not very reassuring, to put it mildly. Unchecked American
global power seems to be rapidly losing its appeal. Indeed, rather than prov-
ing the unilateralists’ point, Iraq illustrates the continuing need for co-
operation and a return to multilateralism as a rich source of legitimacy and
order.
one should turn to the more general theoretical literature on the signifi-
cance of international institutions, identifying where possible the distinct
ways in which international security institutions might (or might not) make
a difference. Especially international security is an issue-area, which can
provide a particularly valuable arena for adjudicating among the compet-
ing claims of different theories insofar as it is the area where theorists of all
stripes have expected international institutions to be least consequential.
(Duffield 2006: 639)
Notes
1 As all the contributions in Part II deal with (mostly the effects of) particular multi-
lateral security institutions, such as the UN, EU and NATO, this volume adheres to
the definition of international institutions given by Robert Keohane, who includes
international organizations in his definition of international institutions (Keohane
1989: 3–4).
2 For the need of future research undertakings to follow these directions, see Schim-
melfennig (2002: 22).
Part I
They can fashion structures to insulate their favorable agencies and pro-
grams from the future exercise of public authority. In doing so, of course,
they will not only be reducing their enemies’ opportunities for future
control; they will be reducing their own opportunities as well. But this is
often a reasonable price to pay, given the alternative. And because they
get to go first, they are really not giving up control – they are choosing to
exercise a greater measure of it ex ante, through insulated structures that,
once locked in, predispose the agency to do the right things. What they
are moving away from – because it is dangerous – is the kind of ongoing
hierarchical control that is exercised through the discretionary decisions
of public authority over time.
Several hypotheses follow immediately from this model of state power and
institutions. First, a leading state should try to lock other states into insti-
tutionalized policy orientations, while trying to minimize its own limitations
on policy autonomy and discretionary power. This is the story that Michael
Crozier tells about politics within large-scale organizations. Each individual
within a complex organizational hierarchy is continually engaged in a dual
struggle: to tie his colleagues to precise rule-based behavior – thereby creating
a more stable and certain environment in which to operate – while also trying
to retain as much autonomy and discretion as possible for himself (Crozier
1964). Similarly, leading states will try to lock other states in as much as
possible while also trying to remain as unencumbered as possible by insti-
tutional rules and obligations. Second, the leading state will make use of its
ability – to the extent the ability exists – to limit its capacity to exercise power
in indiscriminate and arbitrary ways as a “currency” to buy the institutional
co-operation of other states.
The availability of the institutional bargain will depend on several cir-
cumstances that can also be specified as hypotheses. First, the amount of
26 G. John Ikenberry
“currency” available to the leading state to buy institutional co-operation
of weaker states is determined by two factors: the ability of the leading state
to potentially dominate or injure the interests of weaker states and its ability
to credibly restrain itself from doing so. Although all states might offer to
restrain and commit themselves in exchange for concessions by other states,
the willingness and ability of powerful states to do so will be of particular
interest to other states. Chad may offer to lock itself into an institutional
agreement that lowers its policy autonomy and make its future policy orienta-
tion more predictable, but few states will care much about this offer to bind
itself and they are not likely to offer much in return to get it. But if a powerful
state with the capacity for serious domination and disruption offers to
restrain itself – this will get the attention of other states and they are likely to
be willing to offer something to get it. But it is not just the domination and
disruption potential of the leading state that generates “currency” to buy the
institutional co-operation of other states. It is also the capacity to actually
make good on restraint and commitment. If a powerful state cannot credibly
limit its power, its currency will amount to very little.
Two other factors will also determine if the leading state – if it has the
“currency” with which to buy institutional co-operation – will in fact want to
do so. One is the degree to which the leading state is in fact interested in
locking in the policy behavior of other states. This is a question about the
extent to which the actions of other states actually impinge on the interests of
the leading state. The security policy orientation of Europe states would tend
to qualify as important, but other policy orientations of European states –
and the wide range of policy orientations of other states around the world –
are not significant enough to justify efforts by the leading state to lock in
stable and favorable policy behavior, particularly if the price of doing so
entails a reduction of policy autonomy. The other factor is simply the ability
of weaker states to be locked in. The United States may want to lock in the
policy behavior of other states – particularly the security policy behavior –
but not have enough confidence that these institutionalized commitments and
obligations can be effectively locked in.
Taken together, these considerations allow us to see how a leading state and
weaker states might make trade offs about binding themselves together
through multilateral institutions. The four factors are summarized in Table
1.1. The more that the leading state is capable of dominating and abandoning
weaker states, the more that weaker states will care about restraints on the
leading state’s exercise of power – and the more they are likely to make some
concessions to get leading state restraint and commitment. Similarly, the
more that a potentially dominating state can in fact credibly restrain and
commit itself, the more that weaker states will be interested in pursuing an
institutional bargain. When both these conditions hold – when the leading
state can dominate and abandon, and when it can restrain and commit itself –
that state will be particularly willing and able to pursue an institutional bar-
gain. From the perspective of the leading state, the less important that the
State power and international institutions 27
Variable Implications
[i]t was neither in the interest of the United States to create institutions
that would have constrained independent decision making in Washington
nor in the interest of subordinate states to enter institutions in which they
would have minimal control while foregoing opportunities for free-riding
and dependence reduction. Extreme hegemony thus led to a system of
State power and international institutions 31
bilateral relations between states rather than a multilateral system that
emerged in the North Atlantic area around the North Atlantic Treaty
Organization (NATO) and the European Community.
This view is also consistent with the more recent developments. As American
hegemony has declined in relative terms within east Asia and as the United
States has developed more specific lock-in goals for the states within the
region, its interest in multilateral institutional building has increased some-
what (Crone 1993). American support for APEC – while not an institution
that requires much, if any, real policy restraint by the United States – is
emblematic of this new multilateralism in Asia.
In the long run there can be only three possibilities for the future of west-
ern and central Europe. One is German domination. Another is Russian
domination. The third is a federated Europe, into which the parts of
Germany are absorbed but in which the influence of the other countries
is sufficient to hold Germany in her place. If there is no real European fed-
eration and if Germany is restored as a strong and independent country,
we must expect another attempt at German domination.4
Two years later, Kennan was again arguing that “without federation there
is no adequate framework within which adequately to handle the German
problem.”5
If NATO bound both West Germany and the United States to Europe, it
also reinforced British and French commitment to an open and united
Europe. The United States not only was intent on the rehabilitation and
reintegration of Germany, but it also wanted to reorientate Europe itself. In
an echo of Wilson’s critique of the “old politics” of Europe after World
War I, American officials after 1945 emphasized the need for reform of
nationalist and imperialist tendencies. It was generally thought that the best
way to do so was to encourage integration. Regional integration would not
only make Germany safe for Europe, it would also make Europe safe for the
world. The Marshall Plan reflected this American thinking, as did Truman
administration support for the Brussels Pact, the European Defence Com-
munity (EDC), and the Schuman Plan. In the negotiations over the NATO
treaty in 1948, American officials made clear to the Europeans that a security
commitment hinged on European movement toward integration. One State
Department official remarked that the United States would not “rebuild a
fire-trap.”6 The American goal was, as Dean Acheson put it in reference to the
EDC, “to reverse incipient divisive nationalist trends on the continent.”7
American congressional support for the Marshall Plan was also premised, at
least in part, on not just transferring American dollars to Europe but also on
encouraging integrative political institutions and habits.
When Marshall Plan aid was provided to Europe, beginning in 1948, the
American government insisted that the Europeans themselves organize to
jointly allocate the funds. This gave rise to the Organization for European
Economic Co-operation (OEEC), which was the institutional forerunner
of the European Community. This body eventually became responsible for
European-wide supervision of economic reconstruction, and it began to
involve the Europeans in discussion of joint economic management. As one
State power and international institutions 35
American official recalls, the OEEC “instituted one of the major innovations
of postwar international co-operation, the systematic country review, in
which the responsible national authorities are cross-examined by a group of
their peers together with a high-quality international staff. In those reviews,
questions are raised which in prewar days would have been considered a gross
and unacceptable foreign interference in domestic affairs.”8 The United States
encouraged European integration as a bulwark against intra-European con-
flict even as it somewhat more reluctantly agreed to institutionalize its own
security commitment to Europe.
The various elements of the institutional bargain among the Atlantic coun-
tries fit together. The Marshall Plan and NATO were part of a larger insti-
tutional package. As Lloyd Gardner argues: “Each formed part of a whole.
Together they were designed to “mold the military character” of the Atlantic
nations, prevent the balkanization of European defense systems, create an
internal market large enough to sustain capitalism in Western Europe, and
lock in Germany on the Western side of the Iron Curtain” (Gardner 1984:
81). NATO was a security alliance, but it was also embraced as a device to
lock in political and economic relations within the Atlantic area.
Taken together, American power after the war left the European more
worried about abandonment than domination and they actively sought
American institutionalized commitments to Europe. Multiple layers of multi-
lateral economic, political, and security institutions bound these countries
together, reinforcing the credibility of their mutual commitments. The dra-
matic asymmetries of postwar power were rendered more acceptable as a
result. As the post-1945 period unfolded, American lock-in goals for Europe
expanded. Stabilizing the European economies, solving the German problem,
and reorientating British and French security policies required much more
“engineering” than American officials at first expected. To get these insti-
tutional concessions by Europe also entailed reluctant American willingness
to make an institutionalized security commitment and reduce its policy
autonomy.
After eight years during which foreign policy success was largely measured
by the number of treaties the president could sign and the number of
summits he could attend, we now have an administration willing to assert
American freedom of action and the primacy of American national inter-
ests. Rather than contain power within a vast web of constraining inter-
national agreements, the new unilateralism seeks to strengthen American
power and unashamedly deploy it on behalf of self-defined global ends.13
State power and international institutions 39
Indeed, Richard Holbrooke, former US ambassador to the UN has charged
that the Bush administration threatens to make “a radical break with fifty-
five years of a bipartisan tradition that sought international agreements and
regimes of benefit to us.”14
This is surely part of the explanation. But the international context in
which the United States is making decisions about institutional commitments
has also changed. In particular, the rise of unipolarity and the shifting char-
acter of international threats have altered the “values” that go into institu-
tional bargaining calculations by the United States and its postwar partners.
The rise of unipolarity gives the United States a near-monopoly on global
military power. Increased power advantages give the United States more
freedom of action. It is easier for Washington to say no to other countries or
to go it alone. Growing power – military, economic, technological – also gives
the United States more opportunities to control outcomes around the world.
But unipolarity also creates problems of governance. Without bipolar or
multipolar competition, it is not clear what can discipline or render predict-
able American power. Other countries worry more than in the past about
domination, exploitation, and abandonment. They may not be able to organ-
ize a counter-balancing alliance, but they can resist and undermine American
policies. At the very least, they would like to see the unipolar state tied down
through institutional constraints in the manner at the heart of the postwar
institutional bargain.
So unipolarity alters the terms of the institutional bargain. The United
States does not need other countries as much under conditions of unipolarity,
so – everything else being equal – it is less willing to reduce its policy auton-
omy. It would in fact like to use its rising power position to reduce its binding
institutional obligations. Other countries, on the other hand, have growing
worry about American power, and so they in fact would like to see more
restrictions in American policy autonomy.
The second shift in the international environment that alters the insti-
tutional bargain is the shift in security threats. Under the bipolar Cold War,
the United States and its institutional partners were all threatened by the same
external threat – Soviet communism. Indeed, front-line states in Europe and
Asia actually, in some ways, felt the threat more immediately and intensely
than the United States. But the upshot of the security situation was that the
United States had security to offer and other countries wanted the American
provision of security. The end of the Cold War changed this situation. The
rise of terrorist threats compounds this shift. Now it is the United States that
feels threatened – but it does so in a way that other states do not experience.
There is a growing divide in the experience of “insecurity.” The United States
feels insecurity but other states are only secondarily able to be of assistance in
addressing America’s security problem. Other states do not feel the same
threats – and they are less dependent on the United States for the provision of
security. These multiple shifts have the same effect – they reduce incentives on
both sides for an institutional bargain on security (Ikenberry 2005).
40 G. John Ikenberry
In other areas, the rise of unipolarity or new security threats should not
directly impact on the institutional bargain. This is most obviously true in
terms of the world economy. American support for multilateralism is indeed
likely to be sustained – even in the face of resistance and ideological chal-
lenges to multilateralism in the Bush administration – in part because of a
simple logic: as global economic interdependence grows, the need for multi-
lateral co-ordination of policies also grows. The more economically intercon-
nected that states become, the more dependent they are for the realization of
their objectives on the actions of other states. Rising economic interdepend-
ence is one of the great hallmarks of the contemporary international system.
If this remains true in the years ahead, it is easy to predict that the demands
for multilateralism – even and perhaps especially by the United States – will
increase and not decrease.
Conclusion
Several general conclusions can be offered. First, there is a general insti-
tutional logic that combines the instincts of both realist and liberal theory.
Institutional bargains are driven by concerns about policy autonomy, legit-
imacy, the exercise of power, and political certainty. The struggle is to pro-
mote as predictable and favorable international environment in which to
operate. States are self-interested actors who jealously guard their policy
autonomy and sovereign authority, but who also are willing to bargain if
the price is right. Ironically, it is precisely the asymmetry of power that creates
the potential mutually beneficial exchange. The leading state has an incen-
tive to take advantage of its newly dominant position to lock in a favorable
set of international relationships – institutionalizing its pre-eminence. The
subordinate states are willing to lock themselves in – at least up to some point
– if it means that the leading state will be more manageable as a dominant
power.
Second, this model assumes that institutions can play a role in muting
asymmetries in power – thereby allowing the leading state to calculate its
interests over a longer time frame, with institutions serving as a mechanism to
invest in future gains, and allowing the weaker states to be confident that
there can be credible restraints on the arbitrary and indiscriminate exercise of
power. If institutions are unable to play this role, than the calculations and
trade-offs that are highlighted in the model are not likely to be of much
consequence. But American officials themselves have acted in a way that
suggests that at least they think institutions can in fact play such a shaping
and restraining role.
Third, the actual costs and benefits behind the trade-off between policy
autonomy and policy lock-in are difficult to specify in advance. The postwar
crisis in Europe and the multiple engineering tasks that the United States saw
as absolutely critical were real enough and they justified the restraints and
commitments that the United States offered to get these institutionalized
State power and international institutions 41
arrangements in Europe. But some of the other lock-in goals – such as eco-
nomic reforms, human rights standards, and war crimes laws – are not easy to
evaluate as goals worthy of X or Y amount of reduced policy autonomy.
Because of this the institutional model is perhaps better at identifying a
dilemma that states face and less effective at specifying in advance how the
trade-offs will be made.
Notes
This chapter is adapted from G.J. Ikenberry (2003) “State Power and the Institutional
Bargain: America’s Ambivalent Economic and Security Multilateralism,” in R. Foot,
S. Neil MacFarlane and M. Mastanduno (eds) US Hegemony and International Organ-
izations: The United States and Multilateral Institutions, New York: Oxford University
Press, pp. 49–70.
1 Institutions are potentially sticky for at least three reasons. First, they can create
difficult and demanding legal or political procedures for altering or discontinuing
the institutional agreement. Second, the institution can itself over time become an
actor, gaining some independence from states and actively promoting institutional
compliance and continuity. Third, growing vested interests – groups with stakes in
the success and continuation of the institution – along with other positive feed-
back effects produce “increasing returns” to institutions that raise the costs of
ending or replacing the institutions. This view of institutions can be contrasted
with two other perspectives. One is a more narrowly drawn rationalist account that
sees institutions as contracts – agreements that remain in force only so long as the
specific interests that gain from the agreement remain in place. It is the interests
and not the institution that are sticky. The other view is a constructivist view that
sees institutions and the institutionalization of inter-state relations as built upon
shared ideas and identities.
2 To the extent that the locking in of institutional commitments and obligations is
mutual – that is, the leading state also locks itself in, at least to some extent – this
makes the asymmetrical relationship more acceptable and legitimate to the weaker
and secondary states. This, in turn, reduces the enforcement costs.
3 On the ways in which NATO multilateralism restrained the American exercise of
power, see Weber (1993).
4 See “Report of the Policy Planning Staff,” 24 February 1948, Foreign Relations of
the United States, 1948, I, Part 2 (Washington, DC: US Government Printing
Office), p. 515.
5 See “Minutes of the Seventh Meeting of the Policy Planning Staff,” 24 January
1950, Foreign Relations of the United States, 1950, III (Washington, DC: US
Government Printing Office), p. 620.
6 See “Minutes of the Fourth Meeting of the Washington Exploratory Talks on
Security,” 8 July 1948, Foreign Relations of the United States, 1948, III (Washing-
ton, DC: US Government Printing Office), pp. 163–9.
7 See “The Secretary of State to the Embassy in France,” 19 October 1949, Foreign
Relations of the United States, 1949, IV (Washington, DC: US Government Printing
Office), p. 471.
8 L. Gordon in Ellwood (1989: 48–9).
9 Interview of Robert B. Zoellick (US State Dept), 28 May 1999.
10 See A. Lake, “From Containment to Enlargement,” Vital Speeches of the Day, 60
(15 October 1993).
11 Interview, Robert B. Zoellick, 28 May 1999.
42 G. John Ikenberry
12 For an overview of this shift in American policy toward institutions under the
Bush administration, see Daalder and Lindsey (2003).
13 See C. Krauthammer, “The New Unilateralism,” Washington Post, 8 June 2001,
p. A29.
14 Quoted in T.S. Purdum, “Embattled, Scrutinized, Powell Soldiers On,” New York
Times, 25 July 2002, p. 1.
2 Unipolar empire and principled
multilateralism as strategies for
international change
Jack Snyder and Leslie Vinjamuri
Enthusiasts for international change have put forward two strikingly different
strategies for promoting a more democratic and just international order, one
unilateralist and the other multilateralist. Both are problematic because both
are based on flawed theories of social change.
During the 1990s, the loudest lobbyists for change were principled trans-
national activist groups in league with like-minded officials in international
organizations, idealistic international lawyers, and liberal internationalists in
some powerful democratic governments. Using the multilateralist tools of
transnational civil society networks and international organizations, with
intermittent help from liberal states, they promoted a universalistic agenda of
human rights, democratization, civil society promotion, peacekeeping, peace-
building and juridical accountability. The legacy of their handiwork has
included the liberation of Kosovo from Serbian tyranny, the trial of Slobodan
Milosevic, the extradition of Augusto Pinochet, the creation of the Inter-
national Criminal Court (ICC), and the democratic enlargement of the EU,
but it also includes the passivity of the UN peacekeepers during the Srebrenica
massacre and the Rwanda genocide, as well as internationally mandated vot-
ing that triggered mass violence in Burundi in 1993 and in East Timor in 1999.
After September 2001, the initiative for promoting international change
shifted to the Bush administration, and the neo-conservative ideologists who
articulated its principles. Like the principled multilateralists’ agenda, this
strategy too stressed the goal of promoting democracy and bringing evil-
doers to justice as means to end threats to global peace and security, but its
means were distinctively unilateralist, military, and non-legalistic. The mixed
legacy of its handwork has been the invasions of Afghanistan and Iraq,
disputes over the application of international legal principles to perpetrators
of atrocities and prisoners, and the election in Middle Eastern states of can-
didates favoring terrorism (Hamas in the Palestinian territories), nuclear pro-
liferation (President Ahmadinejad in Iran), sectarianism, and warlordism. In
the wake of a May 2005 surge of terror attacks by Sunni insurgents in Iraq,
the American president belatedly added the too-mild disclaimer that “no
nation in history has made the transition from tyranny to a free society
without setbacks and false starts.”1
44 Jack Snyder and Leslie Vinjamuri
These strategies suffer from a willful voluntarism that is inevitably running
up against hard political and social facts. The liberal activists overstated the
efficacy of normative persuasion; the Bush strategy overestimated the efficacy
of military force. Both underestimated the need to ground international
change firmly in a set of facilitative preconditions: an economic basis to
support a liberal political order, a strong political coalition that supports
political reform, and the creation of administrative and judicial institutions
that support the rule of law. In particular, they underestimated the need to
develop a strategy for creating these preconditions in the right sequence,
taking into account the realities of particular political and social contexts.
In this chapter, we want to look at concepts for promoting change in two
areas: democracy promotion and international justice. Our goal will be to
study what happens when weak theories of social change run into the hard
realities of social facts, and then to offer some thoughts on change that have a
better sociological grounding.
Democracy promotion
One of the few points that the Bush administration and the principled activ-
ists agreed upon is that the assertive promotion of democracy is a good idea.5
In particular, both argued that democracy and free speech are pillars of
peace; therefore, to promote peace, you promote democracy. Of course, this is
in principle. In fact, the Bush administration was rightly worried about the
consequences for interethnic relations of holding early elections in Iraq. The
occupation authorities shut down newspapers that spread falsehoods that
inflamed Iraqis to resist the occupation. This is the kind of problem that the
US is likely to face wherever it tries to install democracy in countries that lack
a strong reform coalition and useable institutions for the rule of law.
It is true that no two mature democracies have ever fought a war against
each other. The basic workings of this democratic peace rely on supports in
the material, institutional, and cultural domains. The absence of war between
mature democracies depends on the material motivation of the average mem-
ber of society to avoid needless death and impoverishment (goals widely if
not universally shared across cultures), political institutions that predictably
empower the median voter, and a set of cultural symbols sanctifying civil
rights, free speech, and electoral legitimacy in ways that underpin those
institutions, facilitate peaceful bargaining, and establish a non-threatening,
“in-group” identity among democratic states. The democratic peace works
best when these material, institutional, and cultural elements are all in place
(Russett 1993; Owen 1997).
Moreover, democracy itself has material preconditions. Adam Przeworski
finds that transitions to democracy are almost always successfully consoli-
dated in countries with average annual income above $6,000 per capita in
1985 constant dollars, whereas democratic transitions almost always suffer
reversals below $1,000, with a very few exceptions, such as India (Przeworski
et al. 2000: ch. 2). These economic levels may to some degree be proxies for
48 Jack Snyder and Leslie Vinjamuri
closely related factors such as literacy and the development of a middle class.
Between those levels, consolidation seems to depend on a number of insti-
tutional preconditions, such as the strength of the rule of law and the devel-
opment of civil society organizations (Linz and Stepan 1996: 7–15). The fact
that these material and institutional preconditions often arise along with
symbols and ideas supportive of democracy does not mean that democratic
culture can somehow be a substitute for those conditions. Not surprisingly,
Western arguments in favor of free speech, fair elections, and human rights
have borne little fruit in countries that lack these preconditions (Carothers
1999). There is no cultural shortcut to a global democratic peace.
Proponents of democratic transformation are often too direct and non-
strategic in their approach to achieving their objectives. For example, Thomas
Carothers notes that the typical “strategy” of democracy assistance efforts is
to generate a checklist of the attributes of mature democracies, and then
mount parallel programs to try to install each of them in the targeted country
right away. This approach is flawed because it pays insufficient attention to
interaction effects between these efforts, issues of sequencing and precondi-
tions, strategic responses from resistant actors, and other negative feedback
effects.
Demanding a democratic transition and accountability to international
human rights norms can be risky in settings that lack even the rudiments of
the rule of law or the material resources needed to sustain an independent
civil society and media. In such settings, transformative projects may unleash
a populist form of mass politics at an inopportune, premature moment, when
elites threatened by such changes can exploit social turmoil by playing the
ethnic card. Untimely voting demanded by the international community in
such places as Burundi in 1993 and East Timor in 1999 has led directly to
hundreds of thousands of deaths and refugees (Lund et al. 1998). Arguably, it
has also led to the deepening of ethnic and social cleavages and to the tainting
of democratic remedies.
The risk of such backlashes may be increasing. The “third wave” of dem-
ocratization consolidated democratic regimes mainly in the richer countries
of eastern Europe, Latin America, southern Africa, and east Asia (Diamond
1996). A fourth wave would have to take on harder cases: countries that
are poorer, more ethnically divided, and starting from a weaker base of
governmental institutions and citizen skills.
In an era in which troubled, incomplete democratic transitions may engulf
such geopolitically salient locations as the Middle East, this dynamic could
be one of the fundamental determinants of the course of world politics.
Although democratization in the Islamic world might contribute to peace in
the very long run, Islamic public opinion in the short run is, in most places,
hostile to the United States. Although much of the belligerence of the Islamic
public is fueled by resentment of the US-backed authoritarian regimes under
which many of them live, simply renouncing these authoritarians and press-
ing for a quick democratic opening is unlikely to lead to peaceful democratic
Unipolar empire and principled multilateralism 49
consolidations. All of the risk factors are there: the media and civil society
groups are inflammatory, as old elites and rising oppositions try to outbid
each other for the mantle of Islamic or nationalist militancy.6 The rule of
law is weak, and existing corrupt bureaucracies cannot serve a democratic
administration properly. The boundaries of states are mismatched with those
of nations, making any push for national self-determination fraught with
peril. Per capita incomes, literacy rates, and citizen skills in most Muslim
Middle Eastern states are below the levels normally needed to sustain dem-
ocracy (United Nations 2004; Przeworski et al. 2000: 101; Council on Foreign
Relations 2005: 61–2; Donno and Russett 2004). Electoral results in Egypt,
Iraq, Iran, and the Palestinian territories in 2005 bear out the prediction that
inadequately prepared democratic transitions risk political polarization.
This does not necessarily mean that all steps toward democracy in the
Islamic world would lead to disaster. Etel Solingen argues, for example, that
reforms leading toward “democratization from above,” combined with eco-
nomic liberalization, have been consistent with support for peaceful policies
in such Arab states as Jordan, Tunisia, Morocco, and Qatar. “The more
consolidated democratizing regimes become,” she notes, “the less likely they
are to experiment with populism and war” (Solingen 1998: 213). Consistent
with my argument, these modest success cases indicate that the most promis-
ing sequence for democratization in such settings begins with reforms of
the state and the economy, together with limited forms of democratic partici-
pation, rather than a headlong jump into popular elections before the
strengthening of the institutions – such as efficient and even-handed public
administration, the rule of law, professional journalism, and political parties
– that are needed to make a democratic system work.
In facing this challenge, culturally creative activists and thinkers may play
an important role in changing behavior in the international system, but they
must do so within a context that is structured by the system’s material and
institutional possibilities. This is true for both unilateralist and multilateralist
strategies of change.
Notes
1 R.W. Stevenson, “Bush Says Patience Is Needed As Nations Build a Democracy,”
New York Times, 19 May 2005, p. A12, reporting his speech to the International
Republican Institute of 18 May.
2 These scholars adhere to the constructivist approach to the study of international
Unipolar empire and principled multilateralism 59
politics, but not all constructivists are so clearly wedded to this transformative
political agenda. For more qualified views, see Katzenstein (1996: 536–7), and
Owen (1997: 232–5).
3 “Dr. Condoleezza Rice Discusses President’s National Security Strategy,” Waldorf
Astoria Hotel, New York, 1 October 2002.
4 Bukovansky (2002) explores changing bases of legitimacy as a power resource.
5 This section draws on Snyder (2002).
6 Berman (2003: 265) draws parallels to belligerent civil society in the flawed dem-
ocracy of Weimar Germany and stresses the “Huntingtonian gap” between high
demand for political participation and ineffective state institutions.
7 For elaboration on the arguments in this section, see Snyder and Vinjamuri (2003/
4). On the advocacy community, see Clark (2001). On international human rights
law, which applies to all people at all times, and international humanitarian law,
which concerns the actions of combatants during military conflict, see Best (1994).
8 On proposals for international tribunals, see Kritz (1996) and Minow (1998), as
well as the numerous publications by Human Rights Watch, Amnesty Inter-
national, and the Coalition for International Justice. See also the sources cited in
the balanced critical commentary in Bass (2000: 284–310).
9 On institutionalization of the rule of law as a precondition for successful human
rights promotion, see Putnam (2002) and Ignatieff (2001: 25, 40).
10 Schulz is the executive director of Amnesty International USA. On a philo-
sophical plane, see Nagel (1988: 60).
11 For historical background, see Weschler (2000) and Scheffer (2000).
12 “Macedonia Bolsters Albanian Rights: After Constitutional Change, Amnesty Is
Declared for Former Rebels,” International Herald Tribune, 17–18 November 2001.
13 G. Ash, “Macedonia Is Seeking Control of Land Harboring Ex-Rebels,” New York
Times, 26 November 2001, p. A11.
3 US military commitments
Multilateralism and treaties
Lisa L. Martin
H1. The chance that a completed agreement takes the form of a treaty
increases as the benefits of the agreement for the United States grow.
H2. The chance that a completed agreement takes the form of a treaty
decreases as the reliability of the United States grows.
US military commitments and treaties 67
This prediction is in direct contrast to the predictions of a purely domestic
perspective. Previous studies have argued that it is precisely the inability of
the president to generate approval from the Senate that gives rise to the use of
executive agreements. However, taking signaling considerations into account,
we see that such a move would be interpreted as a sign of unreliability.
Understanding the signals that treaties send to other states leads to new
insights about the form that particular agreements take. In particular, we
should expect the president to be most willing to bear the costs of the treaty
process when the potential benefits of an agreement are particularly high. In
addition we should not see a president who is facing substantial domestic
opposition attempt to evade it by using an executive agreement; such a man-
euver would only confirm his unreliability in the eyes of negotiating partners.
The next section turns to explore these insights with evidence on US security
agreements reached between 1980 and 1999.
Figure 3.1 Number of references in the New York Times to multilateral and bilateral
agreements.
this issue area the real work is done in bilateral negotiations. If so, the results
from the more general analysis would not carry over to the security realm.
Table 3.1 shows how bilateral and multilateral agreements are sorted into
executive agreements and treaties. Just 0.55 per cent of bilateral agreements – 4
out of 728 – take the form of treaties. In contrast, 8.57 per cent of multi-
lateral agreements, 6 out of 70, are treaties. This relationship is highly statis-
tically significant, as indicated by the chi-square statistic. Thus, the general
insight that multilateral agreements offer more potential benefits, and thus
are more likely to take the form of treaties, holds for security agreements. The
intuition behind this finding, according to the signaling model, is that the
president will more often be willing to bear the costs of a treaty as a way to
indicate US reliability when the potential benefits of the agreement are high.
The evasion hypothesis predicts that a president facing high domestic
opposition should more often turn to executive agreements as a way to evade
this opposition. In contrast, the signaling model argues that such a maneuver
would send a signal of unreliability to negotiating partners. If anything, higher
domestic opposition should force the president more often to use treaties as
70 Lisa L. Martin
an attempt to signal reliability. Previous work has used divided government as
an indicator of domestic opposition and prior beliefs about reliability.10
While early work suggested that divided government was in fact associated
with greater use of executive agreements, Martin (2000, 2005) has shown that
in properly specified models, the relationship disappears or even reverses, as
the signaling model predicts.
Table 3.2 presents a logit analysis that allows us to test the effect of divided
government on the probability that an agreement will be a treaty, controlling
for whether the agreement is multilateral. Here, I also control for whether the
president is in an election year or in his first year in office. Some have sug-
gested that presidents might more often turn to executive agreements during
election years as a way to establish their own foreign policy agenda. It is also
possible that a new president, who has not yet developed a working relation-
ship with Congress, may be forced to rely more heavily on executive agree-
ments. I also control for the party of the president, allowing for the possibility
that ideological commitments might push presidents of one party to favor
executive agreements that appear to enhance their autonomy from Congress.
As in the simple bivariate correlation, we find a strong positive relationship
between multilateral agreements and treaties. We also find a positive relation-
ship between a Republican president and the use of treaties, although this
relationship is not quite statistically significant. This is interesting, because
in the larger dataset a significant negative relationship appeared between
Republican presidents and the use of treaties. This suggested that Republicans
favored unilateral presidential action more than Democrats, probably con-
sistent with conventional wisdom. However, this relationship does not hold for
security agreements, and even appears to reverse. The circumstances that led
to this pattern, at least for these decades, may be worth further speculation.
Neither of the year dummies has any effect. This suggests that a purely
domestic logic of the president’s relationship with Congress does not have a
consistent effect on the form of agreements, lending support to a signaling
Table 3.4 Multilateral agreements and the president’s party: logit analysis
It does not control for any other factors that might influence a president’s
incentives or ability to conclude multilateral agreements. Although there are a
large number of such potential factors, one that we can easily control here
is the existence of divided government. Perhaps a president facing a Congress
controlled by the other party would find it more difficult to gain support
for complex multilateral agreements that could commit the United States in
ways that would prove inconvenient in the future. Thus, we might expect that
a president facing divided government would conclude fewer multilateral
agreements. On the other hand, the analysis in the previous section of this
paper suggested that divided government was not, in fact, a block to conclud-
ing agreements. While divided government might raise questions in negotiat-
ing partners’ minds about the reliability of the United States, a president
willing to make a costly signal of intent to live up to the terms of an agreement
can overcome this liability.
In order to control for divided government and to assess its effects, Table 3.4
shows the results of a logit analysis using multilateral agreement as the
dependent variable. That is, this table asks about the odds that any particular
agreement will be multilateral rather than bilateral. The two explanatory
variables are the president’s party and divided government. As in Table 3.3,
we find a significant negative relationship between Republican presidents
and multilateral agreements. Thus, this finding does not simply arise because
Republicans faced divided government more often than Democrats. Perhaps
just as interesting, we find a strongly significant positive relationship between
74 Lisa L. Martin
divided government and multilateral agreements. This suggests that divided
government is not an impediment to negotiating multilateral agreements.
However, the positive coefficient on this variable is somewhat surprising and
deserves further exploration. Why might we see more multilateralism in
periods of divided government? Does Congress simply have a preference for
multilateral over bilateral agreements?
One further step we can take with these data is to examine the records of
individual presidents. Perhaps the fact that Republican presidents concluded
fewer multilateral agreements is not due to partisan ideology, but is more
idiosyncratic to specific presidents, or the result of the particular era in which
they were governing. The data here cover only four different presidents:
Carter (1980); Reagan (1981–8); Bush 1 (1989–92); and Clinton (1993–9).
Figure 3.2 presents a bar chart breaking down the data on multilateral and
bilateral agreements by year.
We can see from this figure some clear differences across presidencies. The
one year that we have for Carter, 1980, shows that about 13 per cent of all
agreements were multilateral. During the first Reagan administration, this
fraction plummeted, with no multilateral agreements in 1983 or 1984. How-
ever, in the second Reagan administration, the percentage of agreements that
are multilateral returns about the same level as observed in 1980. In the first
year of the Bush 1 administration we see no multilateral agreements, but the
numbers return to about their usual levels for the next three years.
The first year of the Clinton administration, 1993, also shows a very low
Notes
My thanks go to Olivia Lau for her excellent research assistance and to participants in
the conference on multilateralism in the security realm in Delphi, Greece, in June 2005.
Appendix to Chapter 3
Table 3.5 Descriptive statistics and data sources
Not long ago, a generation of young Germans who were liberated from the
Nazi regime by American soldiers developed admiration of the political ideals
of a nation that soon became the driving force in founding the United Nations
and in carrying out the Nuremberg and Tokyo tribunals. As a consequence,
classical international law was revolutionized by limiting the sovereignty of
nation-states . . . Should this same nation now brush aside the civilizing
achievement of legally domesticating the state of nature among belligerent
nations?
(Habermas 2002)
Introduction
There is little doubt that the transatlantic relationship is in crisis despite the
patching-up work being done on either side of the Atlantic after the Iraq war.
Therefore, it is time to re-evaluate US–European relations and to take stock
of their current evolution. Such an effort has to take into account, however,
that the history of the transatlantic relationship is a history of crises. Com-
pare the crowds marching against George W. Bush, his rhetoric of the “axis
of evil,” and the Iraq war with the demonstrations against Ronald Reagan,
the talk of “empire of the evil” and the euro-missiles!
If the current conflicts are supposed to be different from the past, we need
convincing analytical arguments pointing to structural changes in world pol-
itics rather than editorial adhocery. Three such changes come to mind: the end
of the Cold War; unprecedented American preponderance; and 11 September
2001, and the rise of transnational terrorism.
Crisis of the transatlantic security community 79
I argue in the following that none of these changes (alone or in combin-
ation) offers sufficient evidence to conclude that structural changes in the
international system are about to spell the end of the transatlantic community
as we have known it over the past fifty years. The transatlantic security com-
munity used to rest on three things: collective identity based on common
values, (economic) interdependence grounded in common material interests,
and common institutions based on norms regulating the relationship. The
current conflicts stem from domestic developments on both sides of the
Atlantic leading to different perceptions of contemporary security threats
including transnational terrorism and, more importantly, different prescrip-
tions on how to handle them. Such differences have existed before and they
have been dealt with through the institutions of the transatlantic community
including European use of domestic access opportunities into the US political
system. Recent evidence suggests that European and US leaders are currently
busy (re-)developing their working relationships to deal with the most urgent
international problems such as Iran’s compliance with the Nuclear Non-
Proliferation Treaty. This is the good news.
The bad news is that unilateral and even imperial tendencies in contempor-
ary US foreign policy and particularly its official discourse have violated
constitutive norms on which the transatlantic security community has been
built over the years, namely multilateralism and close consultation with the
allies. The more US foreign policy in general acts unilaterally and the more it
renounces international agreements and institutions that the US itself has
helped to build, the more it touches upon fundamental principles of world
order and the rule of (international) law in dealing with international con-
flicts. The National Security Strategy (US President’s Office 2002) is indeed
partly at odds with some principles of world order which have been part of
the Western consensus in the post-World War II era. Even though unilateral-
ism is currently receding into the background of US foreign policy, the danger
remains that “instrumental multilateralism” remains the preferred course in
Washington. In this sense then, the current disagreements between Europe
and the US go beyond ordinary policy conflicts and touch issues of common
values and the core of the security community. Moreover, the transatlantic
tensions and, most importantly, the thoroughly negative image of the Bush
administration in the rest of the world including Europe, are beginning to
eat away at the “sense of community” or collective identity as a cornerstone of
the transatlantic security community. To put it differently, the most severe
and global legitimacy crisis of US foreign policy in recent decades affects
the transatlantic relationship directly. The pictures of Abu Grahib and Guan-
tanamo Bay are not only destroying what is left of a positive image of the
United States in the Islamic world, but they also challenge the Western com-
munity of values.
In short, the transatlantic community faces a severe crisis. It is no longer
possible to paper over the differences in joint communiqués and nice photo
opportunities. Rather, we need a new transatlantic bargain (Moravcsik
80 Thomas Risse
2003). Fortunately, the EU has been quick to get its foreign policy act
together after the disastrous internal rows over Iraq. For the first time, the
EU has articulated its own Security Strategy adopted by the European
Council in December 2003 (European Council 2003). It substantially differs
from George W. Bush’s National Security Strategy in that it embraces what
has been called “effective multilateralism,” that is, a foreign policy vision of
a “civilian power with teeth.” Moreover, the European foreign policy strat-
egy is already being expressed in practice – from European efforts in conflict
prevention and peacekeeping to European support for the International
Criminal Court (ICC) and multilateral efforts at dealing with global
environmental challenges. Last not least and slowly but surely, Europe is
putting the “teeth” into its concept of a “civilian power.” In sum, an EU
that gets its foreign policy act together is the pre-condition for a new trans-
atlantic bargain.
Yet, a European (counter-)vision of world order is not meant to wreck
the transatlantic security community. The rhetoric of building a counter-
weight to American hyperpower emanating from politicians and intel-
lectuals in parts of “old Europe” is bound to fail, since it will split Europe
further apart in foreign policy. Rather, efforts at a common European for-
eign policy and a European “grand strategy” should revive a serious trans-
atlantic dialogue and (re-)create the transnational alliances across the
Atlantic among like-minded groups that seem to have been silenced after
9/11.
I proceed in three steps. First, I take stock of and discuss the funda-
mentals of the transatlantic security community, including some alternative
accounts. Second, I analyze domestic developments in the US and Europe in
order to account partially for the current crisis. I conclude with some sugges-
tions for the necessary transatlantic dialogue concerning world order
questions.
The “three Is” can also be used as indicators for the current state of the
transatlantic security community.
Collective identity
Among the three factors, collective identity is probably the most difficult to
measure without getting into tautological reasoning (members of security
communities do not fight each other; therefore, they must identify with each
other, which explains their peacefulness). To measure the strength of collect-
ive identities, we should distinguish them along two dimensions: the salience
Crisis of the transatlantic security community 85
of the “self/other” or “in-group/out-group” distinction, on the one hand, and
the price people are prepared to pay for their sense of loyalty to the group,
on the other. As to the in-group/out-group distinction, democratic security
communities usually score rather high in this regard. Liberal democracies
hold what Giesen and Eisenstadt called a “sacred” identity construction
(Eisenstadt and Giesen 1995). We are the “shining city on the hill” (to quote
from the American collective mythology; similar self-descriptions can easily
be found in French discourses), but others can convert and become part of us,
that is, also become liberal democracies. Liberal security communities engage
in rather strong boundary constructions along the “self/other” divide, which
is a function of a country’s internal order. Once states democratize, they are
eligible as members of the security community. The sharp self/other distinc-
tion explains, for instance, the missionary impulse in American foreign policy.
It also explains why non-democracies are often constructed as “empires of
the evil” and why autocratic leaders are often demonized (cf. the comparisons
of both Saddam Hussein and Slobodan Milosevic with Adolf Hitler, as well
as the description of Osama bin Laden as “personified evil”).
Moreover, there are sufficient examples to sustain the argument that the
often-proclaimed “value community” of the Western alliance does not simply
represent sheer rhetoric. After all, the US prepared itself to sacrifice New
York for Berlin during the Cold War. The hot debates about the credibility
of extended deterrence during the Cold War document that this was not
regarded as an empty threat. And in the post-Cold War era, the Western
security community did fight for its principles several times, from the Gulf
war to the war in Kosovo. While there are material-interest-based explan-
ations for the Gulf war, the Kosovo war and the transformation of most of
ex-Yugoslavia into a Western protectorate can hardly be explained on
material grounds. Rather, the liberal identity of the community and its com-
mitment to humanitarian principles accounts to a large extent why Western
powers agreed to spend substantial economic, military, and human resources
in the Balkans.
But do US Americans and Europeans hold a sufficiently large share of
common values? Evidence from the World Value Surveys demonstrates over-
all similarities as well as some differences (Figure 4.1; see also the chapter by
Fuchs and Klingemann in Anderson et al. 2008). Overall, North Americans
and Europeans still occupy the same value space, that is, the north-eastern
corner of both “secular-rational” and “self-expression” values. When it
comes to support for democracy, human rights, and market economy, the
core values of the transatlantic security community, we can discern very few
differences between Europe and the US At least, the variation in support
for these and other “self-expression values” is greater inside Europe than
between Europeans and North Americans. And there is little evidence that
this picture has changed over the past few years. There is a widening gap
across the Atlantic, though, which concerns the “traditional vs secular-
rational values” continuum. There is only one EU member state, Ireland,
86 Thomas Risse
US Europe US Europe
Transnational interdependence
Concerning the second factor contributing to a security community, trans-
national (economic) interdependence, the transatlantic community is alive
and kicking. Combined indicators for trade, foreign investment, and capital
flows show that the transatlantic region is highly integrated economically
and is only surpassed by the EU’s single market itself. In 1999, 45.2 per cent
of all US foreign investment went to Europe, while 60.5 per cent of all Euro-
pean foreign investment went to the US European investments in Texas alone
are higher than all Japanese investments in the US combined. A German firm
– Siemens – is among the largest employers in the US. Moreover, intra-firm
trade constitutes a large portion of transatlantic trade. EU subsidiaries of US
companies import more than one third of all US exports to the EU, while US
subsidiaries of EU companies import more than two fifths of all EU exports
to the US. Six million jobs on each side of the Atlantic depend on trans-
atlantic economic relations (data according to Krell 2003: 10–17).
The transatlantic market is highly integrated and remains so despite the ups
and downs in the political relationship. The US and the EU not only consti-
tute each other’s most important economic partners, but are also the two
leading world economic powers. The current international economic order is
largely guaranteed and stabilized by the transatlantic economic relationship.
What is less clear, though, is the degree to which high economic interdepend-
ence serves to smooth increasing political conflicts. The spill-over effects from
one area to the other are not clear, in either direction. To what extent can
transatlantic economic interdependence substitute for a lack in transatlantic
90 Thomas Risse
identity when it comes to maintaining and nurturing the political relation-
ship? Historical lessons, particularly the decades preceding World War I,
appear to suggest that economic interdependence does not suffice to stabilize
a deteriorating political relationship, as generations of neorealists have
always been quick to point out (e.g. Waltz 1979; see also chapters by van
Scherpenberg and McNamara in Anderson et al. 2008).
Multilateral institutions
The third factor reinforcing a security community pertains to multilateral
institutions managing the relationship. Again and in parallel to the density of
transnational interdependence, Europe and the transatlantic region constitute
the most tightly coupled institutionalized settings within the larger Western
community. This region of the world also hosts the two strongest political,
economic, and security institutions in terms of robustness of norms, rules,
and decision-making procedures, the EU and NATO. The multilateral
institutions of the transatlantic community serve to manage the inevitable
conflicts inside a security community (Risse-Kappen 1995; see also Haften-
dorn et al. 1999). Strong procedural norms of mutual consultation and policy
co-ordination insure that the members of the community have regular input
and influence on each other’s policy-making processes. These procedural
norms and regulations are among the major tools mitigating power asym-
metries among community members.
Of course, these “voice opportunities” (Ikenberry 2001) suffer, the more
US foreign policy pursues a unilateralist course or falls victim to “imperial
ambitions” (Ikenberry 2002). Unilateralism violates norms of multilateral-
ism, which are constitutive for the transatlantic community. If unilateral ten-
dencies, which have always been a temptation in American foreign policy,
become the prevailing practice, the transatlantic security community’s consti-
tutive norms are endangered. The discourse emanating from Washington
over the past few years concerning “coalitions of the willing” – now
enshrined in the foreign policy doctrine of the United States (US President’s
Office 2002) – stands in sharp contrast to the idea of multilateralism on which
the transatlantic alliance has been based over the past fifty years. NATO was
so successful in the past as an instrument of alliance management, precisely
because it served as a clearing house for potential policy disputes before firm
decisions were taken on either side of the Atlantic. The more consultations in
the alliance framework are reduced to merely informing each other about
decisions already taken, the more NATO becomes irrelevant for the future of
the transatlantic relationship.
This is why the North Atlantic alliance has taken such a toll in the past
years, even before 9/11 and certainly before the Iraq crisis. Neither the US nor
Europeans have made good use of NATO in recent years as the primary
institution to manage their security relationship. After 9/11, Article 5 of the
North Atlantic Treaty was invoked for the first time in the history of the
Crisis of the transatlantic security community 91
alliance – without any further consequences. During the Iraq crisis and war,
the NATO Council apparently never discussed the transatlantic dispute in
detail (see Pond 2004). Both sides violated norms of consultation that are
fundamental for the transatlantic security relationship. If we are in a funda-
mental crisis of the transatlantic relationship, it primarily concerns the norms
governing it, which have been enshrined in its institutions. As long as the US
continues to build its foreign policy on “coalitions of the willing,” this consti-
tutes unilateralism in disguise and is fundamentally at odds with the norms
of the transatlantic security community. No wonder then, that we have seen
rather hectic attempts on both sides to repair the security relationship after
the Iraq crisis. More recently, the US has indeed resumed regular consulta-
tions with its allies. Whether this constitutes a break from unilateral tempta-
tions remains to be seen. It also remains to be seen whether NATO is able to
resume its role as the most important institution to manage the transatlantic
security relationship (see below).
In sum, if we use the “three Is” – identity, interdependence, and institutions
– as indicators for the state of the transatlantic security community, we get
a rather precise picture of its current situation. While transatlantic eco-
nomic interdependence remains strong, the collective identification with each
other has taken quite a beating since 2002/3. US post-9/11 foreign policy
has resulted in a strong spill-over from anti-Bushism to anti-Americanism
in Europe, including Great Britain. At the same time, either fundamental
value and foreign policy orientations on either side of the Atlantic remain
rather comparable or else the value differences point to more fundamental
cleavages dividing American society. Moreover, in the wider world com-
munity, European and North American societies have more in common than
any other societies in the world. Current challenges to the community con-
cern its institutions and the constitutive norms on which they are based.
NATO has taken quite a beating, and whether it is beyond repair remains to
be seen.
In short, the Atlantic has indeed become wider in recent years, but we still
lack an explanation. To understand the sources of conflicts, we need to open
up the black box of the states on both sides of the Atlantic and look at
domestic politics.
The three factions dominating the Bush administration’s foreign policy are
situated on the left-hand side of Figure 4.2. I have also included the dominant
foreign policy coalition in the Democratic Party which is composed of “trad-
itional conservatives” on the one hand and “liberal internationalists” on the
other. The graph also depicts three European foreign policy groups according
to their views. The first group in the upper right corner of the figure could
be called “liberal internationalists.” It is often overlooked that the European
center-left shares with American “liberal” neo-conservatives a commitment to
the promotion of democracy and human rights as their foreign policy prior-
ities. The same is true for the EU’s foreign policy strategy (see also Börzel and
Risse 2004). In sharp contrast to the US right, however, this group is equally
firmly committed to a co-operative foreign policy and to work with and
through multilateral institutions. This group – which, for example, was in
charge of German foreign policy in the Schröder/Fischer coalition – pursues
the foreign policy of a “civilian power” (Maull 1990; Harnisch and Maull
2001) and thus shares a Kantian vision of world order in the sense of the
“perpetual peace” – that is, building a pacific federation of democratic states
and strengthening the rule of law in international affairs (Kant 1795/1983).
European Kantians are not pacifists; they support the use of military force if
necessary (cf. Chancellor Schröder’s stance on Kosovo and Afghanistan).
Yet, military power has to be embedded in political and diplomatic efforts.
Unilateralism is anathema for the European center-left.
There is a second group among the European foreign policy elites which
holds a more realist view of the world than either the American neo-
conservatives or the European center-left. Since this group thinks primarily in
realist, balance-of-power terms, it is very much concerned about the growth
of US power and promotes a European foreign policy of balancing and
building a counter-weight to US primacy. One could call this group the
“European Gaullists” (see e.g. Bahr 2003; Schöllgen 2003), given that French
Crisis of the transatlantic security community 97
presidents from de Gaulle to Chirac shared that world view. Their mantra is
to build a multipolar world in contrast to a unipolar one dominated by US
hyperpower. Interestingly and strangely enough, the Franco-German anti-
Iraq war coalition brought together the European center-left and the Euro-
pean “Gaullists” who joined forces for different reasons. Both were concerned
about American unilateralism. But the center-left primarily opposed the use
force for liberal purposes (“regime change”), while the “Gaullists” opposed
the war because of concern about US “hyperpower.”
The third group among European foreign policy elites can be located in a
similar position as the American traditional conservatives. This group holds
rather moderate world views on either the liberal–realist axis or the militant–
co-operative axis. Above all, however, this group is strongly committed to
preserving the transatlantic partnership, almost no matter what. This group
of “European Atlanticists,” which formed the core of the European “coalition
of the willing” during the Iraq war, is strongly motivated to avoid policy
disagreements with Washington that could weaken the transatlantic com-
munity. British Prime Minister Tony Blair (and his successor Gordon Brown)
as well as German Chancellor Angela Merkel belong to this group. Thus,
Germany’s current grand coalition government is composed of European
Atlanticists as well as European liberal internationalists, thus bringing the
country closer to the US.
Two main conclusions follow from this attempt at locating the various
foreign policy groupings on either side of the Atlantic in a two-dimensional
political space:
Notes
This is an updated and revised version of a paper presented at the American Institute
for Contemporary German Studies, Washington DC, 24 January, 2003, published as
AICGS Seminar Papers, and at the 2004 Annual Convention of the American Political
Science Association. Various versions have been published as Risse (2003, 2006). I
owe a lot to discussions in the research seminar of the Center for Transnational
Relations, Foreign and Security Policy at the Freie Universität Berlin. Last not least,
this chapter benefited from discussions in a transatlantic study group which Jeffrey
Anderson, G. John Ikenberry, and I have chaired over the past few years. See Ander-
son, Ikenberry, and Risse 2008. I thank my students as well as Tanja Börzel and Ingo
Peters for their critical comments.
State attributes
Four state attributes – identity, interests, sovereign control, and use of force –
demarcate the range of viable security arrangements in which any given state
will participate. These attributes do not manifest themselves in fixed relation-
ships or individually exert an unvarying explanatory power, although the
range of values assessed for any one attribute is likely to set the boundary
conditions for the others (see Table 5.1).
Identity has emerged as the central causal variable for those seeking to
explain the emergence and persistence of the European and transatlantic
security communities and by inference the persistence of more primitive forms
of multilateralism elsewhere in the world (Wendt 1994; Jepperson, Wendt,
and Katzenstein 1996; Finnemore and Sikkink 1998; Checkel 1998). Such
analysts emphasize the role of identity in interest formation and claim that
collective identities create shared interests, normatively disciplined patterns
of behavior, and ultimately the stable expectation of non-violent conflict
resolution (Adler and Barnett 1998b). State identities range from the mutual
recognition that states, as states, have the sovereign right of self-preservation
to a fused identity where interstate differentiation is literally nonexistent.
Moreover, identities may be positive or negative: the former indicates an
State attributes and system properties 105
System properties
If an international (sub)system is minimally independent of its parts, then
system properties play an important role in establishing the possible range of
viable security governance outcomes for any group of states. Four system
properties constrain or enable the likely forms of security multilateralism: the
role of power in ordering relations between states, the attachment to the sov-
ereignty principle, the breadth and depth of shared norms, and the legitimacy
of war (see Table 5.2).
Power as a system determinant has the longest pedigree in the study of
international relations (Meinecke 1929; Carr 1938; Dehio 1948; Gilpin 1981;
Mearsheimer 2001). Power is both subjective (is a peer friend or foe?) and
material (where do states fall along the hierarchy of power?). The intersection
of the subjective understanding of power and its material distribution affects
the pattern of interaction between members of the group and those outside
it, as well as the calculation of interest with respect to the source of threat and
how it should be met.
The strength of the sovereignty principle indicates the (un)willingness of
states to abnegate sovereign prerogatives where national interests collide
with group interests, to cede sovereignty to international or supranational
institutions, or to accept that group norms constrain states, particularly when
those norms collide with particularistic national interests. Where the sover-
eignty principle is undiluted, states are unlikely to enter into any form of
security multilateralism beyond contingent and temporary alliances; where
the sovereignty principle is relaxed, an enabling condition for advanced forms
of institutionalized security multilateralism arises.
State attributes and system properties 107
(Continued overlef)
Table 5.4 Continued
Civilianized Within group International law, Norms replace sovereign Deep amity derived from a
security institutionalized conflict prerogatives across a wide positive or collective identity; a
community resolution mechanisms range of issues; constitute state common set of norms have
interests; are substantively and been internalized; security
intrinsically valued dilemma atrophied
Fused security Within group International law, institutional Same as in civilianized security Deep amity derived from a
community conflict resolution mechanisms community single identity and total
absence of differentiation
between within-group
members; security dilemma
not a relevant conceptual
category
Civilian Within group Civil contract law in effect; Sovereignty principle no Amity derived from an
international compulsory adjudication; longer defines interactions inviolable social contract
system voluntary compliance or within the group; normative among the group members
effective enforcement framework substantive and
intrinsic
State attributes and system properties 113
conflict resolution is (in)formally institutionalized although the option of
war remains, a limited number of substantive norms creates a sense of com-
munity and regulates how states interact, and the interaction context is one of
contingent amity and a muted security dilemma.
Since a collective defense arrangement only emerges when one group of
states identifies another state or group of states as a common threat, the
security referent is outwardly directed. Within-group conflicts are mediated
by institutionalized procedures of dispute management and decision-making,
while deterrence and defense mediate conflicts with the adversary. A binding
normative framework is required to offset the required abnegation of sover-
eignty: military forces are likely to be aggregated at some level, defense acqui-
sition and expenditures become a matter of common concern, and strategy is
likely to serve the collective rather than the particularistic interests of its mem-
bers. Yet, each state retains the right to decide whether an act of aggression
has occurred and whether it constitutes a threat. Moreover, when an act of
aggression does occur, the member states have the option, rather than the
obligation, to intervene on behalf of their ally (Wolfers 1962: 182–3; Kelsen
1948: 793–4). A collective defense arrangement emerges in the context of
internal amity and external enmity; the security dilemma gives the arrangement
its raison d’être.
Collective security differs fundamentally from collective defense. In a
collective security arrangement, the security referent is inwardly directed at a
contracting state that initiates an act of aggression. Any party to a collective
security arrangement is contractually and normatively obligated to assist
any other contracting state that is the victim of aggression and to punish
the aggressor. A collective security arrangement makes provision for the
compulsory adjudication of within-group conflicts. Finally, in a collective
security system, the use of force – except in cases warranting immediate self-
help measures – must be wielded and legitimized by a quasi-sovereign entity
(Kelsen: 1948: 784–90; Wolfers 1962: 182–6). States, in effect, are required to
abnegate a core element of sovereignty; viz, the right to decide the where,
when, and why of war. This form of security multilateralism only exists where
there is a strong prohibitionary norm against war and an interaction context
characterized by amity and a moribund security dilemma.
A civilianized security community is the most advanced form of security
multilateralism that has yet emerged in the international system.6 A civilian-
ized security community exists where states have replaced “the military
enforcement of rules (politics based on power) with the internalization of
socially accepted norms (politics based on legitimacy)” (Harnisch and Maull
2001: 4). Five conditions must be met: there are normative constraints on the
use of force and an unwillingness to rely on it for resolving conflicts; inter-
national law serves as the basis for conflict resolution; formal institutional
mechanisms must exist to adjudicate within-group conflict; decision-making
is participatory; and sovereignty plays an instrumental rather than substan-
tive role in the calculation of interest (Harnisch and Maull 2001; Eberwein
114 James Sperling
1995: 350–2). The security referent is predominantly within the group,
conflict is regulated by rule of law, the normative framework is binding
and codified, and an abiding amity complements the absence of a security
dilemma.
A fused security community differs from a civilianized security community
in one critical respect – the nature of the identity shared between the mem-
bers. “Fused” replaces “civilianized” as a modifier where states retain de jure
sovereignty and a nominal notion of nationality, but not where there is a
within-group “other” or the persistence of negative identities. A “fused” secur-
ity community would have two primary characteristics: first, a member state
would not differentiate between a threat to the group and a threat to itself;
second, members would have a single set of security interests derived from an
identical set of norms, values and interests.
Central National National with some overlap No juridical loss, although Yes, particularly within
Asia some territory sovereign-free actors’ own territory
Southeast National, modified by the National with overlapping Largely retained in all areas Yes, but effort to avoid
Asia notion of an “ASEAN Way” interests intramural conflicts
Atlantic National, but underpinned by Common, over-lapping and Largely retained in security Not within area, but out of
a weak notion of community broad affairs, but largely lost in areas area
related to the economy
Europe Community Joint and very broad Largely lost No; reliance upon persuasion
and compromise
116 James Sperling
Central Asia
The SCO states retain a national identity without the underlay of either a
regional or civilizational identity. The Chinese and Russian identities are
national, based on distinct cultures, civilizations, languages and histories; at
the best of times they only share an opposition to an “other” in the form of
the United States or Japan. The other four SCO states, ruled by autocratic
governments deriving their legitimacy from clan loyalties, are all former
republics of the Soviet Union and have weak national identities (Trofimov
2003: 46). Unlike NATO or the EU, there is no mythologized common
culture or civilization that serves as an ideational epoxy providing a rationale
for co-operation. Instead, the SCO states explicitly recognize that they repre-
sent “different civilizations and different cultural traditions” (Shanghai Co-
operation Organization 2001a; Perlo-Freeman and Ståhlenheim 2003: 16).
This cultural barrier to the formation of regional identity is reinforced by
anemic interaction densities: only 2.4 per cent of their total exports, for
example, are intramural (IMF 2004, author’s own calculations).
The SCO emerged from the “Shanghai Process”, the purpose of which was to
settle pre-existing Sino-Soviet border conflicts that involved Tajikistan, Kaza-
khstan, and Kyrgyzstan after the dissolution of the Soviet Union in 1992. The
Sino-Soviet border had been heavily militarized; confidence-building meas-
ures taken in 1990, 1996 and 1997 led to the renunciation of Chinese claims
against Russia (and its successor states) and produced agreements on the
mutual reduction of armed forces (Fravel 2005: 55ff). Compared to the not-so-
distant past, force has become less an issue between states: the Sino-Russian
Treaty of Friendship and Co-operation in July 2001, for example, renounced
“the use or threat of the use of force” in their mutual relations. Force does
remain an issue within states, particularly the combating of Muslim Uighur
and other ethnic separatists. Defense expenditures as a percentage of GDP are
low, but the increases between 1995 and 2004 have been staggering.7 Military
co-operation has been limited: the first joint SCO exercise, which did not
include every member, occurred on Chinese and Kazakh territory in August
2003, Russian troops are stationed along the Tajik-Afghan border, and the
four Central Asian republics are members of the Russian-led Collective Secur-
ity Treaty Rapid Reaction Force (Carlson 2003). This co-operation is leavened
by distrust: Uzbekistan, for example, built new military bases along its border
with Russia and has conducted 22 military exercises with the United States.
All six SCO members have long, porous, and ineffectively policed bor-
ders. Domestic order is threatened by civil conflict between competing, non-
integrated ethnic groups with antagonistic confessions. Governments do not
exercise control over ill-defined and “soft frontiers” (Bailes 2003: 2). Despite
the inability to exert full sovereign control over borders and territory, these
states have not chosen to pool their sovereign prerogatives in formal multi-
lateral institutions – the SCO has only a small secretariat in Beijing and a
recently established regional anti-terrorism center in Tashkent.
State attributes and system properties 117
Interests remain nationally rather than collectively defined. National
calculations of interest shape Sino-Russian bilateral co-operation as well as
their support for the SCO. Both Russia and China desire the withdrawal of
American troops stationed in central Asia, a region that is arguably a natural
sphere of influence for either. The SCO states share an overlapping interest in
preserving their own territorial integrity and regime stability, both of which
are threatened by militant Islam and ethnic rivalries. The Islamic Movement
of Uzbekistan, for example, is active in Kyrgyzstan and Tajikistan, and sup-
ports Uighur separatists in China’s Xinjiang province (Yom 2002; Dongfeng
2004). The 2001 SCO Charter and the 2004 Tashkent Declaration commit
each member to “assign priority to regional security” and seek the “joint
definitions of interests . . . on the basis of respect of their individuality and
sovereign rights,” respectively. Those interests are defined as threats to inter-
nal security posed by the “three forces” of terrorism, separatism, and extrem-
ism. Yet, as the Astana Summit declaration made clear, the member states
retained the right to determine when and how those forces represent a national
security threat (Guang 2005).
Southeast Asia
Identity formation within ASEAN was initially “negative” insofar as it rested
upon a shared “anti-communism” without a reinforcing “positive” identity
derived from a common culture or constitutional form (Acharya 1991: 175;
Gallant and Stubbs 1997: 216). These states are culturally, religiously and
ethnically heterogeneous, their economies fall along the entire development
spectrum, their relations are marked by telling asymmetries of power and
influence, and they have social compacts that strike different balances between
social stability and individual liberty.8 Regional heterogeneity is perhaps
best captured by religious confessions anchored in different civilizations –
European Roman Catholicism in the Philippines, Arabic Islam in Indonesia,
and indigenous Buddhism in Indochina. Diverse European imperialisms in
the region – the British in Malaysia and Burma, the French in Indochina, the
Dutch in the East Indies, the Americans in the Philippines – left behind
different legacies: weak or nonexistent political infrastructures, poorly drawn
borders that created ethnic and linguistic conflicts where none had previously
existed, and economies servicing imperial rather than local requirements.
Collective identity formation is also impeded by historical animosities pre-
ceding the age of European imperialism and gross disparities in economic
wealth – GDP per capita ranges from a low of $104 in Myanmar to a high of
$20,515 in Singapore. The modestly interdependent ASEAN economies –
only 23 per cent of total exports are intramural (ASEAN 2003b: 74, table V.12)
– and their mutual vulnerability to financial panics provides some foundation
for collective identity formation, positive and negative.9 The ASEAN com-
munity is imagined in Benedict Anderson’s (1991) sense that governing elites
purposively created a sense of community based on appeals to the “ASEAN
118 James Sperling
way”. It is also imagined in the narrower sense that it doesn’t exist because
the raw materials for community are absent (Hemmer and Katzenstein
2002: 599).
The ASEAN states exercise greater control over their territory and borders
than do the SCO states, but nonetheless face a transborder security complex
arising from borders made porous by geography and regional economic
interdependencies (Dosch 2003: 490). ASEAN governments can and do con-
trol the flow of individuals, goods and even ideas across national borders,
unencumbered as they are by the legal inhibitions on individual liberty found
in Western democracies.
Even though the ASEAN states have encouraged economic interdepend-
ence as a strategy of growth and regional autonomy, they cling to relatively
narrow definitions of self-interest even at the expense of protecting regional
autonomy (Khoo 2004; Narine 1998). Some point to the Bali II Concord
declaration on comprehensive security as evidence that a common culture
and identity are emerging in the region (Dosch 2003: 485). The intervention
in East Timor belies that claim. Each ASEAN state participating in the
peacekeeping mission did so for narrow national purposes, rather than for
the community interest. Some participated out of the fear that a successful
revolt in East Timor would stoke their own separatist movements and others
wanted to rein in Thailand’s eagerness to stake a leadership claim within
ASEAN. The ASEAN states did share an immediate interest in thwarting the
Australian effort to lead the expedition and claim a regional leadership role,
an interest not inconsistent with the longer-term concern with protecting
against Chinese or American encroachments on regional autonomy (Nabers
2003: 127).
One hallmark of the “ASEAN way” is the rejection of force (Khoo 2004; Ba
2005). That normative injunction, however, has not banished force from the
diplomatic toolbox. Disputes have been militarized, including but not limited
to the 1999 Philippines–Malaysia dispute over reefs in the South China Sea
and the 2001 border clashes between Thailand and Myanmar. While the
militarized incidents in the region have been few in number and can be plaus-
ibly be described as “minor military incidents” (Haacke 2003), it also remains
the case that ASEAN defense expenditures have risen from $11.7 bn in 1994
to $28.8 bn in 2002, an increase of 246 per cent. Even though regional special-
ists insist that those expenditures do not constitute an arms race (Simon 1996:
338; Narine 1998: 203), it would not be unreasonable to infer that military
power remains a highly valued commodity.
Euro-Atlantic
Over the course of the post-war period, positive identity formation between
the states of North America and Europe, as well as within Europe itself,
was facilitated by democratic governments and a shared civilization, both of
which were reinforced by the legitimizing rhetoric of NATO and the EU. The
State attributes and system properties 119
common identity shared within the Atlantic was initially “negative” insofar as
the glue holding NATO together was the common Soviet military threat and
the fear that national communist political parties would enjoy success at the
polls in Western Europe. Europe’s common identity was also initially nega-
tive; it consisted not only of the external threat posed by the Soviet Union
and internal threat posed by national communist parties, but also a fear of
a renascent Germany. While the Europeans and Americans have shared a
commitment to liberal democracy, elites manufactured a common European
and American identity, where arguably only a contingent one exists: the United
States has a “culture” while the Europeans have a “civilization”; Americans are
ostentatiously religious, while Europeans are generally secular; Americans
favor a Darwinian market economy alien to European social democracy; the
American identity remains pristinely national, whereas the EU states possess
in different measure a muddied identity that is both national and European.
These differences have consequences: they partially account for the mutual
suspicion and acrimony that creep periodically into European–American
relations, particularly on security issues.10
The most conspicuous characteristic these states share is the loss of sover-
eign control. Economic and political interdependence were postwar American
and European foreign policy objectives. The European states have ceded con-
trol over most aspects of economic management to the EU, individual eco-
nomic agents, and most recently the European Central Bank (ECB). The real
and financial sectors of the EU economies are fully integrated, a process
begun in earnest with the Single European Act (1986). The euro has replaced
national currencies in the EU (with a few exceptions) and the ECB rather
than national central banks sets monetary policy. The integration of the
North American and European economies is likewise broad and deep. Trade
in manufactured goods is free from high tariffs, capital markets are inte-
grated, the euro and dollar are the world’s two major transaction and invest-
ment currencies, and prior to 11 September 2001 personal travel faced few
administrative hindrances. Philosophical design and technological default
reinforce these interdependencies: the privileging of the individual vis-à-vis
the state and the ubiquity of cyberspace and other forms of electronic
communication constrain further the state’s inability to monitor or control
individual actions.
The interest calculus reveals the largest divergence within the Euro-Atlantic
region. The European states have opted to create or at least strive for a
common foreign and security policy, a European security and defense policy,
and an entire range of common policies along their periphery and beyond.
The United States retains an almost exclusively national calculus for arriving
at its definition of interest, a tendency evident during the Clinton administra-
tion and a hallmark of the Bush administration (Carter and Perry 1999;
Carter 1999–2000; US President’s Office 2002, 2006). The current administra-
tion’s rhetoric and definition of interest have slipped into the solipsism that a
threat only exists if it threatens America. Europeans, however, have largely
120 James Sperling
denationalized the definition of interest within specific spheres of activity,
particularly the promotion of democracy and market economies in their
“neighborhood”. Traditional security concerns remain national at some fun-
damental level, but even here the EU’s solidarity principle represents an
important step towards replacing discrete national interests with a single
European interest (European Union Council 2004).
The transatlantic area is free from the intramural use of force. European
defense expenditures have declined markedly since the end of the Cold War.11
Only the United Kingdom and France actively seek a power projection cap-
ability; the other EU states are content to rely on “civilian” instruments of
statecraft, which in their view are not only normatively preferable, but are
also the more effective means for ameliorating the security threats Europe
faces. American defense expenditures (in constant dollars) declined over
much of the 1990s, but rose from $290.48 bn in 1999 to $417.36 bn prior to the
invasion of Iraq. As important, American expenditures on the non-military
requirements of security have not been negligible, notably the billions spent
on the co-operative threat-reduction program. It remains true that the secur-
ity challenges facing Europe generally resist military solution, while the
global challenges facing the United States are not always militarized out of
choice, but sometimes of necessity.
Central Asia
Power relationships dominate the dynamic of the central Asian subsystem:
China and Russia both seek regional dominance and both are wary of
American troops stationed in Uzbekistan, Kyrgyzstan, and Tajikistan; the
Indian and Pakistani acquisition of nuclear weapons has not only made more
acute the regional security dilemma facing China and Russia, but threatens
State attributes and system properties 121
Table 5.6 Regional system properties of central Asia, southeast Asia, the Atlantic and
Europe
the nuclear-free status of the central Asian republics; and the United States,
China and Japan seek control over or assured access to central Asian energy
resources (Yom 2002; Guang 2005: 506; Dongfeng 2004: 13; Choo 2003).
The protection of sovereign prerogatives, the organizing principle of the
SCO, is codified in the Declaration on Creating the Shanghai Co-operation
Organization [hereafter the Declaration] (SCO 2001a: para 5), the Charter of
the Shanghai Co-operation Organization [hereafter the Charter] (SCO 2001b:
Article 1 and 2), and the Tashkent Declaration (SCO 2004). The SCO mutu-
ally guarantees the member states’ independence, sovereign equality, non-
interference in domestic affairs, and recognition of each state’s territorial
integrity. The preoccupation with preserving de jure sovereignty reflects the
insecurities of nominally sovereign states (Dawisha and Parrott 1997; Jonson
1998), China’s unwillingness to accept any constraints on its freedom of action
(Dongfeng 2004: 5), and a mutual desire to avoid outside meddling in internal
affairs (SCO 2001b: Article 1). Even where China and Russia have a direct
interest in the withdrawal of American troops based in the region, the SCO
Astana Declaration in 2005 left the terms and timetable of those withdrawals
to bilateral negotiations (Guang 2005: 503).
The normative framework governing intra-SCO interactions is rudimen-
tary, but consistent with the unwillingness of the SCO states to surrender
122 James Sperling
sovereignty to an institution or one another. The Shanghai Communiqué
(SCO 2001c) and the Declaration (SCO 2001a: para 5) put forward the basic
ground rules for behavior: the non-use of force; the renunciation of unilateral
military superiority in “contiguous” areas; non-alignment and rejection of
military alliances; and the peaceful resolution of disputes. These behavioral
norms do not deviate significantly from the principles underpinning the law
of nations in eighteenth-century Europe.
War as a means of conflict resolution remains a normatively and instru-
mentally sanctioned option. There is an explicit preference to resolve conflicts
peacefully, but China has not yet demonstrated any greater willingness to
forgo military force possibly leading to war than has the United States when
its interests are threatened. Civil wars and separatist movements are endemic
to the region (Eriksson and Wallensteen 2004: 132 ff). Although the 4,600-
mile Sino-Russian border has been demilitarized, a financially stretched
Uzbekistan nonetheless devoted scarce resources to constructing a military
base along its common border with Russia. Finally, the SCO Charter lacks a
mutual defense or collective security clause; it only provides an obligation to
resolve disputes peacefully which in the not-so-distant past were militarized.
Southeast Asia
Considerations of power bind ASEAN states together and lend ASEAN an
important part of its raison d’être. The region lies at an intersection of the
three great Pacific powers – the United States, China, Japan – with divergent
interests and objectives in the region (Narine 1998: 211; Acharya 1999: 84).
ASEAN increasingly functions as a mechanism for assuring regional auton-
omy and forestalling great power competition between an already established
United States and a presumably aspiring hegemonic China (Dosch 2003:
488). Yet, ASEAN elites recognize that regional autonomy remains depend-
ent upon the United States providing the region with the “oxygen of security”
(Segal 1996: 135; cf. Dibb 1995; Leifer 1996; Acharya and Tan 2006). Power
relationships also shaped ASEAN: elites purposely designed ASEAN so that
it would mitigate the power asymmetry between Indonesia and the others,
thereby diminishing the prospects of either an unrestricted arms race or
Indonesian dominance.
Sovereign recognition is ASEAN’s “main feature” and “highest principle”
(Emmerson 2005: 176). The 2003 Bali II Declaration restated ASEAN’s
two cardinal principles: non-interference in domestic affairs and sovereign
equality (ASEAN 2003a). Sovereign equality is manifest in the formal com-
mitment to reach decisions on the basis of consensus. Non-interference places
criticism of domestic political arrangements out of bounds and precludes a
positive obligation to intervene, even in the case of gross violations of human
rights. Thailand, in response to domestic developments in Myanmar, pro-
posed a modification of the non-intervention principle to allow “enhanced
interaction” or “flexible engagement”. This proposal would have created a
State attributes and system properties 123
principled basis for the intramural monitoring of domestic political devel-
opments, but the proposal violated the sovereignty principle, did not gain
traction, and was subsequently withdrawn.
The normative framework governing intra-ASEAN relations is shallow,
but relatively broad in scope. A set of treaties, conventions and declarations
spell out a set of internally consistent regulatory norms, including the 1995
Treaty on the Southeast Asian Nuclear Weapons Free Zone (the Bangkok
Treaty), the 1976 Treaty of Amity and Co-operation in Southeast Asia (TAC),
and the 2003 Declaration of ASEAN Concord II (Bali Concord II). The
TAC, which has served as the touchstone for subsequent ASEAN agree-
ments, codified the renunciation of the threat or use of force, the peaceful
settlement of disputes, and non-interference in bilateral disputes between
ASEAN members (Emmerson 2005: 176; Haacke 2003: 59). Other governing
norms include decision-making by consensus, the rejection of military pacts
and European-style multilateral security institutions, and regional nuclear
non-proliferation (Ba 2005: 257; Khoo 2004: 40).12 These normative injunc-
tions are the constituent elements of the so-called “ASEAN way,” defined
somewhat ambitiously as a “process of identity building which relies upon
conventional modern principles of interstate relations as well as traditional
and culture-specific modes of socialization and decision-making” (Acharya
2001: 28). The 2003 ASEAN Security Community (ASC) declaration, hailed
as a signal departure for ASEAN, failed to expand mutual obligations or
deepen the normative framework governing regional security co-operation.
The ASC simply expresses the signatories’ intention to protect the region’s
status as a nuclear-free zone and to deepen co-operation in the fight against
terrorism. Moreover, the ASC declaration explicitly declared that it was not
the basis for a military alliance, a defense pact or a joint foreign policy
(ASEAN 2003a). Sovereign prerogatives were left unmolested.
A key feature of ASEAN security co-operation is the proscription of war
as an instrument of statecraft. Although the last major regional conflict
ended in 1998 with the Sino-Vietnamese war, war remains a practical option
although normatively proscribed in treaty. That war should remain viable
should not come as a surprise, but the absence of war and the low number of
militarized conflicts in the region probably should. The absence of war within
ASEAN, however, does not exclude the possibility of it erupting in the future;
there is little empirical evidence supporting the proposition that the aversion
to war is normative rather than instrumental.
Euro-Atlantic
Despite the economic and military power wielded by individual EU states,
power asymmetries do not determine outcomes in EU policy debates. While
little of significance has happened in the EU without a prior Franco-German
agreement, the converse has not been not true: their bargain does not inexor-
ably become Europe’s. Institutional arrangements have also muted power
124 James Sperling
asymmetries: the smaller EU states wield influence disproportional to their
size owing to the assessment of voting weights; qualified majority voting
precludes a unit veto; and the double majority rule has aligned population
size with voting strength, which does not always favor the most economically
or militarily powerful. In the transatlantic area, the United States acts in
accordance with the prerogatives that its power confers upon it. NATO’s
integrated military command has placed a mild constraint on the American
exercise of power, but a significant one on the European. Moreover, there has
been – and there is – little that the NATO allies can do if the United States
acts unilaterally. Thus, within the transatlantic context two contrary dynam-
ics exist: a growing reliance upon democratic decision-making in the EU
tenuously linked to power traditionally measured; and intra-alliance relations
still mediated by the sometimes raw exercise of American power.
The three pillars of the EU – the European Communities, the Common
Foreign and Security Policy (CFSP), Justice and Home Affairs (JHA) – have
progressively encroached on sovereign prerogatives. The two institutional
manifestations best illustrating this development are the European Court of
Justice (ECJ) and the ECB. The ECJ adjudicates conflicts within the EU, and
member states treat those decisions, in principle, as binding.13 The ECB man-
ages euro-zone monetary policy, regulates aspects of the European financial
system, and monitors member-state budgetary policies. The ECB and ECJ
are politically unaccountable and possess sovereign prerogatives historically
reserved to states. Unlike its European allies, the United States has resisted
the sacrifice of significant sovereign prerogatives to international institutions,
particularly in the formulation and execution of security policy. The United
States is the signatory to any number of international treaties and agreements
– and the author of many – but successive administrations have ignored
the provisions of international agreements when they have come into conflict
with material national interests. Moreover, successive American administra-
tions have acted as if NATO’s integrated command functioned primarily to
keep America’s European allies on a short leash.
Norms in the European political space have become institutionalized as
hard law (Abbott et al. 2000: 405; Alter 2000: 492). As the scope and domain
of EU law have expanded, the member states are increasingly “pushed toward
outcomes other than those predicted by power and the pursuit of national
interest” (Ann-Marie Slaughter, quoted in Beyers 1999: 17). Alec Stone Sweet
and Thomas Brunell (1998: 65) detect a “vertically integrated legal regime”
that is transforming the EU into “a multi-tiered system of governance founded
on higher law constitutionalism” (cf. Caldeira and Gibson 1995: 358; Mattli
and Slaughter 1995). The institutionalization of norms as hard law is ongoing
in Pillar I, although the norms and principles governing EU security pol-
icy under the aegis of Pillars II and III are not yet binding (Kirchner and
Sperling 2007). In JHA, the EU has made progress in crafting a common
strategy towards transborder crime and terrorism. It has, for example, estab-
lished common minimum maximum penalties for specific categories of crime
State attributes and system properties 125
and a common definition of terrorism, agreed on a common list of terrorist
groups, created common standards governing the collection of evidence, and
instituted a common European arrest warrant. It would be very difficult to
argue that international norms have recently constrained American behavior
or defined its interests with regard to security matters – the questionable legal-
ity of the Iraq war and the clear violation of the Geneva Convention provi-
sions on the treatment of prisoners of war are only two of the most egregious
examples. Norms play very different roles on either side of the Atlantic.
Arguably, norms constitute European interests across a broad spectrum of
policy issues; norms, albeit central to American rhetoric, are valued instru-
mentally and remain peripheral to the definition of American interests.
The role of war in the Euro-Atlantic region may be summarily dismissed.
Unlike other regions of the world, war plays no role in resolving intramural
disputes. Ole Wæver (1998: 104) has correctly characterized the EU as a
“non-war community”; there is no conceivable set of circumstances that
could serve as a casus belli between Europe and the United States.
SCO
The SCO, and the “Shanghai Process” that preceded it, originally arose out of
Sino-Soviet efforts to resolve outstanding border disputes and to demilitarize
their common border. Shared concerns over the transborder threats posed by
terrorism, separatism, and organized crime have slowly eclipsed in import-
ance the demilitarization process and implementation of confidence-building
measures (Gill 2004: 213–16). These shared security interests have not pro-
duced collective or positive identities and Sino-Russian strategic interests
define the regional dynamic. Thus, the SCO security referent is outwardly
Table 5.7 The varieties of security multilateralism
Central Internal and regional Balance of power Instrumental and extrinsic to Enmity; intense Co-operative security
Asia interests; serve to bolster security dilemma
internal repression and
territorial integrity
Southeast Internal and regional Consensus and force Norms defining “ASEAN Muted enmity; security Concert towards co-
Asia way” have substantive value, dilemma managed operative security
but are not intrinsic to
interest calculation
Atlantic External and global Force outside group Norms are substantively and Strained amity, security Collective defense
intrinsically valued over a dilemma weak towards concert
narrow range of security
issues; there has been a
weakening of those norms
after 11 September
EU Internal and Law and institutions Norms are substantively and Amity; security Civilianized security
neighborhood intrinsically valued across a dilemma not a relevant community
broad range of issues category of analysis
spanning the entire spectrum
of internal and external
governance policies
State attributes and system properties 127
directed to the regional milieu (managing the “three threats”) and inwardly
directed at the management of within-group conflicts.
Intramural conflict is regulated by traditional statecraft, particularly the
reliance upon informal mechanisms for policy co-ordination. War and force
remain viable instruments. Although the renunciation of force is a central
norm of the “Shanghai process”, it remains contingent and instrumental rather
than intrinsic and substantive. China has embarked upon an ambitious mili-
tary modernization program, Russia only exercises influence in the region
owing to its military preponderance, and the other SCO states extended the
United States basing rights, arguably defense expenditure and deterrence by
proxy. The persistence of the sovereignty principle and a particularistic defin-
ition of interest together provide a formidable barrier to the deeper insti-
tutionalization of the SCO process and a greater reliance upon multilateral
mechanisms for resolving conflict.14
The function that norms play in defining national interests is contingent on
whether system-level norms are substantive or instrumental and intrinsic or
extrinsic to national values. The strength of the normative framework is con-
tingent upon the overlapping of norms and interests. The strength of the
sovereignty principle and continuing importance of relative power in intra-
regional relations retard the emergence of a robust normative framework con-
stituting a part of the national security calculus. SCO framework documents
enumerate a consistent set of norms, but those norms only legitimize repres-
sive political regimes, leave unmolested sovereign prerogatives, and reinforce
the primacy of national interests. No SCO state is obligated to carry out an
SCO policy if it conflicts with the national interest; there is no expectation of
sovereign abnegation to further a collective goal (SCO 2001b: Article 7; SCO
2001a: para. 10). Thus, SCO norms are weakly regulative rather than consti-
tutive, contingent rather than binding. As such they have had little impact on
either identity formation or the definition of interest.
The strength of the sovereignty principle, in conjunction with the sovereign
control the member states exercise and seek to exercise over their territory
and citizenry, sustain an interaction context of enmity and bilateral security
dilemmas. The Chinese and Russian governments retain a high degree of
sovereign control over closed political systems, exploit political cultures priv-
ileging the state over society, and highly discount civil and political liberties.
Despite “soft borders” repressive governments in the four remaining SCO
states act as gate-keepers over those aspects of society most likely to touch
upon national security. The sovereignty principle reinforces the “national”
in the national interest and the preoccupation with territorial and political
integrity. Correspondingly, the development of a positive or collective iden-
tity, which would build trust and mitigate the bilateral security dilemmas,
is blocked by a constellation of factors, particularly the militarized intra-
mural conflicts of the not-too-distant past, the unabated great power com-
petition between China and Russia for regional dominance, and the absence
of a civilizational or threat-based foundation for constructing either a “we”
128 James Sperling
independent of the external environment or a common “other” against which
the members are jointly opposed.
The SCO does not meet the criteria of an outwardly directed impermanent
alliance. It would be difficult to demonstrate that the organization’s origin,
continuing rationale, and cohesion (such as it is) can be attributed to a com-
mon interest in “balancing” the United States or the “bandwagoning” calcula-
tions of the smaller central Asian states. The basing of American troops in
three of the SCO states also suggests that an alternative classification is
in order. The SCO fails to meet any of the criteria for the more demanding
forms of security multilateralism that require even a partial abnegation of
sovereignty. Instead, the attributes of the central Asian states and the char-
acteristics of the regional subsystem have produced a weak form of co-
operative security: these states jointly seek an overlapping set of milieu goals
that serve narrowly defined national interests. The multilateralism that does
take place is severely constrained by the external dynamic of anarchy and the
internal dynamic of repression.
ASEAN
The ASEAN states have rejected as undesirable both collective security and
collective defense arrangements. The structure of power continues to play an
important, but not dominant, role in defining relations within ASEAN and
southeast Asia more broadly. ASEAN states seek regional autonomy, a goal
that can only be achieved in opposition to the presumed hegemonic ambi-
tions of China and insulated from the Sino-American competition for Asia-
Pacific dominance. The American security guarantees, which pose a signifi-
cant barrier to Chinese suzerainty or hegemony, permit ASEAN states to
discount intramural considerations of power. The external threats posed to
ASEAN – initially communism and now China – have created a common
identity between the member states, but that identity remains largely negative.
Nonetheless, that negative identity serves as a foundation for the joint defin-
ition of interests and policy co-ordination in a circumscribed set of policy
areas, including security. The ASEAN security referent is both internal
(within group co-operation on jointly defined security threats) and external
(maintaining regional autonomy and mitigating great power conflicts).
The regulator is decentralized and weakly institutionalized by design.
Decentralization represents the confluence of the ASEAN states’ willingness
and preparedness to use force and the episodic eruption of militarized con-
flict within and between them. As the defense budgets of the ASEAN states
attest, the military option remains in place despite the prohibitionary norms
against force found in the TAC and Bali II Concord. The continuing rele-
vance of power and force is moderated by the relatively high levels of eco-
nomic interaction among the more powerful ASEAN states – Thailand,
Singapore, Indonesia, and the Philippines – and a common interest in
expanding commercial and financial ties with China, Japan and the United
State attributes and system properties 129
States. While the structure of trade could contribute steadily to the creation
of a positive identity, if not a sense of “we-ness,” it will remain counterbal-
anced by the continuing resilience of southeast Asian nationalisms, lingering
historical enmities, and domestic political systems ranging from the demo-
cratic to the despotic. These factors work against surrendering significant
sovereign prerogatives to a regional institution for the purposes of regulating
intramural conflict or securing regional milieu goals.
A series of treaties enumerate the norms governing intra-ASEAN relations.
Those norms, which proscribe and prescribe intramural behavior, have taken
on a substantive value for the members, but are not yet intrinsic to the calcula-
tion of national interests (Emmerson 2005). Successful appeals to the “ASEAN
way” have managed intramural disputes and shaped the broader dynamic of
the Asia-Pacific. At a minimum, the ASEAN norms have created the basis
for positive identity formation. The sovereignty principle inhibits progress
towards a more fully formed collective identity or the transition of norms from
the instrumental to the substantive, from the extrinsic to the intrinsic. As
a consequence, the more demanding forms of security multilateralism are
unavailable, albeit the ASEAN states have explicitly rejected Western-style
multilateral frameworks as alien to the region (ASEAN 2004). The southeast
Asian interaction context combines muted enmity between dyads of states
(such as Thailand and Myanmar; Singapore and Malaysia; Vietnam and Laos)
with fully unresolved within-group security dilemmas overlain by a collective
security dilemma vis-à-vis China. The region suffers from a set of unpropitious
circumstances for co-operation – border and territorial disputes persist, sover-
eign prerogatives remain inviolable, and distrust remains high. The persistence
of narrowly defined national interests and the role of power in shaping the
regional context hinder the development of a more fully formed positive iden-
tity and preclude the emergence of a collective one. The ASEAN states’ eco-
nomic success and acknowledged interdependencies, both economic and
strategic, offset these negative factors and contribute to the muted enmity and
the absence of an acute within-group security dilemma.
What kind of security multilateralism does ASEAN represent? ASEAN
shares some of the characteristics found in co-operative security arrangements,
but closely approximates a concert. As a concert, ASEAN has been enabled
to facilitate weakly institutionalized balances of power within ASEAN + 3
(China, Japan and South Korea) or the ASEAN Regional Forum (ARF), the
pan-Pacific security institution. ASEAN + 3 directs its energies towards con-
taining a Sino-Japanese competition in Asia; ARF pursues the balancing of
the major Pacific powers (China, Japan, and the United States). Both aux-
iliary institutions seek general milieu goals of political and strategic stability
in the Asia-Pacific that serve the long-term ASEAN interest in regional
autonomy. It is overly broad and misleading to claim that the Asia-Pacific
exists “somewhere between a balance of power and a community-based
security order” (Ikenberry and Tsuchiyama 2002), particularly since “some-
where” includes virtually every conceivable form of security multilateralism.
130 James Sperling
Security multilateralism in the Asia-Pacific is relatively weak, but ASEAN
represents a regional concert striving to manage intramural conflicts, protect
regime integrity, and create a favorable regional milieu.
NATO
The classification of NATO as a collective defense arrangement ought to be
relatively uncomplicated and uncontested, particularly given the provisions
of the North Atlantic Treaty’s Article 5. Alas, this is not the case. NATO’s
precise character is muddied by those seeking to press NATO into the pigeon
hole of a “security community” based on the confluence of democratic
government, a shared civilization, and the expectation that conflicts will be
resolved non-violently. A second barrier to the simple classification of NATO
is the fundamental geopolitical change occasioned by the end of the Cold War;
viz, NATO was transformed virtually overnight from a compulsory alliance
that derived its cohesive power from a common Soviet threat to a voluntary
alliance with no specific adversary or obvious purpose. Thus the evolution of
the Atlantic area initiated the transformation of the NATO security referent
from a specific, adversarial “other” into a non-specific set of milieu goals. That
change has eroded the negative identity that the Soviet threat gave the alli-
ance. In the absence of an equally cohesive alternative “other”, power has been
reintroduced into NATO’s internal dynamic, particularly with respect to the
defining of common milieu goals and the appropriate geographic reach for
NATO. Paradoxically, the absence of the Soviet Union has placed into ques-
tion the causal relationship between democracy, collective identity, and inter-
est formation. NATO remains outwardly orientated, but the target of the
alliance is uncertain and internal cohesion has weakened.
The regulator of conflict within the alliance is highly institutionalized within
the North Atlantic Council and more importantly within the integrated
command structure. Deterring war and relying upon force to address “com-
mon” security problems was the core function of NATO, but in the changed
environment that consensus has weakened. During the Cold War, Western
Europeans and Americans alike relied upon military force to deter a Soviet
attack and actively prepared for war within the North Atlantic area; conflicts
of interest over how those goals would be best met were resolved within the
NATO unified command or between the member governments within the
institutionalized forum provided by the North Atlantic Council. The sover-
eignty principle was asymmetrically compromised within that framework; the
Europeans by and large yielded to American preferences out of necessity
rather than conviction, particularly on the use of nuclear weapons and deter-
rence strategy. While some argue that the Alliance shared a common identity,
which would imply an undifferentiated understanding of threat and response,
there was in fact a highly differentiated concept of interest outside the general
interest of deterring the Soviet Union. Simply put, the Europeans hoped that
if deterrence failed the subsequent nuclear exchange would take place over
State attributes and system properties 131
their heads, while the United States was determined that a nuclear exchange
would first occur on European soil. That conflict was resolved largely in the
American favor owing to its preponderance of power; after the Cold War
similar fissures within the alliance over strategy are not so easily contained, as
the division over Iraq proved.
The norms embodied in the North Atlantic Treaty are intrinsic and sub-
stantive to the calculation of interest on both sides of the Atlantic over a
narrow range of issues. Norms have been endowed with these characteristics
despite the relative strength of the sovereignty principle within the treaty
itself (sovereign equality) and the American tendency to identify its interests
according to a national rather than collective referent (Carter and Perry 1999;
US President’s Office 2002, 2006). The absence of force as an instrument for
resolving intramural disputes, albeit somewhat offset by the American willing-
ness to exploit the asymmetry of power between itself and its European allies,
created an environment that allowed the transformation of instrumental
norms created in the early 1950s into substantive norms intrinsic to national
calculations of interest. Even the existential threat posed to the United States
on 11 September 2001 and the plausible insularity of the European allies
from a similar attack did not deter them from invoking Article 5 for the first
time in the Alliance’s history and participating in the pacification and occu-
pation of post-Taliban Afghanistan. This chain of events demonstrates that
the collective defense obligation in the North Atlantic Treaty is indeed an
intrinsic norm.15
Amity interrupted by occasional fits of pique defines the NATO inter-
action context. There is no security dilemma within the alliance; controversy
does exist, however, on what constitutes a threat, the sources of those threats,
the best means of addressing those threats, and the geographic reach of the
Alliance. These kinds of controversies existed during the Cold War, but
multiplied after 1992. Russia and Ukraine are unlikely to emerge as a geostra-
tegic “other” reintroducing a renewed source of negative identity to hold the
alliance together. But the Russian failure to evolve into a robust democracy
could reintroduce at a minimum regional enmity.
The durability of NATO as a collective defense organization may be
attributed to the postwar confluence of common interests, common values,
and a manufactured common identity, even though positive and negative
identities coexisted (Hampton and Sperling 2002: 281–302). NATO falls
short of meeting fully the requirements of a security community or a collect-
ive security organization. While it may have appeared to have been more than
a collective defense arrangement during the postwar period, developments
within NATO since 2001 in particular have revealed schisms that are deep
and probably enduring. The NATO states are democracies and there is no
conceivable circumstance under which they would resort to war with one
another. But the selective participation of NATO allies in different peace-
keeping missions and, most tellingly, the invasion of Iraq also suggest that
NATO may be developing a dual personality: an inwardly directed collective
132 James Sperling
defense organization without a specific or likely enemy and an outwardly
directed concert pursuing a disputed set of milieu goals.
EU
The EU has been both a foreign policy objective of its member states as well
as a foreign policy actor. As in the case of NATO, the EU referent is both
inwardly and outwardly directed, although there is no adversarial “other”.
The inward orientation of the EU focuses on the non-traditional aspects of
security that arise from the post-Westphalian character of the member states;
the outward orientation is directed towards a broad and consistent set of
regional milieu goals along its eastern and southern peripheries. The EU
members share a collective identity reinforced by supranational institutions
that have muted asymmetries of power. Power does not play a significant role
in EU relations with its neighboring states. A benign external environment in
combination with the absence of differentiation between member state inter-
ests across a broad spectrum of security issues explains the character of the
EU security referent.
The EU states have pooled or ceded considerable sovereignty to supra-
national institutions (the Commission, ECJ, and ECB) and have constructed
a collective identity over the course of the postwar period. While a European
identity has not superseded the national identities of its members, there none-
theless exists a denationalized understanding of threats common to Europe
and the expectation that those threats will be met jointly. War between the EU
states has become unthinkable; no other state or group of states constitutes a
military threat. The willingness to rely on force remains, but the resort to
force is limited by treaty to the Petersberg Tasks of peace-keeping, humani-
tarian intervention, rescue tasks, crisis-management and conflict prevention.
These permissive internal factors in combination with a settled external
environment have enabled the EU to institutionalize conflict resolution to a
degree only exceeded within states: intramural conflicts are resolved within
the Council of Ministers and European Council, the European Commission
drafts policies meeting common needs, and the ECJ adjudicates conflicts and
the plaintiffs expect voluntary compliance with the court’s decisions.
The norms governing the EU states are substantive and intrinsic to the
calculation of interest. National interests are themselves subject to the soli-
darity principle, which has established the expectation that national security
policies will serve not only the particularistic interests of the member state,
but the collective interests of the Union (EU 2004). The erosion of the sover-
eignty principle, the absence of force in mediating intramural conflicts, and a
broad and deep normative framework progressively institutionalized as hard
law create a context where EU norms constitute the definition of interest.
Amity and the absence of a security dilemma characterize the EU inter-
action context. The within-group dynamic has created and sustained amity:
the states have progressively sacrificed ever greater levels of sovereignty to
State attributes and system properties 133
supranational institutions, while the purposeful loss of sovereign control has
required that transfer of sovereignty. While the rationale for the European
project may have been initially instrumental (Milward 1992), it could only
persist and broaden if accompanied by intramural trust and amity. This same
dynamic altered the calculus of interest from the particular to the collective, a
process unhindered by the prospect of war (a function of the American secur-
ity guarantee and occupation of Germany in the early postwar years). By the
time that the EU acquired a security writ in the late 1980s, the fear of a
renascent Germany and the corresponding security dilemma perceived by its
neighbors (the original motivation for the Brussels Treaty Organization) had
evaporated.
The EU is positioned to adopt the defining characteristic of a collective
security system: Article V of the Western European Union treaty provides for
the positive obligation to intervene on behalf of a signatory state in the event
of aggression.16 The EU does represent a civilianized security community. This
conclusion should not come as a surprise since the concept was developed to
account for the EU as a system of governance. Classifying the EU is not as
important as understanding why the EU developed into a security community,
since the answer to that question has policy implications for those wishing to
reproduce the number of security communities across the globe. What dis-
tinguishes the EU from the other regions is the post-Westphalian character of
the member states and the systemic dynamic of post-Westphalianism that
pushes states towards security co-operation (Falk 2002).
Conclusion
Security multilateralism is about effective governance of the international sys-
tem, particularly the supply of order and the regulation of conflict. The pri-
mary task set in this chapter was to understand how the interaction of state
attributes and system properties produced specific forms of security multi-
lateralism and to establish the limits of security governance in disparate parts
of the world. Secondary objectives included crafting a set of criteria that differ-
entiate between the different forms of security multilateralism and classifying
the SCO, ASEAN, NATO and the EU as systems of security multilateralism.
The assessments of the four regional systems of security multilateralism are
relatively conservative. Contrary to much of the existing literature, the SCO,
ASEAN, and NATO can not be described as a form of collective security
or security community if those concepts are to retain any explanatory or
descriptive power. Neither the SCO nor ASEAN represents a very ambitious
form of security multilateralism. NATO’s qualified classification as a collect-
ive defense arrangement – despite the provisions of the North Atlantic Treaty
– and its devolution towards an amiable concert reflects a change in systemic
conditions conjoined to the asynchronous evolution of the United States and
its European allies towards a post-Westphalian identity. The EU states are
post-Westphalian states and operate in a permissive systemic milieu. These
134 James Sperling
findings provide, at a minimum, preliminary support for the post-Westphalian
hypothesis: the post-Westphalian state is a necessary condition for the most
advanced forms of security governance, but an insufficient one. The sys-
tem continues to function as a significant barrier between the possible and
desirable forms of security multilateralism.
Notes
Thanks are owed to Aris Alexopoulos, Dimitris Bourantonis, Kostas Ifantis, Oliver
Richmond, Keery Walker and Michael Westmoreland for comments made on a much
earlier draft of this paper. The usual disclaimer applies.
Developments since the end of the Cold War have encouraged multilateral
security organizations and humanitarian organizations to orientate their
activities in the same direction. Although the formal structures of multi-
lateral security organizations have not appreciably altered, their purpose has.
During the Cold War most multilateral security organizations operated with
a statist concept of security, restricted their activities to the defense of states,
and viewed security in strictly military terms. Yet over the past fifteen years
many of these same organizations have introduced a humanitarian dimension
into their strategic doctrines and stated purpose. Reflective of the member
states that define their activities, many regional and international organiza-
tions increasingly view as legitimate the idea of humanitarian intervention,
believe that human rights are an important part of security, and occasionally
fancy themselves as humanitarian actors. As they have warmed to the idea
and importance of humanitarian action, many major powers and regional
organizations not only see humanitarian action as an important supplement
to their goals, they also imagine that states and humanitarian organizations
are crime-fighting partners. As former Secretary of State Colin Powell told
a gathering of NGOs in 1991, “just as surely as our diplomats and military,
American NGOs are out there [in Afghanistan] serving and sacrificing on the
frontlines of freedom. NGOs are such a force multiplier for us, such an
important part of our combat team.”1
The meaning and practice of humanitarian action also have expanded over
the last fifteen years. Humanitarian agencies have traditionally defined them-
selves in opposition to “politics” (Nyers 1999: 21).2 Certainly they recognized
that humanitarianism was the offspring of politics, that their activities have
political consequences, and that they are inextricably part of the political
world. Yet the widely accepted definition of humanitarianism – the impartial,
independent, and neutral provision of relief to those who are in avoidable
danger of harm – emerged in opposition to a particular meaning of politics
and helped to depoliticize relief-orientated activities.3
The foundational purpose of humanitarian action, the provision of assist-
ance to those at immediate risk, removed it from politics. Many activities
might alleviate suffering and improve life circumstances, including human
Is multilateralism bad for humanitarianism? 137
rights and development; but these are political because they aspire to
restructure underlying social relations. Humanitarianism provides relief: it
offers to save individuals, but not to eliminate the underlying causes that
placed them at risk.
Humanitarian’s original principles also were a reaction to politics and
designed to obstruct this “moral pollutant.” The principle of humanity com-
mands attention to all humankind and inspires a cosmopolitanism. The
principle of impartiality demands that assistance be based on need and not
discriminate on the basis of nationality, race, religious belief, gender, political
opinions, or other considerations (Pictet 1979). The principles of neutrality
and independence also help to inoculate humanitarianism from politics.
Relief agencies are best able to perform their life-saving activities if, and only
if, they are untouched by state interests and partisan agendas.4 Neutrality
involves refraining from taking part in hostilities or from any action that
either benefits or disadvantages the parties to the conflict. Neutrality is both
an end and a means to an end, because it helps relief agencies gain access
to populations at risk. Independence demands that assistance should not
be connected to any of the parties directly involved in the conflict or who have
a stake in the outcome. Accordingly, many agencies have either refused or
limited their reliance on government funding if the donors have a stake in
the outcome. The principles of humanity, impartiality, neutrality, and
independence have served to depoliticize humanitarian action and create a
“humanitarian space” – a space insulated from politics.
Yet over the last decade humanitarian action has expanded significantly
beyond its “apolitical” confines and now shares space with “politics” as it works
to promote development, human rights, democracy, and peacebuilding. Push
and pull factors were responsible for this expansion, and while some agencies
resisted the flow, others went with it. For many agencies this transgression
into politics produced considerable anxiety because of the fear that the frat-
ernization of politics and humanitarianism would corrupt this sacred idea
and undermine the ability to provide relief. Not only might they lose their
impartiality as they became attached to broader political projects, but they
also would sacrifice their independence as they associated with states.5 For
other agencies, especially those championing human rights and development,
this was a welcome expansion because it deepened their solidarity with the
weak and vulnerable, extended the assistance activities that might be pro-
vided to them, and enabled them to work toward the elimination of the root
causes of conflict. Although there remain important divisions in the humani-
tarian community, “fundamentalists” have lost ground to the “new” humani-
tarians who accept a politicized humanitarianism (Weiss 1999; Minear 2002;
Chandler 2002; Stoddard 2002).
This chapter examines how the emergence of a humanized multilateralism
and a politicized humanitarianism can compromise the provision of relief
and protection of civilians. The first section explores the various factors that
contributed simultaneously to the humanization of multilateralism and the
138 Michael Barnett
politicization of humanitarianism. To better understand how these changes
shaped the meaning and practices of humanitarian action, the second section
looks at external control and examines three branches of organizational the-
ory. The first two, principal–agent analysis and sociological institutionalism,
highlight how the different dimensions of the environment can lead to greater
control over humanitarian organizations. Principal–agent analysis highlights
how states that are increasingly prone to see humanitarian action as an
important feature of their foreign policy might now be encouraged to intro-
duce new control mechanisms on agencies, mechanisms that might threaten
agencies’ independence, impartiality, and neutrality. Sociological institution-
alism focuses on how the desire by organizations for external legitimacy –
legitimacy that can bring resources and status – can encourage agencies to
expand their activities and associate with states.
The legitimation of international human rights norms was a powerful
magnet for relief agencies. Yet organizations were not only forced into new
areas, they also were drawn because of internal dispositions. Although organ-
izational interests played a part, also present was an organizational culture
that compelled staff to try to resolve the tensions they confronted between
their aspirational mandates to help the suffering and the demanding situations
on the ground. Relief can be a temporary salve in the face of ongoing threats
against civilians and the concern that relief does not address the root causes
that make populations vulnerable. To try to reduce suffering, humanitarian
organizations reached into new areas and toward states.
The third section of this chapter explores these issues in the case of
NATO’s “humanitarian war” in Kosovo. Although the willingness of states to
use force in the defense of civilian populations can be interpreted as a victory
for principled action, in this case principled action also represented a poten-
tial threat to humanitarianism. Indeed, the humanitarian sector sponsored
over two dozen evaluations of Kosovo, something of a record for the time
and indicative of the desire to assess not only their technical prowess (or lack
thereof ) but also the larger political implications of this event.6 At issue was
why so many agencies felt so comfortable associating so closely with a com-
batant and suspending their sacrosanct principles of impartiality, independ-
ence, and neutrality, whether that association had harmed their ability to
provide relief and protection, and what this event meant for the future of
humanitarian action. I conclude by reflecting on how different versions of
institutionalism help us understand the different kinds of control mechan-
isms exerted by the environment over humanitarian organizations, the need
for an interpretive perspective to understand why humanitarian organiza-
tions might view this principled development – a humanized multilateralism –
as a threat to their principles, and humanitarianism’s relationship to world
order.
Is multilateralism bad for humanitarianism? 139
Humanizing multilateralism and politicizing humanitarianism
A defining feature of the post-Cold War period was the foregrounding of the
“civilian” as an object of concern.7 The meaning of security underwent a
perceptible change, expanding from an emphasis on state security to include
elements of human security. Reflective of this change, many states, regional
organizations, and international organizations redefined the military’s activ-
ities to include peacekeeping, civilian policing, political stabilization, and
even nation-building, and to consider the legitimacy of humanitarian inter-
vention. Although many security organizations resisted this expansion on the
grounds that it was outside – and would dilute – their core mandate, the
secular trend was toward a humanized multilateralism. The factors that led to
a humanized multilateralism also had a second-order effect on humanitarian
action. Certainly humanitarian organizations did not have to be convinced of
the importance of organizing their activities around the principle of human-
ity, but they did require a more permissive environment that would allow
them to expand into new areas that would enable them to protect populations
at risk. Once states and their regional organizations became more open to the
idea of humanitarian action, humanitarian organizations quickly discovered
that the constraints on their activities decreased and the opportunity struc-
ture increased. Although many humanitarian organizations worried that this
engagement with politics might injure humanitarian action, the secular trend
was toward a politicized humanitarianism.
Humanized multilateralism
A widely accepted definition of multilateralism is that it “coordinates behavior
among three or more states on the basis of generalized principles of conduct”
(Ruggie 1993b: 14). This definition points us to the formal organizational
structure and its organizing principles. However, I am less concerned with
the formal structure than I am with the purpose. Many of the multilateral
security institutions that were established during the Cold War years were
organized around interstate security. Yet with the end of the Cold War
there was an important shift in the purpose of many multilateral arrange-
ments as they broadened their definition of what counts as a threat to inter-
national peace and security and incorporated the civilian as an object of
concern.
Various factors produced the general trend toward the inclusion of
humanitarian emergencies and human rights into the meaning and practice
of international security. Geopolitical shifts associated with the end of the
Cold War and the demise of the Soviet Union increased the demand for
humanitarian action in several ways (de Waal 1997: 133–4). There appeared
to be more humanitarian crises than ever before.8 Although there is consider-
able debate regarding whether, in fact, there were more crises or whether
Great Powers were now willing to recognize populations at risk because their
140 Michael Barnett
policies were no longer the immediate cause, the emergencies now were on the
international agenda (Slim 2004b: 155–6).
As states paid more attention to them, they linked these populations at risk
to an expanding discourse of security. One reason for their visibility was
because they now were viewed as a security issue. During the Cold War, the
UNSC defined threats to peace and security as disputes between states that
might (or had) become militarized, conflicts involving the Great Powers, and
general threats to global stability (White 1993: 34–8; Howard 1993: 69–70).
After the Cold War, and in reaction to the growing perception that domestic
conflict and civil wars were leaving hundreds of thousands of populations at
risk, creating mass flight, and destabilizing entire regions, the UNSC author-
ized interventions on the grounds that they challenged regional and inter-
national security. Operation Provide Comfort, the international intervention
to help the Kurdish refugees, reflected not simply a concern with the non-
traditional security threats but a recognition also that they could destabilize
the more traditional kind. As an unfortunate and tragic consequence of the
Gulf War, the Iraqi Kurdish population was fleeing Saddam Hussein’s mili-
tary to the Turkish border, but Turkish authorities, in violation of inter-
national refugee law, refused to give them temporary refuge. In response, the
UNSC established safe havens for the Kurdish refugees and justified this act
in the name of international peace and security. Subsequent events reinforced
the broadening of international security to include humanitarian dimensions.
Somalia barely qualified as an international threat to peace and security but
shocked the conscience of the international community. Responding to both
the post-Cold War humanitarian emergencies and the growing prominence
of the UNSC in this domain, the General Assembly passed a watershed
resolution that coronated the UN as the new co-ordinating body for governing
the response to humanitarian action.9
Relatedly, states warmed to the idea of humanitarian action as they began
to see it as an important instrument of their strategic and foreign policy
goals. Immediate evidence of their support was their growing financial gener-
osity (see below). Even more impressive was their growing willingness to
support operations whose stated function was to protect civilians at risk, and
even to consider the legitimacy of humanitarian intervention. Although it
remains a matter of fierce legal and political debate whether and when human
rights should be a factor in determining the legitimacy of intervention, as an
empirical matter the international community became increasingly willing to
avail themselves of international bodies to intervene in internal conflicts
when there are threats to human rights.10
States also discovered that humanitarian action was functional for avoid-
ing more costly interventions. For instance, the major powers authorized
UNHCR to deliver humanitarian relief in Bosnia in part because they wanted
to relieve the growing pressure for military intervention. Sometimes states
will label their activities humanitarian because they want to do something;
sometimes it is because they do not. Regardless of whether or not states had
Is multilateralism bad for humanitarianism? 141
the right motives, they were including humanitarianism and human rights in
the international peace and security discourse.11
The expansion of the meaning and object of security imprinted the post-
Cold War reform of various security institutions. As already suggested, the
UN was one of the first international organizations to reform its understand-
ing of security. Reflective and causative of the changes that occurred at the
Security Council, the Secretariat pushed for reform. UN Secretary-General
Boutros Boutros-Ghali’s The Agenda for Peace was an ambitious, forward-
looking document that represented a meditation on the changing nature of
security and called for member states to recognize the salience of non-
traditional security threats and to consider different forms of violence that
directly harm the individual. The UN was doing more than talking; it was
also acting. Between 1989 and 1994 the UNSC authorized 26 operations
across the globe, doubling in five years the number of operations authorized
by the council in the previous forty, and expanding the number of soldiers
seven-fold. While some of these post-1989 operations resembled the “clas-
sical” prototype, most now were situated in much more unstable environ-
ments, where a ceasefire was barely in place, if at all, where government
institutions were frayed and in need of repair, where there were rag-tag armies
that were not parties to the agreement, and where the UN was charged with
multidimensional and complex tasks that were designed to repair deeply-
divided societies, divided in part because of their legacy of violence against
civilians.
A humanized multilateralism also was evident in the reform of regional
security institutions, including NATO. With the demise of the Cold War and
the Soviet Union, NATO’s very raison d’être appeared to vanish. Moreover,
its conceptual and operational definition of security seemed inappropriate
given the rise of non-traditional security threats and the growing emphasis on
the need to contain and prevent domestic instability. In response to charges
that it was built for bygone times and inappropriate for the new security
challenges, NATO underwent a major debate regarding how to reorganize
itself for the new security environment. One important result was its 1999
Strategic Concept, which emphasized: a broad concept of security that rec-
ognized the presence of non-traditional security threats and how domestic
instability can produce regional instability; and a willingness to confront
humanitarian emergencies within its geographical zone and near abroad for
principled and strategic reasons.12 In reference to this proposed “deepening”
of NATO, US Deputy Secretary of State Strobe Talbott said that if NATO is
to remain relevant it must take into account the “more diversified threats . . .
Disputes over ethnicity, religion or territory, can, as we’ve already seen trigger
armed conflict, which in turn can generate cross-border political instability,
refugee flows and humanitarian crises that endanger European security”
(Simma 1999: 14). In general, post-Cold War developments, including new
ideas about security and the idea of protecting the civilian, left its mark on
various security organizations and created a humanized multilateralism.
142 Michael Barnett
Politicized humanitarianism
Four global processes helped to propel the expansion and politicization of
the purpose of humanitarianism.13 One was the already discussed changes in
meaning and practice of international security, which obviously increased the
centrality and importance of humanitarian action. A related development
was the emergence of the category of “complex humanitarian emergencies.” A
complex humanitarian emergency is a “conflict-related humanitarian disaster
involving a high degree of breakdown and social dislocation and, reflecting
this condition, requiring a system-wide aid response from the international
community” (Duffield, M. 2001: 12).14 These emergencies are characterized by
a combustible mixture of state failure, refugee flight, militias, warrior refu-
gees, and populations at risk from violence, disease, and hunger, and they
seem to be proliferating across the world. These emergencies have had several
effects. They created a demand for new sorts of interventions and conflict
management tools. Relief agencies were attempting to distribute food, water,
and medicine in war zones, frequently being forced to bargain with militias,
warlords, and hoodlums for access to populations in need. In situations of
extreme violence and lawlessness the relief agencies frequently lobbied for-
eign governments and the UN to consider authorizing a protection force that
could double as bodyguard and relief distributor. These emergencies also
attracted a range of NGOs to become more involved in the same space (Kelly
1998: 174–5). Relief agencies that were delivering emergency assistance,
human rights organizations aspiring to protect human rights and create a rule
of law, and development organizations keen to sponsor sustainable growth
began to interact and to take responsibility for the same populations. The
growing interaction between different fields in turn encouraged them to
articulate a relief–rights–development linkage within a humanitarian dis-
course that became tied to the construction of modern, legitimate, democratic
states (Duffield, M. 2001). As various international actors began to think
about the causes of and solutions to these humanitarian emergencies, they
situated their arguments under a humanitarian rubric that became tied to a
wider range of practices and goals.
A second factor was a change in the normative and legal environment,
which created new opportunities for humanitarian action that coaxed
humanitarianism into the political world. There was a shift from negative to
positive sovereignty (Jackson 1990). Whereas once state sovereignty was
sacrosanct, now it was conditional on states honoring a “responsibility to
protect” their societies (International Commission on Intervention and State
Sovereignty 2001) Whereas once their legitimacy appeared to have nearly
divine origins, now it was dependent on them possessing certain character-
istics, such as the rule of law, markets, and democratic principles. These
developments created a normative space for external intervention and
encouraged a growing range of actors to expand their assistance activities; in
some cases they were intended to provide immediate relief during conflict
Is multilateralism bad for humanitarianism? 143
situations, in others to eliminate the root causes of conflict and create legit-
imate states. Regardless of the pretext, the new normative environment
greased the tracks for more wide-ranging interventions (Macrae 1999: 6–7).
There also was the related rise of an international human rights discourse.
Although I will soon discuss how the logics of relief and rights differ, for the
moment I want to highlight elements of overlap: they place front and center
the human citizen and humanity; they contain the language of empowerment
as they attempt to help the victims, the weak, and the powerless; and they
favor a human-centered approach that rejects power (Chandler 2002: ch. 1).
The fast-growing human rights agenda pulled humanitarianism from the
margins toward the center of the international policy agenda, and many relief
agencies, increasingly adopting the language of rights, were glad to ride its
coat-tails (Chandler 2002: 21). Bosnia mixed humanitarian action and human
rights in complicated but inextricable ways, as there was a general desire for
humanitarian action to provide relief, but also the fear that such relief was
unintentionally prolonging the suffering because it allowed Western states an
exit. Then Rwanda caused “the great majority of humanitarian agencies [to]
welcome the international community’s recent introduction of the use of
force more explicitly as a key part of international policy to protect human
rights” (Slim 2002c: 2). Human rights ideas shaped the thinking of many
humanitarian organizations, and many human rights organizations began
to champion coercive humanitarianism as the best way to protect civilian
populations and enforce human rights norms.
A fourth development was a growing cosmopolitanism. Cosmopolitanism
concerns the central idea that each person is of equal moral worth and a
subject of moral concern, and that in the “justification of choices one’s
choices one must take the prospects of everyone affected equally into
account” (Beitz 1994: 124).15 Cosmopolitanism underpins humanitarianism.
The very principle of impartiality presumes that all those at risk, regardless
of their identity, deserve equal attention and consideration. The desire to help
those who are suffering regardless of place means that borders do not define
the limits of obligations. This commitment to cosmopolitanism and the very
desire to reduce suffering, however, creates a tension within humanitarianism
(Calhoun 2004). One branch restricts it to the provision of assistance to
victims of conflict; this is the version that emerged in the mid-nineteenth
century and is most closely associated with the International Committee of
the Red Cross. Another branch extends assistance to all those at risk and
imagines eliminating the conditions that are hypothesized to render popula-
tions vulnerable. As one aid worker wrote, “in terms of the destruction of
human life, what difference is there between the wartime bombing of a civil-
ian population and the distribution of ineffective medicines during a pan-
demic that is killing millions of people?” (Bradol 2004: 9). If individuals are
at risk because of authoritarian and repressive policies, then humanitarian
organizations must be prepared to fight for human rights and democratic
reforms. If individuals are at risk because of poverty and deprivation, then
144 Michael Barnett
humanitarian organizations must be prepared to promote development. If
regional and domestic conflicts are the source of violence against individuals,
then humanitarian organizations must try their hand at conflict resolution
and attempt to eliminate the underlying causes of conflict.
These developments expanded the meaning and practice of humanitarian-
ism. Table 6.1 captures the significance of this shift and the principled claims
that account for the divisions between different branches of humanitarian-
ism. There is widespread agreement that humanitarian action has drift from
a “classical” to a “solidarist” position, best represented by the displacement of
traditional relief-based agenda with a rights-based agenda. However, this
trend has been produced not only by human rights organizations but also by
development organizations, which frequently come from a solidarity tradition
and are concerned with long-term structural change.
This trend in humanitarianism has generated serious rifts within the sector,
particularly pronounced in the clash between relief and rights organizations.
Specifically, the logics of relief and rights differ in critical respects. The relief
community will nearly always privilege survival over freedom, while the rights
community is willing, at times, to use relief as an instrument of rights. Rights-
orientated agencies are willing to make relief conditional on the observance
of human rights and thus weaken the very notion of universality, a move many
relief agencies view as nearly incomprehensible.16 Relief agencies hold that
neutrality and impartiality are essential for giving them access to populations,
while many others in the sector believe that neutrality is a false guide in
situations such as crimes against humanity, and that state involvement is
a necessary solution.17 In short, in many situations of conflict and threats
to civilians, relief organizations will think long and hard before loosening
their hold on long-standing principles, while solidarists and rights-based
organizations will do so with ease.
Principal–agent models
Principal–agent approaches examine why principals delegate various tasks to
agents, the conditions under which such delegation is likely to happen, and
the control mechanisms that principals might develop to minimize agency
loss.18 Importantly, principal–agent models recognize that all agents have
some autonomy. Indeed, this can be by design. If one reason why principals
such as states establish agents such as international organizations is to benefit
146 Michael Barnett
from their expertise, then it makes good sense to give them the discretion to
adapt their policies in response to new information, challenges, and circum-
stances. The problem, though, is that agents can use their discretion either to
venture into areas that are unrelated to their mandate (shirk) or to undermine
agent interests (slack). If the agent bumps up against or crosses the line, then
the expectation is that the principal will sanction the agent or rewrite the
contract.
Principal–agent approaches capture why states have imposed more control
mechanisms on humanitarian organizations since the early 1990s. Prior to
the 1990s states funded NGOs with almost no questions asked. They were a
minor part of the budget, governments viewed them as more flexible and
more efficient relative to international organizations, and they had a near
monopoly on providing front-line relief. Beginning in the 1990s, however,
states began introducing various control mechanisms. Humanitarian organ-
izations were now consuming more of the foreign aid budget and states
wanted to ensure that they were getting their money’s worth. States increas-
ingly saw humanitarian organizations as carrying out their foreign policy
objectives. Moreover, the trust between donors and humanitarian organiza-
tions began to erode (Minear and Smilie 2004: ch. 9). Humanitarian organ-
izations were now in the spotlight, and their foibles and failures began to
attract as much publicity as their heroics. For these and other reasons, states
wanted to assert more control over humanitarian organizations.
Four control mechanisms deserve attention because they had a significant
impact on the discretion available to humanitarian organizations. First, and
perhaps most important, was the bilateralization of aid and the earmarking
of funds. Multilateral aid is technically defined as aid that is given to multi-
lateral organizations and is not earmarked; these organizations, therefore,
have complete discretion over how the money is spent. Bilateral aid can mean
the state dictates either to the multilateral organization how the money is
spent or gives the money to a non-multilateral organization such as an NGO.
Earmarking is when the donor dictates where and how the assistance will be
used, frequently identifying regions, countries, operations, or even projects;
this is especially useful if governments have geopolitical interests or pet pro-
jects. Since the 1980s there has been a dramatic shift away from multilateral
aid and toward bilateral aid and earmarking. In 1988 states directed roughly
45 per cent of humanitarian assistance to UN agencies in the form of multi-
lateral assistance. After 1994, however, the average dropped to 25 per cent,
and even lower in 1999 because of Kosovo (Randel and German 2002: 21).
States, moreover, are increasingly earmarking their aid, a trend partly
driven by growing concerns over the performance of UN agencies and multi-
lateral organizations. An important consequence of earmarking is that state
interests, rather than the humanitarian principle of relief based on need,
drive funding decisions. For instance, of the top 50 recipients of bilateral
assistance between 1996 and 1999, the states of the former Yugoslavia, Israel/
Palestine, and Iraq received 50 per cent of the available assistance (Randel
Is multilateralism bad for humanitarianism? 147
and German 2002: 27). In 2002 nearly half of all funds given by donor
governments to the UN’s 25 appeals for assistance went to Afghanistan
(Minear and Smilie 2004: 145). If funding decisions were based solely on
need, then places like Sudan, Congo, northern Uganda, and Angola would
leapfrog toward the top of the list rather than remain neglected at the
bottom. In general, while there was more aid than ever before, it is controlled
by fewer donors who are more inclined to impose conditions and direct
aid toward their priorities. It is now a several-tiered system, with the least
fortunate getting the least attention.19
States also began applying “new public management” principles to the
humanitarian sector. These principles originated with the neo-liberal ortho-
doxy of the 1980s. One of neoliberalism’s goals was to reduce the state’s role
in the delivery of public services and, instead, rely on commercial and volun-
tary organizations that were viewed as more efficient. Because government
agencies justified the shift from the public to the private and voluntary sectors
on the grounds that the latter were more efficient, they introduced monitoring
mechanisms to reduce the possibility of either slack or shirking (Macrae et al.
2002: 18–21). Humanitarian organizations largely escaped this public man-
agement ideology before the 1990s. Because humanitarian assistance was a
minor part of the foreign aid budget, states did not view humanitarianism as
central to their foreign policy goals, and states trusted that humanitarian
agencies were efficient and effective, so there was little reason to absorb the
monitoring costs. However, once humanitarian funding increased, humani-
tarianism became more central to security goals, and states began to question
the effectiveness of humanitarian organizations, they were willing to spend
money on monitoring (de Waal 1997: 78–9).
A third development was the growing interest by states in seeing for them-
selves what was occurring in the field. Toward that end, they began sending
representatives directly into the field to provide first-hand accounts of assist-
ance activities, and began developing the capacity for independent needs
assessments and strategic analyses. An immediate consequence was that
humanitarian organizations no longer benefited from having privileged and
highly authoritative information. Said otherwise, whereas once humanitarian
organizations possessed private information and were the experts because of
their first-hand knowledge and practical experience, the growing presence
of state officials meant that humanitarian organizations lost that monopoly
position, their informational advantages, and their discretion.
Fourth, as states and regional organizations became more involved in
war zones and delivering relief to populations in need, they became more
interested in co-ordinating the actions of humanitarian organizations. Co-
ordination can appear to be a technical exercise whose sole function is to
improve the division of labor, increase specialization, and heighten efficien-
cies. Yet this co-ordination, like all governance activities, is a highly political
exercise that is defined by power (Minear 2002: ch. 2). The power behind co-
ordination has not been lost on humanitarian organizations, especially when
148 Michael Barnett
the donors are either parties to the conflict or have a vested interest in the
outcome (Macrae et al. 2002: ch. 3).
The growing interest and involvement by states in humanitarian action had
the consequence of giving them greater control over the behavior of humani-
tarian organizations. Some of these control mechanisms operated through
subtle and indirect means. After all, when states earmark they are not always
intentionally attempting to redirect the behavior, that is, the exercise of power
in its most visible and fundamental form, but rather acting in ways that give
incentives for aid agencies to shift their activities. States are not always subtle,
though, and sometimes they can use control mechanisms to compel agencies
to change their behavior or suffer the consequences. Western states have
flexed their political and financial muscle to compel humanitarian organiza-
tions to act in ways that are consistent with state interests. In Afghanistan
and Iraq, the United States unveiled these threats and communicated to
NGOs that they expected humanitarian organizations to perform in ways
that would help the United States with its hearts and minds campaigns and
sell the war back home. One NGO official captured the US’s message in the
following terms: “play the tune or they’ll take you out of the band” (quoted
in Minear and Smilie 2004: 143).
These control mechanisms were doing more than simply reducing the
autonomy available to humanitarian organizations – they also were poten-
tially undermining the existing principles of humanitarian action. Certainly
any organization, humanitarian or otherwise, will object to a reduction in its
autonomy and discretion, but also at stake were their principles. This possi-
bility is underscored by the very nature of principal–agent contract. States see
themselves as principals that are providing a temporary transfer of authority
to their agents, humanitarian organizations. Yet humanitarian organizations
do not see themselves as agents of states or operating with delegated author-
ity; instead they see themselves as agents of humanity and operating with
moral authority. The very association with states and its presumption of
delegated authority, then, potentially undermined the moral authority cher-
ished by most humanitarian organization. Moreover, humanitarian organiza-
tions fear that any sort of association with states might compromise their
independence, impartiality, and neutrality. Indeed, if states are funding
humanitarian organizations in order to further their foreign policy goals,
then humanitarian organizations are not unjustifiably paranoid. The very
move by states to try and monitor and regulate humanitarian organizations
almost, by definition, compromises these principles.
Sociological institutionalism
Organizations are embedded in an environment that can control, constrain,
and constitute their practices. Two, related, features of the external environ-
ment are critical. One concerns the broad normative environment. Socio-
logical institutionalism emphasizes the “socially constructed normative
Is multilateralism bad for humanitarianism? 149
worlds in which organizations exist and how the social rules, standards of
appropriateness, and models of legitimacy will constitute the organization”
(Orru et al. 1991: 361).20 The environment in which an organization is
embedded is defined by a culture that contains acceptable models, standards
of action, goals, and logics of appropriateness. Organizations are constituted
by, and will be compelled to adopt, this culture for a variety of reasons. In the
domestic context there are regulatory agencies, laws, professions, and broad
public opinion that will shape organizations and their activities (H. Alford
2000: 49; DiMaggio and Powell 1991). In the international context this
includes regulatory structures associated with international law and organiza-
tions, states demands, transnational actors and epistemic communities, and
international public opinion.21
The second is their resource dependence.22 Organizations depend on others
for the resources they require to do their work. The willingness of others to
fund their activities is contingent, in part, on their perceived legitimacy and
whether they are viewed as acting according to the community’s values. If
they are out of sync with their environment, then they are likely to have their
legitimacy questioned, which, in turn, will threaten their resource base. As
Scott and Meyer summarize, this normative environment contains the “rules
and requirements to which individual organizations must conform if they
are to receive support and legitimacy from the environment” (1993: 140).
Because organizations are rewarded for conforming to rules and legitimation
principles, and punished if they do not, they will tend to model themselves
after their environment.
The international normative environment and resource competition
encouraged humanitarian organizations to expand in new directions. The
growth of the international human rights discourse and the desire to “save
failed states” created incentives for existing organizations to legitimate their
activities along these lines. They were frequently rewarded by states for doing
so.23 For instance, by becoming the lead humanitarian agency and by framing
its activities as instrumental for the pursuit of international peace and secur-
ity, UNHCR was in a position not only to expand its responsibilities but also
to demonstrate its relevance to the very states who paid the bills (Loescher
2001). Development agencies that were suffering something of an ideological
crisis by the end of the 1980s found themselves relegitimated and rejuvenated
by the possibility of claiming that development was now part of humanitar-
ian action (Duffield, M. 2001). Although there was more money than ever
before for humanitarian action, there also were more organizations compet-
ing for these funds. This produced something of a “NGO scramble,” as various
agencies not only competed with each other for these funds but frequently
moved into new activities, outside their central areas of competence, in order
to go where the money was (Cooley and Ron 2002).
150 Michael Barnett
Organizational culture
Principal–agent analysis and sociological institutionalism highlight the
external drivers of control over humanitarian organizations, but there also can
be internal dynamics that lead humanitarian organizations to introduce
changes in their rules and activities that also can leave them more vulnerable to
external control. The organizational culture can be understood as “the solu-
tions that are produced by groups of people to meet specific problems they
face in common. These solutions become institutionalized, remembered and
passed on as the rules, rituals, and values of the group” (Vaughan 1996: 64).24
Although there are various features of this culture that might encourage
expansion into new areas, I want to highlight one in particular: how to work
out various tensions that existed between their moral commitments and their
organizational mandates in new circumstances.25 Organizations may feel the
need to expand in order to resolve the contradiction between their broad
aspirational goals and the more narrowly circumscribed rules that limit
organizational action (Barnett and Finnemore 2004: ch. 6). Humanitarian
organizations are empowered by moral or aspirational claims that can be
much broader than their specific mandates or capacities. After all, while they
act in the name of humanity and attempt to reduce suffering, their mandates
may not necessarily extend to cover all that are at risk. Over time, the former
can exert pressure on the latter: limited organizational structures make it
impossible to fulfill broad mandates, creating reasons for organizational
expansion into new areas. If the goal is to relieve suffering, then it is difficult
to feel gratified by providing temporary relief; instead, they will desire to
eliminate the very conditions that produce a demand for their services.26
Many humanitarian agencies more fully embraced a human rights agenda
and the need to work alongside states as they confronted violent situations
where they were unable to provide relief or protection. In Somalia various aid
organizations, most (in)famously Care International, intensively lobbied for
military intervention to protect the relief lines and aid workers. Rwanda made
clear that there were no humanitarian solutions to humanitarian problems,
and various aid agencies lobbied (unsuccessfully) for outside military inter-
vention, first to halt the genocide and then to evict the genocidaires from the
camps. Playing out alongside Rwanda was the continuing tragedy of Bosnia,
where many relief agencies became convinced that humanitarian action was
nothing more than a “fig leaf ” for anemic Western states who were unwilling to
apply the proper political and military muscle to stop the killing. Under such
circumstances, they increasingly feared that their primary contribution was to
help assist ethnic cleansing and make it easier for Western states and the UN
to avoid military action. One lesson of Bosnia and Rwanda was that there
was no substitute for military action during humanitarian emergencies, and
that humanitarian agencies could and should work with states under certain
conditions. Although aid agencies hotly debated the implications of the
militarization of relief and working alongside states, there was a general
Is multilateralism bad for humanitarianism? 151
willingness to suspend such concerns in the face of gross violations of human
rights.
In general, while both principal–agent and sociological institutionalist
approaches focus on the relationship between the environment and the organ-
ization, they highlight different mechanisms of control that have different
kinds of effects. Principal–agent analyses highlight how states politicize
humanitarianism to the extent that they establish more control mechanisms
that directly alter what organizations can do. Sociological institutionalism
recognizes this possibility but also adds how the environment might change
not only what humanitarian organizations do, but also what they are. Major
states, principal donors, and others that control resources can potentially use
this leverage to control the behavior and activities of humanitarian organiza-
tions. Yet humanitarian organizations might also act in ways that are consist-
ent with the external environment not only because of direct external pressure
but also because of changes in legitimation principles and resource depend-
ence. Not all change is externally-driven, though, for humanitarian organiza-
tions also contained cultural rules that encouraged them to expand outward
as a solution to pressing problems on the ground. There were many roads to a
politicized humanitarianism.
Kosovo
The events that led to NATO’s intervention in Kosovo can be briefly told.
Kosovo had been an autonomous province of the Yugoslavian Republic until
1990, when Yugoslav President Slobodan Milosevic formally abolished its
autonomy.27 From here on out Belgrade steadily took control of Kosovo’s
political, economic, and cultural affairs, and the Albanian population, which
formed the vast majority of Kosovo’s population, began to see their lives
diminished. In response, Ibrahim Rugova, a well-known Albanian writer,
advised passive resistance and established the Democratic League of Kosovo;
soon thereafter, in September 1991 an underground plebiscite overwhelmingly
voted for independence.
The situation in Kosovo remained fairly stable during the Yugoslavian
wars, but once they ended it deteriorated. In response to continuing repres-
sion by the Federal Republic of Yugoslavia (FRY), the Kosovo Liberation
Army (KLA), a previously unknown organization, carried out a series of
attacks in April 1996. International involvement increased beginning in late
1997 and in response to a deteriorating and violent situation. In March 1998
the UNSC adopted Resolution 1160, which called on the KLA and Belgrade
to negotiate a political settlement, imposed an arms embargo on both
parties, and warned of the “consideration of additional measures” in the
absence of progress toward a peaceful solution.28 In response to further vio-
lence, including numerous civilian deaths and the displacement of hundreds
of thousands of individuals, in April the Contact Group for the Former
Yugoslavia (minus Russia) agreed to impose new sanctions on Belgrade. In
152 Michael Barnett
June, UN Secretary-General Kofi Annan informed NATO that there might
be need for a Security Council authorization for future military action in
Kosovo. In September the Security Council adopted Resolution 1199, declar-
ing that Kosovo was a “threat to peace and security in the region.”29
Although Russia permitted this resolution, it served notice that it would
oppose any authorization of military force by the Security Council.
Because of the Russian impediment, the Western states shifted their atten-
tion to NATO. Citing “humanitarian intervention” as the legal justification
for any possible use of force, on 9 October 1998 NATO Secretary-General
Javier Solana warned of future military action if Belgrade did not comply with
international demands.30 Apparently because of this warning, on 25 October
Belgrade agreed to a ceasefire that would be monitored by NATO from the
air and by unarmed OSCE peace monitors on the ground.31 The humanitarian
and security situation improved, but only temporarily; in the absence of a
political agreement, the KLA and the Serbian authorities continued to man-
euver for war. A particularly grisly incident in January 1999, in which 45
civilians were killed by Serbian troops in the city of Racak, led NATO to
threaten air strikes. Indeed, at this point NATO became more fully committed
to coercive diplomacy to force Belgrade to accept various principles regarding
Kosovo’s future status, including the restoration of its autonomy and inter-
national protection by NATO (Simma 1999: 8). Against the backdrop of the
threat of force if there was no negotiated settlement, beginning on 6 February
1999 the combatants and outside parties held a series of talks at Rambouillet,
France. The talks collapsed on 19 March.
Following through on its threat, NATO launched air strikes on 24 March,
its first active military encounter in its 50-year history. A statement by US
President Bill Clinton captured the reasons for this unprecedented action: to
prevent a humanitarian emergency, preserve European stability, and main-
tain NATO’s credibility.32 Given the Bosnian precedent and Serbian viola-
tions of the basic human rights of Kosovar Albanians, Western officials had
good reason to fear the worst either in the immediate or the medium-term
future. As Michael Riesman observed: “The facts were alarming. As always,
information was imperfect, but enough was available to indicate that bad
things were happening, things chillingly reminiscent of some earlier as well
as, lamentably, more recent events in this century; and it was reasonable to
assume (and, to some, irresponsibly naive not to assume) that, given the
people involved, worse things were in store” (Riesman 1999: 860). And, after
having been criticized for their anemic and half-hearted response to Bosnia
and Rwanda, their shadow cast a sense of shame (Roberts 1999). Con-
sequently, NATO proclaimed Kosovo to be a “humanitarian war” that would
protect the Kosovar Albanians.33 There also were security considerations. The
Bosnian conflict always threatened to expand beyond the Yugoslavian bor-
ders, and while the violence was quarantined the political and security effects
were not. Kosovo’s implosion might invite intervention by Greece, Italy,
Turkey, and other European countries. Finally, NATO was concerned about
Is multilateralism bad for humanitarianism? 153
its own future. As NATO was debating its response to Kosovo, many were
using the occasion of NATO’s upcoming fiftieth anniversary to debate
NATO’s relevance and future. Coming on the heels of reactions to the wars
of the former Yugoslavia that had led directly to the Strategic Concept, Kosovo
potentially gave NATO an opportunity to answer its critics and demonstrate
its continued relevance.
NATO’s bombing, however, seemed to trigger the very humanitarian
emergency it was designed to prevent. Milosevic responded to NATO’s air
campaign by unleashing the dogs of ethnic cleansing, causing hundreds of
thousands of Kosovar Albanians to flee. Within two weeks, a half-million
Kosovars had crossed into Albania and gathered at the Macedonian border,
producing the largest refugee flight in Europe since World War II. This
spectacle – mass displacement caused by a humanitarian war – was quickly
becoming a major public relations disaster for an organization that had ini-
tially seen this humanitarian war as a public relations savior. Although few
charged NATO with being directly responsible for this turn of events, it was
heavily criticized for its failure to anticipate Milosevic’s move. But NATO
was not the only organization overwhelmed by the flood of refugees. So, too,
were UNHCR, the lead humanitarian agency, and most relief agencies. In
any event, it was NATO that was accused of creating the situation and it was
NATO that was expected to do something about it. Given all of this, NATO
decided that relief was too important to be left to the relief agencies (Suhrke
et al. 2000; Orbinski 1999: 2). It began holding immediate discussions with
UNHCR.
On 3 April UNHCR High Commissioner Sadako Ogata requested NATO’s
assistance. This was an unprecedented and highly controversial decision
because never before had UNHCR approached a combatant for direct assist-
ance.34 Many at UNHCR objected on the grounds that whatever temporary
benefit UNHCR might receive from NATO’s assistance would be outweighed
by the cost to its independence and ability to work in the field.35 Ogata over-
ruled these objections on the grounds that UNHCR needed NATO to help
overcome Macedonia’s unwillingness to permit entry of refugees (the gov-
ernment feared destabilizing the ethnic balance) and logistical problems in
Albania (Morris, N. 1999; Ogata 2005: 144–8). NATO stepped in and acted as
a “surge protector” (Minear et al. 2000: 76).
NATO made a critical contribution at the outset of the refugee crisis, but
then transformed what was supposed to be a temporary and supporting role
into a permanent and commandeering role throughout the war and long after
its assistance ceased to be needed.36 The agreement between NATO and
UNHCR, as one evaluator observed, was a “Trojan Horse that allowed
NATO to effectively take over the humanitarian operation from the inside”
(Porter 2000: 5).37 NATO became a “full-service” relief agency, helping to
build camps, distribute relief, ensure security, co-ordinate the actions of relief
agencies – and set the agenda (Rieff 2002: 204). Its decision to outstay its
welcome and extend its activities into unauthorized areas had relatively little
154 Michael Barnett
to do with the needs of the refugees and everything to do with NATO’s need
to maintain support for the air campaign (Porter 2000: 5). By continuing to
play a co-ordinating role, NATO was able to cast its actions as humanitarian
and thus continue to legitimate the war. For instance, the leaders of AFOR,
NATO’s Albanian force that was dedicated to relief, commanded that
“all activities undertaken by AFOR should contribute to the enhancement
of NATO’s public image and the undermining of critics of the NATO air
campaign.”38
Although most agencies resented the reduction in autonomy, the surprise
was that there was little outrage or outright rebellion. After all, the same
agencies that had strenuously guarded their humanitarian space – their
independence, impartiality, and neutrality – in places like the Congo and
Sudan were now working alongside, getting assistance, from, and being
directed by a combatant – and doing so with relative ease (Vaux 2001: 16–67;
Roggo 2000; Porter 2000; Apthorpe 2001: 25). MSF was one of the few
organizations that refused to participate on the grounds that doing so violated
basic principles of humanitarian action and placed refugees at risk (Roggo
2000). In general, while some NGOs attempted to distinguish themselves
from governments, “most were happy to go along with these arrangements”
(Porter 2000: 5).39
What explains this development? Certainly some relief workers and organ-
izations believed that they had little choice. MSF’s financial independence
might allow it to walk away, but many agencies did not believe they had the
luxury because of their dependence on Western governments for funding. To
overtly criticize NATO’s heavy-handed presence in the humanitarian oper-
ation or to refuse to work in camps run by their own governments would have
run against their short- and long-term interests (Porter 2000: 5). However, it
was not only that protest was futile or highly discouraged. Many agencies
were happy to go along because they were being rewarded handsomely by
Western states that were showering funds on the relief effort. And, Kosovo
was not some forgotten emergency in the middle of Africa; instead, it was a
heavily-covered crisis in Europe. Therefore, it provided a spotlight for many
agencies to demonstrate to the world and their donors what they could do. In
general, their material interests tilted toward compliance and away from
resistance.
Yet their willingness to ally themselves with NATO owed to more than the
correspondence between their material interests and NATO’s political inter-
ests. It also owed to their perception that they were on the same side. Human
rights organizations and relief agencies that had integrated a rights discourse
into their operations were more open to the idea of coercive humanitarian-
ism. And, like NATO, many aid agencies read Kosovo with Bosnia-colored
glasses.40 In the months leading up to the war, many agencies had continuously
reminded Western powers of what their impotence had wrought in Bosnia
and how the end game required the threat and use of military force, and then
directed the West to apply these lessons learned to Kosovo. Interaction, the
Is multilateralism bad for humanitarianism? 155
association of American NGOs, wrote to the US National Security Council
as early as June 1998 to encourage a military intervention to protect Kosovar
Albanians (Minear et al. 2000: 63). As the violence continued with no polit-
ical settlement in sight, more agencies made more urgent appeals for a more
forceful response. Accordingly, once the diplomatic talks collapsed and the
bombing began, they saw themselves as allied with NATO and part of a
humanitarian operation designed to protect civilians.41
NATO’s commandeering of the relief effort, the alliance between aid agen-
cies and NATO, and the general politicization of humanitarianism had vari-
ous consequences for the provision of relief and protection of civilians. To
begin, it contributed to a bilateralization of the relief effort. Once NATO
took charge of the relief effort, it quickly delegated different zones to differ-
ent governments and their militaries. This had several implications. Now that
NATO was a humanitarian actor, it had less need for multilateral humanitar-
ian organization such as UNHCR, even though that was still formally the
lead agency. NATO and other troop-contributing countries funded directly
their “national” camps and their national NGOs to work in their camps
(Morris, N. 1999: 19; Porter 1999: 22; Houghton and Robertson, 2001; Minear
et al. 2000: 34–45). Although NATO justified this move on the grounds that it
enhanced the efficiency of the relief effort, it also was consistent with their
desire to control the relief effort and get credit (Roggo 2000: 3; Porter 1999:
19, 21). As one aid worker reflected, “NGOs from particular countries were
often selected to work in particular camps where “their” army was in control –
not necessarily because that NGO was the most competent.” And, while
NGOs were flush with funds, UNHCR was enduring a well-publicized
shortfall (Porter 1999: 21).
More problematic, the bilateralization of relief by NATO did not necessar-
ily benefit the refugees. Notwithstanding NATO’s boast that it was more
efficient that NGOs, its lack of experience showed as it made various mis-
takes, including choosing sites that had been previously rejected by NGOs
because of their unsuitability (Porter 1999: 21). Bilateralism also led to vary-
ing standards, inequalities across camps, the failure of specific militaries to
meet the basic needs of the populations, and the attempt by beneficiaries
to play one national authority off against another in order to get the best aid
package (Ogata 2005: 149–50).42
Now that humanitarian agencies and NATO were on the same side, many
agencies felt the need to self-censor their views regarding its conduct of the
war. They had lobbied NATO to use force, if needed, and thus implicitly or
explicitly viewed the start of hostilities as an unfortunate but necessary devel-
opment. Consequently, once the war began they did not feel as if they could
protest when NATO’s wartime conduct potentially increased civilian casual-
ties or violated international humanitarian law (Wiles 2001: 12).43 NATO’s
decision to avoid ground troops and to fight the war from the air made
it easier for Milosevic to execute ethnic cleansing; that is, how NATO fought
this war in the name of protection actually led to a protection crisis.
156 Michael Barnett
Although Oxfam and other such organizations were aware that the onset of
war would hinder civilian protection, Oxfam muted its concerns in order not
to distract from the case for force. Accordingly, when the consequences
unfolded, it felt itself poorly positioned to criticize NATO for delivering
exactly what it wanted (Vaux 2001: 20, 22). Aid agencies also were remark-
ably quiet when NATO was rumored to be using cluster bombs; Human
Rights Watch was one of the few rights-based agencies to vocally object to
this purported development. Although some agencies protested NATO’s
bombing of Belgrade and targeting of non-military facilities, again, the deci-
bel level was noticeably low. Oxfam, for one, did not vocalize its concerns
because it wanted to avoid confronting Western governments at a critical
moment during the war (Vaux 2001: 23).
This politicized humanitarianism also shattered the sacrosanct principle
of impartiality (Porter 2000: 4). The readiness of aid agencies to so quickly
suspend their principles raised troubling issues regarding how primordial this
principle truly is. Indeed, it revealed the extent to which these principles
rested on a functionalist and interest-based logic. Relief agencies developed
and defended these principles because they facilitated their access to popula-
tions at risk, gave them a measure of security and operational freedom,
enhanced their legitimacy and funding, and enabled them to work virtually
anywhere in the world (Leader 2000: 2). Yet in Kosovo impartiality served
no immediate purpose because these goals were already assured. Indeed, in
Kosovo the traditional incentives for impartiality reversed course. “There
were neither security concerns nor difficulties negotiating access to the refu-
gee populations with parties to the conflict. There were no donors insisting
on strategies to minimize the incorporation of aid into the dynamics of the
conflict. On the contrary, working in the camps actually required agencies to
set aside impartiality. That they were prepared to do so with such dispatch
creates the strong suspicion that the value of humanitarian principles for
many agencies is a means more than an end” (Stockton 1998).
The willingness to forgo impartiality, however, was not without costs. From
Serbia’s perspective, NATO’s humanitarian and military activities were one
and the same (Curtis 2001: 10). Indeed, because NATO had militarized the
camps, they became a legitimate target in Serbia’s eyes. And, because relief
agencies were allied with NATO, they also could be treated as a combatant
(Krahenbuhl 2000: 4). There also was relatively little attention to the humani-
tarian situation in Serbia. Serbia had been hosting a very large refugee com-
munity, many of whom had fled the Croatian province of Krajina in the last
act of ethnic cleansing of the Bosnian war. It then experienced civilian casu-
alties as a result of the NATO bombing. In response to these perceived
humanitarian needs, in May a UN Inter-Agency Needs Assessment Mission
called for more assistance to Serbia, but none came. Although impartiality-
guided aid agencies should have shown up on both sides of the border and
attempted to treat all those in need according to the same allocation prin-
ciples, “political considerations seem to have given rise both to humanitarian
Is multilateralism bad for humanitarianism? 157
excesses on one side of the conflict, and an equally dramatic shortfall on the
other” (Porter 2000: 6).44
Parenthetically, impartiality also means that relief is given based on need
and not based on political, geographic, religious, ethnic, or other consider-
ations. Using these criteria, the response toward Kosovo was hardly impartial.
Western states and organizations demonstrated a nearly unprecedented gen-
erosity. The camps, by refugee standards, were lavish and subsequently became
part of humanitarian mythology. Hot showers, video rooms, good lighting,
state-of-the-art medical facilities. Such generosity, though, only highlighted
the West’s lack of concern for other areas in greater need. In Kosovo there
was $207 for every person in need, in Sierra Leone $16 and in Congo $8. The
European Community Humanitarian Office spent more money on Kosovo
than the rest of world combined (Wiles 2001: 13). The US Army’s expend-
itures at Camp Hope, Albania, which housed only 3,000 people for two
months, equaled the UN’s entire outlay for Angola. Although such inequities
might have been tolerated had they been applied efficiently and where neces-
sary to cover the basic needs of the refugees, there was gross duplication of
services and inefficiencies.45
Kosovo represented a stark moment when a humanized multilateralism
met a politicized humanitarianism. For a mixture of motives, NATO launched
a humanitarian war, a military intervention that was designed to protect
human rights. When that humanitarian war contributed to a humanitarian
emergency, it quickly took control of the relief effort in order to maintain
public support for the war. Most aid agencies accepted this development as
the price of doing business with an organization that was acting in a way that
was consistent with their principles and their interests. They were now firmly
committed to human rights and willing to accept that in some cases it would
be necessary to work with states. Yet the willingness to do so was not without
costs to their long-standing principles and their ability to work effectively
for populations in need. As many evaluations concluded, the problems
confronted by aid agencies in Kosovo were only partly technical. They were
profoundly political.
Conclusions
Those in the humanitarian sector continue to debate Kosovo and other
episodes in humanized multilateralism because these events force them to re-
examine what are the meanings and practices of humanitarianism. This
debate raises three issues that deserve greater attention: how the humanitar-
ian actors have been changed by the world they are attempting to change;
the need to supplement organizational theory with interpretive analysis in
order to understand the creation, fixing, and contestation of norms; and the
relationship between humanitarian and world order.
Humanitarianism has been shaped and reshaped by the world in which it is
embedded. So far, what little attention international relations scholars have
158 Michael Barnett
given to principled actors has focused on how they have changed the nature
of world politics (Risse et al. 1999; Keck and Sikkink 1998; Finnemore and
Sikkink 1998). Yet we need to reverse the causal arrow and also examine how
the world has changed these principled actors. Consider modern humanitari-
anism’s very origins. By the mid-nineteenth century changes in military tech-
nology were making war more brutal, there was no tradition of medical relief,
and the emerging profession of war reporting was transmitting gruesome
pictures and accounts of soldiers left to languish and die on the battlefield.
Publics were beginning to rebel at these sights and to express pacifist senti-
ments. In response, state and military elites coopted Henry Dunant’s plat-
form, removed its more radical proposals, accepted new rules governing how
to tend to wounded soldiers on the battlefield, and thus demonstrated to their
publics their commitment to humanize war. The International Committee of
the Red Cross developed its principles in part to differentiate it from the
world of politics and thus to help it gain access to populations in need. But,
while its principal contribution was to rescue soldiers on the battlefield, it also
helped to legitimate modern war. Although humanitarianism has continued
to develop over the decades, such developments have been profoundly influ-
enced, defined, and limited by global forces. I employed principal–agent and
sociological institutionalist analysis to better understand how these environ-
mental forces have shaped what humanitarian organizations do and what
they are. To that extent, they do provide some of the theoretical tools neces-
sary for conceptualizing why and how different elements of the international
environment contain different control mechanisms that have had different
kinds of effects on these actors.
Yet organizational and institutionalist theory devoid of interpretive analy-
sis might very well overlook exactly how and why these features of the
international environment might prove so controversial to humanitarian
organizations. These should be humanitarianism’s golden years. It has never
been better funded, better supported, or more acclaimed. Such impressions
are reinforced by international relations theory. For neo-liberal institution-
alists, humanitarianism’s causal importance is evident because states are
using humanitarian norms to guide their behavior, and are now co-ordinating
their humanitarian activities in and through an impressive number of inter-
national and regional institutions (Keohane and Martin 1995). The very
development of a humanized multilateralism might very well be cause of
celebration, not despair, for humanitarian organizations. As I have already
suggested, constructivists, for their part, are so focused on how principled
actors can change the world that they have neglected that they are not of like
mind regarding what are those principles.
Yet what the theorists label as normative convergence or consensus might
be labeled by the participants as a “crisis.” In order to understand this contest-
ation over norms, the debate over what is humanitarian and what are its
practices, requires recapturing how the participants themselves give meaning
to their actions and debate with others over what public meanings should be
Is multilateralism bad for humanitarianism? 159
ascribed to their actions and events. Kosovo proved so controversial in part
because it challenged humanitarian organizations to re-examine and re-
imagine what are their constitutive norms – that is, what is humanitarian
action. In general, as international relations scholars continue to investigate
the role of NGOs and principled actors in world politics, they need to situate
those organizations within the broader environment, consider how that
environment has shaped the very principles that define principle action, and
how such principles are not simply derivative of international forces but
rather are a result of debate and contestation among actors who are attempt-
ing to adapt their interests and principles to new circumstances.
Kosovo raised troubling concerns regarding whether these adaptations have
erased what made humanitarianism distinctive and have altered humanitari-
anism’s role in global politics. The humanization of multilateralism and the
politicization of humanitarianism destabilized the differentiation principles
that once distinguished humanitarianism from other kinds of actors. Once
upon a time these roles were clearly differentiated. Humanitarian organiza-
tions provided impartial relief to victims of conflict and military organizations
were the ones that made necessary this impartial relief. Yet humanitarian
organizations now engage in broader projects that are clearly political and
turn to military organizations to defend human rights and to help deliver
relief.46 If so, then, states and their militaries also can be humanitarian actors.
Many within the humanitarian sector categorically dismiss this possibility on
the grounds that it is absurd that states, which are political, and militaries,
which use force, could be bona fide humanitarian actors. Yet as Hugo Slim
evocatively observes, humanitarianism is not owned by humanitarian agen-
cies, a position that would be “as disastrous as making humor the sole preserve
of clowns” (Slim 2002a: 4). As humanitarian agencies watch states, militaries,
and commercial firms deliver relief, and as humanitarian agencies increasingly
concern themselves with grander political projects and their organizational
interests, there emerge more questions regarding what, if anything, makes
humanitarian organizations a distinctive social kind. Although there are good
reasons to conclude that humanitarian organizations are still distinct because
of their motives, principles, and social purpose, the very nature of this debate
only highlights how much has changed.
The willingness of humanitarian agencies to engage with politics, working
with states and for grander political projects, also suggests a change in human-
itarianism’s function in the global order. Humanitarianism is now more firmly
part of politics. Certainly it always was part of politics to the extent that its
actions had political effects and relief workers saw themselves as standing
with the weak and against the mighty. Yet humanitarian agencies once saw
themselves as standing outside politics to the extent that their ambition was
to save lives at immediate risk and to keep states at bay – for the principal
reason that it might entangle them with political agendas and thus compro-
mise their goal of relief. No longer satisfied with saving individuals today
so they can be at risk again tomorrow, humanitarianism now aspires to
160 Michael Barnett
transform the structural conditions that make vulnerable populations.
Toward that end, aid agencies desire to spread development, democracy, and
human rights, and to join up with a peacebuilding agenda that aspires to
create stable, effective, and legitimate states. Humanitarianism is increasingly
an ism that has ambitions to transform the world. In this way, aid agencies
are carriers of liberal values as they help spin into existence a global liberal
order.47 Humanitarian organizations may or may not be part of a neo-liberal
agenda, and they may or may not resemble the missionaries of the nineteenth
century, but by their own admission they are now part of a global order that
they once used to resist.
Notes
1 C. Powell, “Remarks to the National Foreign Policy Conference for Leaders of
Nongovernmental Organizations”, Washington, DC, 26 October 2001.
2 In this way, humanitarianism has a logocentric quality, which Jacques Derrida
observes is in play whenever “one privileged term (logos) provides the orientation
for interpreting the meaning of the subordinate term.” For discussion of this
discursive and binary relationship, see Nyers (1999: 21); Cutts (1998: 3); Minear
(2002: 76).
3 This definition draws from Stockton (2004: 15).
4 The ICRC’s principles are largely the “industry standard,” though there are debates
about the prioritization of these principles, their operational meaning, and even
their relevance. For discussions, see Forsythe (2005); Terry (2002); Weiss (1999);
M. Duffield (2001); Minear (2002).
5 For various statements, see Rieff (2002); Minear (2002); Donini (2004); M. Duffield
(2001); Slim (2004a).
6 A fairly exhaustive list of these evaluations can be found at Humanitarian Policy
Network, “Evaluative studies of the international response to the Kosovo crisis”,
online at http://www.odihpn.org/report.asp?ID=1040.
7 For this claim, see Slim (2004). This is related to UN Secretary-General Kofi
Annan’s (2000) call for a “people-centered” approach to security.
8 For an interesting discussion concerning the epistemology of “humanitarian
crisis,” see Stockton (2004).
9 See UN General Assembly Resolution 1991.
10 For the debate on humanitarian intervention, see Cassese (1999); Lang (2003);
International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty (2001); Holzgrefe
and Keohane (2004); Wheeler (2000); Slim (2002c).
11 See Franck (1999: 858) for a brief comment to this effect.
12 For the Strategic Concept, see http://www.nato.int/docu/pr/1999/p99–065e.htm
online.
13 For this claim, see Slim (2004).
14 Also see Weiss (1999: 20).
15 Also see Linklater (1998: ch. 2).
16 For a succinct statement regarding the competing logics of relief and rights, see
Bouchet-Saulnier (2000). Also see Macrae and Leader (2000); Chandler (2002);
Minear (2002: ch. 3).
17 For discussions of differing attitudes toward military intervention, see Minear
(2002: 101–4, 115).
18 For various statements, see McCubbins and Sullivan (1987) and Bendor, Glazer,
and Hammond (2001). For applications to international relations, see Thatcher
Is multilateralism bad for humanitarianism? 161
and Stone Sweet (2002); Abbott and Snidal (1998: 3–32); Nielson and Tierney
(2003); Hawkins et al. (2005).
19 Also see Macrae et al. (2002).
20 Also see Scott (1987); Scott (1995); Scott and Meyer (1993); DiMaggio and Powell
(1991).
21 On organizational legitimacy, see Suchman (1995); also see Dobbin (1994: 126);
Scott (1987); Meyer and Rowan (1977).
22 The heart of the resource dependence approach is that “organizations survive to
the extent that they are effective. Their effectiveness derives from the management
of demands, particularly demands of interest groups upon which the organiza-
tions depend for resources and support. . . . There are a variety of ways of man-
aging demands, including the obvious one of giving in to them” (Pfeffer and
Salancik 2003: 2).
23 See Barnett (2005) for a discussion of variation in response among humanitarian
organizations.
24 For discussions of organizational and bureaucratic culture, see J. Martin (1992)
and Alvesson (1993).
25 On the scramble, see Cooley and Ron (2002).
26 Another factor potentially influencing this expansion is psychological, deriving
from the personal strain of relief work. Relief workers migrate from one night-
mare to another, comforted only by the fact that, at best, they provide temporary
relief. This sort of existence takes a very high emotional toll. Relief workers live in
a twilight of hopelessness, believing that their just acts cannot begin to change the
circumstances that give cause for their services. Wanting to believe that they are
helping to build a better world, they begin to treat human rights, conflict reso-
lution, and nation-building as extensions of humanitarianism (Rieff 2002).
27 The background is informed by Clark (2002); Daalder and O’Hanlan (2001);
Malcom (1999); Mertus (1999); and Judah (2002).
28 UNSC Resolution 1160, 31 March 1998.
29 UNSC Resolution 1199, 23 September 1998.
30 Annan apparently approved of this tactic. See Letter from Secretary-General
Solana to permanent representatives of North Atlantic Council, 9 October 1998.
Cited from Simma (1999: 7).
31 The UNSC essentially backed these agreements with its Resolution 1203 of
24 October 1998.
32 Statement by President Bill Clinton Confirming NATO Air Strikes on Serb Mili-
tary Targets, Federal News Service, 24 March 1999. See also Press Statement of
Javier Solana, Secretary-General of NATO, NATO Press release 040, 24 March
1999.
33 Many NATO members cited the humanitarian circumstances for providing legal
and moral justification for military action absent a UN Security Council author-
ization. See Simma (1999: 11–13) for some of these statements. In addition to
Prime Minister Tony Blair’s (1999) proclaimed “Doctrine of the International
Community”, Czech President Vaclav Havel (1999: 4, 6), also offered a defense of
NATO’s action in the name of humanitarian intervention: “It is fighting out of
concern for the fate of others. It is fighting because no decent person can stand by
and watch the systematic, state-directed murder of other people. It cannot tolerate
such a thing. It cannot fail to provide assistance if it is within its power to do so.”
34 UNHCR was unable to register refugees, the first step toward protecting their
rights, or to play the proper role of determining the priorities surrounding assist-
ance and protection.
35 The general observation is that the military can play three distinct roles in relief
operations: providing security so that relief workers can operate; providing logis-
tical capacity in order to move workers and supplies; and direct delivery of relief.
162 Michael Barnett
In Kosovo, NATO performed all three roles. Subsequent analyses focus on
whether there is a “division of labor” and who might best play what role at which
stage. See Minear (2002: ch. 6) for a general discussion and Minear et al. (2000) for
the case of Kosovo.
36 On NATO’s initial contribution, see Krahenbuhl (2000: 4); P. Morris (1999: 19).
37 Ogata (2005: 149) negatively reflects on the experience as she writes: “NATO had
decided to engage in humanitarian assistance even before the NATO-UNHCR
agreement of April 3 and had gone beyond the defined areas of cooperation”.
38 Quoted from Minear et al. (2000: 64). They also note that NATO’s working defin-
ition of CIMIC [civilian military co-ordination] as it applies to Kosovo and else-
where, is “A military operation, the primary intention and effect of which is to
support a civilian authority, population, international or non-governmental
organization, the effect of which to assist in the pursuit of a military objective.”
39 Also see Vaux (2001: 27–8).
40 The claim that agencies somehow lost their impartiality in this instance overlooks
the simple fact that it has always been difficult for aid agencies and staff “to
maintain a neutral and impartial stance in conflicts in which one party may have
strong claims (including legal ones) to international sympathy and support”
(Roberts 1999: 37). Any compassion NGOs felt for Kosovar Albanians invariably
led to anger at those responsible.
41 While international lawyers and commentators focused on whether the NATO
action was legal because it did not receive Security Council approval, aid agencies
exhibited little concern with such legal niceties, preferring to judge the legitimacy
of the action not on whether it followed the proper legal procedures but whether
its ends were consistent with human rights goals. For the debate among inter-
national legal scholars, see the forum in the American Society of International Law
(1999).
42 Also see Scott-Flynn (1999: x); N. Morris (1999: 17); Minear et al. (2000: 25).
43 One independent evaluation of twelve British aid agencies observed that “given
the scale and profile of the Kosovo crisis, those DEC agencies with an advocacy
remit appeared to carry out only limited public advocacy during the Kosovo
crisis.”
44 Also see MacFarlane (2000: 19); Overseas Development Institute (2000: 78); and
Vaux (2001).
45 For discussions, see Vaux (2001: 30–1).
46 As Peter Fuchs of the ICRC observed: “The respective roles of politicians, gen-
erals, and humanitarian actors are not clear anymore.” Quoted from Chandler
(2002: 48).
47 For a general argument regarding how NGOs are constituted by a global rational-
ization processes, and are carriers of rational-legal values, see Boli and Thomas
(1999).
7 Horizontal and vertical
multilateralism and the
liberal peace
Oliver Richmond
Introduction
This chapter takes as its starting point the debate about the qualities and
dynamics of the liberal peace in the context of multilateral relations between
IOs, states, NGOs and other non-state actors. The “problem of peace” in most
regions of the world has been dealt with by strategies of both elite-level
multilateralism and the promotion of vibrant civil societies, in the context
of democratization, human rights, the rule of law, and development. These
dimensions of the contemporary project to construct the liberal peace encom-
pass the activities of a broad range of state, official, agency, IO, regional
organizations (RO), and NGO actors, which take as their starting point
an assumed conceptualization of the “liberal peace”, present in most
academic and policy documentation.
Multilateralism has traditionally been viewed as a way through which
realist and liberal/idealist interpretations of the propensity of international
relations (IR) towards anarchy can be brought under control. Traditional
notions of multilateralism, prevalent in realist and liberal thinking depict an
international system in which states are persuaded to adhere to a liberal form
of peace by a set of international guardians. These take the shape of institu-
tions, ROs and IOs, organized to defend and enforce a set of liberal norms in
IR. These frameworks inform, guide and monitor state behavior. The focus is
inevitably on state behavior, and so such thinking favors the state, official-
dom, and the elites associated with the control of power and resources, those
who make social, economic, developmental, legal, and political policy, and
those who decide policy norms in these areas. This essentially encapsulates
the multilateralism inherent in state–donor liberal peacebuilding today, and
especially in the state reconstruction and transitional administrations in many
conflict zones around the world at present.
It has also been increasingly recognized since about the late 1980s that non-
state actors play a vital role in such activities, and this has raised the question
of state–non-state actor co-ordination in terms of donor activities and project
management, and more generally in terms of the complexity of the liberal
peace project. State networks and officialdom no longer have absolute control
164 Oliver Richmond
over resources, whether for peace or violence. The state’s Weberian control of
violence or of peace has been moderated by a “global civil society”, “human
security” discourse, the requirement for post-conflict justice in some form,
and the need for the marginalized populations of many conflict zones to be
heard in any peace process. The new multilateralism reflects these new linkages
between states, IOs, IFIs, ROs, agencies, and NGOs, as well as the require-
ment to build capacity in civil societies emerging from conflict. This reflects
an “orthodox” version of the liberal peace, and is an important development.
However, the inherent bias of multilateralism towards state-centricity means
that even an orthodox form of the liberal peace masks what is a “virtual
peace” in many conflict zones.
“Old”, elite, and formal forms of multilateralism – in the context of inter-
national and regional organization, and governance – may increasingly be
eclipsed by the multilateral activities of non-state actors, which have also
emerged as a qualifying factor of the dominance of states, IOs, and their
“rational-legal” authority (Barnett and Finnemore 1999: 699). Multilateral
actors, as Barnett and Finnemore have shown, do indeed have their own
agency and pathologies despite them being creatures controlled by powerful
states, but so too do many other non-state actors involved in peacebuilding
(Barnett and Finnemore 1999: 705). Thus differing levels of horizontal and
vertical multilateralism, formal and informal, are key to understanding the
efficacy and sustainability of the liberal peace model, and to its construction
in post-conflict zones around the world. “Winning the peace” cannot occur
without sophisticated forms of multilateralism (Ruggie 1992: 587) effectively
directed and supported by “willful communities” (Ruggie 1994: 565). How-
ever, it is important to develop our understanding of multilateralism as more
than merely a formal and horizontal architecture of IR (Caporaso 1992:
601), but also representative of a vertical architecture, which implicitly means
that the constructivist, critical theory, and postmodernist agendas of justice,
identity, inter-subjectivity, hegemony, universalism and cosmopolitanism pro-
vide points of departure for understanding the liberal peace, its construction,
and its sustainability. Horizontal forms of multilateralism are defined here as
relationships between official actors, states, and diplomats, and relationships
between a broad range of unofficial and private actors. The “new”, vertical
multilateralism is defined by any relationship between an official and private/
unofficial actor. Vertical multilateralism allows a replication of the norms
that arise in the context of horizontal multilateralism within conflict societies,
but in tandem with at least some level of local debate and custodianship of
peacebuilding.
While the liberal peace is assumed to be unproblematic in its internal struc-
ture, and in its acceptance in post-conflict zones, its methodological applica-
tion may be far from smooth (Paris 2004: 18–20). Indeed its main components
– democratization, the rule of law, human rights, free and globalized markets,
and neo-liberal development – are increasingly being critiqued from several
different perspectives. These critiques have focused upon the incompatibility
Horizontal and vertical multilateralism 165
of certain stages of democratization and economic reform, the ownership of
development projects and thick and thin versions of the neo-liberal agenda,
the possible incompatibility of post-conflict justice with the stabilization of
society, the problem of crime and corruption in economic and political reform,
and the establishment of the rule of law. These terrains are relatively well
explored (Snyder 2000: 43; Annan 2002: 136; Chopra and Hohe 2004: 292;
Rieff 2002: 10; Paris 2002: 638). In this context it is crucial to understand
the way in which multilateralism affects and even facilitates the multiple
interventions designed to construct the liberal peace as a self-sustaining end to
war and conflict. These approaches have led to a “peacebuilding consensus”
(Richmond 2004b: 85)1 that reaches far beyond simply reconstructing the
shell of the state, though with limited success. This consensus of course
implies an inherent multilateralism, driven by a willful community’s (the
so-called international community) view of peace and what must be done to
make it sustainable.
Consequently, this chapter argues that new and often informal forms
of multilateralism have had an important impact on liberal peacebuilding.
Horizontal and vertical forms of multilateralism are vital if the peacebuilding
process is to receive wide support, for the transmittal of norms of governance,
and to have a plausible chance of leading to a sustainable peace. Whether or
not these new forms operate an as extension of the old multilateralism, or
are representative of a radical departure from it, remains to be seen, but it
is now mainly through vertical multilateralism that norm transmittal and
diffusion now occurs within conflict zones – even if this does mean the export
and import of dominant norms and pathologies associated with liberal state
donors, the UN, EU, OSCE, World Bank, IMF, and other international
organizations and agencies (Barnett and Finnemore 1999: 705). In what fol-
lows, this chapter examines the components of the liberal peace and related
levels of multilateralism, and also what vertical forms of multilateralism offer
in the quest to bequeath a sustainable peace to post-conflict polities by the
liberal peacebuilding community.
Figure 7.2 illustrates that unilateral forms of intervention that do not have
broad consent amongst internationals are unlikely to lead to sustainable out-
comes. In the cases of Iraq and Afghanistan, a sustainable and orthodox
version of the liberal peace looks very unlikely in the short to medium term.
But, in other cases where there has been broad consent for the use of force,
Horizontal and vertical multilateralism 177
such as in Sierra Leone, Bosnia and Kosovo, and East Timor, it seems that
there has been movement along this typology to a more sustainable peace.
However, even in Iraq and Afghanistan, there is now a sizeable peace con-
stituency that seems intent on making sure that the liberal peace and its
components survive. What this indicates is that what is key to the sustain-
ability of the liberal peace is ideally multilateral international involvement
that rapidly develops a vertical component, and a broad local constituency
that also accepts this project. Without this in place, any progression would be
unlikely or, at best, tortuous (as in Somalia).
Another aspect of this liberal peace model throws some doubt on even this
minimalist prognosis. In Cambodia, depicted above as being at an orthodox
stage of the liberal peace after 13 years of international peacebuilding involve-
ment, progress has been excruciatingly slow in building a self-sustainable
situation. It not just that unilateralism results in slow progress as the cases of
Afghanistan and Iraq suggested, or some progress as the additional cases of
the Balkans and Sierra Leone suggest, but that all of these attempts to build
the liberal peace result in excruciatingly slow progress. The evidence suggests
that the situation improves when more actors are involved and more con-
sent is available – though co-ordination, conditionality, dependency, and the
acquisition of the necessary resources then become problems – but also that
unilateralism does not necessarily mean that progress cannot be made. What
Figures 7.1 and 7.2 show most importantly, however, is that all unilateral
interventions, if they are aimed at building the liberal peace, eventually become
multilateral. This is because the liberal peace is such a complex project that
one actor simply cannot succeed alone.
178 Oliver Richmond
Conclusion
Multilateralism remains crucial to a sustainable peace. Where an intervention
has not been multilateral, there is great pressure to overcome international
political opposition in order to make the peacebuilding process and the con-
struction of the liberal peace multilateral as it is implicitly recognized that a
multilateral peace process has more chance of creating a sustainable peace.
Furthermore, a vertical and informal form of multilateralism both provides
enhanced capacity for a sustainable liberal peace, and also advocates such
a peace. Entry into a conflict zone is often predicated on a conservative
version of the liberal peace, which is unilateral, with the aspiration of moving
towards the orthodox position, which is inherently multilateral. A significant
number of examples can be provided for this movement, as Figure 7.2 illus-
trates, but a significant number also remain mired within the conservative
gradation of the liberal peace. No cases can be located within the emancipa-
tory gradation, and indeed, the lack of social justice, and socio-economic
well-being and development seems to have marred all international involve-
ments in the post-Cold War era (Paris 2004; Bellamy and Williams 2004;
Chandler 2002; Chopra and Hohe, 2004; Cousens and Kumar 2001; Caplan
2002). Clearly, the above diagrams illustrate the tendency for internationals to
enter a conflict environment somewhere within the conservative gradation,
and then aspire (both the internationals and local recipients included) to move
along the axis to the orthodox peace, which is perceived both to be sustainable
and to allow the internationals to withdraw.
This requires the development of both horizontal and vertical multilateral-
ism, a combination of which has the effect of guiding recipients’ governance
frameworks while not denying their sovereignty as more traditional forms of
multilateralism might. “Willful” actors are required to drive this, including
state and non-state actors, if it is to maintain high levels of legitimacy, par-
ticularly with recipient actors. However, experience seems to show that where
force is used in a hyper-conservative initial approach, moving along the axis
towards the orthodox category tends not to occur quickly. The best illustra-
tions of this appear to be Bosnia and Kosovo, where the political entity (state
or not) is weak, and may even be socially and economically unsustainable
despite the length of time the internationals have been involved. Where entry
is based upon a peace agreement with broad consensus, it often occurs within
the conservative gradation but moves rapidly towards the orthodox, as many
of the cases in Figure 7.2 indicate. In other words, multilateralism at both
international and domestic levels offers a greater chance of a sustainable peace.
One of the eternal truths of IR is that for any agreement to be made and then
to be implemented, it must be done multilaterally, with both horizontal multi-
lateralism – including that between officials (between state-level actors and
international institutions) and non-officials (between private actors, both
civilian and militarized) – and a vertical multilateralism between officials,
private actors, states and institutions, whether NGO, militarized, or both
Horizontal and vertical multilateralism 179
formal and informal. This is the clearest lesson of the last two decades of
attempts to build liberal states and the liberal peace.
Notes
I take responsibility for all errors in this essay as is the custom. Thanks go to Roland
Bleiker, Costas Constantinou, Jason Franks, A.J.R. Groom, Ian Hall, Vivienne Jabri,
Anthony Lang, Farid Mirabagheri, Nick Rengger, Chandra Sriram, R.J.B. Walker,
Alison Watson, and Peter Wallensteen. I would like to thank the many people, local
and international, private or official, from East Timor and the DRC to the Balkans,
who were willing to talk to me during the course of my fieldwork on which this article
is based. I am also grateful to the Leverhulme Trust, the Carnegie Trust, and the
Russell Trust for providing funding for various parts of the fieldwork.
1 This phrase indicates a weak consensus between the UN, major states and donors,
agencies, and NGOs, that a liberal peace should incorporate a democratic market,
democracy, the rule of law, and development, and that all international interven-
tion, both humanitarian or security-orientated should be contingent upon this.
This consensus masks a deeper dissensus in terms of the application of resources,
the use of force to establish the basis for such a reform, and the efficacy of different
actors involved in the many roles this requires.
2 See for example Penn (1693/1993: 5–22).
3 For exceptions see Chopra and Hohe (2004); Paris (2004); Lund (2003).
4 See “Speech of the Special Representative of the Secretary-General for Afghani-
stan,” Opening of 55th Annual DPI/NGO conference, Rebuilding Societies Emer-
ging from Conflict: A Shared Responsibility, New York, 9 September 2002.
5 See for example the UN Tribal Liasons Office.
6 See UNSC Resolutions 1401 of 28 March 2002 and 1272 of 25 October 1999.
7 UNSC Resolution 1272 of 25 October 1999.
8 Personal interview with S. Frietas, Program Manager, Democracy and Governance
Program, USAID, 11 November 2004.
9 Personal interview with O. Ofstad, Head of Delegation, International Federation
of Red Cross and Red Crescent Societies, Dili, 11 November 2004.
10 See Goldstone (2004: 87).
11 In meetings with senior World Bank Staff in Dili, they were at pains to point out
their concern about local ownership, and about not offending local politicians and
the government, however. Personal interviews, 9 November 2004, Dili.
12 President Xanana Gusmao, “Peacekeeping and Peacebuilding in Timor Leste”,
Seminar of the role of the UN in Timor Leste, Dili, 26 November, 2004.
13 Here Mitrany reflects upon the working peace system without defining what it was
to achieve in terms of peace. However, it is clear that he has a somewhat broader
notion of the concept than was generally accepted in the policy world at the time.
Part II
Assessing multilateral
security institutions
8 Transatlantic relations,
multilateralism and the
transformation of NATO
Frank Schimmelfennig
Introduction
When the Soviet Union and the Warsaw Pact collapsed at the beginning of
the 1990s, NATO lost its most important raison d’être: to counter the com-
munist military threat to, and deter a possible attack on, western Europe.
This landmark change forced the Western alliance to redefine its relationship
to the former enemy, to reappraise its security environment, and to review
its organizational set-up, its force structure, and its security strategies and
policies.
The transformation of NATO has had two main dimensions. In its external
relations, NATO introduced partnership organizations for co-operation with
central and eastern European countries (CEECs) and opened the door for
new members from this region. In January 1994, NATO agreed on the Part-
nership for Peace (PfP) program, which deepened security co-operation and
consultation between NATO and the CEECs. In 1997, NATO invited the first
CEECs (the Czech Republic, Hungary, and Poland) to join the alliance and,
in 1999, established the Membership Action Plan (MAP) for the remaining
CEECs interested in becoming full members. Seven of them joined NATO in
March 2004. In lockstep with the enlargement decisions, NATO upgraded its
institutionalized relationship with Russia and Ukraine in 1997 (NATO-Russia
Founding Act; Charter on a Distinctive Partnership between Ukraine and
NATO) and 2002 (NATO-Russia Council, NATO-Ukraine Action Plan).
Internally, NATO responded to the disappearance of the common Soviet
threat and the rise of new, more diverse and unpredictable risks and chal-
lenges to the security of its members by developing more flexible and diversi-
fied structures. At its 1994 Brussels summit, NATO endorsed the Combined
Joint Task Force (CJTF) Concept calling for “easily deployable, multi-
national, multiservice military formations tailored to specific kinds of military
tasks.”1 In 1996, NATO agreed to build a European Security and Defense
Identity (ESDI) within NATO, which would permit and support autono-
mous military operations led by the EU. At the Washington summit of 1999,
NATO launched the Defense Capabilities Initiative to equip its forces for new
tasks of crisis management and intervention. The Prague summit in October
184 Frank Schimmelfennig
2002 gave new impetus to the transformation of NATO. In June 2003, NATO
defense ministers agreed on a new and streamlined command structure
with a single command (Allied Command Operations) with operational
responsibility and another command (Allied Command Transformation)
responsible for overseeing the transformation of NATO forces and capabil-
ities. In October 2003, NATO inaugurated a highly flexible, globally deploy-
able and interoperable NATO Response Force based on a pool of troops and
military equipment.
Finally, and paradoxically at first sight, it was only after the end of the Soviet
threat, for which it was established, that NATO became involved in actual
warfare, invoked the mutual assistance and consultation articles of the North
Atlantic Treaty (NAT) and sent member state troops outside the North
Atlantic region – each for the first time in its history. In 1995 and 1999 NATO
used its airpower to intervene in Bosnia-Herzegovina and Kosovo and put an
end to ethnic violence in these parts of former Yugoslavia. On 12 September
2001, the North Atlantic Council (NAC) agreed to regard the terrorist
attacks on New York and Washington as an attack on all alliance members
according to Article 5 NAT, and in October 2003 NATO assumed the
command and co-ordination of the International Stabilization and Assist-
ance Force (ISAF) in Afghanistan. At the same time, however, NATO mem-
ber states were deeply split over the war on, and occupation of, Iraq in 2003
and any NATO involvement in it. The strongest opponents of the Iraq war
(Belgium, France, and Germany) for some time failed to agree to NATO
preparations to protect their ally Turkey against a possible Iraqi counterattack
and have rejected any substantial NATO role in Iraq to this day.
It is the aim of this chapter to review the transformation of NATO in the
perspective of multilateralism with regard to both institutional structure and
actual co-operation. Has NATO become more or less multilateralist in form
and practice in the course of its transformation? And how do we explain
institutional change and behavioral variation? Following John Gerard Rug-
gie, multilateralism is defined as a generic institutional form that “coordinates
relations among three or more states on the basis of generalized principles of
conduct: that is, principles which specify appropriate conduct for a class of
actions, without regard to the particularistic interests of the parties or the
strategic exigencies that may exist in any specific occurrence.” These “general-
ized organizing principles logically entail an indivisibility among the mem-
bers of a collectivity with respect to the range of behavior in question” and
generate “expectations of ‘diffuse reciprocity’ ” (Ruggie 1993b: 11).
In the first part of this chapter, I describe and explain the flexibilization
of NATO, the main feature of its external and internal post-Cold War insti-
tutional transformation. In the second part, I assess the multilateral quality
of NATO post-Cold War co-operation. Above all, I seek to account for the
variations in member state co-operation on the core policies and decisions of
the past decade: enlargement and the decisions to intervene in Yugoslavia and
the Middle East.
Transatlantic relations and NATO 185
The main argument of the chapter draws on different theoretical appro-
aches. First, I argue that the institutional transformation of NATO has made
NATO less multilateralist and this is best explained in functional terms by the
nature of the core co-operation problem that the old NATO and the new
NATO address. The old NATO faced a common and certain threat and the
enforcement problem of extended deterrence: to “keep the Americans in” and
to prevent the allies from free-riding under the US nuclear umbrella. The
functional response to this situation was a restriction of membership and
flexibility.
In contrast, post-Cold War NATO has not been confronted with common
or clearly identifiable threats. Within NATO, the core co-operation problem
was potential deadlock caused by consensual decision-making under the
condition of heterogeneous strategic views, threat perceptions, and security
interests. A functional response to this problem was institutional flexibility.
With regard to the former Warsaw Pact countries, the main problem was
uncertainty resulting from a lack of information on security problems and
preferences in this region and a lack of trust. Under these conditions, high
flexibility made sense in order to gain knowledge and create trust.
The more flexible and less multilateralist structure of the new NATO does
not lead per se to a less multilateralist behavior of its members. Rather,
behavior varies with the kind of security threats or challenges at issue. Multi-
lateral co-operation has been strongest when core values and norms of the
liberal transatlantic community were at stake – either as a result of their
massive violation (as in the “ethnic cleansing” in the Balkans) or their strong
reaffirmation (as in the candidates for NATO membership). It was weakest
in the Iraq case, which was neither located in the core community region nor
related initially to the protection of liberal community values. In between are
the Afghanistan and Darfur cases. In the absence of a direct common threat,
it is their common values that still promote multilateral co-operation between
NATO members.
Conclusion
In the post-Cold War era, NATO has become more flexible. This change in
institutional design can be explained plausibly as a functional response to the
disappearance of the common and certain Soviet threat and its replacement
with a diversity of less common and clear security issues and with uncertainty
about the new security environment in the East. At the same time, however,
Transatlantic relations and NATO 201
the more flexible institutional design of post-Cold War NATO, which allows
for varying degrees and constellations of co-operation among NATO mem-
bers, is indeterminate with regard to actual international co-operation. It
does not tell us why and how member state policies sometimes converge
toward multilateral co-operation and sometimes do not. I have argued in this
chapter that, in the absence of a common and clearly identifiable threat to
their security, the member states of NATO are mainly held together – and
bound to act together – by their common liberal democratic identity and the
shared liberal values and norms of the transatlantic community of all mem-
ber states. Whenever this identity was at stake, member states eventually felt
compelled to co-operate, even in the absence of a threat to their own security.
Notes
I thank participants in the Delphi workshop for useful comments on the first draft of
this chapter.
What we are talking about here are values and standards, values and stand-
ards which underpin the European Union, and which Bosnia and Herzegovina
must honour if it wishes to move forward in its relations with the EU.
(Ashdown: 2004b)
Introduction
The extent to which international institutions bring about change in the
domestic systems of states has long been a matter of inquiry. The academic
literature has burgeoned since the end of the Cold War to match and even
overtake the examples of multilateral involvement and intervention. It has
ranged from the general to the particular, with the role of the EU a frequent
focus of study (see for example the issue of International Organization, Fall
2005). Yet while there is widespread agreement that institutions such as the
EU can and do play a role, the weight and importance to be attached to them
varies. On the one hand, much, inevitably, depends on the international con-
text itself as well as the nature of the international institution. On the other
hand, central, too, are the circumstances of the target state – whether it is
failing, frail, rogue-ish, or post-conflict – and the obduracy or responsiveness
of its authorities, the strength and capacities of its domestic institutions, its
economy, its geo-strategic position and its conceptions of itself. Moreover,
the debate has taken place at a variety of different levels, pitching, for
example, positivists against constructivists. Whereas the former might focus
on the strategic assessment of costs and benefits and whether incentives out-
weigh the costs of standing out or defecting, the latter have explored less
tangible issues such as identities, norms and cultural practices. There have
also been further divisions between enforcement theorists and management
theorists, the former focusing more on coercive strategies undertaken by the
international institution, the latter on social learning and capacity building
(Tallberg 2002). For their part, Finnemore and Sikkink (1998) have pointed
to the diverse roles of norm entrepreneurs in bringing about change – not
least in holding actors responsible for their violations.
Persuasion and norm promotion in the Balkans 203
This chapter, taking its lead from the quotation from Paddy Ashdown
above, focuses more on norms and on the ability of international institutions
to bring about changes in the values and standards of the political actors in
Bosnia and Herzegovina (BiH).1 This is because the preoccupations in the
Office of the High Representative (OHR) and generally in the EU–BiH rela-
tionship so intimately concern normative structures relating to the rule of
law, democracy, human rights and fundamental freedoms. They touch so
closely on issues of identity that they both construct and circumscribe the
behavior of the various parties and groups in BiH. They also, as Wiener and
others have argued, relate closely with the institutional context since strate-
gies and the policies they give rise to are inevitably constructed within such
frameworks (Wiener 2004).
In the case of BiH, the institutional framework is particularly complicated
because it involves both the basic constitutional structure as well as the inter-
related legal and economic elements laid out in Dayton in 1995, together with
an overarching framing of the issues through the prospect of EU member-
ship, institutionalized since November 2005 in the negotiations of the Stabil-
ization and Association Agreement (SAA) but in prospect since 1999. To
reach the goal of EU accession, BiH is being called on to go through a double
transition: firstly, to overcome the legacy of Tito, that is, the legacy of a
socialist self-management economy and a single party political system; and,
secondly, to vanquish the horrors of war that have dispersed populations
through ethnic cleansing and massive population upheaval, deepened the
already formalized corruption that existed at all levels of society, and left
political power in the hands of nationalist parties seemingly determined to
continue the war by political means. This, especially in the case of those in the
Republika Srpska (RS), has led to a fierce insistence on maintaining the
constitutional position laid down in the Dayton Agreement of 1995. Even if
the transition from Titoism to economic liberalism can be comparable, war
and its consequences put BiH in a very different position in their develop-
ment from the countries of central and eastern Europe (CEECs), different as
they were from each other (see, for example, Pridham et al. 1997; Henderson
1999; Zielonka and Pravda 2001; Vachudova 2003). The CEECs have not
only avoided the experience of war and ethnic cleansing, but they have not
had a military presence – whether in the form of the Peace Implementation
Force (IFOR), the Stabilization Force (SFOR), both led by NATO, or finally
EUFOR, led by the EU – to ensure the implementation and continuation
of the peace, or a representative of the international community with such
powers as those of the Office of High Representative.
Nonetheless, despite these vital differences, the EU’s enlargement to take in
the CEECs has been of critical relevance to BiH and the western Balkans for
two reasons. Firstly, the success in bringing the CEECs into the EU on the
basis of the so-called “Copenhagen criteria” of 19932 inspired member states,
as Noutcheva put it, “to replicate the model in a region that has been a
security concern for the EU for over a decade. The recipe worked once, it was
204 Geoffrey Edwards and Mladen Tošić
believed it would work a second time” (Noutcheva 2004: 1). This was despite
the fact that in the CEECs, as Batt has noted, “the phases of stabilization,
transition and integration indeed overlapped, they did basically follow one
another. In the western Balkans, EU integration is a condition of stabiliza-
tion, rather than the other way round” (Batt 2004: 19). Insofar as it suggests
that all the elements need to be pursued simultaneously, it inevitably creates
confusion between Dayton-derived and integration-inspired reform which
has been difficult to accept. Secondly, the EU’s role has to be put in the whole
context of the Union’s past relations with the Balkans. The failure of the EU
to prevent or to resolve the conflict in the former Yugoslavia, especially in
BiH and later in Kosovo, has meant that the EU has now every incentive to
prove itself to be a credible foreign policy actor, able to play an active and
constructive role in establishing and maintaining peace and stability in
Europe – to the extent of using all available foreign and external policy
instruments, with membership as the ultimate prospect.
The Copenhagen criteria call not only for the adoption of democratic
norms and a liberal economy but also for the administrative capacity actually
to implement the acquis communautaire. The criteria may have gradually
gained substance with the enlargement to the CEECs but they leave, nonethe-
less, a great deal open for interpretation by the European Commission and
the member states at a point when there have been expressions of “enlarge-
ment fatigue” if not skepticism about further enlargement as an intermediate
necessity. Moreover, the extent to which governments, parties and people in
BiH are already clear as to what such a remote goal might mean also remains
an open question. Nonetheless, while raising questions of consistency and
co-ordination, among others, the “return to Europe” and future membership
have been policy goals pursued with determination and ingenuity by both the
OHR and the EU, especially in the shape of the European Commission. They
have therefore constituted powerful norm entrepreneurs even if not quite in
the same way as the non-governmental issue, policy or advocacy networks
suggested by, say, Keck and Sikkink (1998). They have, nonetheless, been a
vital factor in seeking to mobilize change both through their own actions and
by attempting to co-ordinate those of others.
This chapter unfolds in three sections, beginning with an examination of
the role of international institutions as norm entrepreneurs and their ability
to persuade domestic actors. The second section assesses the contextual
framework in which these find themselves in BiH, while the third focuses on
the role of the two most prominent international institutions active in BiH,
the OHR and the EU, and the impact of the prospect of EU membership.
The conclusion points to the dilemma facing international institutions seek-
ing to bring about changes in the values and standards of political actors
derived from the experience in BiH.
Persuasion and norm promotion in the Balkans 205
Entrepreneurs and powers of persuasion
Different paradigms inevitably evoke different approaches to their role. The
key issues here are the processes by which the institutions have brought about
the transformation that has so far occurred, the “transformative dynamics”
as Checkel has termed them (2005). Much of the literature, whether positivist
or constructivist, has focused on conditionality – constructivists thereby earn-
ing the criticism of Payne for using such material incentives and levers (Payne
2001: 41). But for conditionality to work effectively, the overall objectives and
goals have to be clear and acceptable to those targeted and the incentives have
to be regarded as credible and valuable, in both the longer and shorter term,
not just at governmental level but also more widely among the people. In
addition, they have to be seen as being consistently applied both over time
within the targeted state and when compared to others. As Schimmelfennig
put it, “if international organizations were perceived to subordinate con-
ditionality to other political, strategic or economic considerations, the target
state might either hope to receive the benefits without fulfilling the conditions
or conclude that it will not receive the rewards in any case” (Schimmelfennig
2005: 5). In the BiH case – as in other instances – not only have there been
questions raised about the consistency of EU policies, but there have been
doubts as to the credibility of eventual membership and whether all member
states are actually committed to western Balkan accession, which inevitably
have had an impact on the situation in BiH.
In such conditions of uncertainty, persuasion through the provision or
denial of rewards becomes a particularly sensitive issue. Much depends on
considerations such as “the depth of cooperation,” when the key condition
is that the “shadow of the future is long enough that states have to care
sufficiently about future payoffs” (Fearon 1998: 270). Or, from a less game-
theoretic perspective, the question of the “goodness of fit” has relevance
whereby “the lower the compatibility between European and domestic pro-
cesses, policies, and institutions, the higher the adaptational pressure” (Börzel
and Risse 2000: 5, emphasis in original). When domestic and European
“norms, rules, and the collective understandings attached to them are largely
compatible,” the pressures are less and compliance and implementation less
contested. Both approaches assume states are not ultimately opposed to
change. In the BiH case, however, some elements have most certainly been
against basic change and participate in the process only with the greatest
reluctance and in the absence of alternatives. Others have been against par-
ticular policies and norms of behavior.
There has thus been a cycle from which it has proved extremely difficult to
break: the greater the pressures for change, the more reluctance has been
displayed in embracing it; that has then engendered the greater need for
enforcement mechanisms, which in turn has often inhibited policy compli-
ance and acceptance of the desired norms. In the absence of agreement on
reforms, the HR has had recourse to more coercive measures. The failure to
206 Geoffrey Edwards and Mladen Tošić
comply actively with the International Criminal Tribunal for the former
Yugoslavia at the Hague (ICTY), for example, as well as continued resistance
to policing and defense reforms which had led NATO to reject BiH’s applica-
tion for a Partnership for Peace agreement (PfP), caused the HR to dismiss
some 60 party officials and police from their offices in June 2004, including
the President of the Serb Democrat Party (SDS) and the Chairman of the RS
National Assembly.3 Nationalist parties resistant to change and hostile to
incursions into areas of control have, therefore, been able to exploit such
actions with their electorates to reinforce opposition to further change.
Such a spiral of coercive activity, of intervention and sanction in BiH, has
been largely tied up in the role of the High Representative and his office
(OHR) – with which the EU in its various guises are linked if separate. But
implementing Dayton which reflected above all a “logic of consequentialism,”
while promoting European norms that are a part of “logics of appropriate-
ness” (March and Olsen 2004) in the face of continued resistance, there has
been inevitable tension. It has meant behavior by the HR that has often been
“explicitly inappropriate” (Finnemore and Sikkink 1998: 897). That raises
not only questions about norms and practices but also the likely effectiveness
of persuading or inducing local actors to accept different, democratic, lib-
eral norms when the entrepreneurs may have international support but their
actions allow for little sense of any local accountability.
What therefore remain important, even for constructivists, are the incentives
and a rational assessment of future benefits set against sanctions through
imposed conditionality (see, for example, Schimmelfennig and Seidelmeier
2004: 664). The problem for the HR and the EU has been the creation of
incentive structures that would encourage such socialization. On the one
hand, as Caplan has argued, while outside experts can “encourage ‘owner-
ship’ of ‘best policies’ through persuasion”, the degree of ownership likely to
be achieved will be “much greater if those who must carry out the policies are
actively involved in the process of shaping and adapting, if not reinventing
these policies in the country itself” (Caplan 2005: 472). It is when, how-
ever, local actors reject ownership, and measures have been imposed, that a
“dependency syndrome” builds up. As one former HR put it, “every piece of
legislation that I impose with my authority as the High Representative, gives
politicians in BiH a perfect excuse not to do their job properly” (Petritsch
1999). It may mean that, if the measures are then implemented (which does not
necessarily follow), local actors are perforce acting in ways that raise ques-
tions about the level or genuineness of any socialization that the institutions
might have been hoping for.
The alternative – and key to the EU’s approach – has been the emphasis on
rewards (especially long-term rewards) if criteria are met. It may be that, as
Joseph Stiglitz has declared, “good policies cannot be bought” (quoted in
Checkel 2000: 3), but such conditionality remains the favored policy of most
international institutions, including the EU. Since all Bosnian actors have
signed up to the idea of eventual EU membership, at least in principle, and
Persuasion and norm promotion in the Balkans 207
despite the confusion of Dayton and EU criteria, it is not surprising that
there has been frustration on the institutions’ part when the Bosnians do
not accept EU-generated rules and processes and seem almost to prefer the
tougher tactics of persuasion used by the HR.
The confusion of EU and HR criteria raises the possibility that it is less the
deliberate refusal of actors to comply than their inability to do so. Tallberg in
his 2002 article looks back to theorists such as Oran Young (1992) or Chayes
and Chayes (1993) who saw a general propensity to comply (whether through
considerations of efficiency, interests or norms) countered or undermined by
factors such as the ambiguity of the rules, their lack of transparency which
made them difficult to monitor, and the limited capacity to implement them.
These, Young described as factors endogenous to the institutional arrange-
ments themselves (as opposed, that is, to exogenous or contextual factors)
(Young 1992: 176). In such circumstances, coercive action might be mis-
guided since the emphasis might be better placed on management-orientated
measures such as economic and administrative aid and training, with, for
Young, considerable importance attached to the institutional design and the
arrangements laid out. In the BiH case, it may not only be the political and
economic consequences of war that have inhibited political and administrative
capacity, but also popular opposition to change.
A rather different dimension to institutional design and capacity building
to consider, emphasized by constructivists, is the importance of social learn-
ing in bringing about compliance. Social learning, whether by persuasion,
argumentation, monitoring and ultimately exposing those who resist the pro-
cess, emphasizes both the rules by which bargaining should take place and the
alternative outcomes possible, including their costs and consequences. It pre-
supposes a degree of acceptance of the parameters of the possible outcomes.
But while socialization and even a growing element of Europeanization may
be brought about by continuous interaction of the parties involved, it does
not necessarily imply more than a strategic calculation of advantage and
benefits. The ideas and norms being circulated may resonate with the target
audience, but not always in the sense of them becoming more than a part
of the political intercourse. That may give them a credibility and an ele-
ment of legitimacy; it may not guarantee any permanent switch of logic or
internalization.
The problem in such approaches is, of course, when non-compliance is
actually the preference – even if that may be complicated by a lack of cap-
acity. It is here that Tallberg sees the need for both enforcement and manage-
ment measures to build capacity, to monitor compliance in order to enhance
transparency and expose violations, and to ensure that the legal system can
deal with the violators. Transparency also at least invites accountability to a
wider audience, both domestic as well as international. At the intra-state
level, it allows the various actors to see whether practice and implementation
match agreement; at the international level it also encourages greater co-
ordination of effort (Tallberg 2002: 612–13). In the tangled web of the BiH,
208 Geoffrey Edwards and Mladen Tošić
however, issues of ownership of the reform process are entwined with com-
peting legal systems and principles. Issues of accountability have, too, become
blurred given the number of international institutions (the OHR, the EU, the
Council of Europe and the OSCE) that are responsible for, or involved in, not
just reconstruction but state and democracy building.
Contextual framework
The intimate and complex inter-relationship between the conditions laid
down for EU membership and the Dayton Agreement have been of funda-
mental importance in the BiH’s history since the late 1990s. Dayton, after all,
set out the constitutional structure for BiH. Opinion as to the compatibility
of that structure with continued stability as well as possible membership of
the EU has been divided. Cox, for example, has pointed out that there has
been “the tendency of peace negotiations to produce highly decentralized
constitutional structures, which provide a poor foundation for a state” (Cox
2001: 6). On the other hand, Bose in 2005 argued that “the notion that a
(con)federal, consociational structure of government is an inherent obstacle
to Bosnia’s journey to Europe . . . is sadly misguided” (Bose 2005: 329). The
problem was well expressed by the former President of the RS and of BiH’s
tripartite presidency, Mirko Šarović, who declared in 2003:
Let’s not play games with each other. We had a war here. We wanted to
secede and join with Serbia, while people in the Federation wanted an
independent Bosnia. We got peace in Dayton that we all accepted. Now,
we are not going to give up any bit of our sovereignty that we got at
Dayton.
(International Crisis Group 2003: 21)
And yet, while not seeking to revise Dayton as such, both the HR and the
EU have sought to change key powers or competences in the interests of an
effective and efficient BiH.
Uncertainty and confusion as to how far such reforms might go in under-
mining key constitutional and institutional norms and the role of the entities
has been at the heart of the opposition. Ahmet Hadžipašić, the Federation
Prime Minister, remarked on the inevitability of further centralization of BiH
governance, because
when you make new police regions, you will have to make the same
regions for the judiciary. So, once you have made this rationalization in
the area of finance, security, and the judiciary, then what is left for us as
the entities? We can clean parks and that’s about it.4
For its part, the RS position was summed up by Mladen Ivanić when he
commented that there needed to be a dual-track process, one that kept a
Persuasion and norm promotion in the Balkans 209
decentralised structure “since this is the reflection of reality in BiH.” But he
recognised, too that “the institutions of BiH must have the authority to fulfil
European conditions.” The question for him, therefore, was “not a choice
between the state or the entities, but to have the state and the entities . . . A
balance can be found, such as it exists in every federal state.”5
It not simply a question of constitutional structures, therefore, but also
a matter of the practices to which they give rise and which embed them
further. Nearly four years of war had concentrated wealth and power struc-
tures within the military and political elites in each of the ethnic groupings
with the result that there were strong vested interests that were opposed to a
strong functioning state, whether decentralized or not. Democratic control
and economic liberalization have simply not been in the interests of many
of the hard-line nationalist parties and/or those determined to perpetuate
a vicious cycle of corruption. Pugh, for example, while seeking to explain
how the criminal and shadow economy flourished in Milošević’s Yugoslavia
and its successor states saw it as a way of enabling people to cope – which
was not to excuse “the ruthless, predatory and socially destabilizing role of
mafia-networks, or the political grip of rent-seeking, patron-client ties, or
nepotism among newly enriched war elites.” But, he went on, “such networks
and elites retain their power partly because of the services they perform for
their followers and dependants” (Pugh 2004: 54).
Control of socially-owned assets provided revenues for nationalist parties
and those dependent on them. But the situation was made worse by the,
certainly unintended, consequences of the privatization policies urged on BiH
by the international community, which reinforced the position of the former
war elites, and allowed them to extend their networks beyond their political
protectors to those responsible for tackling crime. As Hadžipašić expressed it:
The people who led the war had status that they wanted to transfer into
capital. In order to hold onto this capital they then had to hold onto
political power after the war and so we still have local sheriffs who are
dominant in politics. Transition is the perfect opportunity for all this.
In any system it would be a difficult task. But, during transition it is
possible to make and break laws. According to these people the process
of transition needs to be as long as possible.6
a clear lesson from the Balkan dramas is that when the EU, the United
States and NATO are united and work together, we can achieve great
results . . . The opposite, as the war itself illustrated all too clearly, is also
true. Linked to this point that we Europeans have to be willing and able
to act ourselves to tackle security situations where we feel more strongly
or differently than the United States does.
(Solana 2005)
The problem was how to extricate himself and his office from the ensuing
dilemma when “ownership” of the political process of “normalization” and
“Europeanization” had clearly not passed to the BiH, whose elites remained
largely obdurate in the face of the OHR’s activities. That opposition and
obduracy, whether determined by vested interests or because political leaders
preferred not to compromise their position with their electorates, meant that
ideas of partnership for further development within a European framework
were continuously being found wanting.
Yet it has been a key assumption of the international institutions that the
prospect of EU membership could be the critical driver for reform in BiH and
elsewhere in the Balkans. What Paddy Ashdown declared he was pursuing as
HR was not “an exit strategy, but rather an entry strategy for BiH into broader
European structures, with EU membership as the ultimate goal” (Ashdown
2003). Ashdown’s own appointment as the EU’s Special Representative was
an indication of the EU’s commitment. It was of particular importance given
the problems of moving from the emphasis on reconstruction in BiH to state-
building and in the aftermath of Kosovo, that the rationalization of EU
214 Geoffrey Edwards and Mladen Tošić
policy towards the Balkans included the offer of EU membership
once, that is, the Copenhagen criteria had been met (Glenny 2001). The
“repackaging” of the various Balkan initiatives into the Stabilization
and Association Process was the result. Meeting the conditions laid down
by the EU has been seen as critical with all the implications of continuous
monitoring to ensure compliance. What the EU sought to avoid, however,
was the dilemma created by the OHR and his Bonn powers; if BiH was
to show itself capable of undertaking all that European membership
entailed, it had to show both capacity and the ability to adapt to European
norms.
The offer of prospective membership went along with another indication
of the EU’s commitment, the move to replace the NATO-led SFOR with an
EU-led force. This finally took place in 2004. EUFOR’s mission, however,
remains very largely that of SFOR yet within different parameters: it is to
“provide deterrence and continued compliance” with Dayton, “to achieve
core tasks in the OHR’s Mission Implementation Plan and the Stabilisation
and Association Process” (emphasis added), as well as provide support to
ICTY and the security environment in BiH in which the police could act
against the organized criminal network.8 Despite therefore the efforts on the
part of the Commission’s delegation to be seen as separate from the OHR,
there remains an inherent inseparability. In that sense, the EU has faced an
uphill struggle in terms of its capacity to persuade and to bring about any
great rapidity in the process of socialization.
One of the ways is to vote against their return to power. Frankly . . . this
is not very likely to happen . . . There is a different way too. The HDZ in
Zagreb is an example of that. This is not the same HDZ as it was under
Tudjman. By forcing the nationalist parties to implement reform you get
factions within the party. That is the case of Raguz vs. Covic, and you
can find the very same elements in other political parties.
(Ashdown 2004a)
But the process has been a slow one. In terms of the formulation of policies
consistent with the process of transition towards potential EU membership,
for example, Bosnian attitudes remain ambivalent and/or suspicious. Legisla-
tion consistent with the acquis has invariably been drawn up by lawyers from
the EU and the member states. However, rather than representing the future,
the legislation is regarded in the BiH as “sometimes not compatible with our
general legal framework or legal culture,”18 or alien and not easily under-
stood or accepted.19 Implementing such legislation then becomes politically
sensitive and enforcing it sometimes impossible.20 Such reluctance to imple-
ment legislation emphasizes the importance as well as the difficulty of
continuous monitoring. It, and the presumption of the political impact of
Persuasion and norm promotion in the Balkans 219
“shaming” non-implementers and violators, are critical elements both in terms
of conditionality and social learning. But if the process of non-compliance
simply results in action by the OHR in order to keep processes going, then the
normative significance of the reforms begins to lose its impact and adaptation
becomes regarded with little more than indifference, at best.
Conclusions
Very clearly, the international community – in the form of the OHR and the
EU – has brought about changes in the values and standards that prevail in
BiH. Both have sought to ensure peace and stability, which has meant tack-
ling the extreme nationalist parties and the corrupt networks that did well out
of the war, and bringing BiH into line with the conditions demanded by the
EU of those who seek membership. But they have been changes that have
frequently been brought about by imposition on the part of the OHR. Critics
have therefore argued that, while many of the statebuilding measures are
necessary for effective, open and democratic governance in contemporary
Europe, their imposition, in the face of opposition from elected leaders,
undermines those same values. At a minimum, such an argument would claim,
there are limits to the extent that “inappropriate” measures can be taken in the
interests of bringing about a logic of appropriateness. On the other hand, the
role and powers of the HR have, indeed, created a dilemma. It is, after all,
improbable that, in the absence of the Bonn powers, those who have been
manipulating the political, economic and judicial systems through corrupt
networks would have quietly given up that control in the interests of adapting
to the Copenhagen criteria and some future membership of the EU.
But the roles of the HR and the EU raise important questions about
compliance with the demands of the international community and the nature
of rewards and sanctions. However much the image has been created that
“nobody does anything until the IC makes them,”21 there is a commitment on
the part of BiH leaders to European integration. What then becomes confus-
ing is the fact that the HR is also the EU’s Special Representative and the EU
qua Commission has been attempting to separate out the areas covered by the
SAP/integration process from that of stabilization, reconstruction and state-
building, which remain the responsibility of the OHR with its Bonn powers.
The primary instrument of both is, of course, persuasion, but for the EU it
has become a matter very largely of the use of conditionality to ensure con-
tinuous progress towards the possibility of future EU membership. The
rewards of compliance are continued movement in opening up the SAP pro-
cess and continued assistance; sanctions in essence add up to non-movement,
but not the withdrawal of aid. For the OHR, there has been the opportunity
and frequent recourse to the Bonn powers and the imposition of measures,
the removal of officials, party leaders, and so on. For so long as the inter-
national community sees the need for reform in the interests of state viability
as well as adhesion to the norms of open democracy, sound administration
220 Geoffrey Edwards and Mladen Tošić
and economic liberalization in opposition to vested political and economic
interests, there is likely to be continued need for those powers and the OHR.
The inevitable overlap between the norms and standards both the EU and
OHR (and OSCE, IMF etc.) wish to see adopted in BiH equally inevitably
gives rise to confusion of roles. This, in turn, has provided opportunities for
those opposed or reluctant to engage in the transfer to exploit. The clarity
and credibility of the message as well as, therefore, the co-ordination of the
messengers are vital factors in any successful norm promotion.
Conditionality and monitoring continue to be regarded by the EU as criti-
cal in ensuring compliance. It had, after all, worked in the case of the coun-
tries of central and eastern Europe who had sought EU membership. The
continuous need for the intervention of the OHR indicated that circum-
stances in BiH were somewhat different and that, despite the rhetoric and
lack of alternatives, not all BiH parties were wholly enthusiastic about the
changes EU membership seemed to presage. The rush towards privatization
and the use of “one size fits all model of economic transformation” (Donais
2002: 14) paid too little attention to the specifics of the BiH case and ignored
the possible consequences. In political terms, the legacy of the past – of Tito
as well as Milošević and of the war – cast a significantly longer shadow than
that of any future within the EU, and skepticism whether the EU actually
wanted BiH then made the shadow even darker.
Schimmelfennig and others have been particularly insistent that for con-
ditionality to be effective in bringing about compliance, there needs to be
clarity, credibility and consistency. In BiH’s case, in the efforts of the HR and
the EU, at least as represented by, for example, Ashdown’s Mission Statement
of 2002 or the European Commission’s Feasibility Report of 2003, there
were clear principles enunciated. The latter’s 16 points, while seemingly
numerous, were nonetheless sometimes couched in fairly general terms. The
problem has thus been in the application of the policy prescriptions that
underlay them, the degree to which they were known and understood among
both elites and the wider BiH public, and were acceptable to them. Added to
that have been the problems of co-ordination among EU actors, between the
institutions responsible for foreign and external policy matters, or the fight
against international crime or in establishing the acquis. Given the range of
policy commitments and the complexity of the situation, such problems of
consistency are probably unavoidable. But they have not always helped in
winning over a skeptical public or an entrenched politico-economic elite –
particularly when access to the media has often been constrained.
Against this, however, to the extent that the process is to be monitored and
judged by the EU, issues of “ownership” that have continuously plagued the
Bosnian–OHR relationship do not arise in the same way. This is not a peace
agreement imposed on warring factions. It is a process leading towards a
goal on which all, ostensibly at least, are agreed. However, as we have seen,
that commitment is often only partial or faint-hearted. The degree to which
European norms and values have become more than superficially accepted is
Persuasion and norm promotion in the Balkans 221
debatable. As the BiH Foreign Minister Ivanić has suggested, any promotion
of European values has nearly always had to be balanced by the concern of
alienating political support; European values might be entering into Bosnian
patterns of thought, but operationalizing them remains unattractive, at least
in the short term.22 So far, it would seem, there is rather more a strategic
deployment of acceptable arguments than any internalisation of norms.
However, even here it may be a case for looking to the notion put forward
by Elster of “the civilising force of hypocrisy” (Elster 1998: 109–12, quoted by
Checkel 2001a) where, however manipulative the motive, the publicity may
have a “civilizing” effect and ultimately change preferences. Schimmelfennig,
too, has written of rhetorical entrapment in relation to the EU’s eastward
enlargement (Schimmelfennig 2001) which may work in both the case of BiH
elites and the EU, even if that rhetoric may not yet extend to Turkey or even
to all Balkan countries. The uncertainties on both sides cannot but perpetu-
ate problems in any BiH socialization process. It is clear that, even if in only
quantitative terms, the rate of exposure of BiH elites to European standards
and practices has intensified and that has brought a growing familiarity with
them. That, combined with what might still only be public lip-service to
European norms, creates a momentum or dynamism that establishes its own
benchmark against which to hold leaders to account and may yet drive BiH
towards a less uncertain future. The problem, however, lies in the extent to
which the public knows, accepts and identifies with those norms and the
norm entrepreneurs. On that score, there remains rather less optimism that
the international institutions have been able to persuade.
Notes
The authors are grateful to those who consented to be interviewed: Renzo Daviddi,
Deputy Head of Delegation, European Commission Delegation, BiH, Ahmet Hadži-
pašić, Prime Minister of the Federation of Bosnia-Herzegovina, Mladen Ivanić,
Foreign Minister of Bosnia-Herzegovina, Osman Topčagić, Director of the Director-
ate for European Integration, BiH, OSCE Staff Member, OSCE Mission to Bosnia-
Herzegovina and OHR Staff Members, OHR Sarajevo; and to Tarak Barkawi of
the Centre of International Studies, University of Cambridge, for reading an earlier
version of this chapter.
Introduction
The disagreement of the 1980s and 1990s about whether institutions matter
or not has given over to a disagreement – or to much less agreement – over the
last decade about exactly how institutions affect states’ behavior (Martin and
Simmons 2001: 43). Thus, the preoccupation of scholars to respond mostly
to the realist premise that institutions are epiphenomenal and they can only
serve as useful leverages in the hands of the most powerful states to promote
their preconceived national interests1 has been replaced by rational (mainly
neo-liberal institutionalist) and social constructivist accounts about how
institutions have affected states’ behavior.
However, although rational and constructivist efforts have so far generated
some promising propositions to better specify the mechanisms of institutional
effects and the conditions under which international institutions are expected
to lead to the internalization of new roles or interests from their member
states,2 much less has been done on the role institutions play as facilitators
of co-operation and conflict management and/or transformation.3 Bridging
“rational-institutionalist” and “constructivist” accounts, this chapter aims at
exploring the impact of two of the most successful and prominent inter-
national institutions, namely NATO4 and the European Union, have had on
the management and/or transformation of the long-standing Greek–Turkish
territorial dispute.
Interestingly, the phenomenon of the Greek–Turkish conflict – which so far
has been heavily biased by policy-oriented perspectives – has long consti-
tuted an anomaly in the security community of Europe.5 Especially with
regard to NATO, the Greek–Turkish conflict is a case that goes against the
conventional wisdom of alliance co-operation, and it is thus dismissed as an
exception to the positive identification achieved among the Alliance’s other
members (Law and McFarlane 1996: 39). The loosening of the structural
constraints of the Cold War, the reconstruction of the Alliance’s identity,
especially after NATO’s eastern expansion and the strengthening of the insti-
tution’s status as “a collective security system” (Wendt 1994: 386; Wendt
1996: 53; Risse-Kappen 1996: 357–99) and a community of “like minded
224 Panayotis Tsakonas
democracies” (Hampton 1998–9: 235), and the strategic upgrading of the
eastern Mediterranean region as the new central front of the Alliance seemed
to constitute the very factors why the new NATO would be more likely to
adopt a bolder approach toward the settlement of the Greek–Turkish dispute.
Interestingly though, the Greek–Turkish conflict was exacerbated after the
end of the Cold War.
A strong optimism that Greece and Turkey would seek ways of resolving
their long-standing territorial dispute also emerged after 1999 due to Turkey’s
candidacy and potential accession into the EU. It seems, however, that the
EU is itself a contentious issue between Greece and Turkey. This is due to the
fact that Greece has been a member of the EU since 1981, whereas Turkey,
although recognised as a membership candidate at the Helsinki European
Council in 1999 and in spite of accession negotiations which began in October
2005, is still generally seen as being a long way from full membership.6 Inter-
estingly then, the Greek–Turkish dispute may prove to be a “hard case”
regarding the impact of the EU on conflict transformation; indeed it may be
possible that the EU, due to its particular involvement in this conflict, may
have had a detrimental rather than a positive effect.
Overall, it is indeed puzzling how the feelings of mistrust and threat per-
ception between the two states have persisted in institutional contexts that
should have led to the emergence of shared norms, understandings and a
sense of collective identity, paving the way for the peaceful resolution of their
disputes. Although one may argue that these institutional contexts have
restrained the two states from full-scale war, they have not succeeded in
generating the sense of collectively being part of a security community given
that both states have continued to consider military means a rational and
justifiable way to relate to each other.
Hence, the examination of the impact NATO and EU have on the man-
agement and/or transformation of the Greek–Turkish conflict has both the-
oretical value and policy relevance. Indeed, the examination of the effects of
particular international institutions on the conflict between two states may
provide insights into an especially valuable arena, international security,
where theorists of all stripes have expected international institutions to be
least consequential (Lipson 1984: 1–23; Keohane 1984: 6–7; Grieco 1988: 504;
Grieco 1990: 11–14; Mearsheimer 1994–5: 5–49). Moreover, the theoretical
inquiry that research should increasingly turn to the question of how institu-
tions matter and emphasize theoretically-informed analysis based on observ-
able implications of alternative theories of institutions (Martin and Simmons
2001: 437) may also be served. An academic inquiry of that kind allows also
for a departure from the currently dominant single-issue, single-organization
and single-country format to comparative research across time, across states
and across international institutions (Simmons and Martin 2002: 205), while
the effects of “international socialization” – a process introduced and fol-
lowed by both NATO and the EU – are to be analyzed in a theory-informed
and comparative way (Schimmelfennig 2002: 22; Wichmann 2004: 129).
NATO, EU and the Greek–Turkish conflict 225
Last, but not least, the policy relevance of a study examining NATO’s and
the EU’s impact on the Greek–Turkish conflict is directly related to the Greek
and Turkish policy makers’ ability to better define their countries’ future
expectations from those two institutions. By analogy, it may also provide
NATO and the EU with insights into the limits and/or the unintended effects
of their actions, and thus contribute to their ability to refine the strategies they
follow in ways that would lead to the positive transformation of the disputants’
conflict.
The chapter is divided into three parts. In the first part a review of the
relevant literature regarding the role of international institutions in interstate
conflict is presented; particular reference is made to research efforts under-
taken so far in investigating whether and how NATO and the EU matter in
managing and/or transforming the Greek–Turkish conflict. Secondly, two
core arguments, which seem to account most for the positive and/or negative
impact of EU and NATO on the Greek–Turkish conflict, are presented. A
point of methodological nature is also made; it refers to the need to assess
NATO and EU institutional effects on the Greek–Turkish dispute by adopt-
ing a multi-stage process: one that links an institution’s characteristics with
certain institutional effects and socialization outcomes. Thirdly, relevant
empirical evidence is used to test the chapter’s central arguments and to
explain why NATO’s role is doomed to remain poor and parochial in the
years to come, while that of the EU can change the interests and/or the
identity scripts of the conflict parties.
Literature review
Depth of internalization
As suggested by the relevant literature, the mechanisms that institutions use
to exert their norms are not competing or mutually exclusive and can be
differentiated according to the logic of action they follow. Thus, the mechan-
isms following the “logic of appropriateness” (when actors do what is deemed
appropriate) can be either “cognitive” [they teach domestic actors what is
deemed appropriate in a given situation] or “normative” [they seek to con-
vince states of their norms]. On the other hand, the mechanisms following the
“logic of consequentiality” (based on a cost–benefit analysis, actors choose
the action that maximizes their individual utility) may either be “rhetorical”
[institutions use social-psychological rewards for compliance and punishment
for non-compliance] or “bargaining” [institutions use material threats and
promises either directly to coerce a state to follow its norms or indirectly to
alter the domestic balance of power in favor of actors that support its norms]
(Schimmelfennig 2002: 12–13; Checkel 1999). Needless to say those insti-
tutional mechanisms are to be directed towards the conflict parties’ elites and/
or societies.
Through the aforementioned mechanisms and following particular sociali-
zation policies, institutions exert their norms and, most importantly, impact
the domestic landscape of the states to be socialized. A useful categorization
of the “domestic impact” distinguishes between normative effects and the
depth of internalization (Schimmelfennig 2002: 9–10). The former refers to
the kind of institutional impact and includes the “formal conception of
norms” (mainly seen in the transfer of institutional norms to domestic laws
or in the creation of formal institutions that enforce the institutional norm),
“the behavioral conception of norms” (measured by the extent the behavior
of the states under socialization is consistent with the behavior set by the
institutional norm) and the “communicative conception of norms” (related
to the ways the communication or discourse among the domestic actors is
being affected). The depth of internalization or the “norm salience” (Cortell
and Davis 2000: 70–1) refers to the extent the international norm has been
transposed into a state’s domestic political institutions and culture. By impli-
cation one may refer to degrees or levels of internalization and/or salience
(high/intermediate/low internalization or high/moderate/low degree of sali-
ence). Needless to say, different kinds of normative effects (formal, behavioral,
240 Panayotis Tsakonas
communicative) may also be detected at different levels of internalization or
norm salience.
Obviously, it is a rather difficult enterprise to measure the depth of
internalization or salience of the institutional norms, rules and conditions.
In assessing NATO and EU normative effects and internalization on the
Greek–Turkish conflict, empirical evidence is used for the exploration of only
measurable effects of NATO and the EU on the conflict, such as changes in
the disputants’ (especially in Turkey’s) institutions and policies, due to inter-
nalization of institutional norms (Cortell and Davis 2000: 70). Needless to
say, it is a rather difficult enterprise for changes in the domestic political
discourse to be objectively assessed, although they seem to be the most impor-
tant ones. However, an effort will be made to assess changes in the disputants’
behaviors and strategies towards co-operation and resolution of their conflict
as “deeper” changes in the disputants’ interests and identities.
As has already been noted, throughout the Cold War and the post-Cold
War era the norms exerted by the Atlantic Alliance with regard to the conflict
between two of its allies were weak and regulative, focusing on securing
operational stability in the Alliance’s southern flank. What is of particular
importance, however, is that the particular norms exerted by NATO were
directed – and are still being directed – only towards the disputants’ elites.
Indeed, NATO’s regulative norms, basically limited to regulating behavior in
individual issue areas between the disputants’ governments, such as norms of
military co-ordination and standardization, have been transmitted through
cognitive and normative mechanisms to the Greek and Turkish elites only.
NATO inability to ameliorate the Greek–Turkish security dilemma and pro-
vide a sense of collective identity between Greece and Turkey is attributed
mainly to the domestic discourse in Greece and Turkey about its role. Specif-
ically, both Greece and Turkey viewed NATO as a strategic instrument to serve
their preconceived national interests, rather than as an institutional platform
to realize their collective security interests.30
It was characteristic in Greek security thinking during the Cold War that
NATO was valued more as constraining Turkey than for contributing to col-
lective security against the Warsaw Pact. Indeed, Greek military expenditures
have always been more influenced by Turkish military spending than by com-
mon alliance defense policy vis-à-vis a common external threat (MacKenzie
1983: 117). The Turkish invasion of Cyprus – an island considered by Greece
as an integral part of “Hellenism” as well as of its borders – in July 1974,
brought about a major change in Greek strategic thinking. For the majority
of the Greek public as well as Greek security analysts and policy makers the
fact that “a NATO member, using NATO weapons, had taken 35,000 troops
out of the NATO structure in order to occupy another democratic European
country” (Moustakis and Sheehan 2000: 96) was ample proof of NATO’s
inability to play the role of guarantor of Greek–Turkish borders in Cyprus.
By implication, Greece in the mid-1970s found that it had neither insti-
tutional nor military safeguards against potential Turkish aggression. Thus,
NATO, EU and the Greek–Turkish conflict 241
for the majority of the Greek public, NATO was seen to fail since Cyprus and
the Aegean disputes were regarded as the results of Turkish expansionism
that the West refused to curb (Borowiec 1983: 29–81; Alford 1984: 13).
Greece’s withdrawal from NATO in the wake of the Turkish invasion of
Cyprus in 1974 was a decision taken by the Greek premier Karamanlis for the
appeasement of an infuriated public, which blamed the Alliance for “doing
nothing” to deter Turkish revisionist policies against Greece and Cyprus.
It is worth noting that a certain amount of anti-Americanism, and by
implication of anti-NATOism, seems to be an endemic characteristic of the
Greek political and social discourse, reflected in the reaction of the Greek
public to the Yugoslav wars, the NATO bombing in Kosovo, the terrorist
attacks in New York and on the Pentagon, and more recently during the US
invasion of Iraq. This anti-US and anti-NATO stance seems to be something
that goes much further than the traditional anti-Americanism of the Left and
completely transcends Greece’s political spectrum (Michas 2002).
By exerting regulative and short-term norms to Greece’s elite and by main-
taining an attitude of detached concern, a hands-off policy and impartiality to
the conflict, NATO has reinforced these anti-NATO and anti-US feelings and
attitudes. Neither has it managed to change the Greek elite’s long-standing
assumption that the United States and NATO should be more actively
engaged in its defense and thus be turned into “security-providing” hege-
mons.31 Hence, the participation of Greece in NATO was seen by the Greek
elite to be useful as a deterrent factor, a factor of limitation, or one of allied
mediation, in an eventual Greek–Turkish confrontation (this was precisely the
reason for Greece’s reintegration into the Alliance in 1980) but in no case did
it take the form of mediation for the resolution of Greek–Turkish differences.
Being a military alliance, NATO regulative rules and norms have been
addressed – almost by default – to the military part of the Turkish elite, which
has a constitutionally preponderant status and role in Turkish politics. Inter-
estingly enough, the fact that the socialization of the Turkish elite into the
Western mentality during the Cold War occurred mainly in the military
delayed, if not prevented, the process of democratization in Turkey (Vamvakas
2001). Indeed, almost convinced that the generals would keep Turkey within
the orbit of NATO, while managing more successfully the internal instability,
the United States – the Alliance’s dominant power – co-operated actively
during the Cold War with particular Turkish military regimes and signed
several defense and economic agreements (Oguzlu 2004: 462).
In the post-Cold War era and following an exclusive “socialization from
the outside” strategy of community building, NATO exerted particular con-
stitutive norms by making clear references to democratic principles as well
as to civil dominance over the military. Although the transmission of such
norms has been relatively successful in east and central European states –
where the prospects of membership induced states to undertake democratic
and economic reforms – it played relatively little role in promoting democracy
in Turkey.
242 Panayotis Tsakonas
Interestingly, for the Turkish elite the internalization of NATO’s post-Cold
War identity, which resembled more a pan-European security organization
rather than a collective defense alliance, appeared as a way to register its
Western, and most importantly, its European identity. As a result Turkey
took part in many NATO-led peacekeeping and peacemaking operations in
and around Europe and became an ardent participant in NATO’s Partner-
ship for Peace. However, this process resulted only in the increase of Turkey’s
bargaining power and significance in the eyes of the US, rather than in the
confirmation of Turkey’s European identity (Oguzlu 2004: 468–72). Hence,
apart from not internalizing the normative ideational elements of the Western
international community, neither did the Turkish elite manage to use NATO
as the institutional platform upon which to prove its “Europeanness.”
Things have seemed to evolve much more positively with regard to the
results produced by the exertion by the EU of strong norms, rules and condi-
tions to the disputants’ elites and society. The good news about the potential
impact of the EU on the transformation and resolution of the Greek–Turkish
conflict is that the EU’s strong norms and positive conditions exerted since
the 1999 EU summit in Helsinki have started producing some promising
results with regard to changes of the disputants’ strategies and interests
towards co-operation and positive identification. The bad news is that this
process seems to have been seriously damaged by the “watering down” of the
norms, rules and conditions related to the resolution of the Greek–Turkish
conflict decided at the 2004 EU summit in Brussels.
As has been illustrated above, the EU impact on the transformation and
resolution of the Greek–Turkish conflict remained parochial until the late
1990s. At the 1999 Helsinki summit the EU put into motion a mix of cogni-
tive, normative, rhetorical, and most importantly, bargaining mechanisms32
for internalizing a set of strong norms and rules in the disputants’ domestic
agenda (Tallberg 2002: 609–43). Thus, apart from agreeing on making the
resolution of the conflict a community principle and providing the Turkish
elite with the strong carrot of candidacy along with a positive conditionality,
the EU also actively promoted Turkey’s democratization by asking it to pro-
ceed with a “small revolution” internally in order for the European acquis to
be internalized.
The new EU policy of “conditional rewards” was received positively by the
Turkish elite, who started reconsidering past views that decisions in the EU
were fully captured by Greece. They were now prepared to accept a comprom-
ise deal for the resolution of Turkey’s long-standing conflict with an EU
member.33 It is worth noting that almost all EU summits and councils’ con-
clusions and decisions from Helsinki onwards have established certain proce-
dures and mechanisms to monitor Turkey’s progress in fulfilling the conditions
set by the EU.34 Moreover, the EU compliance system seemed to be operating
using a combination of enforcement and management mechanisms in apply-
ing norms, which contributed to the EU’s ability to combat detected violations,
thereby reducing non-compliance to a temporal phenomenon. By implication,
NATO, EU and the Greek–Turkish conflict 243
the use of carrot and stick by the EU to promote political reforms in Turkey
seemed to be having a multi-pathway impact on the Greek–Turkish conflict.
An examination of Turkey’s internalization of the European acquis after
its EU candidacy in 1999 reveals that a “thorough” adoption of the EU’s
legislation, norms, rules and requirements was put into motion.35 Most
importantly, such a thorough adoption of the acquis took place with the
participation of, and legitimacy provided by, several political and social act-
ors, beyond those in government. More specifically, these normative and
internalization effects of the EU on Turkey took place on a series of levels,
namely on “the domestic institutions” level, the “elite” level and the “societal”
level.
Various EU Council conclusions ask for certain EU norms and rules (in
the form of conditions) to be enmeshed into domestic institutions. Indeed,
from 2001 to 2004 various political reform packages were adopted in order to
fulfill the Copenhagen political criteria that resulted in deepening Turkey’s
Europeanization process (Bac 2003: 21). Turkey has so far taken some big
steps forward in order to fulfill these conditions and has thus managed – inter
alia – to regulate the constitutional role of the National Security Council as
an advisory body and in accordance with the practice of EU member states,36
to fulfil certain economic and legal conditions (e.g., harmonization of the
country’s legislation and practice with the European acquis) and to extend cul-
tural rights of minority groups in practice (allowing mother-tongue broad-
casting and education as well as the liberalization of laws restricting freedom
of speech and association).
At the elite level, the formal conception of norms (the transfer of EU norms
to national laws) had, in turn, certain internalization effects (constitutive
effects) on the basic political actors in Turkey. Especially the civil-military
elite, which appears as the primary “securitizing actor” able to define the
internal and external threats to the state – whose EU membership becomes
the primary objective – has slowly, painfully, but steadily entered a process
of “de-securitization.” It was the EU, especially through the acquis commun-
autaire, that increased the chances of successful de-securitization by providing
a reference point to legitimize conflict-diminishing policies.
One may at this point stress the change in Turkey’s elite interests over the
Cyprus issue due to the EU membership incentive and the EU’s normative
impact on Turkey’s political elite (Tsakonas 2001: 1–40). Indeed, despite
strong reservations about the role of the EU and veiled threats to EU mem-
bers that the Turkish Republic of Northern Cyprus (TRNC) would be either
integrated into Turkey or that Turkey would withdraw its own candidacy if
the Greek-Cypriot administration was accepted as a full member before the
Cyprus problem was solved, nothing happened. Quite the contrary, it seemed
that there was a general understanding among the Turkish elite that the
Cyprus issue had to a great extent been Europeanized and that Turkey would
need to reach acceptable compromises with Greece, the Greek Cypriots and
the European Union should it aspire to join the EU. Particular credit should
244 Panayotis Tsakonas
be given to the Turkish government, which had firstly neutralized and finally
replaced the intransigent Turkish-Cypriot leader Rauf Denktash in order for
the Greek-Cypriot community to support the Annan Plan for the reunifica-
tion of the island. Ironically, the EU had a less positive impact on the Greek-
Cypriot elite and the Greek-Cypriot public who rejected the UN Secretary
General’s plan for the reunification of the island.
Most importantly, at the societal level, Turkey’s EU membership candidacy
has empowered the domestic actors in both Greece and Turkey who are in
favor of promoting Greek–Turkish co-operation, and allowed them to use the
EU to legitimize their co-operative policies and activities. Indeed, the explicit
link made by the Helsinki Council decisions – between Turkey’s progress on
EU membership and the peaceful resolution of the Greek–Turkish dispute –
has given official and private efforts to promote Greek–Turkish co-operation
significance, urgency, and most importantly, legitimacy. Thus, after 1999 a pro-
EU coalition (benefited by the EU’s mixed strategy of conditions and incen-
tives) emerged, which gradually and steadily gained ground over another vocal
“anti-EU” coalition (Onis 2003: 9–34). In addition, Turkey’s EU membership
candidacy has unleashed funding to civil society efforts directed toward
Greek–Turkish co-operation. The effectiveness of the EU in promoting Greek–
Turkish co-operation has thus stemmed, not so much from its direct interven-
tions, as from the success of various domestic actors in using the EU as a
funder, a symbol and a legitimating handle (Rumelili 2005: 43–54).37
In a general sense, the more democratization has taken root, the more
diverse societal and political groups have challenged the primacy of the
Kemalist understanding of foreign policy. To put it differently, it has gradually
become more difficult for the National Security Council, the Foreign Ministry
and the Chief of the General Staff, the traditional actors in the Turkish foreign
policy-making process, to have the luxury of ignoring what public opinion
thinks on foreign policy issues. It seems therefore that the ongoing democra-
tization process in Turkey is continuously having an impact on the process,
style and content of Turkey’s foreign policy, leading towards a more rational-
ized and multilateralist stance and a gradual re-definition of Turkey’s national
interest that is closer to European rules and norms of behavior.38
An overall assessment of the normative and internalization effects of the
EU on Turkey suggests that the degree of salience or the level of internaliza-
tion could be characterized as “moderate to high.” Indeed, although norms
appearing in the domestic discourse have produced some change in Turkey’s
national agenda as well as in its institutions, they still confront countervailing
institutions, procedures and normative claims. However, although for some
norms and rules the domestic discourse still admits exceptions, reservations
and special conditions, it seems that gradually a legitimization of alternative
policies at the elite level has been taking place and the activities of civil
society and norms retain more and more salience as a guide to behavior and
policy choice.
In the 2004 summit in Brussels, however, there was a setback to the EU’s
NATO, EU and the Greek–Turkish conflict 245
willingness to actively contribute to the resolution of the Greek–Turkish con-
flict. As noted above, with Greece’s concession, the EU decided to withdraw
the Helsinki timetable, which had set December 2004 as a deadline for the
resolution of the conflict either through an agreement between the disputants
or via the compulsory reference of the Greek–Turkish dispute to the ICJ. The
2004 Brussels decision thus had certain consequences not only for the cred-
ibility of the EU to be “an active player” in the resolution of the Greek–
Turkish conflict but also for its ability to be viewed “as a framework” with
potential positive effects in the long run.
Indeed, from 1999 to 2004 the EU made the long-term goal of the reso-
lution of the conflict a community principle and exerted clear and strong
rules and norms to the disputants.39 Most importantly, the strength of the
norms the EU exerted after 1999, being supported and transcended by a
mix of cognitive, normative, rhetorical and bargaining mechanisms, man-
aged to achieve a moderate degree of internalization by Turkey, the dispu-
tant whose behavior deviated more from institutional norms. It would seem,
by de-linking progress on Turkey’s membership with the resolution of its
dispute with Greece, the 2004 EU summit decreased both disputants’, espe-
cially Turkey’s, incentives to search for a – solely bilateral – compromise
solution.
Even worse, a series of other developments may further exacerbate the
EU’s ability to constructively intervene and contribute to the resolution of
the Greek–Turkish conflict. Indeed, in the years to come the resolution of the
Greek–Turkish conflict is expected to become even more secondary to the
EU’s priorities in its enlargement policy (Celik and Rumelili 2006: 208).
Moreover, representations of Turkey as “non-European,” especially after the
rejection of the European Constitution by France and The Netherlands, have
resurfaced in many EU countries, Greece included, as the European identity
discourse began to emphasize the “non-European” characteristics of Turkey.
Such developments may move Turkey back to an ambiguous, if not threaten-
ing, institutional position in relation to the EU and thus have detrimental
consequences for the resolution of its conflict with Greece.
Conclusions
The examination of the impact NATO and the EU have had on the manage-
ment, transformation and/or resolution of the Greek–Turkish conflict has
both theoretical value and policy relevance. Building on various theoretical
strands, research – on the effects of NATO and the EU on Greece’s and
Turkey’s strategies toward co-operation and positive identification and, more
specifically, on their conflict transformation – has shown whether and mainly
how these institutions matter.
The relevant literature has so far argued for a parochial role of the Atlantic
Alliance in the Greek–Turkish conflict while a certain amount of optimism
has been expressed, especially after 1999, for a promising EU role in the
246 Panayotis Tsakonas
transformation of the Greek–Turkish dispute. Through a comparative assess-
ment of the empirical records of NATO and EU roles in the transformation
of the Greek–Turkish conflict, this chapter argues that two interrelated condi-
tions seem to account most for NATO’s perverse role and the EU’s promising
role in the Greek–Turkish conflict.
The first is related to the strength of the norms the two institutions have
exerted on the conflict parties, while the second concerns the “type of social-
ization” and/or the depth of internalization the two institutions’ mechanisms
have produced. Specifically, and in accordance with recent findings, which
argue that compliance crises tend to occur when the implementation of inter-
governmental agreements is not backed by a public discourse at the societal
level (Zurn and Joerges 2005), empirical findings show that in order for a
“thorough” internalization to take place institutional norms should be directed
at both the elite and the public. This chapter also draws attention to the need
for international security institutions that fulfill the aforementioned condi-
tions to be careful to promote the right mix of conditionalities and incentives
to the disputants in order to positively contribute to the transformation and/
or resolution of an inter-state dispute.
Notes
1 Structural realism believes that international institutions matter only at the mar-
gins of international relations, and whatever power they have is derived from the
power of their members (Mearsheimer 1994–5).
2 See the special issue of International Organization on “International Institutions
and Socialization in Europe” (2005).
3 The literature distinguishes between conflict management (regulation of conflict-
ual relations) and conflict transformation (the transformation of subject positions
from incompatibility/antagonism to compatibility/tolerance).
4 We here adopt Keohane’s remark that “alliances are institutions” (Keohane 1988:
74). However, Russett’s and Oneal’s point that “the ways alliances affect interstate
relations will not be the same as the ways that institutions with economic functions
operate” (Russett and Oneal 2001: 166) is also taken into account.
5 Greece and Turkey have been allies in NATO since 1952. They have also been
associate members of the European Community since 1961 and 1963, respectively.
Greece became a full member in 1981, and Turkey became a candidate of the EU
in 1999. However, despite their joint participation in and/or close association with
these institutions, Turkey and Greece have continued to maintain antagonistic
relations. In addition to armed conflict over Cyprus in 1974, Turkey and Greece
have been in numerous near-war situations in 1964, 1967, 1976 and in 1996, over
Cyprus and the continental shelf, airspace and small islets in the Aegean.
6 Greece has in the past vetoed financial protocols in relation to the Association
Agreement with Turkey, and caused a delay in the conclusion of a Customs Union
between Turkey and the EU. Although these issues are now largely settled, many
Turkish politicians see Greece as an enemy inside the EU, causing unfavorable and
unjustified treatment.
7 As Monteagle Stearns has noted: “instead of enabling them to reconcile their
differences by direct negotiation, their [Greece and Turkey] common alliance
with the United States and Western Europe often appears to act as an impediment.
Bilateral disputes acquired multilateral dimension.” See Stearns (1992: 5).
NATO, EU and the Greek–Turkish conflict 247
8 After the end of the Cold War, NATO’s policy made provisions for the transfer-
ence of the comparatively more sophisticated weapon systems of certain countries
(e.g., United States, Germany), which had to be reduced under the CFE Treaty,
to those NATO member states that had obsolete weapon systems, in order to
streamline the latter.
9 See Koucik and Kokoski (1994: 36). In accordance with NATO’s Cascade Pro-
gram, Greece received 986 tanks, 350 ACVs and 403 artillery pieces, while Turkey
received 922 tanks, 800 ACVs and 203 artillery pieces.
10 Responding to Paul Kowert and Jeffrey Legro’s remark that “the literature has
generally been biased toward studying those norms that have affected state pol-
icies” (Kowert and Legro 1996), this chapter deals with an institution whose weak
norms have failed in affecting the policies of two of its members that are in conflict
in a way that would promote the adoption of co-operative strategies.
11 For the distinction between “constitutive” and “regulative” norms, see Dessler
(1989: 454).
12 One of the most recent examples of NATO’s failure to play the role of guarantor
of a particular confidence-building enterprise taking place within the Alliance’s
institutional context was during an Alliance exercise named Destined Glory in
September 2000. During that exercise – whose main goal was to build confidence
between Greece and Turkey – in the Aegean, NATO failed to make clear, espe-
cially to the Turkish side, that any defection of what had been discussed and
agreed within the context of the Alliance would entail certain costs for the party
that decided to defect. However, although none of the participants expressed a
reservation or an objection to the exercise plans during the initial phase of the
planning in NATO Headquarters, Turkey decided some days after the beginning
of the exercise to prohibit the flights of the participating Greek aircraft over the
Greek islands of Lemnos and Ikaria, which according to Turkey should be
demilitarized. Although NATO’s Office of the Legal Adviser rejected Turkish
claims, Turkey insisted on preventing Greek aircraft from executing their NATO
missions by intercepting them while flying above the Greek island of Lemnos. The
closing of Turkish national airspace to Greece’s aircraft participating in the exer-
cise, which Turkey had previously harassed and intercepted, rendered Greece’s
further participation impossible and compelled it firstly to ask for the suspension
of the exercise and then to withdraw from it. It would have been particularly useful
had NATO managed to ensure the participation of all forces in the entire area of
the exercise as well as to conduct the exercise as previously agreed during its
planning phase. Unfortunately, NATO’s mismanagement of the particular exer-
cise sent wrong messages to the party that decided to deviate from the scenario
agreed within the alliance’s institutional context, given that Turkey’s determin-
ation to exploit the conduct of a NATO exercise in order to score politically
against Greece did not entail any costs. Most importantly, it made NATO’s ability
to play the role of guarantor of any confidence-building enterprise between
Greece and Turkey rather questionable.
13 For some analysts this is related to internal power configuration, namely to
NATO’s continuing dependence on US preponderance and sufferance.
14 Gallarotti’s work on “adverse substitution” is very telling about the destabilizing
effects of International Organizations (IOs). According to Gallarotti, an IO is
prone to failure when it – inter alia – serves as a substitute (i.e., a less costly and
less viable multilateral scheme offering short-run and ad hoc solutions) for more
substantive and long-term solutions (i.e., managing the conflict, not resolving it).
In his words: “the institution provides a ‘patch work’ solution that consolidates the
abnormal to both sides’ status quo and thus reduces the incentives for disputants
to find a better way of resolving it.” See Gallarotti (2001: 381–2).
15 Contrary to Tuschoff’s observation regarding the perceived impartiality of NATO
248 Panayotis Tsakonas
high-level military commanders, which has enabled them to resolve conflicts and
gain national concessions on disputed issues (Tuschoff 1999: 140–61), the Greek–
Turkish case aptly demonstrates that NATO has never been in the position to serve
as a neutral actor in politically charged situations.
16 This did not mean, however, that the Alliance had ceased to be perceived by
successive Greek governments as a potential provider of security against the
“Turkish threat.” See Tsakonas and Tournikiotis (2003). For reference to particular
examples regarding successive Greek governments’ efforts to get a formal security
guarantee, see Dimitras (1985).
17 For these remarks, see Oguzlu (2004: 466).
18 With an increase in the United States’ relative power vis-à-vis the European mem-
bers of the Alliance, in the post-Cold War era NATO has mainly remained a
political instrument of the US Government. Decisions about enlargement, the
definition of the new missions of the Alliance and of the geopolitical boundaries
of the Alliance have mainly reflected the concerns and priorities of the successive
US governments in the 1990s. As such, NATO has gradually turned out to be a
state-centric platform for the US to enlist possible allies in their global-scale secur-
ity initiatives and undertakings. See Layne (2000) and Croft (2000).
19 In the words of one senior Greek official: “Turkey would thus think twice to attack
an EU member state.” See The Economist, 26 July 1975, and The Guardian, 19
May 1976 (as quoted in Valinakis 1997: 279). See also the speeches of the premier,
Constantine Karamanlis, in Kathimerini [Greek daily], 11 April 1978 and 1 January
1981, as quoted in Valinakis (1997: 283).
20 It was not until March 1995 that Greece decided to lift its veto towards the EU-
Turkey Customs Union agreement. In exchange for the removal of the Greek veto
on the Customs Union, accession negotiations between the EU and Cyprus would
begin in March 1998. Cyprus would thus be included in the next round of
enlargement accession negotiations. With regard to Turkey’s European orienta-
tion, decisions made in Luxembourg and Cardiff, in January and June 1998
respectively, further burdened the already tense and fragile Greek–Turkish security
agenda, as the postponement of Turkey’s accession negotiations remained linked
to Greece’s deliberate policy of keeping the doors of the EU closed.
21 In 1986, Greece vetoed the resumption of the Association relationship between
Turkey and EC and the release of frozen aid to Turkey. A year later, when Turkey
applied for EC membership, Greece was the only member that openly opposed
referring the application to the EC Commission for an Opinion. See Guvenc
(1998–9). It is characteristic that even up to the EU-Turkey Association Council in
April 1997, Greece maintained its veto and continued blocking EU aid to Turkey
worth 375 million ECUs. As explained by the then Greek Minister of Foreign
Affairs, Theodoros Pangalos, the veto was to be maintained until Turkey stopped
disputing Greek sovereignty in the Aegean. See Athens News Agency, Daily
Bulletin, 30 April 1997, statement by Foreign Minister Pangalos.
22 Declaration adopted by the Fifteen Ministers of Foreign Affairs of the EU at the
General Affairs Council on 15 July 1996, Brussels, SN 3543/96.
23 Turkey’s eligibility for EU membership after Helsinki depended on resolving two
issues: its border conflict with an EU member-state, Greece, and the Cyprus issue.
With regard to Greek–Turkish relations, Helsinki made it clear to Turkey that it
had four years – until 2004 – to resolve the conflict with neighboring Greece before
the rather critical review that would assess Turkey’s path towards the European
Union took place. Paragraph 4 of the Helsinki European Council Conclusions
states: “[. . .] the European Council stresses the principle of peaceful settlement of
disputes in accordance with the United Nations Charter and urges candidate
States to make every effort to resolve any outstanding border disputes and other
related issues. Failing this they should within a reasonable time bring the dispute
NATO, EU and the Greek–Turkish conflict 249
to the International Court of Justice. The European Council will review the situ-
ation relating to any outstanding disputes, in particular concerning the repercus-
sions on the accession process and in order to promote their settlement through
the International Court of Justice, at the latest by the end of 2004.” Regarding the
Cyprus issue, the Helsinki European Council reiterated in Paragraphs 9a and 9b
that although a political settlement of the Cyprus problem would facilitate
Cyprus’s accession to the EU, this very settlement would not be a precondition for
accession. At the same time, the European Council ambiguously stressed that “all
relevant factors” would be taken into account for the final decision on accession.
The fifteen Heads of State and Government of the European Union have sent a
clear message to Turkey that the division of Cyprus must end by the date of the
next EU meeting at the latest. After that date, even a divided Cyprus would
become member of the Union. In that sense, Turkey, which illegally occupies the
northern part of the island, could no longer block the accession of Cyprus to the
European Union. See Helsinki European Council Conclusions, online at http://
www.europa.eu.int/council/off/conclu/dec99_en.htm.
24 Both the Helsinki Conclusions and the provision on Greek–Turkish relations, in the
“medium-term priorities” of the Accession Partnership, do refer to the resolution
of the two states’ outstanding border disputes.
25 For this remark, see Rumelili (2004b: 14). The approach adopted in the Helsinki
Summit is indeed different from past approaches. For example, the EU Council
of Ministers stated in July 1996 (after the Imia crisis) that “the cases of disputes
created by territorial claims, such as the Imia islet issue, should be submitted to the
International Court of Justice.” Similarly, the Luxembourg Council Decisions of
December 1997 urged “the settlement of disputes, in particular, by legal process,
including the ICJ.”
26 Commission discourses also include references to the continuous improvement in
relations between Greece and Turkey. The improvement is sometimes linked with
words like “significantly” (EU Commission Regular Report 2001: 89) or “dramat-
ically” (EU Commission Regular Report 2004: 52). In this context, the Regular
Reports refer to the signing of bilateral agreements that aim to deepen the co-
operation between the two countries (EU Commission Regular Report 2003: 41
and EU Commission Regular Report 2002: 18 and 44), agreement on a number of
confidence-building measures (2004: 2003: 41; 2002: 44; 2001: 31), the exploratory
talks in the Aegean that started in March 2002 (EU Commission Regular Reports
in 2004 and 2002: 18 and 44) as well as symbolic movements such as the “official
visit” of the Turkish PM to Greece and his “private visit to Western Thrace where
he called on the Turkish-speaking Muslim minority to contribute to Greece’s
prosperity” (EU Commission Regular Report 2004) and the public commitments
at the highest level to continued rapprochement (EU Commission Regular Report
2003: 41). In some documents, there have also been references to the Greek–
Turkish rapprochement at the level of civil society (EU Commission Regular
Report 2001: 89). The evolution of Turkish foreign policy and its perception
of security interests towards EU standards has also been recorded, though the
Greek–Turkish dispute remains unresolved (EU Commission Report, October
2004). See Pace (2005).
27 The EU acquis, also known as acquis communautaire, concerns the “legal order”
of the Union.
28 According to the EU Commission discourse, Greek–Turkish conflict appears as
a series of “issue conflicts”: “There are a number of contentious issues in the
Aegean area between Turkey and an EU Member State, Greece, including dis-
putes about the demarcation of the continental shelf. Turkey also challenges sover-
eignty over various islets and rocks. The boundaries of the two territorial waters
and airspace are also problematic” (Regular Report 1998: 51). The European
250 Panayotis Tsakonas
Commission sees the role of the EU as a forum where the Greek–Turkish dispute
can be discussed in the context of political dialogue (Regular Report 2001: 33)
while the use of carrot and stick to promote political reforms in Turkey could be
seen to have a multi-pathway impact on the Greek–Turkish conflict. See Pace
(2005).
29 The government that emerged from the parliamentary elections in March 2004,
burdened with the rejection of the Annan Plan by the Greek/Cypriots and hesitant
to pay the cost that a compromise settlement with Turkey before the Helsinki
deadline (i.e. the end of 2004) would entail, opted for a transference of the dis-
pute’s resolution to the future. For an analysis of Greece’ “socialization” strategy
vis-à-vis Turkey, see Tsakonas (2007).
30 There is a plethora of examples, both during the Cold War and in the post-Cold
War era, that verify this thesis. Back in mid-1950s Greece argued for the establish-
ment of a NATO patrol-boat base on the island of Leros, which was vetoed by
Turkey because the latter considered that this Dodecanese island – in accordance
with the 1923 Lausanne and 1947 Paris treaties – should remain demilitarized.
See Iatrides (2000: 32–46). By analogy, Turkey was constantly vetoing the inclu-
sion of the island of Lemnos in the planned military exercises of the Alliance in
the region in order to prevent the promotion of Greece’s goals through NATO; see
Karaosmanoglu (1988: 85–118).
31 Several cases during the Cold War and after can be reviewed to illustrate Greece’s
attempts to get from either NATO or the US a formal security guarantee. They
include Premier Andreas Papandreou’s request in 1981 to the Alliance to provide
Greece with a security guarantee against another ally, namely Turkey. The rejec-
tion of such a request by the Alliance led to Papandreou’s refusal to sign the
particular NATO summit final communiqué; the same request was posed again in
1990 to the US government in return for its access to military bases and other
facilities in Greece. See Dimitras (1985); Tsakonas and Tournikiotis (2003).
32 Making use of its bargaining power means that EU conducts policies through
which it addresses primarily the political leadership of the conflict parties. This is
probably the most obvious way through which the EU attempts to exert influence.
In its relations with Turkey the EU has, on the one hand, repeatedly used the
“carrot” of a future membership in order to “convince” the Turkish government not
only to pursue conflict transformation vis-à-vis the Cyprus conflict or the con-
tested border issues with Greece, but also to engage in far-reaching constitutional
and economic reforms. On the other hand, the “stick” of threatening suspension of
financial assistance has in the past been used by the EU to exert political pressure
on Turkey and normative power.
33 On elite receptivity as a factor essential to the socialization process, see Ikenberry
and Kupchan (1990: 284).
34 After Helsinki and in order to prepare for membership, the Accession Partnership
called upon Turkey to prepare a National Program for the Adoption of the Acquis
(NPAA), which should be compatible with the priorities established in the Acces-
sion Partnership. The purpose of the Accession Partnership was to set out the
specific short-term and medium-term priorities and intermediate objectives for
political, economic and legal/administrative reforms in a single framework, and
touch upon Turkey’s internal, as well as external, front. In July 2003, the Turkish
government revised its National Programme on the Adoption of the Acquis in line
with changes and political reforms adopted since 2001.
35 For a good account of the political and legal reforms which have been stimulated
since Turkey’s EU candidacy, see Bac (2003: 17–31).
36 A development that has had certain repercussions for the Turkish military ability
to solely define the issues that concern the country’s national interest.
37 Especially after 1999, again slowly but steadily, one could notice, both within
NATO, EU and the Greek–Turkish conflict 251
Turkey and the TRNC, the surfacing of a plethora of political parties, business
associations and civil society organizations which have challenged the “orthodox”
well-established Turkish policy on Cyprus and started demanding that Turkey and
TRNC cease adopting a skeptical view of the EU and the accession of the island
to the EU.
38 Our focus on the institutional effects on Turkey’s foreign policy behavior is mainly
related to the fact that, as theory suggests, convergence effects appear when institu-
tions exert their greatest influence on precisely those states whose behavior devi-
ates substantially from institutional norms. See Martin and Simmons (2001). In
the Greek–Turkish dyad, Turkey is undoubtedly the one of the disputants whose
behavior deviates more from institutional norms. Hence, the assessment of the
EU’s ability to exert its normative and internalization effects on Turkey’s foreign
policy.
39 Based on the observation that the level of internalization of the EU’s norms and
rules on Turkey has been a moderate one, we consider the EU norms and rules as
particularly strong. This assessment follows Cortell and Davis’ remark that “the
strength of a norm is a function of its level of “institutionalization”, namely of
the norm’s tenets in the states’ constitutional, regulative and/or judicial systems.”
See Cortell and Davis (2000: 70).
11 Evaluating multilateral
interventions in civil wars
A comparison of UN and
non-UN peace operations
Nicholas Sambanis and
Jonah Schulhofer-Wohl
Introduction
As the prevalence of civil war around the world peaked in the mid-1990s, the
international community responded by increasing the number of peacekeep-
ing operations to end those wars and prevent their recurrence. Both the num-
ber and scope of peacekeeping operations expanded drastically after the end
of the Cold War. The UN took the lead in those efforts, but other regional
organizations and individual countries also engaged in peacekeeping activ-
ities. The UN had some spectacular failures in Somalia and Rwanda, but also
some impressive successes, in Cambodia, El Salvador, Mozambique, and
elsewhere. The record of non-UN peacekeeping is less well-known. Have
peacekeeping operations by organizations other than the UN had the same
overall success rate as UN peace operations? This is the question that we
address in this chapter. The evidence that we present suggests that the UN
has been much more successful in peacekeeping than other organizations.
We analyze that evidence and suggest some possible explanations for this
empirical fact.
UN officials and advocates see the UN’s legitimacy as one of its key vir-
tues. The UN “premium” of international legitimacy as an impartial mediator
is often seen as a critical component of UN peacemaking and peacekeeping.1
Legitimacy is distinct from the organization’s resources and technical cap-
abilities, and derives from its commitment to maintain peace and order in
accordance with the rules of the UN Charter. Thus the UN’s legitimacy is
not necessarily a characteristic of other actors engaged in peacekeeping
(individual countries or regional organizations), even if those actors have the
capabilities to engage in peacekeeping. These assertions, evident in journal-
istic accounts, case studies of UN peacekeeping, and speeches by diplomats
and UN officials, skirt key policy questions. Why might UN operations be
more likely to achieve good peacebuilding results than non-UN operations?
Are the mechanisms behind UN success fundamentally unavailable to non-
UN operations? We address this question in this chapter, by suggesting some
possible explanations. These explanations do not resolve the debate. Rather,
Interventions in civil wars: a comparison 253
they highlight the fact that we do not yet know why there is a difference in the
relative effectiveness of UN and non-UN peacekeeping and point the way to
more research that could resolve this puzzle.
The literature on peace operations has provided several, often conflicting
perspectives on the effectiveness of UN and non-UN peacekeeping. Several
studies describe potential advantages and disadvantages of UN and non-UN
approaches to peacekeeping (see, e.g., Diehl 1993), and case studies offer
detailed accounts of the histories of particular operations (see, e.g., Durch
1996). But a theoretical account of the differences between the two types of
UN missions is in short supply. There are also only a few empirical analyses
of the differences between UN and non-UN missions. Here, the results that
authors have presented are not consistent. Heldt and Wallensteen (2005) have
observed that UN peace operations appear to be more successful than non-
UN operations because the former, while succeeding at the same rate as the
latter, tend to be deployed in more difficult conflict environments. Yet, Heldt
(2004) is cited in the same study, arguing that, controlling for the degree of
mission difficulty, UN and non-UN operations appear not to differ in their
rate of success. Fortna’s (2004a) analysis finds that peace missions (UN and
non-UN missions combined) have had a positive effect on continued peace,
but this result is driven by the effects of UN missions.
We compare the effects of UN and non-UN peace operations by building
on Doyle and Sambanis’ (2000, 2006) ecological model of peacebuilding.
According to the model, there are three main dimensions to the peacebuild-
ing “space” after civil war. Levels of war-related hostility, pre- and post-war
levels of local capacities, and available international capacities interact to
deliver specific post-conflict outcomes. The higher the levels of hostility, and
the lower the local and international capacities, the lower will be the prob-
ability of a successful transition to peace. The main measure of international
capacities in the Doyle and Sambanis model is UN peacekeeping. UN oper-
ations are successful if they respond to the type of co-ordination or co-
operation problem facing parties to the conflict. In other words, not all types
of peace operations work all the time. Their empirical analysis has shown that
UN peace operations have a robust, large and statistically significant positive
effect on the probability of peacebuilding success and that this effect is larger
in the short run. All types of UN mandates can have a positive effect, though
consent-based operations make the larger difference. A central conclusion of
this work that we bring to our analysis is that an operation affects peacebuild-
ing success through its interaction with the characteristics of the conflict.
All types of peace operations should, in principle, have a positive effect if
they offer sufficient international capacities to counteract the negative effects
of hostility and to compensate for deficiencies in local capacities. Thus, on the
basis of Doyle and Sambanis (2000, 2006), our prior belief is that non-
UN operations are no less likely to have a positive effect on peacebuilding than
UN-operations themselves. This is grounded in the more theoretical literature
on external or “third party” intervention, which analyzes intervention in
254 Nicholas Sambanis and Jonah Schulhofer-Wohl
conflict abstractly, in contrast to the vast majority of the literature on peace
operations as such. We provide support for this prior belief by offering an
overview of the conventional wisdom on the differences between UN and
non-UN peace operations. Here, we indicate that perceived differences
between the two types in fact vary across both UN and non-UN operations,
such that the two may not necessarily be understood as natural categories.
Note that in contrast to the literature on peace operations as such, more
theoretically orientated studies of external or “third party” interventions in
conflict, whether formal or empirical, apparently proceed based on this
assumption. Historical evidence on pre-UN peace operations also supports
this claim (see Heldt and Wallensteen 2005).
We test our hypothesis about the effectiveness of non-UN operations
empirically, using data from Doyle and Sambanis (2006). We find that the
data do not support our hypothesis and that non-UN operations have no
significant effect on peacebuilding success, in contrast to UN operations,
which have a large significant positive effect. This result is robust across
multiple models employing different operationalizations of the dependent
variable, different controls, and different econometric assumptions. We find
support for the idea that the presence of a non-UN peace operation in the
same conflict may complement the effectiveness of a multidimensional UN
operation.2 We postulate several possible explanations for the result that non-
UN operations have no significant effect on peacebuilding success and we
explore the differences between the outcomes of UN and non-UN peace
operations as a way to analyze the determinants of the composition of a
peace operation.
Literature review
The perceived differences between UN and non-UN peace operations are
many. Non-UN operations, which could range from efforts by regional organ-
izations to multinational undertakings, or potentially even intervention by a
single state, are thought to be subject to problems of impartiality, bias, logis-
tics, vulnerability to domestic politics, and lack of financial, technical and
coercive resources.3 Interestingly enough, the reverse of all of these problems
have also been noted as potential advantages of non-UN operations, as are
some additional characteristics: the potential for operational stability in con-
trast to regularly reviewed and renewed UN mandates, and greater local and
external support based on the ability to incorporate stakeholders (Diehl
1993). These often directly contradictory advantages and disadvantages lead
us to conclude that both UN and non-UN operations vary in their avoidance
of the problems listed above and their provision of the services hypothesized
as needed to build peace. The logic is that falsification of purported regular-
ities in the differences between UN and non-UN peace operations implies
that variation in the characteristics of peace operations exists, regardless of
their source.
Interventions in civil wars: a comparison 255
Yet while a large body of literature treats abstractly external intervention in
conflict, a category to which peace operations undoubtedly belong, and ana-
lyzes its characteristics and effects as varying in ways that are not inherent to
a particular actor,4 we feel obliged to falsify one additional set of claims
about differences between UN and non-UN operations. Non-UN operations
are held to lack the special kind of “moral authority” the UN confers on its
undertakings (Dorn 1998) or require accountability to the UN itself (Weiss,
Forsythe, and Coate 2004). Some may also see them as lacking the unique
legitimacy of UN operations (Bellamy and Williams 2005). Such analyses
allude to the existence of something like a UN “brand” that enhances peace
operations by its essence, not its characteristics. (We could call this the pri-
mordialist theory of peacekeeping!) Thus, Diehl (2000: 357) concludes that:
Our argument
Based on an ecological model of peacebuilding, we argue that the effect of
peace operations should not differ across organizations, controlling for the
relevant elements of these operations. The specifics of an operation and how
well it is matched to the characteristics of the conflict should affect peace-
building success. To develop this line of argument further, we specify the
characteristics of conflict to which peace operations should respond in order
to facilitate peacebuilding.
The resolution of conflict is characterized by co-ordination and co-
operation problems, with some conflicts reflecting entirely one or the other,
and others reflecting a mix of the two, either simultaneously or in sequences.
Co-ordination problems have a payoff structure that gives the parties no
incentives to unilaterally move out of equilibrium, once they reach equi-
librium.10 It is well established that the best strategy to resolve co-ordination
problems is information provision and improvement of the level of com-
munication between the parties.11 Communication gives the parties the ability
to form common conjectures about the likely outcomes of their actions.
Without the ability to communicate, they will not choose the most efficient
outcome.
In a game of pure co-ordination, both parties want to pursue compatible
strategies. But if neither knows the rules or what the other party prefers, they
will be tempted to experiment, to try one and then another of the strategies,
and this of course can be costly. Co-ordination can be readily achieved by
credible information on rules, payoffs, and the parties’ compliance with the
rules or stated preferences. Once the rule is known or the other parties’ pref-
erences are clear, co-ordination can be achieved. UN monitors or observers
Interventions in civil wars: a comparison 257
can assist such communication and help the parties co-ordinate to an efficient
outcome.
One formulation of a co-ordination problem is the “assurance” game. The
classic story (as told by the eighteenth-century French philosopher Jean
Jacques Rousseau) is a stag hunt in which catching the stag depends on all the
hunters co-operating. But if a rabbit suddenly appears, some of the hunters
may be tempted to defect in order to catch the rabbit which, though less
desirable than the hunter’s share of the deer, can be caught (in this story) by
one hunter on his own. If all chase the rabbit, they divide the rabbit. Here, if
players A and B can choose between strategies of co-operation and defection,
we get a payoff structure such as the following: mutual co-operation yields an
equal payoff (4, 4) for players A and B, as each gets a half-share of the deer.
When A co-operates and B defects, A gets 0 and B gets 3 (the rabbit); cor-
respondingly when A defects and B co-operates, A gets 3 and B, 0. When both
defect, each gets 1.5 (a half-share of the rabbit). In this case, peacekeeping
needs to be more involved than in the previous co-ordination game. In both
cases communication should be sufficient, but the temptation to defect out of
fear that another hunter will do so first (even though this is rational for
neither) requires more active facilitation and continual reassurance. Informa-
tion alone may not be enough; the peacekeepers may need to provide regular
reports on each party’s compliance, and so reduce the costs of communica-
tion between the parties and allow them to co-ordinate their strategies.12 The
more the peacekeepers need to increase the costs of non-co-operation, the
more we move from a co-ordination game to a game of co-operation.
In the more complicated framework of actual peace processes, many par-
ties that have a “will” to co-ordinate lack the “way.” Co-ordination is promoted
when parties receive assistance in capacity building, demobilizing armies and
transforming themselves from military factions to coherent political parties.
Such assistance permits them to act rationally according to their preferences,
rather than incoherently.
By contrast, co-operation problems create incentives to renege on agree-
ments, particularly if the parties discount the benefits of long-term co-
operation in favor of short-run gain. In one-shot games of co-operation the
parties will try to trick their adversaries into co-operating while they renege
on their promises. A well-known example is the Prisoner’s Dilemma. Two
accomplices in police custody are offered a chance to “rat” on their partner.
The first to rat gets off and the “sucker” receives a very heavy sentence. If
neither rats, both receive light sentences (based on circumstantial evidence);
and, if both rat, both receive sentences (but less than the sucker’s penalty).
Even though they would be better off trusting each other by keeping silent,
the temptation to get off and the fear of being the sucker make co-operation
extremely difficult.
Co-operation problems are much more difficult to solve. How can co-
operation failure (defection) be avoided? In the classic Prisoner’s Dilemma
one-shot game, we always end up at double defection (both rat) unless there is
258 Nicholas Sambanis and Jonah Schulhofer-Wohl
some external enforcement mechanism. Conditions of repeated play (iter-
ation) may produce co-operation in infinite-horizon games even without
external enforcement, but not if there is a visible end to the game.13 Short-term
defection from agreements may even be possible from iterated games if one
of the parties discounts the future severely. Strong third party involvement
would be necessary to support effective co-operation, unless the parties’
agreements are self-enforcing. However, self-enforcement of peace agreements
in internal conflicts may be impossible for at least three reasons.
First, many conflicts are characterized by power asymmetry, which implies
that the costs of co-operating while other parties are defecting may be
extremely large for the weaker party. In internal conflicts, a settlement implies
that the rebels would need to disarm, making themselves vulnerable to an
attack by the state, even if the state can later renege on the agreement. Walter
(1997) argues that this is the “critical barrier” to negotiated settlement in
civil wars. The potential for time-inconsistent behavior by the state makes
the settlement non-credible.
Second, internal conflicts – especially of the ethnic variety – can escalate to
the point where one or more of the groups are eliminated, forcibly displaced,
or weakened to the point of not having any bargaining leverage. This seems to
have been the strategy of the genocidaires in Rwanda, and of the Serbs in the
Bosnian war. This also implies that the potential gains from short-term defec-
tion for the stronger party could be infinite if such defection could eliminate
the weaker party from future bargaining. Thus, the usual long-term benefits
to co-operation in iterated play need not be greater than short-term gains
from defection.
Third, in computer-simulated results of iterated prisoner’s dilemma games
(where the solutions from iterated play come from), players have access to
strategies that cannot be replicated in real life. For example, tit-for-tat
punishment strategies of permanent exclusion of one of the parties may be
feasible in a simulated environment, but are not realistic in actual civil wars.
Parties that defect from peace agreements cannot be permanently excluded
from further negotiation, so reciprocal punishment strategies against defec-
tion are implausible.14 This should increase the discounting of expected
future costs of short-term violations by parties who can expect to be included
in future negotiations regardless of their previous behavior.
Given these enforcement problems, strong peacekeeping is necessary in
internal conflicts resembling co-operation problems to increase the parties’
costs from non-co-operation, or reduce the costs of exploitation, or increase
the benefits from co-operation – and ideally all three at once. Can peacekeep-
ing have such an impact? And if so, how? The literature suggests that peace-
keepers can change the costs and benefits of co-operation by virtue of the
legitimacy of their UN mandate, which induces the parties to co-operate;
by their ability to focus international attention on non-co-operative parties
and condemn transgressions; by their monitoring of and reporting on the
parties’ compliance with agreements; and by their function as a trip-wire that
Interventions in civil wars: a comparison 259
would force aggressors to go through the UN troops to change the military
status quo.
Ultimate success, however, may depend less on changing the incentives for
existing parties within their preferences and more on transforming prefer-
ences – and even the parties themselves – and thus turning a co-operation
problem into a co-ordination problem. The institution-building aspects of
peacebuilding can be thought of as a revolutionary transformation in which
voters and politicians replace soldiers and generals; armies become political
parties; and war economies, peace economies. Reconciliation, when achieved,
is a label for these changed preferences and capacities. To be sure, the dif-
ficulty of a transformative strategy cannot be overestimated. Most post-war
societies look a great deal like they did prior to the war. However, if, for
example, those who have committed the worst war crimes can be prosecuted,
locked up and thus removed from power, the prospects for peace rise. The
various factions can begin to individualize rather than collectivize their
distrust and hostility. At minimum, the worst individuals are no longer in
control.15
Therefore, even where enforcement is used at the outset, the peace must
eventually become self-sustaining and consent must be won if the peace
enforcers are ever to exit and have their work remain complete. As consensual
peace agreements can rapidly erode, forcing peace enforcers to adjust to the
strategies of “spoilers,” their success or lack of success in doing so tends to
be decisive in whether a sustainable peace follows.
These structural differences between co-operation and co-ordination
problems imply that different peacekeeping strategies should be used in each
case. Strong intervention strategies, such as multidimensional peacekeeping
or enforcement with considerable international authority, are needed to
resolve co-operation problems, whereas weaker peacekeeping strategies,
such as monitoring and traditional peacekeeping, are sufficient to resolve co-
ordination problems. Weak peacekeeping has no enforcement or deterrence
function. Stronger peacekeeping through multidimensional operations can
increase the costs of non-co-operation for the parties and provide positive
inducements by helping rebuild the country and restructure institutions so
that they can support the peace. Enforcement may be necessary to resolve the
toughest co-operation problems.16 Not all civil war transitions are plagued by
co-operation problems. Some wars resemble co-ordination problems, whereas
frequently both types of problems occur, in which case intervention strategies
must be carefully combined or sequenced (Doyle and Sambanis 2006).
Table 11.1 illustrates how peacebuilding strategies can be matched success-
fully with different types of conflict.
In our empirical analysis, we will consider if UN and non-UN peace
operations match the right mandate to the right peacebuilding ecology.
Peacebuilding success would depend on the assignment of the right mandate
to each case. Thus, if we find systematic differences between the UN and
other organizations in the design of appropriate mandates, this could be a
260 Nicholas Sambanis and Jonah Schulhofer-Wohl
Peacebuilding strategy
Weak Strong
source of difference in the success rates of peace missions from these different
organizations.
Data
The dataset used is from Doyle and Sambanis (2006). It covers all peace
processes after civil war from 1945 until the end of 1999,17 coding 145 civil
wars in that period. Wars that were ongoing as of 31 December 1999 and/or
wars in which there had been no significant peace process prior to that point
were dropped.18 If a peace process started and failed immediately, a failure of
the peace was coded in the first month of the peace process.19 Rules for coding
the start and end of a civil war, including criteria used to separate civil wars
from other forms of political violence and to distinguish bouts of civil war
in the same country are reproduced from Doyle and Sambanis (2006) in
the Appendix, where we also provide a list of civil wars and peace operations.20
Dependent variable
We analyze peacebuilding using several measures. The main dependent vari-
ables are sovereign and participatory peace two years after the end of the war.
These are coded as combinations of four intermediate variables.
Sovereign peace is attained when there is no war recurrence, no residual
violence, and no divided sovereignty. The resumption of civil war in a country
is captured in the Warend variable, with a suffix to indicate the time elapsed
after which this outcome is evaluated. Warend2 indicates whether there is still
peace two years after the end of civil war: it is coded 1 if civil war has not
re-started after two years and 0 otherwise.21 The variable No Residual Vio-
lence (Noviol) codes lower-level, or residual, violence after the war, referring
to what other datasets call intermediate armed conflict – about 200 deaths
per year22 – and the presence of mass violations of human rights, such as
politicide, genocide, widespread extra-judicial killings, torture, and mass
imprisonments of the political opposition. If there is no evidence of these
events two years after the end of the war, then Noviol=1; otherwise it equals 0.
The suffix again indicates the time period of evaluating outcomes (Noviol2
refers to residual violence two years after the war’s end). Finally, the govern-
ment’s ability to exercise its sovereignty throughout the country’s territory is
Interventions in civil wars: a comparison 261
a component of peacebuilding. If state sovereignty is undivided, then Sover-
eign = 1. If there is de facto or de jure partition or regional autonomy that
obstructs government control of an area of the country, then this criterion
is not satisfied and Sovereign = 0. Thus, sovereign peace two years after the
war (pbs2lr3) is coded 1 if Warend2 = 1, Noviol2 = 1, and Sovereign = 1; and 0
otherwise.
Participatory peace adds a measure of political openness to sovereign peace,
based on the country’s polity score two years after the end of the war (pol2).
This is the difference of the regime’s democratic and autocratic character-
istics.23 The variable ranges from 0 (extreme autocracy) to 20 (maximum
democracy).24 The cutoff point used is a low score of 3 on that scale. Regimes
that fall below this cutoff point are coded as participatory peace failures – we
are effectively coding the “peace of the grave” in completely authoritarian
regimes as peacebuilding failures. All other regimes above this very low
threshold are considered successes, if they also satisfy the sovereign peace
criteria.
These coding rules imply that several cases – those where the UN has not
departed for at least two years before the end of the dataset, December 1999 –
must be excluded from the analysis.25 PB (peacebuilding) outcomes are coded
for 119 cases with non-missing data for any of the explanatory variables.
There are 84 participatory peace failures (69.42 per cent) and 37 successes
(30.58 per cent).26 Achieving sovereign peace is easier, with 68 failures and 53
successes.27
Explanatory variables
The ecological model of peacebuilding posits that the variables that deter-
mine success fall into three categories: level of hostility, local capabilities,
and international capacities. Peace operations are the key measure of inter-
national capacities. We use all the controls from Doyle and Sambanis’ core
model (2006): For level of hostility, we control for the log of the number of
deaths and displacements (Logcost),28 the type of war (ethno-religious or
not) as Wartype,29 the number of factions (Factnum), and whether a peace
treaty was ever signed by the majority of the parties (Treaty).30 For local
capacities, we control for socio-economic development proxied by electricity
consumption per capita (idev1)31 and dependence on natural resources, prox-
ied by primary commodity exports as a percentage of GDP (isxp2) or oil-
dependence (oil). Finally, for international capacities, in addition to UN (and
non-UN missions), we control for foreign economic assistance, proxied by
the amount of net current transfers per capita to the balance of payments of
the country (transpop).32
We describe in more detail only the variables relating to UN and non-UN
peace operations. The variables of interest are the presence and mandate
of peace operations, which are a large portion of the international capacities
in the model. Mandate proxies for the mission’s strength, its technical and
262 Nicholas Sambanis and Jonah Schulhofer-Wohl
military capabilities, and the level of international commitment.33 Coding
reflects the types of missions:34 fact-finding and mediation (mediate);35 obser-
ver missions (observe); traditional peacekeeping (tradpko); multidimensional
peacekeeping (multipko); and enforcement with or without transitional
administration (enforce). A categorical variable (unmandate) captures the dif-
ferent mandate types. The binary indicator unintrvn identifies all cases of UN
intervention, while the categorical variable unops lumps together monitoring
missions (observer and traditional peacekeeping operations) and the more
intrusive missions (multidimensional, enforcement, and transitional adminis-
tration). Combined multidimensional and enforcement are also grouped
together into a variable labeled strongUN, because strong missions should be
more effective in difficult peacebuilding ecologies. The variable PKO com-
bines all Chapter VI UN peacekeeping missions, excluding observer and
enforcement missions. Finally, the variable Ch6 identifies all missions author-
ized under Chapter VI of the UN Charter (i.e., it excludes enforcement mis-
sions).36 These different versions of the UN’s involvement will allow us to
develop a more nuanced argument about the conditions under which UN is
likely to help build self-sustaining peace. UN mandates were coded based on
a close reading of each operation’s operational guidelines, status of forces
agreements (where available), and a review of UN documents that indicated
how much of the mandate was actually implemented.37
Non-UN peace operations were coded using Heldt (2002) and sup-
plemented in most cases with additional research. There are two versions of a
non-UN peace operation variable. The first, nonunops, is coded exactly as the
unops variable but for non-UN operations, thus distinguishing between
strong and weak operations by grouping observer and traditional non-UN
operations together and grouping multidimensional, enforcement, and tran-
sitional non-UN operations together. The second, nonUN, captures the pres-
ence of any non-UN operation. In order to deal with overlapping UN and
non-UN operations, if bilateral or regional involvement took place in the
context of a UN mandate, then we code a UN peace operation. But in some
cases, both a UN mission and a separate third-party peace operation took
place simultaneously and we code both in those cases.38
Our data include 34 UN peace operations (13 observer missions, 8 trad-
itional peacekeeping missions, 7 multidimensional peacekeeping missions,
and 6 cases of enforcement or transitional administration) and 44 cases of
non-UN peace operations (broken down into 15 observer missions, 12 trad-
itional peacekeeping missions, and 17 peace enforcement or transitional
administration missions).
Table 11.2 The effect of UN and non-UN peace operations on participatory peace
Models
Peace operations
Strong UN 3.2456 3.4546 – –
(StrongUN) (1.1108) (1.1755) – –
Any UN – – 2.1809 2.0856
(Unintrvn) – – (0.6532) (0.6570)
Strong non-UN mandate 0.1568 – −0.3569 –
(Nonunops) (0.4191) – (0.4066) –
Any non-UN – 0.6749 – −0.4219
(NonUN) – (0.6904) – (0.6575)
Level of hostilities
Ethnic war −1.5963 −1.5566 −1.6221 −1.6451
(Wartype) (0.5132) (0.5114) (0.4934) (0.4930)
Deaths and displaced −0.3201 −0.3150 −0.3405 −0.3468
Natural log (Logcost) (0.1338) (0.1332) (0.1453) (0.1438)
Number of factions −0.6259 −0.6610 −0.5989 −0.5861
(Factnum) (0.2389) (0.2539) (0.2554) (0.2553)
Signed peace treaty 1.5182 1.4326 1.6933 1.6835
(Treaty) (0.7088) (0.7030) (0.7300) (0.6900)
Local capacities
Electricity consumption with 0.0006 0.0006 0.0004 0.0004
missing values imputed (0.0003) (0.0003) (0.0003) (0.0003)
(Idev1)
Primary commodity exports/ −7.8379 −7.9091 −7.6404 −7.8397
GDP (Isxp2) (2.2256) (2.2556) (2.1070) (2.1742)
Other international capacities
Net transfers per capita 3.75e–06 3.57e–06 3.15e–06 3.03e–06
(Transpop) (1.25e–06) (1.26e–06) (1.06e–06) (1.07e–06)
Logistic regression; reported are coefficients and robust standard errors in parentheses; bold
indicates significance at the 0.05 level; italics indicate significance at the 0.05 level with one-tailed
test.
Models 1.1 and 1.2 control for the effects of combined multidimensional
and enforcement operations (strongUN ). Here, none of the operationaliza-
tions of non-UN operations – whether presence (nonUN ) or strength (obser-
ver and traditional operations versus multidimensional, enforcement, and
transitional authority operations) – has a statistically significant effect on
participatory peace two years after the war. Models 1.3 and 1.4 control for
264 Nicholas Sambanis and Jonah Schulhofer-Wohl
the presence of any UN operation (unintrvn). Again, no operationalization of
non-UN operations has a statistically significant effect.
Next, we look at the different components of the participatory peace defin-
ition. We begin by dropping the undivided sovereignty criterion (pbs2s3_no-
sov) and present these results in Table 11.3.
The substantive result of no statistically significant effect of non-UN oper-
ations from Table 11.2 does not change if we use a different concept and
measure of peacebuilding success or if we change the model specification.
But there appears to be an interaction effect between UN and non-UN peace
operations. First, the coefficient on strongUN in Model 2.1 is larger than
the coefficient on strongUN in Model 2.3 (at 2.74 compared to 2.35), the only
difference between the two specifications being that model 2.3 does not con-
trol at all for non-UN operations, whereas Model 2.1 controls for nonunops.
Both strongUN coefficients are statistically significant at the 0.05 level. Simi-
larly, a comparison between Model 2.1 and Model 2.7 indicates that, when
strongUN is controlled for, the coefficient on nonunops is slightly more than
168 per cent of the equivalent result when no controls for UN operations are
in place, at 0.4542 compared to 0.2698, while its standard error decreases,
from 0.3119 to 0.3059, an almost two per cent reduction. Second, this effect
appears to be particular to the relationship between non-UN operations and
the category of multidimensional and enforcement UN operations. A com-
parison between Model 2.1 and Model 2.8 shows that the coefficient on
nonUN, denoting the presence or absence of any kind of non-UN peace
operation, in fact decreases once the strongUN control is added. Additionally,
the point estimates of the non-UN operation coefficients change systematic-
ally from Models 1.3 and 1.4 to Models 2.5 and 2.6. Each of these models
controls for the presence of UN operations only. However, Models 2.5 and
2.6 drop the undivided sovereignty requirement from the coding of the
dependent variable while Models 1.3 and 1.4 include this. These results may
suggest that non-UN operations act to freeze the situation on the ground
rather than re-establishing undivided sovereignty in the country receiving the
intervention.
Models 2.1 and 2.2 look at how changing the control for natural resources
affects the results. Whether we control for the ratio of primary commodity
exports to GDP (isxp2) or oil export dependence (oil), our results are
unaffected. Model 2.3 drops the control for non-UN operations to establish a
baseline with which to compare other results. Models 2.5 and 2.6 use any UN
intervention as a control and consider both operationalizations of non-UN
operations. Finally, Models 2.7 and 2.8 drop the controls for UN operations
and just look at strong non-UN operations or the presence of any non-UN
operation, but non-UN missions do not “soak up” the significance of UN
missions in those regressions. Thus, any interaction between UN and non-
UN missions runs in the direction of non-UN missions enhancing the effects
of UN missions.
Next, we examine different components of participatory peace at the two-
Table 11.3 The effect of UN and non-UN peace operations on participatory peace, without the undivided sovereignty criterion
Models
Explanatory variables 2.1 2.2 2.3 2.4 2.5 2.6 2.7 2.8
Peace operations
Multidim PKO and enforce 2.7395 2.6299 2.3487 – – – – –
(StrongUN) (0.9457) (0.9398) (0.8667)
UN enforcement – – −0.9456 – – – –
(Enforce) (0.8502)
Any UN intervention – – – – 1.9956 1.9843 – –
(Unintrvn) (0.6309) (0.6266)
Strong non-UN 0.4542 0.2702 – 0.0622 0.1353 – 0.2698 –
(Nonunops) (0.3059) (0.3444) (0.3550) (0.2978) – (0.3119)
Any non-UN mission – – – – – 0.4360 – 0.6641
(NonUN) (0.7205) (0.7026)
Level of hostility
Ethnic war −1.0374 −0.9299 −0.9678 −0.8822 −1.0627 −1.0473 −0.9873 −0.9548
(Wartype) (0.4752) (0.4700) (0.4650) (0.4586) (0.4644) (0.4656) (0.4604) (0.4595)
Deaths and displaced −0.2525 −0.2964 −0.2234 −0.2623 −0.2684 −0.2652 0.2182 −0.2111
Log (Logcost) (0.1066) (0.1127) (0.1087) (0.1043) (0.1140) (0.1127) (0.0986) (0.0987)
Number of factions −0.3622 −0.3535 −0.3212 −0.1829 −0.3666 −0.3706 −0.1845 −0.1964
(Factnum) (0.1880) (0.1764) (0.1934) (0.1594) (0.2214) (0.2169) (0.1663) (0.1695)
Signed peace treaty 0.9159 0.8572 1.0263 1.2471 0.9754 0.9443 1.2922 1.2445
(Treaty) (0.6355) (0.6568) (0.6454) (0.6189) (0.6468) (0.6621) (0.5977) (0.6211)
Local capacities
Electricity consumption with 0.0011 0.0014 0.0012 0.0013 0.0010 0.0009 0.0010 0.0010
missing values imputed (Idev1)
(0.0003) (0.0004) (0.0003) (0.0003) (0.0003) (0.0003) (0.0003) (0.0003)
(Continued overleaf )
Table 11.3 Continued.
Models
Explanatory variables 2.1 2.2 2.3 2.4 2.5 2.6 2.7 2.8
Logistic regression; reported are coefficients and robust standard errors in parentheses; bold indicates significance at the 0.05 level; italics indicate significance at
the 0.05 level with one-tailed test.
Interventions in civil wars: a comparison 267
year evaluation point. We consider war recurrence (warend2) alone, and then
war recurrence and residual violence (warnoviol2). Table 11.4 presents our
results.
Neither UN nor non-UN peace operations have a statistically significant
effect if we look only at war recurrence (Models 3.1 and 3.2). Strong UN
operations, however, have a positive statistically significant effect on no war
recurrence and no residual violence (Models 3.3 and 3.4). Here, the effect
of strong UN operations is significant at the 0.05 level with a single-tailed
test in Model 3.3 and significant at the 0.05 level in Model 3.5. We return
to this result when we look at war recurrence in the longer term, using
survival analysis methods that allow us to account for the right-censoring
effect that is inherent in the coding of our dependent variable in the logit
regressions.
Finally, we consider sovereign peace (pbs2lr) rather than any version of
participatory peace. These results are presented as Table 11.5. Here, as in
Tables 11.2 and 11.3 we see that strong UN operations have a positive, statis-
tically significant effect on peacebuilding (here, sovereign peace). Non-UN
operations, however operationalized, still do not have a statistically signifi-
cant effect on the measure of peacebuilding.
Immediately of note considering all the results is that non-UN peace oper-
ations do not have the effect hypothesized in any of the short-run models. The
coefficients of the three non-UN variables, across all specifications of the
model, are not statistically significant. We have confirmed that non-UN mis-
sions are not significant using alternative estimation methods for the short
run (propensity score matching and selection models) and they also apply to
long-term models (survival models of the duration of the peace).
One complication is that it is often difficult to clearly distinguish biased
military interventions by non-UN actors from peacekeeping interventions. In
the case of UN intervention, the article of the Charter which authorizes those
interventions allows us to make this classification, and the rules of engage-
ment as well as the mandate of the mission are often quite different if the UN
mission is authorized under Chapter VII of the UN Charter as compared to
Chapter VI (no consent is required in the former). In non-UN missions, it is
harder to make this distinction and this is consequential, since partial inter-
vention may well have different effects than impartial intervention. Some
(Regan 2002) have shown that partial military intervention prolongs the dur-
ation of civil war, for example. Sorting out those non-UN peace missions that
had a clear enforcement mandate and could therefore more easily be con-
fused with war-making rather than peacekeeping, we found that the results
on non-UN peace missions did not change and even consent-based non-UN
peacekeeping did not have a significant impact on any of the ways that we
used to code peacebuilding success.
Average numbers of deaths and displacements, levels of development,
numbers of factions, and net current transfers are roughly equal in cases of
UN and non-UN peace missions as compared to the null category in each
268 Nicholas Sambanis and Jonah Schulhofer-Wohl
Dependent variable
Models
Explanatory variables 3.1 3.2 3.3 3.4
Peace operations
Multidimensional PKO and 1.1891 1.3339 1.8791 2.0805
enforce (StrongUN)
(1.1132) (1.1448) (0.9934) (1.0534)
Strong non-UN (Nonunops) −0.0500 – 0.1619 –
(0.2324) – (0.2366) –
Any non-UN mission – 0.2184 – 0.7066
(NonUN)
– (0.5288) – (0.5626)
Level of hostility
Ethnic war (Wartype) −0.0941 −0.0889 −0.3143 −0.2850
(0.4623) (0.4641) (0.3691) (0.3696)
Deaths and displaced log −0.2303 −0.2368 −0.1289 0.1311
(Logcost)
(0.1343) (0.1348) (0.1044) (0.1027)
Number of factions (Factnum) −0.2400 −0.2572 −0.3542 −0.3819
(0.1308) (0.1253) (0.1395) (0.1297)
Signed peace treaty (Treaty) −0.7356 −0.7879 0.1241 0.0318
(0.5133) (0.5074) (0.4930) (0.5071)
Local capacities
Electricity consumption with 0.0007 0.0006 0.0007 0.0006
missing values imputed (Idev1)
(0.0004) (0.0004) (0.0003) (0.0003)
Primary commodity exports/ −2.6247 −2.6752 −2.6838 −2.7680
GDP (Isxp2)
(1.2698) (1.2884) (1.7769) (1.8438)
Oil export dependence (Oil) – – – –
– – – –
Other international capacities
Net transfers per capita 4.33e–06 4.13e–06 5.82e–06 5.43e–06
(Transpop)
(2.81e–06) (2.69e–06) (4.91e–05) (4.45e–06)
Constant 4.7218 4.8116 2.5196 2.5815
(1.6954) (1.7033) (1.0952) (1.0806)
Observations 119 119 119 119
Pseudo-R2 18.79% 18.86% 17.05% 17.78%
Log-likelihood −58.54 −58.49 −68.41 −67.82
Logistic regression; reported are coefficients and robust standard errors in parentheses; bold
indicates significance at the 0.05 level; italics indicate significance at the 0.05 level with one-tailed
test.
Interventions in civil wars: a comparison 269
Table 11.5 The effect of UN and non-UN peace operations on sovereign peace
Models
Peace operations
Multidim. PKO and enforce (StrongUN) 2.1437 2.3773
(1.0448) (1.0907)
Any UN (Unintrvn) – –
– –
Strong non-UN (Nonunops) −0.2149 –
(0.2908) –
Any non-UN (NonUN) – 0.1518
– (0.5184)
Level of hostilities
Ethnic war (Wartype) −0.8230 −0.8245
(0.4408) (0.4439)
Deaths and displaced natural log (Logcost) −0.1751 −0.1817
(0.1071) (0.1039)
Number of factions (Factnum) −0.5652 −0.5884
(0.1823) (0.1807)
Signed peace treaty (Treaty) 0.7204 0.6181
(0.5326) (0.5329)
Local capacities
Electricity consumption with missing values 0.0002 0.0002
imputed (Idev1)
(0.0003) (0.0003)
Primary commodity exports/GDP (Isxp2) −4.5695 −4.7591
(2.9392) (3.0470)
Other international capacities
Net transfers per capita (Transpop) 4.57e–06 4.29e–06
(2.14e–06) (2.17e–06)
Constant 4.1604 4.2488
(1.1313) (1.1034)
Observations 119 119
Pseudo-R2 22.87% 22.55%
Log-likelihood −63.07 −63.33
Logistic regression; reported are coefficients and robust standard errors in parentheses; bold
indicates significance at the 0.05 level; italics indicate significance at the 0.05 level with one-tailed
test.
case; and non-UN missions are no more likely than UN missions to intervene
in harder-to-resolve ethno-religious wars or in wars with more factions. So, it
does not seem to be the case that the relative ineffectiveness of non-UN
peacekeeping is because non-UN missions become involved in harder con-
flicts, with a lower ex ante probability of success.39 Also, comparing mean
values of the other covariates for strong peace missions only again does
not reveal any systematic difference between UN and non-UN missions. For
270 Nicholas Sambanis and Jonah Schulhofer-Wohl
example, average levels of development and primary commodity export
dependence are about the same in cases of UN and non-UN enforcement.40
Some indicators of the levels of hostility point to a harder peacebuilding
ecology in cases of non-UN enforcement. For example, deaths and displace-
ments are somewhat higher for non-UN enforcement cases. But other hostil-
ity indicators point in the opposite direction: the number of factions, for
example, is not significantly different in UN and non-UN cases; and UN
enforcement has been used exclusively in ethno-religious wars, which are
harder to resolve, while the same is not true for non-UN peace missions.
Thus, in terms of our earlier theoretical discussion, summarized in Table
11.1, it is not clear that the reason for the differential effectiveness of UN and
non-UN missions is any major difference in assigning the right mandate to
the right case. This comparison, however, is complicated by the fact that non-
UN missions do not field multidimensional missions, so we are left with
comparing enforcement missions here (and we could do the same for observer
missions). But the fact that non-UN missions are missing this valuable com-
bination of limited enforcement and civilian administration that we find in
UN multidimensional missions can by itself help explain at least part of the
difference in the relative effectiveness of UN and non-UN missions. Since
that multidimensional mandate is judged to be necessary in some conditions
– where local capacities are low and hostility is high, while a peace treaty
forges some degree of local consent for international assistance – the fact that
non-UN peace missions have not responded with such a multidimensional
mandate can be considered a strategic failure that could explain at least par-
tially the results that we have presented here.
We should return, however, to our earlier discussion of a possible inter-
action effect between non-UN and UN operations (see discussion of Table
11.3). We looked more closely at that by separating non-UN missions in
which advanced industrialized countries and/or countries with advanced
militaries participated, and all others. “Advanced” country missions include
missions with troops from the United States, Europe, Canada, Australia,
New Zealand, and CIS countries; 25 out of 44 non-UN missions are from the
group of “advanced” countries. If we replace our control for non-UN mis-
sions with one that counts only those 25, we find no substantive change in the
results with respect to participatory peace, which is not surprising because
those missions typically focused on monitoring and/or enforcement and not
on building capacities for self-sustaining peace (see Table 11.6, Model 5.1).
With respect to war recurrence alone, those missions are also non-significant
(p-value is 0.105), but they are much more significant than UN missions and
have double the coefficient (Model 5.2).
When we turn to a longer-term analysis of war recurrence using survival
models, we find that UN missions are in fact effective in preventing war
recurrence (see Table 11.7, Model 6.1) whereas non-UN missions are not (p-
value = 0.11; Model 6.2). But, when we add both together, they become much
more significant both jointly and individually (Model 6.3). The reason that
Interventions in civil wars: a comparison 271
Models
Peace operations
Any UN (Unintrvn) 1.8324 0.7857
(0.7657) (0.6967)
Militarily advanced non-UN (nonUNdev) 0.3878 1.4785
(0.8725) (0.9122)
Level of hostilities
Ethnic war (Wartype) −1.6237 −0.1498
(0.5454) (0.4904)
Deaths and displaced natural log (Logcost) −0.3423 −0.2754
(0.1288 (0.1207)
Number of factions (Factnum) −0.5598 −0.2531
(0.2559) (0.1530)
Signed peace treaty (Treaty) 1.6460 −0.6548
(0.6391) (0.5450)
Local capacities
Electricity consumption with missing values 0.0004 0.0004
imputed (Idev1)
(0.0004) (0.0005)
Primary commodity exports/GDP (Isxp2) −7.8817 −3.1213
(3.0456) (1.5620)
Other international capacities
Net transfers per capita (Transpop) 2.72e–06 3.64e–06
(1.82e–06) (2.75e–06)
Constant 5.4456 5.2836
(1.6263) (1.5271)
Observations 119 119
Pseudo-R2 32.36% 20.57%
Log-likelihood −49.89 −57.26
Logistic regression; reported are coefficients and robust standard errors in parentheses; bold
indicates significance at the 0.05 level; italics indicate significance at the 0.05 level with one-tailed
test.
Models
Peace operations
Any UN (Unintrvn) 0.4746 – 0.4122
(0.1527) – (0.1273)
Militarily advanced non-UN – 0.4127 0.3548
(nonUNdev)
– (0.2277) (0.1975)
Level of hostilities
Ethnic war (Wartype) 1.4318 1.3090 1.2702
(0.3841) (0.3262) (0.3045)
Deaths and displaced natural log 1.1111 1.1248 1.1362
(Logcost)
(0.0698) (0.0735) (0.0752)
Number of factions (Factnum) 1.0808 1.0673 1.1135
(0.0915) (0.0943) (0.0783)
Signed peace treaty (Treaty) 1.1596 0.9553 1.2377
(0.3438) (0.2170) (0.2853)
Local capacities
Annual rate of growth of GDP 0.9602 0.9594 0.9566
(gdpgrof1) (0.0111) (0.0101) (0.0112)
Cox regression; reported are hazard ratios and robust standard errors clustered by country in
parentheses; bold indicates significance at the 0.05 level; italics indicate significance at the 0.05
level with one-tailed test.
the technical capacity and enforcement potential of the mission and would
have given a clear signal of international interest, which could help explain
why success was more likely in those cases.
So we see more evidence in favor of a mutually reinforcing relationship
between UN and non-UN missions, if those missions come from countries
with the resources and technical capacities to keep the peace. The fact that the
effects of non-UN missions are restricted to preventing a resumption of
violence and do not extend to higher-order, participatory peace leads us to
Interventions in civil wars: a comparison 273
conclude that there should be a division of labor in peacebuilding missions,
with the UN performing the capacity-building functions while enforcement
and policing are delegated to missions from advanced countries.
Notes
1 Bellamy and Williams (2005); see also United Nations (2005).
2 See the results of our Models 2.1, 2.9 and 2.10.
3 See Diehl (1993) for an excellent summary of these concerns in the case of regional
and multi-national operations and also Weiss, Forsythe, and Coate (2004).
4 For examples, see Mason and Fett (1996); Regan (1996, 2000, 2002); Balch-
Lindsay and Enterline (2000); Elbadawi and Sambanis (2000); Siquiera (2003);
and A. Smith and Stam (2003).
5 See Barnett (1997) and Claude (1966).
6 See Paris (2002) for a discussion of understanding the UN in this light.
7 See, for example, complaints about sexual abuse by UN peacekeepers in Burundi,
Congo, Haiti, Ivory Coast, Kosovo, Liberia, and Sierra Leone (C. Lynch, “Offi-
cials Acknowledge ‘Swamp’ of Problems and Pledge Fixes Amid New Allega-
tions in Africa, Haiti.” Washington Post, 13 March 2005, p. A22) and complaints
about organizational malfeasance at headquarters during the Rwandan genocide
(Gourevitch 1998).
8 A good example is given by several UN missions where a consent-based mandate
was eventually transformed into an enforcement mandate due to the parties’ lack
of co-operation, which often stemmed from the parties’ realization that the UN
would be an obstacle to their aims (since, if the UN maintains the status quo in a
situation where one of the parties believes that it can change the status quo
through the use of force, then it follows that the UN’s impact is not “impartial” in
the ordinary sense of the term since it benefits the parties that are more committed
to the peace). There are also other examples where the UN’s motives for interven-
ing are doubted by one or more of the parties. For accounts of Patrice Lumumba’s
Interventions in civil wars: a comparison 275
accusations that ONUC was acting on behalf of the CIA, see Doyle and Sambanis
(2006).
9 A test of the proposition that UN operations are more effective because they carry
greater legitimacy is difficult because we cannot measure the legitimacy of the
intervening party directly. A conceivable test of this proposition would be to con-
sider legitimacy as the residual category. We would then need to be able to capture
all other differences between UN and non-UN operations. If a difference in the
efficacy of UN and non-UN operations persists, we might then be able to attribute
it to legitimacy.
10 See Morrow (1994) and Kreps (1990) for a precise definition of co-ordination and
collaboration games.
11 For a summary see Keohane and Axelrod (1986).
12 Regional powers can play this role, if organized by an impartial party with broad
legitimacy. See Doyle, Johnstone and Orr (1997) for a discussion of the role played
by the “Friends of the Secretary-General” in the El Salvador negotiations.
13 By contrast, even in finite, yet multiple-iteration games, if the timing of the game’s
end is not known, players can be expected to play as if they were engaged in an
infinite horizon game. But if the endgame is visible, then finite game strategies will
be used.
14 As an impartial third party, the UN cannot formally exclude parties from negoti-
ations. The inclusion of the Khmer Rouge in the negotiations leading to the Paris
Accords over the Cambodian civil war is a case in point. Moreover, exclusion of
parties from the terms of the settlement can generate grievances that lead to
renewed fighting.
15 See Bass (2000); and, for the difficulties, Snyder and Vinjamuri (2003–4).
16 Strong peacekeeping is different from peace enforcement. Strong peacekeeping can
only deter or punish occasional violations. If the violations are systematic and
large-scale, a no-consent enforcement operation might be necessary.
17 One civil war in the dataset started in 1944, but all peace processes started after
1945.
18 In a few cases, a war was ongoing in 1999, but a serious peace effort had taken
place earlier (and obviously failed). Those cases are included, but the analysis
remains robust if they are dropped.
19 These are cases where a military victory fails to end the war (e.g., Afghanistan in
1992) or where the UN intervenes to end the fighting, but fails (e.g., Angola; Sierra
Leone; Somalia). We do not include any peace processes that started after 31
December 1999 and this causes us to lose a few UN missions (e.g., UNAMA in
Afghanistan; MONUC in the Democratic Republic of the Congo (DRC);
UNAMSIL in Sierra Leone).
20 Sambanis (2004) contains an extensive discussion of the definition of civil war
used in these data.
21 Details on the coding of war resumption are given for each country in the online
supplement to Doyle and Sambanis (2006) and in comments inserted in their
dataset.
22 See, e.g., Gleditsch et al. (2001).
23 This uses the Polity dataset (version 2000). For the years in which Polity scores are
missing (i.e., they indicate regime transition or war in the country), scores are
interpolated. The “Polity2” series of the 2002 version of the database is already
interpolated by the Polity database coders (Marshall and Jaggers 2004).
24 This is computed as democracy (ranging from 0 to 10) plus 10 minus autocracy
(also ranging from 0 to 10).
25 These are all cases where the UN has not yet failed by any of the criteria. So,
dropping them from the analysis should make it harder to find significant effects
for UN missions.
276 Nicholas Sambanis and Jonah Schulhofer-Wohl
26 Two of these cases are dropped due to missing data in our models, but can be
included in other specifications if imputed values are used for some of the
covariates.
27 Using a five-year cutoff point, there would be 74 participatory peace failures and
35 successes; and 58 sovereign failures and 51 successes. Doyle and Sambanis
(2006) also code an alternative version of PBS, where all ambiguous cases are
either dropped (if the criteria for coding a civil war may not be met) or re-coded as
the opposite outcome (if the initial coding of PB outcome was questionable). For
participatory peace two years after the war, the alternative version has 78 failures
and 25 successes (for a total of 103 observations).
28 Since there is a large variance in this variable, the natural log is used. Deaths and
displacements are combined. Doyle and Sambanis (2006) provide comments and
sources for the coding of each case in their online supplement in the document
labeled “Civil War coding” and as comments in the spreadsheet and single-record
version of their dataset.
29 See Sambanis (2002). There is not much documentation in the literature for the
classification of wars into “ethnic” or “non-ethnic” varieties. Doyle and Sambanis
(2006) use their own coding, based on a set of detailed notes on each conflict, to test
the robustness of the original Wartype variable used in Doyle and Sambanis (2000).
30 Doyle and Sambanis (2006) post supplementary information online, including a
comparison of the coding of Treaty across several datasets for cases shared in
common. The definition of treaty is different from that in Doyle and Sambanis
(2000). Where coding differs from the coding of other authors, they provide a
summary explanation, including a description of the case and excerpts from the
actual treaty text.
31 This measure is highly correlated with income: 77.67 per cent with Fearon and
Laitin’s (2003) income series (gdpen) and 79.78 per cent with the income series
(aclplvs) in Przeworski et al. (2000).
32 This variable is sometimes measured several years away from the war’s start or
end. Doyle and Sambanis (2006) used data from the IMF’s International Finan-
cial Statistics to code this variable. See IMF (various years).
33 Mandates should be correlated with numbers of troops and budgets for UN mis-
sions. Sometimes they are not, which indicates planning failure at the level of the
Security Council.
34 Unmandate includes peacekeeping and enforcement mandates as well as serious
efforts at peacemaking and mediation that are not followed up by a peacekeeping
operation. The variable untype excludes cases of mediation.
35 These were cases of UN mediation or peacemaking without, however, a follow-up
peacekeeping mission.
36 There is little ambiguity about the coding of UN mandate types. Doyle and Sam-
banis (2006) discuss this issue in detail in their supplement. The results are robust
to recoding several cases according to suggestions made by other scholars or in
cases where Doyle and Sambanis (2006) thought the mandate was ambiguous, and
are sometimes better.
37 See the online supplement for Doyle and Sambanis (2006) for a list of supporting
documents, including summaries of the mandate, list of functions actually per-
formed by each mission, information on changes in mission mandate over time,
and copies of relevant UN documents.
38 The cases of non-UN third-party peace operations and information on these mis-
sions (names, deployment dates, departure dates, and mandates) are given in the
online supplement to Doyle and Sambanis (2006).
39 This is evident by comparing the results of equality of means tests for all the
variables in the model, sorted by UN intervention and then by non-UN
intervention.
Interventions in civil wars: a comparison 277
40 There are only a few cases to compare: the average (with 6 cases) for UN missions
is .17 while for non-UN (17 cases) it is .18. Electricity consumption per capita
levels are also about the same (608 versus 633 kWh).
41 For an interesting effort, see Heldt (2001), who coded whether the force com-
mander of a UN operation was from the same ethnic group as the majority of the
population in the war-affected country. The difficulty here would be to ascertain if
the selection effect is overcome by coding the identity of the force commander. In
some cases, such high-level assignments may be random, yet in others they may
well reflect an assessment at headquarters of the likely effect of the force com-
mander’s identity on the prospects for successful discharge of the peacekeepers’
mandate.
Appendix to Chapter 11
A: Coding criteria for civil wars (from Doyle and Sambanis 2006)
An armed conflict is classified as a civil war if:
a. The war takes place within the territory of a state that is a member of the
international systemi with a population of 500,000 or greater.ii
b. The parties are politically and militarily organized and they have publicly-
stated political objectives.iii
c. The government (through its military or militias) must be a principal com-
batant. If there is no functioning government, then the party representing
the government internationally and/or claiming the state domestically
must be involved as a combatant.iv
i This includes states that are occupying foreign territories that are claiming independence
(e.g., West Bank and Gaza in Israel, and Western Sahara in Morocco). A strict application
of this coding rule could drop those cases where the international community (through the
UN) rejects the state’s claims of sovereignty on the occupied territories.
ii Countries could be included after their population reaches the 500,000 mark, or from the
start of the period if population exceeds the 500,000 mark at some point in the country series.
If a civil war occurs in a country with population below the threshold, we could include it and
flag it as a marginal case. Cases of civil war close to the 500,000 mark are Cyprus in 1963
(578,000 population) and Djibouti in 1991 (450,000 population). Use of a per capita death
threshold to code civil war would allow the population threshold to be relaxed.
iii This should apply to the majority of the parties in the conflict. This criterion distinguishes
insurgent groups and political parties from criminal gangs and riotous mobs. But the dis-
tinction between criminal and political violence may fade in some countries (e.g., Colombia
after 1993). “Terrorist” organizations would qualify as insurgent groups according to this
coding rule, if they caused violence at the required levels for war (see other criteria). Non-
combatant populations that are often victimized in civil wars are not considered a “party” to
the war if they are not organized in a militia or other such form, able to apply violence in
pursuit of their political objectives.
iv Extensive indirect support (monetary, organizational, or military) by the government to
militias might also satisfy this criterion (an example is Kenya during the ethnic clashes in the
Rift Valley). However, in such cases it becomes harder to distinguish civil war from com-
munal violence. In other cases, where the state has collapsed, it may not be possible to identify
parties representing the state as all parties may be claiming the state and these conflicts will
also be hard to distinguish from inter-communal violence (e.g., Somalia after 1991).
278 Nicholas Sambanis and Jonah Schulhofer-Wohl
d. The main insurgent organization(s) must be locally represented and must
recruit locally. Additional external involvement and recruitment need not
imply that the war is not intra-state.v Insurgent groups may operate from
neighboring countries, but they must also have some territorial control
(bases) in the civil war country and/or the rebels must reside in the civil
war country.vi
e. The start year of the war is the first year that the conflict causes at least
500–1,000 deaths.vii If the conflict has not caused 500 deaths or more in the
first year, the war is coded as having started in that year only if cumula-
tive deaths in the next three years reach 1,000.viii
f. Throughout its duration, the conflict must be characterized by sustained
violence at least at the minor or intermediate level. There should be no
three-year period during which the conflict causes fewer than 500 deaths.ix
g. Throughout the war, the weaker party must be able to mount effective
resistance. Effective resistance is measured by at least 100 deaths inflicted
on the stronger party. A substantial number of these deaths must occur
in the first year of the war.x But if the violence becomes effectively one-
v Intra-state war can be taking place at the same time as inter-state war.
vi This rule weeds out entirely inter-state conflicts with no local participation. The Bay of Pigs,
for example, would be excluded as a civil war because the rebels did not have a base in Cuba
prior to the invasion. Some cases stretch the limits of this definitional criterion: e.g., Rwanda
in the late 1990s, where ex-FAR recruits with bases in the DRC engaged in incursions and
border clashes against government army and civilians. If this is a civil war, then so is the
conflict between Lebanon-based Hezbollah and Israel (assuming the other criteria are met).
vii This rule can be relaxed to a range of 100–1,000 since fighting might start late in the year (cf.
Senegal or Peru). Given the lack of high-quality data to accurately code civil war onset, if
no good estimate of deaths is available for the first year, onset can be coded at the first year
of reported large-scale armed conflict provided that violence continues or escalates in the
following years. Note that in the dataset, start/end month is also coded where possible. In
some cases, coding rules can be used to identify the start month (e.g., in cases where the war
causes 1,000 deaths in the first month of armed conflict). But in most cases, the month only
indicates the start of major armed conflict or the signing of a peace agreement, which can
gives a point of reference for the start/end of the war, respectively.
viii This rule also suggests when to code war termination if the three-year average does not add up
to 500. In such a case, the end of the war can be coded at the last year with more than 100
deaths unless one of the other rules applies (e.g., if there is a peace treaty that is followed by
more than six months of peace).
ix This criterion makes coding very difficult, as data on deaths throughout the duration of a
conflict are hard to find. However, such a coding rule is necessary to prevent one from
coding too many war starts in the same conflict or coding an ongoing civil war for years
after the violence has ended. Three years is an arbitrary cut-off point, but is consistent with
other thresholds found in the literature. Data notes (see online supplement to Doyle and
Sambanis 2006) give several examples of cases where the coding of war termination has
been determined by this criterion. A more lenient version would be a five-year threshold
with fewer than 500 deaths.
x This criterion must be proportional to the war’s intensity in the first years of the war. If the
war’s onset is coded the first year with only 100 deaths (as often happens in low-intensity
conflicts), then it would not be possible to observe effective resistance in the first year of the
war if effective resistance was defined as 100 deaths suffered by the state.
Interventions in civil wars: a comparison 279
sided, even if the aggregate effective resistance threshold of 100 deaths
has already been met, the civil war must be coded as having ended and a
politicide or other form of one-sided violence must be coded as having
started.xi
h. A peace treaty that produces at least six months of peace marks an end to
the war.xii
i. A decisive military victory by the rebels that produces a new regime should
mark the end of the war.xiii Since civil war is understood as an armed
conflict against the government, continuing armed conflict against a new
government implies a new civil war.xiv If the government wins the war, a
period of peace longer than six months must persist before we code a new
war (see also criterion k).
j. A ceasefire, truce, or simply an end to fighting mark the end of a civil war
if they result in at least two years of peace.xv The period of peace must be
longer than what is required in the case of a peace agreement, as we do
not have clear signals of the parties’ intent to negotiate an agreement in
the case of a truce/ceasefire.xvi
xi This criterion distinguishes cases in which insurgent violence was limited to the outbreak of
the war and, for the remainder of the conflict, the government engaged in one-sided violence.
A hypothetical example is a case where insurgents inflicted 100 deaths on the government
during the first week of fighting and then the government defeated the insurgents and
engaged in pogroms and politicide for several years with no or few deaths on the govern-
ment’s side. If it is not possible to apply this rule consistently to all cases (due to data
limitations), then periods of politicide at the start or end of the war should be combined with
war periods. This implies that civil wars will often be observationally equivalent to coups that
are followed by politicide, or other such sequences of different forms of political violence.
xii Treaties that do not stop the fighting are not considered (e.g., the Islamabad Accords of 1993
in Afghanistan’s war; the December 1997 agreement among Somali clan leaders). If several
insurgent groups are engaged in the war, the majority of groups must sign. This criterion is
useful for the study of peace transitions, but may not be as important if researchers are
interested in studying, for example, civil war duration.
xiii Thus, in secessionist wars that are won by the rebels who establish a new state, if a war erupts
immediately in the new state, a new war onset would be coded in the new state (an example
is Croatia in 1992–5), even if the violence is closely related to the preceding war. A continu-
ation of the old conflict between the old parties could now count as an inter-state war, as in
the case of Ethiopia and Eritrea who fought a war in 1998–2000, after Eritrea’s successful
secession from Ethiopia in 1993.
xiv This criterion allows researchers to study the stability of military victories. Analysis of the
stability of civil war outcomes would be biased if an end to civil war through military
victory was coded only when the victory was followed by a prolonged period of peace. This
would bias the results in favor of finding a positive correlation between military out-
comes and peace duration. This criterion is important to analyze war recurrence, but not
necessarily war prevalence.
xv Peace implies no battle-related deaths, or, in a lenient version of this criterion, fewer deaths
than the lowest threshold of deaths used to code war onset – i.e., fewer than 100 deaths
per year.
xvi These situations are different from those where there is no violence as a result of armies
standing down without a ceasefire agreement, which would fall under criterion f.
280 Nicholas Sambanis and Jonah Schulhofer-Wohl
k. If new parties enter the war over new issues, a new war onset should be
coded, subject to the same operational criteria.xvii If the same parties return
to war over the same issues we generally code the continuation of the old
war, unless any of the above criteria for coding a war end apply for the
period before the resurgence of fighting.
Using these coding rules, Doyle and Sambanis (2006) code 145 civil war
starts from 1944 to 1999 (2.08 per cent of 6,966 non-missing observations in
an annual frequency time-series cross-sectional dataset, covering 161 coun-
tries). Without coding new war onsets in countries with already ongoing civil
wars, the number of civil wars is 119 (1.93 per cent of 6,153 non-missing
observations). Out of these cases, 20 may be called “ambiguous” – that is, they
may not meet one or more of the coding rules. Doyle and Sambanis (2006) con-
sider these as sufficiently close to the concept of civil war as to include them
in the analysis.
xvii These incompatibilities must be significantly different or the wars must be fought by different
groups in different regions of the country. For example, three partially overlapping wars
would be coded in Ethiopia (Tigrean, Eritrean, Oromo) from the 1970s to the 1990s. New
issues alone should not be sufficient to code a new war, as there is no “issue-based” classifica-
tion in the definition of civil war. Such a rule could be applied if civil wars were classified
into categories – e.g., secessionist wars versus revolutions over control of the state. In
addition to having new issues, most parties must also be new before a new war onset can be
coded.
Appendix to Chapter 11
B: Civil wars starting in 1945–1999 and short-run peacebuilding outcomes*
Country War start War end Sovereign Participatory Type of UN operation Type of non-UN
peace peace operation
Country War start War end Sovereign Participatory Type of UN operation Type of non-UN
peace peace operation
Country War start War end Sovereign Participatory Type of UN operation Type of non-UN
peace peace operation
Country War start War end Sovereign Participatory Type of UN operation Type of non-UN
peace peace operation
* Note: This list includes some cases that are not included in the analysis. Ongoing wars, for example, are excluded. The USSR wars are excluded due to missing
data in several of our variables, and because they started before the start of our analysis period. There are some differences between our civil war list and some
others in the literature.
12 Why no UN Security
Council reform?
Lessons for and from
institutionalist theory
Erik Voeten
This chapter is based on the premise that institutional reform and the absence
thereof are revealing about the effects of institutional design on outcomes, or
at least how governments perceive these effects to be. In the past fifteen years,
we have witnessed major institutional reforms and innovations in the inter-
national arena. The EU broadened, deepened, and moved increasingly
towards a supranational decision-making structure. NATO accepted ten new
member states and modernized its military command structure. The inter-
national trade system was transformed fundamentally by the replacement of
GATT with the World Trade Organization (WTO) and its highly legalized
dispute-resolution mechanism. The World Bank responded to pressure by
non-governmental organizations (NGOs) and others to formally incorporate
environmental issues into their decision-making procedures (Nielson and
Tierney 2003). And, the creation of the International Criminal Court (ICC)
and the Kyoto Protocol, while not embraced universally, signal that there
is considerable appetite in many parts of the globe for new and extended
institutional solutions to global issues.
At the same time, some institutional configurations have remained remark-
ably stable. The UN Security Council (UNSC) is an important example.
What makes the UNSC’s institutional persistence so interesting is that its
activities have changed rather dramatically with the Cold War’s ending. The
Council has not only initiated many more sanctions and peacekeeping
missions, but it has also broadened the scope of what it can do – at times not
shying away from authorizing the use of force to topple regimes. Moreover,
states, including great powers, are paying more attention to the UNSC than
ever before. Whereas the absence or presence of UN authorization had little
bearing on the use of force in the Cold War period, the absence of such
authorization is now widely lamented and appears to affect the depth and
breadth of multilateral co-operation in a non-trivial manner (Voeten 2005).
This upsurge in activity has not been paired with a “constitutive moment”
similar to what occurred at the ends of World Wars I and II. At those
junctures, multilateral security institutions were purposively designed by the
Why no UN Security Council reform? 289
victors of the latest grand war, perhaps with the objective to “lock in”
favorable institutional structures that would outlast the immediate power
advantages that resulted from the last war (Ikenberry 2001). The UNSC is the
quintessential example of this: it granted permanent membership and veto
power to the five “victors” of World War II, while excluding the defeated
powers1 and raising an entry barrier for potential rising powers.
The antiquated nature of the UNSC’s institutional structure has invited
incessant calls for institutional reform,2 varying from carefully crafted diplo-
matic proposals to Thomas Friedman’s cavalier suggestion that veto powers
ought to be elected by the fans of the UN such that France could be “voted
off the island”.3 Discussing the latest reform effort, the December 2004 report
by the High-Level Panel on Threats, Challenges, and Change (hereafter: the
High-Level Panel), UN Secretary-General Kofi Annan argued that this is
“most decisive moment for the international system since the UN was founded
in 1945.”4 Yet, while governments have expressed consensus support to make
the UNSC “more representative, efficient and transparent” in numerous
anniversary UNGA (General Assembly) resolutions,5 the issue has barely
advanced beyond discussions by blue-ribbon committees and low-level dip-
lomats.6 Bruce Russett captures the general sentiment well: “been there and
not done that” (Russett 2005: 155).
Why has the activity of the UNSC increased so much, but its institutional
structure changed so little? The typical answers are that the end of the Cold
War allowed the UNSC to become more active, while the persistence of the
UNSC’s institutional structure can be attributed to institutional “stickiness.”
These accounts are not entirely inaccurate. Yet, they are limited. Most
importantly, if institutional design matters, then it is problematic to rely on a
theory that privileges continuity to explain institutional design while singling
out a massive exogenous shock as the explanation for increased activity. Insti-
tutionalists argue that fundamental institutional change generally occurs
in response to an exogenous shock that undermines the mechanisms that
generate continuity (e.g., Pierson 2000). The end of the Cold War represents
precisely the kind of external shock that could be expected to lead to a
“critical juncture” for institutional change (Ikenberry 2001). Moreover, the
very same factors that created an increased demand for multilateralism are
likely to also create a demand for institutional adjustments. If the relevance
of the end of the Cold War resides in a normative shift towards a set of global
liberal norms that generate new demand for multilateralism, then we would
surely expect this normative shift to be reflected in institutional changes. If
the end of the Cold War is relevant primarily for the shift in the balance of
power (or threats), then we would expect the institutional structure of the
UNSC to be adjusted to that new power structure.
In this chapter, I evaluate various plausible explanations for the UNSC’s
institutional persistence in the context of its increased activity. I argue that in
order to understand these issues, we need a fuller appreciation of how the
UNSC fits in its strategic environment. Strategic explanations should fare
290 Erik Voeten
well in the context of the UNSC: there are relatively few actors, with well-
defined interests, bargaining over high stakes. Yet, analyses of the UN tend to
assume away strategic behavior7 and/or look at the UN in isolation from the
outside world. As Stanley Hoffmann put it:
I argue that the UNSC forms an institutional solution to two sets of prob-
lems that arise from the incompleteness of any contract that seeks to regulate
uses of force, while not outright forbidding them. The UNSC is asked to
make decisions on whether particular uses of force by states are appropriate
and if (and how much) collective action should be produced in response to
threats to international peace and security. From the perspective of insti-
tutional design, this solution is sub-optimal. The task of determining the
appropriateness of interventions is best delegated to an independent (neutral)
institution, such as a court, and the determination of public good production
to a majoritarian (political) institution. Yet, the optimality of such a dual
institutional solution collapses once we take into account the problem of
enforcement: the UNSC cannot actually prevent individual states from going
it alone in the absence of its blessing. Moreover, the willingness of individual
states to go it alone can sometimes be critical for the production of collective
goods.
I show how this availability of outside options profoundly affects issues of
institutional design, and thus, reform. Perhaps most importantly, it curtails
the extent to which formal institutional power translates into “real world”
power. Analyses of formal bargaining power in the UNSC typically conclude
that the veto players distribute the gains equally among themselves and that
non-permanent members are virtually powerless (e.g., O’Neill 1997; Winter
1996). If this were true, there would be little reason for non-permanent
members to abide by UNSC decisions and help finance peacekeeping oper-
ations. Moreover, veto powers that possess more outside options have greater
bargaining power than veto powers that have fewer resources, despite equal
institutional status. Hence, in practice, informal decision-making practices
reflect asymmetric capabilities, even if these are not reflected in the UNSC’s
formal institutional structure. This chapter then, points to the limits of the
expected effects of formal institutions, and thus institutional reform, in the
context of enforcement problems.
The chapter proceeds with a brief sketch of the increase in UNSC activity
following the end of the Cold War or, perhaps more accurately, the start of
Why no UN Security Council reform? 291
the first Gulf War. It then discusses various common explanations for insti-
tutional persistence. The following sections introduce the issues that arise in
delegating decisions regarding uses of force to an international institution
and provide some simple illustrations of how outside power affects bargain-
ing in an institution such as the UNSC. The chapter concludes with some
implications for institutionalist theory, as well as for the debates surrounding
UNSC reform.
Self-defense
The self-defense exception is open to ex post opportunism: states may and
frequently do resort to expanded conceptions of self-defense in attempts to
justify unilateral uses of force (Schachter 1989). This issue could potentially
be resolved by assigning an independent institution, such as a court, the task
to evaluate the validity of the claims for self-defense. This has not occurred.
There is little impetus in the High-Level Panel Report16 or elsewhere to grant
the ICJ a greater role in this regard nor does the Panel favor rewriting
Article 51 to identify more precisely when uses of self-defense are permitted.
The Panel’s treatment of the issue (paragraphs 188–192) pertains mostly to
the question of whether preventive uses of force could be justified under
Article 51, which the Panel rejects. The discussion is a thinly disguised judg-
ment that the US invasion of Iraq was illegal. The Panel is clearly worried
about the erosion of a norm (“allowing one to so act is to allow all”) but
offers no suggestion for institutional reform other than to point to the neces-
sity of UNSC authorization for such actions.
The UNSC has little formal authority on this matter. States must report
298 Erik Voeten
self-defense uses of force to the UN – something that they have not always
done (Schachter 1989). The Council is not, however, assigned the task of
assessing the legitimacy of self-defense claims. In practice, however, states do
behave “as if ” Council authorization makes questionable uses of the self-
defense concept more acceptable, as illustrated by Resolution 1373, which
reaffirms the right of the United States to act forcefully in its self-defense
against terrorist activities and de facto legitimized the US military action in
Afghanistan.17
Presumably, governments care about UNSC resolutions authorizing force
in the name of self-defense because they are concerned about their general
reputation for upholding norms and rules that regulate uses of force. They
may do so out of an inherent appreciation for these norms, to please domestic
publics, or because they believe that others are more likely to co-operate with
states that show a general inclination to comply with rules and norms. One
should be aware, however, that the judgment whether a particular use of self-
defense is permitted is ultimately a political one and not subject to judicial
review. Thus, one should not expect judgments that are independent or con-
sistent from a legal perspective and it is not entirely clear what the value is of
lamenting the lack of such consistency – though it is a prominent theme in
the legal literature.18
It is also unclear what the value would be of reforms that seek to insti-
tutionalize new rules for the use of force, given the necessary incompleteness
of such rules and the absence of independent arbitration. Such rules will be
upheld only if they become generally accepted norms outside the insti-
tutional setting of the UNSC (i.e., they must be self-enforcing). Any new
institutional adoption of rules for the use of force will likely reflect, rather
than instigate, such norm acceptance.
The fact that the acceptance or rejection of self-defense claims is ultim-
ately determined through a political process also implies that some states
will be more likely than others to obtain the blessing of a multilateral
institution. To understand more precisely how this affects the functioning of
the institution, we need to turn to an analysis of how the outside power of
states interacts with formal institutional rules, an exercise that will be
undertaken in the next section. Such an analysis is also important to better
understand the manner in which the authorization of collective actions and
the evaluation of appropriate unilateral uses of force are related. Collective
action authorized by the UNSC has been most extensive and effective when
there has been a strong lead state, such as Australia in East Timor or the
United States in the first Gulf War (e.g., Fearon and Laitin 2004). The
willingness of a state to “go it alone” helps solve the free-rider problem in
the production of public goods. Yet, generally states are only willing to do
this if they are granted leeway in executing the intervention. As such,
the UNSC cannot simultaneously restrict military interventions by outside
actors to unambiguous uses of self-defense and be effective at maintaining
international peace and security.
Why no UN Security Council reform? 299
Outside power and formal institutions
Institutionalists generally claim that power is “important,” but they rarely
explicitly model its consequences for institutional behavior or design (see also
Brooks and Wohlforth 2005 and Voeten 2001). This omission results at least
partly from the perception that the toolkit of institutional analysis is unsuit-
able for the analysis of power asymmetries. For example, in a special issue on
the rational design of institutions published in International Organization, the
motivation for de-emphasizing the role of power was the absence of “compel-
ling results” in the formal literature (Koremenos et al. 2001b: 1067).
Here I will use insights from a very simple bargaining model to shed light
on this issue (see also Voeten 2001). The illustration is based on a fairly
straightforward situation of heterogeneous preferences over outcomes, as
depicted in Figure 12.2. One of the permanent members, typically the United
States, prefers to act militarily in response to some situation. At least one
other veto power prefers a milder response, such as sanctions, or even no
response. This describes the basic strategic dilemma that states faced for
example in Iraq’s invasion of Kuwait, the removal of Aristide from power in
Haiti, ethnic cleansing in Kosovo, or Iraq’s failure to comply with weapons
inspections. When there is distributional conflict among the veto powers, no
multilateral agreement exists that defeats the status quo (no action). Hence,
any proposal between the ideal points of powers 1 and 3 will be vetoed, and
stalemate is the result.19
Now suppose that veto power 1 has the ability to act unilaterally or with a
few allies. In that case, she could just act alone and not bother with a multi-
lateral institution at all. However, veto power 1 may have some incentive to
sway others to co-operate. UNSC authorization may encourage burden-
sharing, it may decrease the perception among citizens at home and abroad
that the military action is threatening or it may in some other way enable the
continuance of beneficial co-operation (see Voeten 2005).
Suppose for the moment that the benefit of UNSC authorization is
exogenous and in utility terms equivalent to a policy compromise at point
M. This assumption implies that everything else being equal, veto power 1
prefers to have UNSC authorization rather than not have it.20 If this is
true, then there exists a point along the continuum in Figure 12.2 where
Power 1 is indifferent between the disutility of a compromise and the absence
Figure 12.2 Bargaining with heterogeneous preferences: the effects of outside options.
300 Erik Voeten
of multilateral agreement. That is: Power 1 prefers any multilateral action
between her ideal point and point M to going at it alone. Similarly, veto
powers 2 and 3 prefer these multilateral agreements to unilateral action by
Power 1, which would create a (from their perspectives) undesirable military
intervention over which they would have no influence. Thus, the presence of a
credible outside option and some incentive for co-operation combine to cre-
ate a bargaining range where none exists in the absence of the outside option.
This very simple analysis has a few relevant implications. First, it points to
a straightforward way in which the end of the Cold War increased UNSC
activity. Two characteristics of the Cold War were that there were two veto
powers that both had extensive outside options and who were reliably on
opposite sides of the spectrum (like powers 1 and 3 in Figure 12.2). It is easy
to see that in such a scenario UNSC action can do little but help maintain a
status quo (first-generation peacekeeping), even if there were some inherent
advantages to multilateralism. Asymmetric outside options, however, create
the possibility that the UNSC can act in the absence of harmony among the
five veto powers.
This is exactly the opposite conclusion from those who argue that uni-
polarity has killed the UNSC (e.g., Glennon 2003). The bargaining perspec-
tive suggests that unipolarity made multilateral actions possible in cases
where bipolarity did not. The evidence for the latter view is that the most
extensive UN authorizations of force were almost all in cases where the US
either implicitly or explicitly threatened to act outside the Council. This is
certainly true for the first Gulf War, Somalia, Haiti, Bosnia,21 Kosovo,22 and
Afghanistan.
Second, the current UNSC is not just a forum based around great power
consent for collective actions, but it has also become an institution that offers
states the possibility of imposing some measure of constraint on a super-
power. This is a rather different purpose than originally intended by the
Charter. The value of veto power to individual states in exercising the latter
task is at best mixed. In the world sketched by Figure 12.2, the policy prefer-
ences of a new veto power affect outcomes only under rare circumstances.23
The new permanent member could potentially use its leverage to obtain some
side-payments. But there might also be downsides to having the formal power
to veto a multilateral initiative. For example, in the lead-up to the Iraq war,
Gerhard Schröder was able to acquire the domestic benefits of opposing
the war, while much of the US ire was directed at France, the country with the
power to block UNSC authorization of the mission. Most states will want
some measure of constraint on the US but few states will want to be in the
position to apply that constraint. To current UNSC members, veto power
confers some measure of status and influence that is difficult to give up,24 but
that status may not be sufficiently valuable to outsiders in comparison to the
resources that would be necessary to acquire it.
Third, in the absence of bargaining failures, institutional reforms would be
irrelevant. In the simple world of Figure 12.2, states would always be able to
Why no UN Security Council reform? 301
achieve a multilateral compromise at point M and avoid unilateral actions. In
reality, bargaining failures prevent this from occurring. The argument is
essentially identical to rationalist explanations for war (Fearon 1995). Given
that war is costly, there always exists some Pareto improving agreement that
does not result in war. Similarly, if unilateralism is costly, then there should
be some multilateral solution that benefits all.
Bargaining failures can have many causes. I discuss two. First, states
may have asymmetric information.25 For example, veto power 1 may know
how much it is willing to compromise in exchange for UNSC authorization,
but others may not. Player 1 will have difficulties credibly communicating
her willingness to compromise, given that she has incentives to under-report
her willingness to do so. Second, domestic politics may interfere. For example,
the rise of nationalism made it virtually impossible for Russia to publicly
agree to the Kosovo intervention. At the same time, Russia worked hard to
avoid an intervention over which it had no say. Russia’s foreign minister Igor
Ivanov traveled to Belgrade on 12 March to try to persuade Milosevic to
accept a peacekeeping force – the same force the Russians had been objecting
to so far in the UNSC.26 Some newspaper reports even suggested that Russia
effectively participated in the NATO force by allowing its vessels to transport
military supplies.27
A similar story applies to French opposition over the Iraq war. A French
general met with General Command staff on 16 December 2002 to discuss
the details of a French contribution of 10,000 to 15,000 troops and French
President Jacques Chirac told his troops to prepare for action in a speech at
the Ecole Militaire on 7 January 2003 (Cantaloube and Vernet 2004; Cogan
2003). Clearly there was room for a compromise, but things changed, appar-
ently at least in part for domestic political reasons.
Given that bargaining failures are likely, adding more states with veto
power would surely make the UNSC less able to act. Similarly, reforms
that enhance the transparency of UNSC debates may increase stalemate.
Public speeches in formal settings tend to raise the cost of withdrawing
from a position, while generally having only minimal persuasive impact.
There is some value to negotiating behind closed doors (Goldstein and
Martin 2000).
Conclusions
What does all this tell us about the extent to which institutional reform
could make the UNSC perform better? One major hindrance to improving
the UNSC is that the institution is called upon to solve two rather distinct
political problems: the initiation of collective actions to produce public goods
(e.g., Sudan) and the imposition of some measure of constraint on the exercise
of force by a superpower (e.g., Iraq). From an efficiency perspective, the
two tasks pose different demands on institutional design. Moreover, the
extent to which an individual use of force fits either case is a matter of
302 Erik Voeten
fierce contestation. Hence, there is no straightforward way to redesign the
institutional structure that would address the concerns separately.
First, consider the case of the Sudan (Darfur). The UNSC’s failure here
is its inability to produce an extensive response that potentially could have
prevented genocide. To a large extent, this failure results from a lack of
willingness among the great powers to contribute resources. We could, how-
ever, redesign the UNSC to marginally improve the incentives for participa-
tion. For example, a country with a low general willingness to contribute to
global public goods should not be able to block resolutions out of private
concerns (China). Also, giving wealthy countries such as Japan and Germany
positions of responsibility could plausibly enhance their perceived interest in
attempting to stop genocide far away.
In the case of the latest Iraq war, it is much less clear if and how the
UNSC has failed. To some, the UNSC has failed in that it did not prevent
the US intervention. More realistically, the UNSC can achieve two things in
a case like Iraq. First, if a multilateral solution fails, this failure should be
perceived as costly by the offending state. If this is so, then it raises the cost
of future unilateral actions. From this perspective, the UNSC may not
have failed at all. Second, a multilateral compromise could have been
achieved that would have given other states more control over the interven-
tion. Depending on the outcome, this might have been perceived as a failure
or as a success. Regardless of this, the demands on institutional design are
clearly different from the Sudan case. For example, whereas China has, des-
pite some recent changes, not been a major contributor to collective actions,
it is obviously a necessary participant in evaluating the political expedience of
an intervention.
What institutional reform is necessary, then, depends strongly on what
function we expect the UNSC to perform. One could argue, for instance, that
a body that decides by weighted majority rule and that would consist of only
democratic states, would be respected more in the US and hence could
impose greater constraints on it (greater value of M in Figure 12.2). Yet, it is
unclear why we would expect such a body to respond more effectively to
global crises. Moreover, a majoritarian body runs the risk of making itself
irrelevant by making decisions that are not enforceable.
The main implication for the institutionalist literature is the need to go
beyond the “power also matters” approach towards institutional design. If
power matters, then it should be modeled explicitly, rather than separated
from the effects of institutions. This chapter has illustrated some extremely
simple ways to do this. I would contend that the toolkit of formal models is
very suitable to explicitly model the impact of power asymmetries. In game
theoretic terms, power resides in the ability to commit oneself. This is not
mere “cleverness” (Krasner 1991), but may stem from having the military
capacity to pursue interventions unilaterally. At the same time, power does
have other sources, such as the ability to raise audience costs, ability to delay,
and specific institutional features such as agenda-setting or veto power. How
Why no UN Security Council reform? 303
formal institutional power transfers into actual bargaining power should be
higher on the agenda of institutionalist research.
More generally, the analysis points to the limits of the impact that insti-
tutional reform and design have when decisions need to be self-enforcing and
non-institutionalized power asymmetries matter. When we take into account
the interaction with its external environment, the stakes for institutional
reform appear to be much lower than when we lock ourselves up inside the
UNSC. This may explain, for instance, why the push for institutional reform
comes primarily from high-level bureaucrats within the foreign ministries of
countries such as Germany and Japan, rather than from the executives of
those countries. The bureaucracies may care a great deal about the prestige
attached to formal membership, while the executives care more about actual
influence and may be wary of the additional responsibilities attached to per-
manent membership.
While the impact of institutional design is constrained, the particularities
of formal institutions are certainly not completely irrelevant. Outcomes real-
ized through multilateral institutions look different from outcomes that are
not, though not in ways that we can understand without a proper analysis
of power asymmetries and enforcement problems. Moreover, the current
decision-making procedures do contain certain inefficiencies that increase
the chance for bargaining failures and lead to an underproduction of public
goods (peace). Nevertheless, the benefits of clever constitutional engineering
will likely be relatively small both for the production of public goods as well
as for the private interests of individual states.
Notes
An earlier version of this paper was presented at the workshop Assessing Multilateral-
ism in the Security Domain, Delphi, 3–5 June 2005. I thank the participants at that
workshop, especially Dimitris Bourantonis and Arturo Sotomayor, for useful com-
ments and suggestions.
1 This exclusion was formalized in the Charter through the so-called Enemy
Clauses, which have never been repealed.
2 For extensive analyses of the history of UN reform, see Bourantonis (2005) and
Luck (2003).
3 Friedman, T. (2003) “Vote France off the Island,” New York Times, 9 February
2003.
4 These precise words are from a speech given at the Banqueting House, Whitehall,
London, 10 February 2005 (http://www.una-uk.org/10feb05/sgspeech.html) and
refer explicitly to a similar statement in his 4 December 2003 UNGA speech in
which he installed the Panel.
5 See the 2005 World Summit Outcome, the 2000 Millennium Declaration, and the
Declaration on the Occasion of the Fiftieth Anniversary of the United Nations from
1995. The 2005 text reads (point 153): “We support early reform of the Security
Council – an essential element of our overall effort to reform the United Nations –
in order to make it more broadly representative, efficient and transparent and thus
to further enhance its effectiveness and the legitimacy and implementation of its
304 Erik Voeten
decisions. We commit ourselves to continuing our efforts to achieve a decision to
this end and request the General Assembly to review progress on the reform set out
above by the end of 2005.”
6 As Brian Urquhart writes, on the High-Level Panel report: “In the past many
excellent and forward-looking ideas have died a dismal death being torn to pieces
by junior diplomats in the committees of the General Assembly” (Urquhart 2005:
185). From the UNGA session following the 2005 World Summit, there is little
evidence the High-Level Panel report will experience a different fate.
7 For example, by assuming that states engage in “role-oriented” behavior and hence
are not opportunistic (Frederking 2003).
8 This statement is based on conversations with various long-time participants in
negotiations over UN reform. The latter part of the statement holds especially for
countries such as Mexico and Argentina, who would prefer not to have Brazil
become their permanent representative but at the same time see little benefit in
obtaining an institutional position that would likely bring them into unwanted
conflict with the US, given that domestic public opinion would likely force these
countries to frequently offer resistance to US initiatives.
9 For Japan, see Law Concerning Co-operation for United Nations Peacekeeping
Operations and Other Operations (the International Peace Co-operation Law)
originally passed in June 1992. For Germany, see especially the ruling by the
Bundesverfassungsgericht [Federal Constitutional Court] 90, 286, 12 July 1994.
10 For instance, having voted against the war became a serious liability for 2004
Democratic presidential candidate John Kerry.
11 Even though the nature of the anarchical environment in international politics
differs from that of a market, international relations theorists have long recog-
nized that the existence of transaction costs and asymmetric information provide a
compelling raison d’être for international institutions (for an overview, see Martin
and Simmons 1998). As such, scholars have used the tools of contract theory, in
particular principal–agent theory, to explore if, when, why, and how states delegate
authority to IOs (e.g., Pollack 1997; Nielson and Tierney 2003).
12 There is some debate as to the legal standing of this (Blokker 2000).
13 This paragraph is adopted from Voeten (2005).
14 A fixed burden-sharing system was put in place in 1973 by UNGA Resolution 310.
15 I have taken some liberties in interpreting Maggi and Morelli, who argue that the
EU uses qualified majority rule on issues that are less “important.” I believe that
the enforcement interpretation more accurately reflects their formal results and
the data.
16 The ICJ receives one mention, on page 12, acknowledging that “disputes were
remedied under the International Court of Justice.”
17 UNSC Resolution 1373, 28 September 2001.
18 For example, on the application of the self-defense concept in Resolution 1373,
see Farer (2002).
19 For a discussion of how vote buying may alter this, see Voeten (n.d.).
20 We may show how this benefit arises endogenously either from domestic inter-
actions or from reputation effects through repeated interactions, but such an
analysis would contribute little to the issues at stake here and unnecessarily com-
plicate matters.
21 The most forceful UN resolutions were adopted only after the US threatened
to unilaterally lift the arms embargo against Bosnian Muslims (see Christopher
1998).
22 The authorization of KFOR after the intervention had taken place. This is a
somewhat different case from the others.
23 They only matter if the new veto power’s ideal point is smaller than M. For more,
see Voeten (2001).
Why no UN Security Council reform? 305
24 For example on Russia, see Bourantonis and Panagiotou (2004).
25 For a formal analysis of this argument, see Voeten (2001).
26 “Igor Ivanov rectifies mistakes of Americans,” Izvestia, 12 March 1999.
27 “Russia is already participating in NATO operations in Balkans,” Izvestia, 10
March 1999.
13 The reform and efficiency of
the UN Security Council
A veto players analysis
Aris Alexopoulos and
Dimitris Bourantonis
Introduction
Since the beginning of the 1990s, we observe a growing number of proposals
to increase the representativeness of the UNSC. The reasoning behind these
proposals is that in this way the UNSC will improve its efficiency in the
implementation of its decisions. However, there are counter-arguments, which
tend to dominate the debate, that a potential enlargement or a more demand-
ing decision rule almost by definition will reduce the decision capacity of the
body. Most scholarly accounts of UNSC reform, while in favor of UNSC
enlargement, take it as a self-evident truth that its bigger size would weaken
its decision-making capacity and in other words its ability to act swiftly and
effectively. Russett (2005: 161) for instance, argues that “anything . . . that
increases the number of players that have leverage in its [i.e., the UNSC]
negotiations throws one more bucket of sand into the wheels of rapid and
decisive action by the Council.” Reviewing the history of UNSC reform
Sutterlin (1987: 4) has underlined that “to be an effective body in dealing with
threats to the peace, the Council had to be small and capable of quick
decisions.” In the same line of reasoning, Wallensteen (1997: 106), Weiss
(2003: 149), Caron (1993: 567), the members of the UN Secretary-General’s
High-Level Panel on Threats, Challenges and Change and others1 have called
for a trade-off between better representation through Council enlargement
and efficiency. Their convictions that “concern for efficiency argues for a
relatively small Council,” or that “a Security Council of 21 or 25 members
would hardly improve effectiveness” or “the number of members must be
kept small for the sake of efficient argument” as such sound like axioms or
arbitrary judgments. With this work we examine various scenarios of reform
of the UNSC, based on enlargement and change in the decision rule, and
obtain that a reduced decision capacity is not always the case. We will show
that there are types of reform that may lead in the opposite direction, to
increase the decision capacity of the body.
The central element in the decision structure of the UNSC is the veto
power, which either institutionally or positionally the involved players
hold. It is this reason, which drives us to apply, by analogy, to such an
UN Security Council: a veto players analysis 307
international decision structure, the work of Tsebelis (2002) on the role of
veto players in decision-making games, a theory produced to explain the
functioning of domestic political institutions. To do so, the chapter is organ-
ized in three sections. Firstly, we introduce the tools of Tsebelis’s veto players
theory needed in the analysis of the various reform scenarios. Secondly, based
on the main findings we analyze the current functioning of the UNSC.
Thirdly, we discuss the decision capacity of the system under alternative
reform scenarios on the membership and institutional arrangements of the
future UNSC.
Figure 13.1 Three- and five-member unanimity cores in two dimensions, where five
members can reach a decision more easily than a three-member decision
body that is more distant.
UN Security Council: a veto players analysis 309
greater core. The important element is the location of the ideal preference
points of the players in the decision game, and not the number of the players.
Applying the above-mentioned theoretical propositions on the functioning
of the UNSC, we compose the following argument for the proposed reform
scenarios: The increase of the membership of the UNSC does not necessarily
correspond to a reduced capacity to make decisions. The key element is the
location of the policy preferences of the new members in the policy space
regarding the SQ. Hence, it is not the increase of the members of the UNSC
alone, but its combination with the divergence of the decision makers’ secur-
ity policy preferences in the UNSC that produces less collective action for the
promotion of the international security.
In the following parts we will examine in more detail the current function-
ing and various reform scenarios of the UNSC, in terms of their decision
capacity, based on the argument raised above, about the number and the
location of veto players, incorporating in our analysis specific alternative
member states. We will show that the important element to produce a more
efficient UNSC is not the number of veto players in the decision process but
the distance of their preferences over two distinct forms of enforcement
actions that are available to the UNSC under Chapter VII of the UN Charter
(i.e., sanctions or use of armed force) and their economic development
agenda.
these points constitutes “the unanimity 5/5 core” of this set of decision-
makers. We can also divide the fifteen members several times, picking 9 out of
15 points and creating 9/15 majorities. The lines, such as the one drawn
through the points 1 and 8, which can leave 9 points on the one side of them,
including 1 and 8, are called “9/15 qualified majority dividers” (q-dividers in
Tsebelis 2002: 52). We draw all the possible q-dividers, creating each time an
enneagon (say the 1, 8, 9 . . . 15). Anywhere within each enneagon the
correspondent veto players cannot unanimously (9/9) agree to change the SQ
if the last is located within the enneagon. This enneagon constitutes the
unanimity core of the nine selected players. If we now select all possible
enneagons, their intersection constitutes the area within which no point
can be defeated by any 9/15 majority. This intersection is the hatched small
312 Aris Alexopoulos and Dimitris Bourantonis
polygon in Figure 13.2 and represents the “9/15 qualified majority core” of
the fifteen-player decision-making body.
In the case of the UNSC, if the status quo on a peace crisis is laid within the
five permanent members’ unanimity core, no matter whether it is not con-
tained within the “60 per cent qualified majority” core, no draft resolution can
be adopted by the UNSC, since it will be vetoed as less preferred by at least
one of the permanent members. If the SQ lies outside the five permanent
members’ unanimity core and within the “60 per cent qualified majority” core
of the fifteen members of the UNSC, it again cannot be defeated by any other
draft resolution since it will not be supported by at least 9/15 votes. If the SQ
lies outside both cores, but within the area contained by the straight lines that
connect the extreme points of the unanimity and the 9/15 core, it again cannot
be defeated. Actually, if the draft resolution is closer to one of the two cores,
then it will be vetoed by the members of the other core since the draft proposal
moves things away from their ideal policy preferences. Therefore, the core of
the UNSC is the area that covers and connects the two cores and represents
their convexification – the hatched and shaded areas in Figure 13.3.
The greater the differences between the permanent and the non-permanent
members of the UNSC and the greater the preference dispersion (less homo-
geneous) inside these two groups, the greater is the size of the core of the
UNSC, and, hence, the greater the possibility for unilateral or (let us say)
non-collective actions under UNSC auspices. In the case of non-decision for
the UNSC, there are two possible policy outcomes: either mostly unilateral
We start our mapping exercise by locating on our policy space the perman-
ent members of the UNSC. What matters in this picture is not the absolute
mark but the relative distance between the states. The US, being the most
active and taking initiatives for peacemaking, holds the highest score on the
scale favoring military force. The UK is the closest to US ideal position;
however, in our measurement exercise it obtains a slightly lower score due to
segments of domestic pacifists’ constraints incorporated into the governing
Labor party. Because of both pacifist constraints in the French political sys-
tem and the anti-US legacy in foreign policy, we locate France close to US but
even lower than the UK. Russia, in most of the cases discussed in the UNSC,
usually votes in favor of respect for national sovereignty and blocs proposals
for the use of military force; for this reason, it takes a much lower grade in
our scale. China is in line with Russia, but much more in favor of respect for
national sovereignty and against the use of military force, so it takes the
lowest grade.
The knowledge of the new size of the body is not enough to drive us to a safe
inference. In order to determine the outcome of such an exercise we also need
to know the exact position of the ideal preference points of all the members
of our modified decision body.
Concluding remarks
Our discussion may be summarized as follows. According to Tsebelis’ veto
players theory, the important element for the decision capacity of the UNSC
is not its size but the location of the ideal preference points of its members
and the decision rule according to which these members vote for the
322 Aris Alexopoulos and Dimitris Bourantonis
proposed draft resolutions. We have shown that it is misleading to connect,
as many used to do, enlargement with less decision capacity in the UNSC.
We have shown that we could have a UNSC larger than the current one,
with more permanent members equipped with institutional veto power,
which could however arrive at a decision with less difficulty than the current,
smaller UNSC. We examined the various reform scenarios based on the main
analytical tool provided by the veto players theory, according to which, the
larger the core is, the smaller is the decision capacity of a decision body. We
have found that the three parts of the core of the UNSC may be reshaped in
various and many times opposite directions, which make prediction of its
decision capacity an extremely demanding exercise. However, we managed to
show that the key element in the solution of this puzzle is the positioning of
the member states on the decision space, and not the size of the decision
body.
Finally, we want to exclusively state that our motivation to do this work
was not to embark upon a normative discussion of the future of the UNSC.
On the contrary, we tried to limit ourselves to positive discussion, locating
our arguments on the same side as those who believe that the fruitful way to
do social science is not to mix the two cognitive worlds. We also share the
opinion that positive evidence may help a better normative discussion based
on feasible goals and more efficient means. If the goal is a more efficient
UNSC, we have shown that this has nothing to do with its size. If the goal is
to increase the legitimacy of the decisions of the UNSC, and we want to do
this based on input legitimacy, we could increase its size in order to make it
more representative without losing in efficiency. On the contrary, the effi-
ciency might be improved if we chose, as new members, states with ideal
preference points over security and foreign economic policy located in such a
way as to drive the current decision core to shrink.
Notes
1 See Laurenti (1997: 11); Russett et al. (1997: 155); Blum (2005: 632); Zacher (2003:
11), Reisman (1993: 96).
2 Kim and Russett (1996) arrived at the conclusion that there are two significant,
underlined factors in the voting behavior of states: the issue of self-determination
of states and the promotion of political rights in domestic politics. Some years
later, with the same data set, Voeten (2000) showed these results of factor analysis
were false, with an alternative method called nominate model and concluded that
the post-Cold War voting behavior of states in the UNGA is one-dimensional,
according to hegemonic or antihegemonic preference of the states in the world
security system.
3 For arguments in favor of unidimentionality, see also Frieden (2004).
4 Dreher, Sturm and Vreeland (2006) argue and provide evidence that there is a
positive correlation between a country’s participation in IMF programmes and the
coincidence of this country being a member of the UNSC. The IMF loans pro-
vided to these countries increased during their service on the UNSC and decreased
before and after the service.
UN Security Council: a veto players analysis 323
5 Kim and Russett (1996: 648) in their statistical evaluation of the roll-call votes of
the UNGA find strong correlation between the first dimension produced by factor
analyzing the data, the self-determination dimension, and GNP per capita, with a
coefficient of very high negative value (−7.5). For indicative arguments in favor of
or against the use of GDP for measuring the power and influence of countries on
foreign affairs, see also the discussion in Fearon (2005).
6 According to Greenberg (1979), a core always exists if q<n/(n+1), where q is the
decision rule and n the dimensionality of the policy space.
7 See “The Common Position of the Proposed Reform of the United Nations:
The Ezulwini Consensus,” African Union, Executive Council, 7th Extraordinary
Session, 7–8 March 2005.
8 During the Gulf War of 1991, Egypt supported the use of force under the terms of
Resolution 678 of the UNSC.
9 See “Comments of the Non-Aligned Movement on the Observations and Recom-
mendations Contained in the Report of the High-Level Panel on Threats, Chal-
lenges and Change,” UN Doc. A/59/565 and A/59/565 CORR.1, 28 February
2005, p. 6.
10 Ibid., p. 17.
11 See Resolution 940 adopted by the UNSC on 31 July 1994.
12 See the remarks of Mr Castro, Permanent Represntative of Brazil to the UN, in
UN Doc. S/PV.3334, 4 February 1994, pp. 27–8.
13 See the remarks of Mr Sardenberg, Permanent Representative of Brazil to the
UN, in UN Doc. S/PV.3413, 31 July 1994, p. 9.
14 Tsebelis and Yataganas show the same for a seven-member decision body and a 5/7
decision rule. See G. Tsebelis and X. Yataganas (2005) “The Treaty of Nice, the
Convention Proposal, and the Treaty Establishing a Constitution for Europe: A
Veto Players Analysis”, European Constitutional Law Review 1(3): 429–51.
References
Abbott, K. and Snidal, D. (1998) “Why States Act through Formal International
Organizations”, Journal of Conflict Resolution 42(1): 3–32.
Abbott, K., Keohane, R., Moravcsik, A., Slaughter, A-M. and Snidal, D. (2000) “The
Concept of Legalization”, International Organization 54(3): 401–19.
Acharya, A. (1991) “Association of Southeast Asian Nations: ‘Security Community’
or ‘Defence Community’?”, Pacific Affairs 64(2): 159–78.
Acharya, A. (1999) “A Concert of Asia”, Survival 41(3): 84–101.
Acharya, A. (2001) Constructing a Security Community in Southeast Asia: ASEAN
and the Problem of Regional Order, London: Routledge.
Acharya, A. (2004) “How Ideas Spread: Whose Norms Matter? Norm Localization
and Institutional Change in Asian Regionalism”, International Organization 58(2):
239–76.
Acharya, A. and Tan, S.S. (2004) “Introduction”, in S.S. Tan and A. Acharya (eds),
Asia-Pacific Security Cooperation: National Interests and Regional Order, Armonk,
NY: ME Sharpe.
Acharya, A. and Tan, S.S. (2006) “Betwixt Balance and Community: America,
ASEAN, and the Security of Southeast Asia”, International Relations of the Asia-
Pacific 6(1): 37–59.
Ackerman, B., and Golove, D. (1995) “Is NAFTA Constitutional?”, Harvard Law
Review 108(4): 799–929.
Adler, E. and Barnett, M. (1998a) “A Framework for the Study of Security Commu-
nities”, in Adler and Barnett (eds) Security Communities, Cambridge: Cambridge
UP, pp. 29–65.
Adler, E. and Barnett, M. (eds) (1998b) Security Communities, Cambridge: Cam-
bridge UP.
Alford, H. (2000) Organization Evolving, Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Alford, J. (1984), Greece and Turkey: Adversity in Alliance, New York: St. Martin’s
Press.
Allison, R. (2004) “Regionalism, Regional Structures and Security Management in
Central Asia”, International Affairs 80(3): 463–83.
Alter, K.J. (2000) “The European Union’s Legal System and Domestic Policy: Spillover
or Backlash?”, International Organization, 54(3): 489–518.
Alterman, J. (2003) “The United States and Egypt: Building the Partnership”, Middle
East Note, Washington, DC: Center for Strategic and International Studies.
Alterman, J. (2005) “Dynamics Without Drama: New Options and Old Compromises
References 325
in Egypt’s Foreign Policy”, Cambridge Review of International Affairs 18(3):
357–69.
Altmann, F.L. and Whitlock, E. (eds) (2004) European and US Policies in the Balkans,
Berlin: Stiftung Wissenschaft und Politik.
Alvesson, M. (1993) Cultural Perspectives on Organizations, New York: Cambridge UP.
American Society of International Law (1999) Forum on Kosovo, 93(4), October.
Amoo, G.S. and Zartman, I.W. (1992) “Mediation by Regional Organizations: The
Organization for African Unity (OAU) in Chad”, in J. Bercovitch and J.Z. Rubin
(eds) Mediation in International Relations. Multiple Approaches to Conflict Man-
agement, New York, St. Martin’s Press, pp. 131–48.
Anderson, B. (1983) Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of
Nationalism, New York: Verso.
Anderson, B. (1991) Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origins and Spread of
Nationalism, London: Verso.
Anderson, J., Ikenberry, G.J. and Risse, T. (eds) (2008) The End of the West? Crisis and
Change in the Transatlantic Order, Ithaca, NY: Cornell UP.
Anderson, J., Ikenberry, G.J. and Risse, T. (eds) (forthcoming) The End of the West?
The Crisis of the Transatlantic Relationship, Ithaca, NY: Cornell UP.
Anderson, K. (2004) “Humanitarian Inviolability in Crisis: The Meaning of Impar-
tiality and Neutrality for U.N. and NGO Agencies Following the 2003–2004
Afghanistan and Iraq Conflicts”, Harvard Human Rights Journal, 17 (Spring):
41–74.
Annan, K. (2000) We The Peoples: The Role of the United Nations in the 21st Century,
New York: United Nations.
Annan, K. (2002) “Democracy as an International Issue”, Global Governance, 8(2):
134–42.
Apthorpe, R. (2001) “International Emergency Relief Aid in Kosovo 1999–2000: Was
it Humanitarian or Not?”, paper presented at Kosovo and the Changing Face of
Humanitarian Action Conference, Uppsala, Sweden, May.
Arquilla, J. and Ronfeldt, D. (2001) Networks and Netwars: The Future of Terror,
Crime, and Militancy, Santa Monica, CA: RAND Corporation.
Art, R. (1996) “Why Western Europe Needs the United States and NATO”, Political
Science Quarterly 111(1): 1–39.
ASEAN (2003a) “Declaration of ASEAN Concord II (Bali Concord II)”, Online at
<http://www.aseansec.org/15160.htm> (accessed on 23 February 2006).
ASEAN (2003b) ASEAN Statistical Yearbook, Jakarta: The ASEAN Secretariat.
ASEAN (2004) “ASEAN Security Community Plan of Action”, Online at <http://
www.aseansec.org/16827.htm> (accessed on 26 April 2005).
Ashdown, P. (2003) “The Rule of Law in a Post-War Society: The Latest Develop-
ments from Bosnia and Herzegovina”, 80 Club Lecture, 19 June.
Ashdown, P. (2004a) “Yes, I did go to Karadzic”, OHR Press Office, 24 January.
Ashdown, P. (2004b) Press Interview, 30 June, CEPS Europa-South East Monitor,
Issue 56.
Asmus, R., Everts, P. and Isernia, P. (2003) Power, War, and Public Opinion. Thoughts
on the Nature and Structure of the Trans-Atlantic Divide, Washington, DC: Trans-
atlantic Trends.
Augustine of Hippo (427/1991), City of God, XIX, 13: 1, London: Penguin Classics.
Axelrod, R. (1998) “How to Negotiate for Reform of the UN Security Council”,
Online at <http://www-personal.umich.edu/~axe/>.
326 References
Axelrod, R. and Keohane, R. (1986) “Introduction” and “Conclusion,” in K. Oye
(ed.) Cooperation Under Anarchy, Princeton: Princeton UP.
Aybet, G. (2000) A European Security Architecture after the Cold War: Questions of
Legitimacy, Houndmills: Macmillan Press.
Ba, A.D. (2005) “On Norms, Rule-breaking, and Security Communities: A Construct-
ivist Response”, International Relations of the Asia-Pacific 5(2): 255–66.
Bac, M.M. (2003) “Turkey’s Political Reforms and the Impact of the European
Union”, South European Society and Politics 10(1): 17–31.
Bahr, E. (2003) Der deutsche Weg. Selbstverständlich und Normal, München: Karl
Blessing Verlag.
Bailes, A.J.K. (2003) “Armament and Disarmament in the Caucasus and Central
Asia: An Introduction” in A.J.K. Bailes et al. (eds) Armament and Disarmament in
the Caucasus and Central Asia, Stockholm: SIPRI, policy paper, no. 3, pp. 1–7.
Baker, J.A. (1995) The Politics of Diplomacy: Revolution, War and Peace, 1989–1992,
New York: Putnam’s Sons.
Balch-Lindsay, D. and Enterline, A.J. (2000) “Killing Time: The World Politics of Civil
War Duration, 1820–1992”, International Studies Quarterly 44(4): 615–42.
Barnett, M. (1997) “Bringing in the New World Order: Liberalism, Legitimacy, and
the United Nations”, World Politics 49(4): 526–51.
Barnett, M. (2005) “Humanitarianism Transformed”, Perspectives on Politics, 3(4):
723–40.
Barnett, M. and Finnemore, M. (1999) “The Politics, Power, and Pathologies of IOs”,
International Organization 53(4): 699–732.
Barnett, M. and Finnemore, M. (2004) Rules for the World: International Organiza-
tions and World Politics, Ithaca, NY: Cornell UP.
Bass, G.J. (2000) Staying the Hand of Vengeance: The Politics of War Crimes Tribunals.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP.
Batt, J. (2004) “Introduction: The Stabilization/Integration Dilemma”, in J. Batt
(ed.) The Western Balkans: Moving On, Chaillot Paper No. 70, Paris: Institute for
Security Studies.
BBC World Service (2005) “In 18 of 21 Countries Polled, Most See Bush’s Re-election
as Negative for World Security”, London: BBC World Service 22-Nation Poll on
Bush’s Re-election, 19 January.
Beetham, D. (1985) Max Weber and the Theory of Modern Politics, New York: Polity.
Beitz, C. (1979) Political Theory and International Relations. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
UP.
Beitz, C. (1994) “Cosmopolitan Liberalism and the States System”, in C. Brown
(ed.) Political Restructuring in Europe: Ethical Perspectives, London: Routledge,
pp. 123–36.
Bellamy, A, and Williams, P. (2004) Special Issue on Peace Operations and Global
Order, International Peacekeeping 10(4): 1–212.
Bellamy, A.J. and Williams, P.D. (2005) “Who’s Keeping the Peace? Regionalization
and Contemporary Peace Operations”, International Security 29(4): 157–95.
Bendor, J., Glazer, A. and Hammond, T. (2001) “Theories of Delegation”, Annual
Review of Political Science 4: 235–69.
Bennett, A., Lepgold, J. and Unger, D. (1994) “Burden-Sharing in the Persian Gulf
War”, International Organization 48(1): 39–75.
Bercovitch, J. and Langley, J. (1993) “The Nature of Dispute and the Effectiveness of
International Mediation”, Journal of Conflict Resolution 37(4): 670–91.
References 327
Berman, S. (2003) “Islamism, Revolution, and Civil Society”, Perspectives on Politics,
1(2): 257–72.
Best, G. (1994) War and Law since 1945, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Blair, T. (1999) “Doctrine of the International Community”, speech delivered to the
Economic Club of Chicago, 22 April. Online at <http://www.globalpolicy.org/
globaliz/politics/blair.htm>.
Bleiker, R. (2000) Popular Dissent, Human Agency, and Global Politics, Cambridge:
Cambridge UP.
Blokker, N. (2000) “Is the Authorization Authorized? Powers and Practice of the UN
Security Council to Authorize the Use of Force by Coalitions of the Able and
Willing”, European Journal of International Law 11(3): 541–68.
Blum, Y. (2005), “Proposals for UN Security Council Reform”, American Journal of
International Law 99(3): 632–49.
Bobbitt, P. (2002) The Shield of Achilles: War, Peace, and the Course of History,
New York: Anchor Books.
Bocheva, L. and Martin, L. (2001) “Institutional Effects on Satte Behavior: Con-
vergence and Divergence”, International Studies Quarterly 45(1): 1–26.
Boli, J. and Thomas, G. (eds) (1999) Constructing World Culture: International
Nongovernmental Organizations Since 1875, Stanford, CA: Stanford UP.
Bolton, P. and Dewatripont, M. (2005) Contract Theory, Cambridge: MIT Press.
Borowiec, A. (1983), The Mediterranean Feud, New York: Praeger.
Börzel, T.A. and Risse, T. (2000) When Europe Hits Home: Europeanization and
Domestic Change, European Integration online Papers (EIoP) Vol. 4, No. 15,
Online at <http://www.eiop.or.at/eiop/texte/2000–015a.htm>.
Börzel, T.A. and Risse, T. (2004) One Size Fits All! EU Policies for the Promotion of
Human Rights, Democracy and the Rule of Law, paper prepared for the Workshop
on Democracy Promotion, 4–5 October, Center for Development, Democracy and
the Rule of Law, Stanford University–Heidelberg–Berlin: Institution.
Bose, S. (2005) “The Bosnian State a Decade after Dayton”, International Peacekeeping
12(3): 322–35.
Bouchet-Saulnier, F. (2000) “Between Humanitarian Law and Principles: The Prin-
ciples and Practices of “Rebellious Humanitarianism” ”, Online at <http://www.
msf.org/msfinternational/invoke.cfm?component=article&objectid=6589C8A5-
DC2C-11D4-B2010060084A6370&method=full_html>.
Bourantonis, D. (2005) The History and Politics of UN Security Council Reform,
London: Routledge.
Bourantonis, D. and Panagiotou, R. (2004) “Russia’s Attitude towards the Reform of
the United Nations Security Council, 1990–2000”, Journal of Communist Studies
and Transition Politics 20(4): 79–102.
Bradol, J.H. (2004) “The Sacrificial International Order”, in F. Weissman (ed.) In the
Shadow of “Just Wars”: Violence, Politics, and Humanitarian Action, Ithaca, NY:
Cornell UP, pp. 1–22.
Braml, J. (2004) “Die religiöse Rechte in den USA”, SWP-Studie, S 35. Berlin: Stiftung
Wissenschaft und Politik, September.
Brooks, S. and Wohlforth, W. (2002) “American Primacy in Perspective”, Foreign
Affairs 81(4): 20–33.
Brooks, S. and Wohlforth, W. (2005) “International Relations Theory and the Case
against Unilateralism”, Perspectives on Politics 3(3): 509–24.
Bukovansky, M. (2002) Legitimacy and Power Politics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP.
328 References
Bulmer, S., Jeffery, C. and Paterson, W.E. (2000) Germany’s European Diplomacy:
Shaping the Regional Milieu, Manchester: Manchester UP.
Burchell, G., Gordon, C. and Miller, G. (eds) The Foucault Effect: Studies in Govern-
mentality, Hemel Hempstead, Herts: Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Burns, J.F. (2002) “Political Realities Impeding Full Inquiry into Afghan Atrocity”,
New York Times, 29 August.
Byers, M. (1999) Custom, Power, and the Power of Rules: International Relations and
Customary International Law, Cambridge: Cambridge UP.
Caldeira, G.A. and Gibson, J.L. (1995) “The Legitimacy of the Court of Justice in the
European Union: Models of Institutional Support”, American Political Science
Review 89(2): 356–77.
Calhoun, C. (2004) “A World of Emergencies: Fear, Intervention, and the Limits
of Cosmopolitan Order”, Online at <http://www.google.com/search?q=cache:
JrRXlGFxbucJ:www.ssrc.org/programs/calhoun/publications/a_world_of_
emergencies.pdf+%22World+of+Emergencies%22&hl=en>.
Camacho, C., Higgins, T. and Luger, L. (2003) “Moral Value Transfer from Regula-
tory Fit: “What Feels Right Is Right” and “What Feels Wrong Is Wrong” ”, Journal
of Personality and Social Psychology 84(3): 498–510.
Cambell, D. (1992) Writing Security, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Cantaloube, T. and Vernet, H. (2004). Chirac contre Bush: l’Autre Guerre, Paris:
Jean-Claude Lattes.
Caplan, R. (2002) A New Trusteeship? The International Administration of War-torn
Territories, The Adelphi Papers, Oxford: Oxford UP.
Caplan, R. (2005) “Who Guards the Guardians? International Accountability in
Bosnia”, International Peacekeeping 12(3): 463–76.
Caporaso, A. (1993) “International Relations Theory and Multilateralism: The
Search for Foundations” in J.G. Ruggie (ed.) Multilateralism Matters: The Theory
and Praxis of an Institutional Form, New York: Columbia UP, pp. 51–90.
Caporaso, J. (1992) “IR Theory and Multilateralism”, International Organization 46(3):
599–632.
Carlson, C. (2003) “Central Asia: Shanghai Cooperation Organization Makes Mili-
tary Debut”, Online at <http://globalsecurity.org/military/library/news/2003/08/
mil-03085-rfel54708.htm> (accessed on 5 May 2005).
Caron, D. (1993) “The Legitimacy of the Collective Authority of the Security Council”,
American Journal of International Law 87(4): 552–88.
Carothers, T. (1999) Aiding Democracy Abroad, Washington, DC: Carnegie Endow-
ment for International Peace.
Carr, E.H. (1938) The Twenty Years’ Crisis, 1919–39: An Introduction to the Study of
International Relations, London: Macmillan.
Carter, A.B. (1999–2000) “Adapting US Defense to Future Needs”, Survival 41(4):
101–23.
Carter, A.B. and Perry, W.J. (1999) Preventive Defense: A New Security Strategy for
America, Washington, DC: Brookings Institution.
Carter, W.H. (1936) in the Foreword to C. Van Vollenhoven, The Law of Peace,
London: Macmillan.
Cassese, A. (1999) “Ex Iniuria Ius Oritur: Are We Moving Towards International
Legitimation of Forcible Humanitarian Countermeasures?”, European Journal of
International Law 10(1): 23–30.
Ceadal, M. (1987) Thinking about Peace and War, Oxford: Oxford UP.
References 329
Celik B.A., and Rumelili, B. (2006) “Necessary but not Sufficient: The Role of the
EU in Resolving Turkey’s Kurdish Question and the Greek-Turkish Conflicts”,
European Foreign Affairs Review 11(2): 203–22.
Chan, S. (1997) “In Search of Democratic Peace: Problems and Promise”, Mershon
International Studies Review 41(1): 59–91.
Chandler, D. (2002) From Kosovo to Kabul: Human Rights and International Interven-
tion, London: Pluto.
Chandler, D. (2004) “The Responsibility to Protect: Imposing the “Liberal Peace” ”,
International Peacekeeping 11(1): 59–81.
Chayes, A. and Chayes, A. (1993) “On Compliance”, International Organization 47(2):
175–205.
Chayes, A. and Chayes, A. (eds) (1996) Preventing Conflict in the Post-Communist
World: Mobilizing International and Regional Organizations, Washington, DC:
Brookings Institution.
Checkel, J.T. (1997) “International Norms and Domestic Politics: Bridging the
Rationalist-Constructivist Divide”, European Journal of International Relations
3(4): 473–95.
Checkel, J.T. (1998) “The Constructivist Turn in International Relations Theory”,
World Politics 50(2): 324–48.
Checkel, J.T. (1999) “Why Comply? Constructivism, Social Norms and the Study of
International Institutions”, Oslo, ARENA Working Paper, no. 24.
Checkel, J.T. (2000) “Compliance and Conditionality”, ARENA Working Paper, WP
00/18.
Checkel, J.T. (2001a) “Taking Deliberation Seriously”, ARENA Working Paper, WP
01/14.
Checkel, J.T. (2001b) “Why Comply? Social Learning and European Identity Change”,
International Organization 55(3): 553–88.
Checkel, J.T. (2005) “International Institutions and Socialization in Europe: Introduc-
tion and Framework”, International Organization 59(4): 801–26.
Choo, J. (2003) “The Geopolitics of Central Asian Energy” in J. Sperling, S. Kay and
S.V. Papacosma (eds) Limiting Institutions? The Challenge of Eurasian Security
Governance, Manchester: Manchester UP, pp. 112–77.
Chopra, J. (2000) “The UN’s Kingdom of East Timor”, Survival 42(3): 27–39.
Chopra, J. and Hohe, T. (2004) “Participatory Intervention”, Global Governance 10(3):
289–305.
Christopher, W. (1998) In the Stream of History: Shaping Foreign Policy for a New Era,
Palo Alto, CA: Stanford UP.
Cilliers, J. (1999) An Emerging South African Foreign Policy?, Institute for Security
Studies, Occasional paper, no. 39, April.
Clark, A.M. (2001) Diplomacy of Conscience: Amnesty International and Changing
Human Rights Norms, Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP.
Clark, I. (2001) The Post-Cold War Order, Oxford: Oxford UP.
Clark, W. (2002) Waging Modern War, New York: Public Affairs Press.
Claude, I. (1966) “Collective Legitimization as a Political Function of the United
Nations”, International Organization 20(3): 367–79.
Cogan, C. (2003) French Negotiating Behavior: Dealing with La Grande Nation, Wash-
ington, DC: Institute of Peace.
Coicaud, J.-M. (2001) “International Organizations, the Evolution of International
Politics, and Legitimacy”, in J.-M. Coicaud and V. Heiskanen (eds) The Legitimacy
330 References
of International Organizations, Tokyo and New York: United Nations UP, pp.
189–220.
Congressional Research Service [CRS] (1993) Treaties and Other International
Agreements: The Role of the United States Senate, Washington, DC: Government
Printing Office.
Constas, D. (ed.) The Greek–Turkish Conflict in the 1990s: Domestic and External
Influences, New York: St. Martin’s Press, pp. 157–163.
Cooley, A. and Ron, J. (2002) “The NGO Scramble”, International Security 27(1): 5–39.
Cooper, R. (2003) The Breaking of Nations, London: Atlantic Books.
Cortell, A.P. and Davis, J.W. (1996) “How Do International Institutions Matter? The
Domestic Impact of International Rules and Norms”, International Studies
Quarterly 40(4): 451–78.
Cortell, A.P. and Davis, J.W. (2000) “Understanding the Domestic Impact of Inter-
national Norms: A Research Agenda”, International Studies Review 2(1): 65–87.
Couloumbis, T. (1983) The United States, Greece and Turkey: The Troubled Triangle,
New York: Praeger.
Couloumbis, T. (1994) “Introduction: The Impact of EC Membership on Greece’s
Foreign Policy Profile”, in P. Kazakos and P.C. Ioakimidis (eds) Greece and EC
Membership Evaluated, London: Pinter Publishers, pp. 189–98.
Council of Europe Assembly (2004) “Honouring of Obligations and Commitments by
Bosnia and Herzegovina”, Doc. 10200, 4 June.
Council of Europe Assembly (2005) “The Way towards the Future of Bosnia and
Herzegovina Goes through The Hague”, 21 June.
Council on Foreign Relations (2005) In Support of Arab Democracy: Why and How,
Task Force Report 54, New York: Council on Foreign Relations.
Cousens, E. and Kumar, C. (2001) Peacebuilding as Politics, Boulder, CO: Lynne
Rienner.
Cox, M. (2001) “State Building and Post-Conflict Reconstruction: Lessons from
Bosnia”, CASIN Project, Online at <http://www.209.85.129.104/search?q=
cache:I5JZMwbF_rEJ:www.casin.ch/web/pdf/cox.pdf+Marcus+Cox,+state+
building+and+postconflict+reconstruction&hl=en&ct=clnk&cd=1>.
Cox, R.W. (1981) “Social Forces, States and World Orders: Beyond International
Relations Theory”, Millennium: Journal of International Studies 10(2): 126–55.
Crocker, A.C., Hampson, O.F. and Aall, P. (1999) “Multiparty Mediation and the
Conflict Cycle” in Crocker, Hampson and Aall (eds) Herding Cats: Multiparty
Mediation in a Complex World, Washington, DC: United States Institute of Peace,
pp. 19–45.
Croft, S. (2000) “The EU, NATO and Europeanization: The Return of Architectural
Debate”, European Security 9(2): 1–20.
Crone, D. (1993) “Does Hegemony Matter? The Reorganization of the Pacific Political
Economy”, World Politics 45(4): 501–25.
Crozier, M. (1964) The Bureaucratic Phenomenon, Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Curtis, D. (2001) “Politics and Humanitarian Aid: Debates, Dilemmas, and Dissen-
sion”, in Humanitarian Policy Group Report 10, POLIS at the University of Leeds
and CAFOD Conference, London: Overseas Development Institute, 1 February.
Cusimano, M. (2000) “Beyond Sovereignty: The Rise of Transsovereign Problems”, in
M. Cusimano (ed.) Beyond Sovereignty: Issues for a Global Agenda, Boston and
New York: Bedford/St. Martin’s, pp. 1–40.
References 331
Cutts, M. (1998) “Politics and Humanitarianism”, Refugee Survey Quarterly 17(1): 1–15.
Daalder I. and Lindsey, J. (2003) American Unbound: The Bush Revolution in Foreign
Policy, Washington, DC: Brookings Institution.
Daalder, I. and O’Hanlan, M. (2001) Winning Ugly: NATO’s War to Save Kosovo.
Washington, DC: Brookings Press.
Dawisha, K. and Parrott, B. (eds) (1997) Conflict, Cleavage, and Change in Central
Asia and the Caucasus, Cambridge: Cambridge UP.
Deering, C.J. and Maltzman, F.M. (1999) “The Politics of Executive Orders: Legislative
Constraints on Presidential Power”, Political Research Quarterly 52(4): 767–83.
Dehio, L. (1948) Gleichgewicht oder Hegemonie. Betrachtung über ein Grundproblem
der neueren Staatengeschichte, Krefeld: Scherpr.
Deibert, R.J. and Gross Stein, J.G. (2002) “Hacking Networks of Terror”, International
Organization Dialogue 1(1): 1–14.
Der Derian, J. (2001) Virtuous War, Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Dessler, D. (1989) “What’s at Stake in the Agent-Structure Debate?”, International
Organization 43(3): 441–73.
Deutsch, K., Burrell, S. and Kann, R. (1957) Political Community and the North
Atlantic Area: International Organization in the Light of Historical Experience,
Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP.
Diamond, L. (1996) “Is the Third Wave Over?”, Journal of Democracy 7(3):
20–37.
Dibb, P. (1995) Towards a New Balance of Power in Asia, Adelphi Paper 295, Oxford:
Oxford UP.
Diehl, P.F. (1993) “Institutional Alternatives to Traditional U.N. Peacekeeping: An
Assessment of Regional and Multinational Options”, Armed Forces and Society
19(2): 209–30.
Diehl, P.F. (2000) “Forks in the Road: Theoretical and Policy Concerns for 21st
Century Peacekeeping”, Global Society 14(3): 337–60.
Diez, T., Stetter, S., and Albert, M. (2006) “The European Union and Border Con-
flicts: The Transformative Power of Integration”, International Organization 60(3):
563–93.
DiMaggio, P. and Powell, W. (1991) The New Institutionalism in Organizational
Analysis, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Dimitras, P. (1985) “Greece: A New Danger”, Foreign Policy 78(19): 134–50.
Dimitrova, A. and Pridham, G. (2004) “International Actors and Democracy Pro-
motion in Central and Eastern Europe: The Integration Model and its Limits”,
Democratization 11(5): 91–112.
Dobbin, F. (1994) “Cultural Models of Organization: The Social Construction of
Rational Organizing Principles”, in J. Martin (ed.) The Sociology of Culture,
Boston: Basil Blackwell, pp. 117–41.
Donais, T. (2002) “The Politics of Privatization in Post-Dayton Bosnia”, Southeast
European Politics 3(1): 3–19.
Dongfeng, R. (2004) “The Central Asia Policies of China, Russia and the USA, and
the Shanghai Cooperation Organization Process: A View from China”, Online at
<http://www.editors.sipri.se/pubs/CentralAsiaSCO.pdf> (accessed on 15 January
2006).
Donini, A. (2004) The Future of Humanitarian Action: Implications of Iraq and Other
Recent Crises, Medford, MA: Tufts University, Feinstein International Famine
Center.
332 References
Donno, D. and Russett, B. (2004) “Islam, Authoritarianism, and Female Empower-
ment: What Are the Linkages?”, World Politics 56(4): 582–607.
Dorn, W. (1998) “Regional Peacekeeping is not the Way”, Peacekeeping and Inter-
national Relations 27(3/4): 1–3.
Dosch, J. (2003) “Changing Security Cultures in Europe and Southeast Asia:
Implications for Inter-Regionalism”, Asia Europe Journal 1(4): 483–501.
Downs, G.W., Rocke, D.M. and Barsoom, P.N. (1996) “Is the Good News about
Compliance Good News about Cooperation?”, International Organization 50(3):
379–406.
Downs, G.W., Rocke, D.M. and Barsoom, P.N. (1998) “Managing the Evolution of
Multilateralism”, International Organization 52(2): 397–419.
Doyle, M. (1983) “Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs”, Philosophy and Public
Affairs 12(3): 205–35.
Doyle, M. and Sambanis, N. (2000) “International Peacebuilding: A Theoretical and
Quantitative Analysis”, American Political Science Review 94(4): 779–801.
Doyle, M. and Sambanis, N. (2006) Making War and Building Peace: United Nations
Peace Operations. Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP.
Doyle, M., Johnstone, I. and Orr, R. (eds) (1997) Keeping the Peace: Multidimensional
UN Operations in Cambodia and El Salvador, Cambridge: Cambridge UP.
Dreher, A., Sturm, J-E. and Vreeland, J. (2006), “Does Membership on the UN Secur-
ity Council Influence IMF”, Swiss Federal Institute of Technology, Working
Paper, No. 131.
Duffield, J. (1994) “Explaining the Long Peace in Europe: The Contributions of
Regional Security Regimes”, Review of International Studies 20(4): 269–88.
Duffield, J. (1994–5) “NATO’s Functions after the Cold War”, Political Science
Quarterly 109(5): 763–87.
Duffield, J. (2006) “International Security Institutions: Rules, Tools, Schools or
Fools?”, in R.A. Rhodes, S.A. Binder and B. Rockman (eds) The Oxford Handbook
of Political Institutions, Oxford: Oxford UP, pp. 633–53.
Duffield, M. (2001) Global Governance and the New Wars: The Merging of Development
and Security, New York: Zed Press.
Dunn, D. (2003) “Myths, Motivations and ‘Misunderestimations’: The Bush Admini-
stration and Iraq”, International Affairs 79(2): 279–98.
Durch, W.J. (ed.) (1996) UN Peacekeeping, American Politics and the Uncivil Wars of
the 1990s, New York: St. Martin’s Press.
Eberwein, W-D. (1995) “The Future of International Warfare: Toward a Global
Security Community?”, International Political Studies Review 16(4): 341–60.
Eisenstadt, S.N. and Giesen, B. (1995) “The Construction of Collective Identity”,
European Journal of Sociology 36: 72–102.
Elbadawi, I. and Sambanis, N. (2000) “External Interventions and the Duration of
Civil Wars”, paper presented at the workshop on the Economics of Civil Violence,
Princeton University, NJ, 18–19 March.
Elgström, O. and Jönsson, C. (2000) “Negotiation in the European Union: Bargaining
or Problem-solving, Journal of European Public Policy 7(5): 684–704.
Ellwood, D. (ed.) (1989) The Marshall Plan Forty Years After: Lessons for the Inter-
national System Today, The Bologna Center of the Johns Hopkins University
School of Advanced International Studies.
Elman, M.F. (1999) “The Never-Ending Story: Democracy and Peace”, International
Studies Review 1(3): 87–103.
References 333
Elster, J. (ed.) (1998) Deliberative Democracy, New York: Cambridge UP.
Elster, J. (1999) Alchemies of the Mind: Rationality and the Emotions, Cambridge:
Cambridge UP.
Emmerson, D.K. (2005) “Security, Community, and Democracy in Southeast Asia:
Analyzing ASEAN”, Japanese Journal of Political Science 6(2): 165–85.
Eriksson, M. and Wallensteen, P. (2004) “Appendix 3A. Patterns of Major Armed
Conflicts, 1990–2003”, in SIPRI Yearbook 2004: Armaments, Disarmament and
International Security, Oxford: Oxford UP.
Europäische Union (2005) Vertrag über eine Verfassung für Europa. Luxemburg: Amt
für Amtliche Veröffentlichungen der Europäischen Gemeinschaften.
European Commission (2003) COM (2003) 692, Report from the Commission to the
Council on the Preparedness of Bosnia and Herzegovina to Negotiate a Stabilisation
and Association Agreement with the European Union, Brussels, 19 November.
European Council (2003) A Secure Europe in a Better World – European Security
Strategy, Brussels: European Institute for Security Studies, 12 December.
European Stability Initiative (ESI) (2004) Governance and Democracy in Bosnia and
Herzegovina: Post Industrial Society and the Authoritarian Temptation, Online at
<http://unpan.un.org/intradoc/groups/public/documents/UNTC/UNPAN018624.pdf>
(last accessed 17 April 2006).
European Union Council (2004) “EU Solidarity Programme on the Consequences of
Terrorist Threats and Attacks (revised/widened CBRN Programme) – Adoption”,
DG 1, 15480/04, 1 December.
Falk, R. (2002) “Revisiting Westphalia, Discovering Post-Westphalia”, Journal of
Ethics 6(4): 311–52.
Farer, T. (2002) “Beyond the Charter Frame: Unilateralism or Condominium Frame?”,
American Journal of International Law 96(2): 359–64.
Fearon, J.D. (1995) “Rationalist Explanations for War”, International Organization
49(3): 379–414.
Fearon, J.D. (1997) “Signaling Foreign Policy Interests: Tying Hands versus Sinking
Costs”, Journal of Conflict Resolution 41(1): 68–90.
Fearon, J.D. (1998) “Bargaining, Enforcement, and International Cooperation”,
International Organization 62(2): 269–305.
Fearon, J.D. (2005) “Reforming International Institutions to Promote International
Peace and Security”, Paper prepared for the International Task Force on Global
Public Goods, 6 January.
Fearon, J.D. and Laitin, D.D. (2003) “Ethnicity, Insurgency, and Civil War”, American
Political Science Review 91(1): 75–90.
Fearon, J.D. and Laitin, D.D. (2004) “Neotrusteeship and the Problem of Weak
States”, International Security 28(4): 5–74.
Festić, A. and Rausche, A. (2004) “War by Other Means: How Bosnia’s Clandes-
tine Political Economies Obstruct Peace and State Building”, Problems of Post-
Communism 51(3): 27–34.
Finnemore, M. (1993) “International Organizations as Teachers of Norms: The
United Nations Educational, Scientific, and Cultural Organization and Science
Policy”, International Organization 47(4): 556–97.
Finnemore, M. (1996) National Interests in International Society, Ithaca, NY: Cornell
UP.
Finnemore, M. and Sikkink, K. (1998) “International Norm Dynamics and Political
Change”, International Organization 52(4): 887–917.
334 References
Finnemore, M. and Sikkink, K. (1999a) “International Norms and Political Change”,
in P. Katzenstein, R. Keohane and S. Krasner (eds) Exploration and Contestation in
the Study of World Politics, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 247–78.
Finnemore, M. and Sikkink, K. (1999b) “Taking Stock: The Constructivist Research
Program in International Relations and Comparative Politics”, Annual Reviews of
Political Science 4: 391–416.
Fisher, J.R., and Keashley, L. (1991) “The Potential Complementarity of Mediation
within a Contingency Model of Third Party Intervention”, Journal of Peace
Research 28(1): 29–42.
Fleishman, J.L. and Aufses, A.H. (1976) “Law and Orders: The Problem of Presidential
Legislation”, Law and Contemporary Problems 40(3): 1–45.
Forsythe, D. (2005) The Humanitarians: The International Committee of the Red
Cross, New York: Cambridge UP.
Fortna, V.P. (2004a) “Does Peacekeeping Keep Peace? International Intervention
and the Duration of Peace After Civil War”, International Studies Quarterly 48(2):
269–92.
Fortna, V.P. (2004b) “Interstate Peacekeeping: Causal Mechanisms and Empirical
Effects”, World Politics 56(4): 481–519.
Foucault, M. (1991) “Governmentality”, in G. Burchell, C. Gordon and P. Miller
(eds) The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality, Hemel Hempstead, Herts:
Harvester Wheatsheaf, pp. 87–104.
Franck, T. (1999) “Lessons of Kosovo”, American Journal of International Law 93(4):
857–60.
Fravel, M.T. (2005) “Regime Insecurity and International Cooperation: Explaining
China’s Compromises in Territorial Disputes”, International Security 30(1):
46–83.
Frederking, B. (2003) “Constructing Post-Cold War Collective Security”, American
Political Science Review 97(3): 363–78.
Frieden, J. (2004) “One Europe, One Vote? The Political Economy of European
Union Representation in International Organizations”, European Union Politics
5(2): 261–76.
Friis, L. and Murphy, A. (2000) “Turbo-charged Negotiations: the EU and the
Stability Pact for South Eastern Europe”, Journal of European Public Policy 7(5):
767–86.
Fukuyama, F. (2004) State Building: Governance and Order in the Twenty-First
Century, London: Profile.
Gallant, N. and Stubbs, R. (1997) “APEC’s Dilemmas: Institution-building Around
the Pacific Basin”, Pacific Affairs 70(2): 203–18.
Gallarotti, G. (2001) “The Limits of International Organization: Systemic Failure in
the Management of International Relations” in L. Martin and B. Simmons (eds)
International Institutions, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 365–403.
Gardner, L.C. (1984) A Covenant with Power: American and World Order from Wilson
to Reagan, New York: Oxford UP.
Garton, A.T. (2001) “Is There a Good Terrorist?” New York Review of Books, 29
November: 30–3.
Geipel, G.L. (1999) “The Cost of Enlarging NATO”, in J. Sperling (ed.) Two Tiers or
Two Speeds? The European Security Order and the Enlargement of the European
Union and NATO, Manchester: Manchester UP, pp. 160–80.
Gerhards, Jürgen, and Michael Hölscher (2005) Kulturelle Unterschied in der
References 335
Europäischen Union. Ein Vergleich zwischen Mitgliedsländern, Beitrittskandidaten
und der Türkei. Wiesbaden: VS Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften.
Gheciu, A. (2005) “Security Institutions as Agents of Socialization? NATO and the
‘New Europe’ ”, International Organization 59(4): 973–1012.
Giddens, A. (1991) Modernity and Self Identity in the Late Modern Age, Cambridge:
Polity Press.
Gill, B. (2004) “China’s New Security Multilateralism and its Implications for the
Asia-Pacific Region”, in SIPRI Yearbook 2004: Armaments, Disarmament and
International Security, Oxford: Oxford UP, pp. 381–8.
Gilpin, R. (1981) War and Change in World Politics, Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP.
Gleason, G. and Shaihutdinov, M.E. (2005) “Collective Security and Non-State
Actors in Eurasia”, International Studies Perspectives 6(2): 274–84.
Gleditsch, N.P., Strand, H., Eriksson, M., Sollenberg, M. and Wallensteen, P. (2001)
“Armed Conflict, 1945–99: A New Dataset”, Journal of Peace Research 39(5):
615–37.
Glennon, M.J. (2003) “Why the Security Council Failed”, Foreign Affairs 82(3): 16–35.
Glenny, Misha (2001) Memorandum submitted to the Select Committee on Foreign
Affairs 27 March 2001, Online at <http://www.publications.parliament.uk/pa/
cm2001/cmselect/cmfaff/246/1021303.htm> (last accessed 22 December 2004).
Goldgeier, J.M. (1999) Not Whether but When: The US Decision to Enlarge NATO,
Washington, DC: Brookings Institution.
Goldsmith, J.L. and Posner, E.A. (2005) The Limits of International Law, New York:
Oxford UP.
Goldstein, J. and Martin, L. (2000) “Legalization, Trade Liberalization, and Domestic
Politics: A Cautionary Note”, International Organization 54(3): 503–632.
Goldstone, A. (2004), “UNTAET with Hindsight”, Global Governance 10(1): 83–98.
Gordon, P.H. (1998) “Europe’s Uncommon Foreign Policy”, International Security
22(1): 74–100.
Gourevitch, P. (1998) We Wish To Inform You That Tomorrow We Will be Killed With
Our Families, New York: Farrar, Straus & Giroux.
Grabbe, H. (2001) “How Does Europeanization Affect CEE Governance? Condition-
ality, Diffusion and Diversity”, Journal of European Public Policy 8(6): 1013–31.
Greenberg, J. (1979), “Consistent Majority Rule over Compact Sets of Alternatives”,
Econometrica 47(3): 627–36.
Greenberg Research (1999) The People on War Report: ICRC Worldwide Consultation
on the Rules of War, Geneva: International Committee of the Red Cross, October,
Online at <http://www.icrc.org/icrceng.nsf>.
Grieco, J.M. (1988) “Anarchy and the Limits of Cooperation: A Realist Critique of
the Newest Liberal Institutionalism”, International Organization 42(3): 485–507.
Grieco, J.M. (1990) Cooperation among Nations: Europe, America, and Non-tariff
Barriers to Trade, Ithaca, NY: Cornell UP.
Guang, P. (2005) “The Astana Summit. A New Stage in the Development of the
Shanghai Cooperation Organization”, Asia-Europe Journal 3(4): 501–6.
Gusmao, X. (2004) “Peacekeeping and Peacebuilding in Timor Leste”, Seminar on
the Role of the UN in Timor Leste, Dili, 26 November.
Guvenc, S. (1998–9) “Turkey’s Changing Perception of Greece’s Membership in the
European Union”, Turkish Review of Balkan Studies 4: 103–30.
Haacke, J. (2003) “ASEAN’s Diplomatic and Security Culture: A Constructivist
Assessment”, International Relations of the Asia-Pacific 3(1): 57–87.
336 References
Haas, E. (1983) “Regime Decay: Conflict Management and International Organiza-
tions, 1945–1981”, International Organization 37(2): 189–256.
Habermas, J. (2002) “Letter to America”, The Nation, 16 December.
Haftendorn, H., Keohane, R. and Wallander, C. (1999) Imperfect Unions. Security
Institutions over Time and Space, Oxford: Oxford UP.
Hall, P. and Taylor, R. (1996) “Political Science and the Three New Institutionalisms”,
Political Studies 44(5): 936–57.
Halliday, F. (2001) “The Romance of Non-State Actors”, in D. Josselin and W. Wallace
(eds) Non-State Actors in World Politics, London: Palgrave, pp. 21–37.
Hamill, J. and Lee, D. (2001) “A Middle Power Paradox? South African Diplomacy in
the Post-Apartheid Era”, International Relations 15(4): 33–59.
Hampton, M.N. (1998–9) “NATO, Germany and the United States: Creating Positive
Identity in Trans-Atlantia”, Security Studies 8(2/3): 235–69.
Hampton, M.N. and Sperling, J. (2002) “Positive/Negative Identity in the Euro-Atlantic
Communities: Germany’s Past, Europe’s Future?”, Journal of European Integration
24(4): 281–302.
Hanrieder, W. (1978) “Dissolving International Politics: Reflections on the Nation-
State”, American Political Science Review 72(3): 1276–87.
Hansen, A. (2004) “Security and Defence: The EU Police Mission in Bosnia-
Herzegovina” in W. Carlnaes, H. Sjursen and B. White (eds) Contemporary European
Foreign Policy, London: Sage, pp. 173–85.
Hardt, M. and Negri, A. (2000) Empire, Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP.
Harnisch, S. and Maull, H.W. (2001) “Introduction”, in Harnisch and Maull (eds)
Germany as a Civilian Power? The Foreign Policy of the Berlin Republic, Manchester:
Manchester UP, pp. 1–9.
Harper, J.L. (1996) American Visions of Europe, New York: Cambridge UP.
Hasenclever, A. (2001) Die Macht der Moral in der Internationalen Politik. Militärische
Interventionen Westlicher Staaten in Somalia, Ruanda und Bosnien-Herzegowina,
Frankfurt: Campus.
Hasenclever, A., Mayer, P. and Rittberger, V. (1997) Theories of International Regimes,
Cambridge: Cambridge UP.
Hassner, P. (2002) The United States: The Empire of Force or the Force of Empire?,
Chaillot Papers No. 54, Paris: Institute for Security Studies, European
Union.
Havel, V. (1999) “Kosovo and the End of the Nation-State”, New York Review of
Books, 10 June, pp. 4–6.
Hawkins, D., Lake, D., Nielson, D. and Tierney, M. (eds) (2005) Delegation Under
Anarchy: States, International Organizations, and Principal Agent Theory, book
manuscript.
Hayner, P.B. (2001) Unspeakable Truths: Confronting State Terror and Atrocity,
New York: Routledge.
Held, D. (1995) Democracy and the Global Order, Cambridge: Polity.
Heldt, B. (2001) “Conditions for Successful Intrastate Peacekeeping Missions”, Work-
ing Paper, National Defence College of Sweden, June.
Heldt, B. (2002) “Peacekeeping Operations by Regional Actors, 1948–2000”,
Unpublished paper, National Defence College of Sweden, 18 November.
Heldt, B. (2004) “UN-led or Non-UN-led Peacekeeping Operations?”, IRI Review 9(2):
113–38.
Heldt, B. and Wallensteen, P. (2005) Peacekeeping Operations: Global Patterns of
References 337
Intervention and Success, 1948–2004, Sandöverken: Folke Bernadotte Academy
Publications.
Hemmer, C. and Katzenstein, P.J. (2002) “Why is There No NATO in Asia? Collective
Identity, Regionalism, and the Origins of Multilateralism”, International Organiza-
tion 56(3): 575–607.
Henderson, K. (ed.) (1999) Back to Europe, London: UCL Press.
Héritier, A. (1999) Policy-Making and Diversity in Europe: Escaping Deadlock,
Cambridge: Cambridge UP.
Herrmann, R.K. 2004. “George W. Bush’s Foreign Policy”, in C. Campbell and
B. Rockman (eds) The George W. Bush Presidency, Washington, DC: CQ Press,
pp. 191–225.
Herz, J.H. (1957) “The Rise and Demise of the Territorial State”, World Politics 9(4):
473–93.
Higgins, E.T. (2000) “Making a Good Decision: Value from Fit”, American Psycholo-
gist 55(11): 1217–30.
Hoare, Q. and Nowell-Smith, G. (eds) (1972) Selections from the Prison Notebooks of
Antonio Gramsci, London: Lawrence & Wishart.
Hoffmann, S. (1998) World Disorders: Troubled Peace in the Post-Cold War Era,
Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Holsti, K.J. (1995) “War, Peace and the State of the State”, International Political
Science Review 16(4): 310–39.
Holsti, O.R. (1996) Public Opinion and American Foreign Policy, Ann Arbor, MI:
Michigan UP.
Holsti, O.R. (2001) “Public Opinion and Foreign Policy”, in R. Lieber (ed.) Eagle
Rules: Foreign Policy and American Primacy in the 21st Century, Englewood Cliffs,
NJ: Prentice Hall, pp. 16–46.
Holzgrefe, J.L. and Keohane, R. (eds) (2004) Humanitarian Intervention, New York:
Cambridge UP.
Homer-Dixon, T.F. (1995) “On the Threshold: Environmental Changes as Causes of
Acute Conflict”, in S. Lynn-Jones and S. Miller (eds) Global Dangers: Changing
Dimensions of International Security, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 43–83.
Horowitz, D. (1985) Ethnic Groups in Conflict, Berkeley and Los Angeles: University
of California Press.
Houghton, R. and Robertson, K. (eds) (2001) “Humanitarian Action: Learning from
Evaluation”, ALNAP Annual Review Series, London: Overseas Development
Institute.
Howard, M. (1993) “The Historical Development of the UN’s Role in International
Security”, in A. Roberts and B. Kingsbury (eds) United Nations, Divided World:
The UN’s Roles in International Relations, New York: Oxford UP.
Howard, M. (2000) The Invention of Peace and War, London: Profile Books.
Howell, W.G. (2003) Power Without Persuasion: The Politics of Direct Presidential
Action, Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP.
Huelshoff, M.G., Sperling, J. and Hess, M. (2005) “Is Germany a “Good European”?
German Compliance with EU Law”, German Politics 14(3): 354–70.
Hunjoon, K. and Sikkink, K. (2007) Do Human Rights Trials Make a Difference?,
paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Political Science Associ-
ation, Chicago, Illinois, August 30–September 2.
Huntington, S.P. (1968) Political Order in Changing Societies, New Haven, CT: Yale UP.
Huntington, S.P. (1999) “The Lonely Superpower”, Foreign Affairs 78(2): 35–49.
338 References
Hurd, I. (1997) “Security Council Reform: Informal Membership and Practice” in
B. Russett (ed.) The Once and Future Security Council, New York: St. Martin’s
Press, pp. 135–52.
Hurd, I. (1999) “Legitimacy and Authority in International Politics”, International
Organization 53(2): 379–408.
Hurd, I. (2005) “The Strategic Use of Liberal Internationalism: Libya and the UN
Sanctions, 1999–2003”, International Organization 59(3): 495–526.
Huth, P. (1988) Extended Deterrence and the Prevention of War, New Haven, CT:
Yale UP.
Hyde-Price, A. (2000) Germany and the European Order: Enlarging NATO and the EU,
Manchester: Manchester UP.
Iatrides, J.O. (2000) “NATO and Aegean Disputes: The Cold War and After”, in A.
Chircop, A. Gerolymatos and J.O. Iatrides (eds) The Aegean Sea After the Cold
War. Security and Law of the Sea Issues, London: Macmillan, pp. 32–46.
Ignatieff, M. (ed.) (2001) Human Rights as Politics and Idolatry, Princeton, NJ:
Princeton UP.
Ignatieff, M. (2003) Empire Lite: Nation-building in Bosnia, Kosovo and Afghanistan,
London: Vintage.
IISS (2004) The Military Balance, 2004–2005, Oxford: Oxford UP.
Ikenberry, G.J. (1989) “Rethinking the Origins of American Hegemony”, Political
Science Quarterly 104(3): 375–400.
Ikenberry, G.J. (2000) Whither Pax Americana? Balance of Power, Hegemony, and the
Future of American Preponderance, manuscript. Washington, DC.
Ikenberry, G.J. (2001) After Victory: Institutions, Strategic Restraint, and the Rebuild-
ing of Order After Major War, Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP.
Ikenberry, G.J. (2002) “America’s Imperial Ambition”, Foreign Affairs 81(5): 44–60.
Ikenberry, G.J. (2003) “State Power and the Institutional Bargain: America’s Ambiva-
lent Economic and Security Multilateralism”, in R. Foot, S.N. MacFarlane and
M. Mastanduno (eds) U.S. Hegemony and International Organizations: The United
States and Multilateral Institutions, New York: Oxford UP, pp. 49–70.
Ikenberry, G.J. (2005) “Ruling Unipolarity: American Power and the Logic of Inter-
national Order”, unpublished paper.
Ikenberry, G.J. and Kupchan, C.A. (1990) “Socialization and Hegemonic Power”,
International Organization 44(4): 283–315.
Ikenberry, G.J. and Tsuchiyama, J. (2002) “Between Balance of Power and Community:
The Future of Multilateral Security Co-operation in the Asia-Pacific”, International
Relations of the Asia-Pacific 2(1): 69–94.
IMF (1949–98) Financial Statistics, Washington, DC: IMF.
IMF (2004) Direction of Trade Statistics Yearbook 2004, Washington, DC: IMF.
IMF (2006) World Economic Outlook Database, September.
Inoguchi, T. and Bacon, P. (2006) “Japan’s Emerging Role as a “Global Ordinary
Power” ”, International Relations of the Asian-Pacific 6(1): 1–21.
International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty (2001) “The
Responsibility to Protect”, Ottawa: International Development Research Centre.
International Crisis Group (2003) “Bosnia’s Nationalist Governments: Paddy
Ashdown and the Paradoxes of State Building”, Balkans Report no. 146, 22
July.
International Crisis Group (2005) “Bosnia’s Stalled Police Reform: No Progress, No
EU”, Europe Report No. 164, September.
References 339
International Organization (2005) Special Issue on “International Institutions and
Socialization in Europe”, 59(4): 860–1079.
Jabri, V. (1996) Discourses on Violence, Manchester: Manchester UP.
Jackson, R. (1990) Quasi-States, New York: Cambridge UP.
Jakobsen, P.V. (2002) “The Transformation of United Nations Peace Operations in the
1990s”, Cooperation and Conflict 73(3): 267–82.
Jepperson, R.L., Wendt, A. and Katzenstein, P.J. (1996) “Norms, Identity, Culture and
National Security”, in P.J. Katzenstein (ed.) The Culture of National Security:
Norms and Identity in World Politics, New York: Columbia UP, pp. 33–74.
Jervis, R. (2002) “Theories of War in an Era of Leading Power Peace”, American
Political Science Review 96(1): 1–14.
Jervis, R. (2003) “The Compulsive Empire”, Foreign Policy 137 (July/August): 82–7.
Jonson, L. (1998) Russia and Central Asia: A New Web of Relations, London: Royal
Institute of International Affairs.
Johnston, A.I. (2001) “Treating International Institutions as Social Environments”,
International Studies Quarterly 45(4): 487–515.
Judah, T. (2002) Kosovo: War and Revenge, New Haven, CJ: Yale UP.
Kagan, R. (2002) “Power and Weakness”, Policy Review 113 (June–July), Online at
<http://www.policyreview.org/JUN02/kagan.html>.
Kagan, R. (2003) Of Paradise and Power. America and Europe in the New World Order,
New York: Knopf.
Kang, D. (2003) “Getting Asia Wrong: The Need for New Analytical Frameworks”,
International Security 27(1): 57–85.
Kant, I. (1795/1983) “To Perpetual Peace. A Philosophical Sketch”, in T. Humphrey
(ed.) Immanual Kant. Perpetual Peace and Other Essays on Politics, History, and
Morals, Indianapolis: Hackett, pp. 107–43.
Karaosmanoglu, L.A. (1988) “Turkey and the Southern Flank: Domestic and External
Contexts” in J. Chipman (ed.) NATO’s Southern Allies: Internal and External
Challenges, London: Routledge, pp. 85–118.
Katzenstein, P. (1996) The Culture of National Security, New York: Columbia UP.
Katzenstein, P. (1997) “The Cultural Foundations of Murakami’s Polymorphic
Liberalism”, in K. Yamamura (ed.) A Vision of a New Liberalism? Critical Essays,
Stanford, CA: Stanford UP, pp. 23–40.
Katzenstein, P.J. (2002) “September 11 in Comparative Perspective: The Antiterrorism
Campaigns of Germany and Japan”, Dialogue-IO 1(1): 45–56.
Kaufman, S.J. (2001) Modern Hatreds: The Symbolic Politics of Ethnic War, Ithaca,
NY: Cornell UP.
Kay, S. (2003) “Geopolitical Constraints and Institutional Innovation: The Dynamics
of Multilateralism in Eurasia,” in J. Sperling, S. Kay and S.V. Papacosma (eds)
Limiting Institutions? The Challenge of Eurasian Security Governance, Manchester:
Manchester UP, pp. 125–43.
Keck, M. and Sikkink, K. (1998) Activists beyond Borders: Transnational Advocacy
Networks in International Politics, Ithaca, NY: Cornell UP.
Kelly, C. (1998) “On the Relief-to-Development Continuum”, Disasters 30(2): 174–5.
Kelsen, H. (1948) “Collective Security and Collective Self-Defense under the
Charter of the United Nations”, The American Journal of International Law 42(4):
783–96.
Keohane, R.O. (1984) After Hegemony: Cooperation and Discord in the World Political
Economy, Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP.
340 References
Keohane, R.O. (1986) “Reciprocity in International Relations”, International Organ-
ization 40(1): 1–27.
Keohane, R.O. (1988) “Alliances, Threats, and the Uses of Neorealism”, International
Security 13(1): 169–76.
Keohane, R.O. (1989) International Institutions and State Power: Essays in Inter-
national Relations Theory, Boulder, CO.: Westview Press.
Keohane, R.O. (2001) “Governance in a Partially Globalized World”, American Polit-
ical Science Review 95(1): 1–13.
Keohane, R. and Axelrod, R. (1986) “Achieving Cooperation Under Anarchy”,
in K. Oye (ed.) Cooperation Under Anarchy, Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP, pp.
226–45.
Keohane, R.O. and Martin, L.L. (1995) “The Promise of Institutionalist Theory”,
International Security 20(1): 39–51.
Khoo, N. (2004) “Deconstructing the ASEAN Security Community: A Review Essay”,
International Relations of the Asia-Pacific 4(1): 35–46.
Kim, S.Y. and Russett, B. (1996) “The New Politics of Voting Alignments in the
United Nations General Assembly”, International Organization 50(4): 629–52.
King, G. and Ragsdale, L. (1988) The Elusive Executive: Discovering Statistical
Patterns in the Presidency, Washington, DC: Congressional Quarterly Press.
Kirchner, E.J. and Sperling, J. (2007) Governing European Security, Manchester:
Manchester UP.
Kirisci, K. and Carkoglu, A. (2003) “Perceptions of Greeks and Greek-Turkish
Rapprochement by the Turkish Public”, in B. Rubin and A. Carkoglu (eds), Greek-
Turkish Relations in an Era of Détente, London: Frank Cass.
Knaus, G. and Fox, M. (2004) “Bosnia Herzegovina: Europeanisation by Decree?”, in
J. Batt (ed.) The Western Balkans: Moving on, EU-ISS Chaillot Paper 70, pp. 55–68.
Knock, T.J. (1992) To End All Wars: Woodrow Wilson and the Quest for a New World
Order, New York: Oxford UP.
Koremenos, B., Lipson, C. and Snidal, D. (2001a) “The Rational Design of Inter-
national Institutions”, International Organization 55(4): 761–99.
Koremenos, B., Lipson, C. and Snidal, D. (2001b) “Rational Design: Looking back to
Move Forward”, International Organization 55(4): 1051–82.
Koucik, S. and Kokoski, R. (eds) (1994) Conventional Arms Control: Perspectives on
Verification, Oxford: Oxford UP.
Kowert, P. and Legro, J. (1996) “Norms, Identity and their Limits: A Theoretical
Reprise” in P. Katzenstein (ed.) The Culture of National Security: Norms and
Identity in World Politics, New York: Columbia UP, pp. 451–97.
Krahenbuhl, P. (2000) “Conflict in the Balkans: Human Tragedies and the Challenge
to Independent Humanitarian Action”, International Review of the Red Cross 837:
11–29.
Kramer, H. (1987) “Turkish Application for Accession to the European Community
and the Greek Factor”, Europa Archiv 42(10): 605–14.
Krasner, S.D. (1991) “Global Communications and National Power: Life on the
Pareto Frontier”, World Politics 43(3): 336–66.
Krasner, S.D. (1995–6) “Compromising Westphalia”, International Security 20(3):
115–51.
Krasner, S.D. (1999) Sovereignty: Organized Hypocrisy, Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP.
Krasner, S.D. (2001) “Abiding Sovereignty”, International Political Science Review
22(3): 229–51.
References 341
Krebs, R. (1999) “Perverse Institutionalism: NATO and the Greco-Turkish Conflict”,
International Organization 53(2): 343–77.
Krell, G. (2003) Arroganz der Macht, Arroganz der Ohnmacht. Der Irak, die Weltord-
nungspolitik der USA und die Transatlantischen Beziehungen, HSFK-Report 1/2003,
Frankfurt/Main: Hessische Stiftung Friedens- und Konfliktforschung.
Kreps, David M. (1990) Game Theory and Economic Modeling, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Kritz, N.J. (1996) “Coming to Terms with Atrocities: A Review of Accountability
Mechanisms for Mass Violations of Human Rights”, Law and Contemporary Prob-
lems 59(4): 127–52.
Kritz, N.J. (1999) “War Crime Trials: Who Should Conduct Them – and How”, in
B. Cooper (ed.) War Crimes: The Legacy of Nuremberg, New York: TV Books,
pp. 168–82.
Kubbig, B.W. (1988) Amerikanische Rüstungskontrollpolitik: Die innergesellschaftlichen
Kräfteverhältnisse in der ersten Amtszeit Reagans (1981–1985), Frankfurt/Main:
Campus.
Kull, S. (2005) Opportunities for Bipartisan Consensus: What Both Republicans and
Democrats Want in US Foreign Policy, Baltimore, MD and Menlo Park, CA: PIPA/
Knowledge Networks Poll, 18 January.
Kupchan, C. (2003) The End of the American Era: U.S. Foreign Policy and the
Geopolitics of the Twenty-First Century, New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
Kupchan, C. and Kupchan, C. (1991) “Concerts, Collective Security and the Future of
Europe”, International Security 16(1): 114–61.
Kupchan, C. and Kupchan, C. (1995) “The Promise of Collective Security”, Inter-
national Security 20(1): 52–61.
Kutnjak, I.S. and O’Connor, S.T. (2005) “The Bosnian Police and Police Integrity”,
European Journal of Sociology 2(4): 428–64.
Kydd, A. (2001) “Trust Building, Trust Breaking: The Dilemma of NATO Enlarge-
ment”, International Organization 55(4): 801–28.
Lang, T. (ed.) (2003) Just Intervention, Georgetown,: Georgetown UP.
Laurenti, J. (1997) Reforming the Security Council: What American Interests?, UNA-
USA Occasional Paper Series, New York, United Nations Association of the
United States.
Law, M.D. and McFarlane, S.N. (1996) “NATO Expansion and European Regional
Security” in D.G. Haglund (ed.) Will NATO Go East? The Debate Over Enlarging the
Atlantic Alliance, Kingston, Ontario: Queen’s University Center for International
Relations.
Layne, C. (2000) “U.S. Hegemony and the Perpetuation of NATO”, Journal of Stra-
tegic Studies 23(3): 59–92.
Leader, N. (2000) The Politics of Principle: The Principles of Humanitarian Action in
Practice, London: Overseas Development Institute.
Lebow, R.N. and Stein, J.G. (1990) “Deterrence: The Elusive Dependent Variable”,
World Politics 42(3): 336–69.
Lehne, S. (2004) “Has the ‘Hour of Europe’ Come at Last? The EU’s Strategy for the
Balkans”, in J. Batt (ed.) The Western Balkans: Moving on, EU-ISS Chaillot Paper
70, pp. 111–24.
Leifer, M. (1996) The ASEAN Regional Forum: Extending ASEAN’s Model of Regional
Security, Adelphi Paper 302, Oxford: Oxford UP.
Liberman, P. (2006) “An Eye for an Eye: Public Support for War against Evildoers”,
International Organization 60(3): 687–722.
342 References
Liberman, P. (2007) “Crime, Punishment, and War”, International Security,
forthcoming.
Linklater, A. (1998) The Transformation of Political Community, Columbia: University
of South Carolina Press.
Linz, J. and Stepan, A. (1996) Problems of Democratic Transition and Consolidation,
Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins UP.
Lipson, C. (1984) “International Cooperation in Economic and Security Affairs”,
World Politics, 37(1): 1–23.
Lipson, C. (1991) “Why Are Some International Agreements Informal?”, International
Organization 45(4): 495–538.
Lipson, C. (2003) Reliable Partners: How Democracies Have Made a Separate Peace,
Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP.
Loescher, G. (2001) The UNHCR and World Politics: A Perilous Path, New York:
Oxford UP.
Long, W.J. and Brecke, P. (2003) War and Reconciliation: Reason and Emotion in
Conflict Resolution, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Luck, E.C. (2002) “The United States, International Organizations, and the Quest for
Legitimacy”, in S. Patrick and S. Forman (eds) Multilateralism and U.S. Foreign
Policy, London: Lynne Rienner, pp. 47–74.
Luck, E.C. (2003) Reforming the United Nations: Lessons from a History in Progress,
New Haven, CT: Academic Council on the United Nations System, Working paper.
Lund, M.S. (2003) “What Kind of Peace is Being Built: Taking Stock of Post-Conflict
Peacebuilding and Charting Future Directions”, paper presented on the 10th
Anniversary of Agenda for Peace, International Development Research Centre,
Ottawa, Canada, January.
Lund, M., Barnett, R. and Hara, F. (1998) “Learning from Burundi’s Failed Demo-
cratic Transition, 1993–1996”, in R. Barnett (ed.) Cases and Strategies for Prevent-
ive Action, New York: Century Foundation, pp. 47–92.
Lutz, E. and Sikkink, K. (2000) “International Human Rights Law and Practice”,
International Organization 54(3): 633–59.
Lynn-Jones, S. and Miller, S. (1995) “Introduction”, in Lynn-Jones and Miller (eds)
Global Dangers: Changing Dimensions of International Security, Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press, pp. 3–14.
MacFarlane, N. (2000) “Politics and Humanitarian Action”, Occasional Papers, Insti-
tute for International Studies, Providence, RI: Brown University.
MacKenzie, K. (1983) “Greece and Turkey: Disarray on NATO’s Southern Flank”,
Conflict Studies no. 154, London: Institute for the Study of Conflict.
Macrae, J. (1998) “Death of Humanitarianism? An Anatomy of the Attack”, Disasters
22(4): 309–17.
Macrae, J. (1999). “Aiding Peace . . . and War: UNHCR Returnee Reintegration and
the Relief–Development Continuum”, New Issues in Refugee Research 14, Geneva:
UNHCR.
Macrae, J. and Leader, N. (eds) (2000) Terms of Engagement: Conditions and Con-
ditionality in Humanitarian Action, London: Overseas Development Institute.
Macrae, J., Collinson, S., Buchanan-Smith, M., Reindorp, N., Schmidt, A., Mowjee,
T. and Harmer, A. (2002) Uncertain Power: The Changing Role of Official Donors in
Humanitarian Action, Humanitarian Policy Group Report 12. London: Overseas
Development Institute.
Maggi, G. and Morelli, M. (2003) “Self Enforcing Voting in International
References 343
Organizations”, NBER Working Paper No. W10102, September, Online at
<http://ssrn.com/abstract=468789>.
Malcom, N. (1999) Kosovo: A Short History, New York: NYU Press.
Mandelbaum, M. (2002) The Ideas that Conquered the World, New York: Public Affairs.
Mansfield, E.D. and Snyder, J. (1995) “Democratization and the Danger of War”,
International Security 20(1): 5–38.
Mansfield, E.D. and Snyder, J. (2002) “Incomplete Democratization and the Outbreak
of Military Disputes”, International Studies Quarterly 46(4): 529–50.
March, J.G. and Olsen, J.P. (1989) Rediscovering Institutions: The Organizational Basis
of Politics, New York: Free Press.
March, J.G. and Olsen, J.P. (1998) “The Institutional Dynamics of International Polit-
ical Orders”, International Organization 52(4): 943–69.
March, J.G. and Olsen, J.P. (2004) “The Logic of Appropriateness”, ARENA Working
Papers 04/09.
Margolis, L. (1986) Executive Agreements and Presidential Power in Foreign Policy,
New York: Praeger.
Marshall, Monty, and Jaggers, Keith (2004) Polity IV Project. Codebook and Data
Files, Online at <http://bsos.umd.edu/cidcm/inscr/polity> [Accessed on 25 March
2005].
Martin, J. (1992) Cultures in Organizations: Three Perspectives, New York: Oxford UP.
Martin, L.L. (1992) “Interests, Power, and Multilateralism”, International Organiz-
ation 46(4): 765–92.
Martin, L.L. (1993) “The Rational State Choice of Multilateralism”, in J.G. Ruggie
(ed.) Multilateralism Matters: The Theory and Praxis of an Institutional Form, New
York: Columbia UP, pp. 91–121.
Martin, L.L. (2000) Democratic Commitments: Legislatures and International Cooper-
ation, Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP.
Martin, L.L. (2005) “The President and International Commitments: Treaties as
Signaling Devices”, Presidential Studies Quarterly 35(3): 440–65.
Martin, L.L. and Simmons, B. (1998) “Theories and Empirical Studies of Inter-
national Institutions”, International Organization 52(4): 729–57.
Martin, L.L. and Simmons, B. (2001) “Theories and Empirical Studies of International
Institutions”, in L.L. Martin and B. Simmons (eds), International Institutions,
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 437–65.
Mason, T.D., and Fett, P.J. (1996) “How Civil Wars End: A Rational Choice Approach”,
Journal of Conflict Resolution 40(4): 546–68.
Matthiesen, P. (2004) “The Western Balkans – the EU, NATO and the US – Expect-
ations versus Reality”, in F-L. Altmann and E. Whitlock (eds) European and US
Policies in the Balkans, Berlin: Stiftung Wissneschaft und Politik, pp. 15–9.
Mattli, W. and Slaughter, A-M. (1995) “Law and Politics in the European Union: a
Reply to Garrett”, International Organization 49(1): 183–90.
Maull, H.W. (1990) “Germany and Japan: The New Civilian Powers”, Foreign Affairs
69(5): 91–106.
Mayer, K.R. (1999) “Executive Orders and Presidential Power”, Journal of Politics
61(2): 445–66.
Mayer, K.R. and Price, K. (2002) “Unilateral Presidential Powers: Significant Execu-
tive Orders, 1949–99”, Presidential Studies Quarterly 32(2): 367–86.
McCubbins, M. and Sullivan, T. (eds) (1987) Congress: Structure and Policy, New York:
Cambridge UP.
344 References
Mead, M. (1990) “Warfare is Only an Invention–Not a Biological Necessity” in
D. Hunt (ed.) The Dolphin Reader, 2nd ed, Boston: Houghton Mifflin, pp. 415–21.
Mead, W.R. (2001) Special Providence: American Foreign Policy and How It Changed
the World, New York: Knopf.
Mearsheimer, J.J. (1990) “Back to the Future: Instability in Europe after the Cold
War”, International Security 15(1): 5–56.
Mearsheimer, J.J. (1994–5) “The False Promise of International Institutions”, Inter-
national Security 19(3): 5–49.
Mearsheimer, J.J. (1998) “The False Promise of International Institutions”, in M.E.
Brown, O.R. Coates, S.M. Lynn-Jones and S.E. Millar, Theories of War and Peace,
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 329–83.
Mearsheimer, J.J. (2001) The Tragedy of Great Power Politics, New York and London:
W.W. Norton.
Meinardus, R. (1991) “Third-Party Involvement in Greek-Turkish Disputes” in
D. Constas (ed.) The Greek – Turkish Conflict in the 1990s, New York: St. Martin’s
Press.
Meinecke, F. (1929) Idee der Staatsräison in der Neueren Geschichte, München:
R. Oldenburg.
Merkl, P.H. (2005) The Rift Between America and Old Europe: The Distracted Eagle,
London: Routledge.
Merlinguen, M. and Ostrauskaite, R. (2005) “Power/Knowledge in International
Peacebuilding: The Case of the EU Police Mission in Bosnia”, Alternatives 30(3):
297–323.
Mertus, J. (1999) Kosovo: How Myths and Truths Started a War, Berkeley, CA: Uni-
versity of California Press.
Meyer, J. (1991) “Institutionalized Organizations: Formal Structure as Myth and
Ceremony”, in W. Powell and P. DiMaggio (eds) The New Institutionalism in
Organizational Analysis, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 41–62.
Meyer, J. and Rowan, B. (1977) “Institutional Organizations: Formal Structure as
Myth and Ceremony”, American Journal of Sociology 83(2): 340–63.
Miall, H. (1992) The Peacemakers: Peaceful Settlement of Disputes since 1945,
New York: St. Martin’s Press.
Michas, T. (2002), “America the despised – Letter from Athens”, The National Interest,
Online at <http:// www.findarticles.com> [accessed on 15 November 2006].
Millett, S.M. (1990) The Constitutionality of Executive Agreements: An Analysis of
United States v. Belmont, New York: Grand Publishing.
Milward, A.S. (1992) The European Rescue of the Nation-State, Berkeley, CA: Uni-
versity of California Press.
Minear, L. (1999) “The Theory and Practice of Neutrality: Some Thoughts on the
Tensions”, International Review of the Red Cross 833: 63–71.
Minear, L. (2002) The Humanitarian Enterprise: Dilemmas and Discoveries, Bloom-
field, CT: Kumarian Press.
Minear, L. and Smilie, I. (2004) The Charity of Nations, Bloomfield, CT: Kumarian Press.
Minear, L., van Baarda, T., and Sommers, M. (2000) “NATO and Humanitarian
Action in the Kosovo Crisis”, Occasional Papers, Institute for International Studies,
Providence, RI: Brown University.
Minow, M. (1998) Between Vengeance and Forgiveness: Facing History after Genocide
and Mass Violence, Boston: Beacon Press.
Mitrany, D. (1975) The Functional Theory of Politics, London: Martin Robertson.
References 345
Moe, T.M. (1990) “Political Institutions: The Neglected Side of the Story”, Journal of
Law, Economics, and Organization 6 (Special Issue): 213–53.
Moe, T.M. and Howell, W.G. (1999a) “The Presidential Power of Unilateral Action”,
Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization 15(1): 132–79.
Moe, T.M. and Howell, W.G. (1999b) “Unilateral Action and Presidential Power: A
Theory”, Presidential Studies Quarterly 29(4): 850–73.
Moravcsik, A. (1997) “Taking Preference Seriously: A Liberal Theory of International
Politics”, International Organization 51(4): 513–53.
Moravcsik, A. (2003) “Striking a New Transatlantic Bargain”, Foreign Affairs, 82(4):
74–89.
Moravcsik, A. and Vachudova, M.A. (2002) “National Interests, State Power and EU
Enlargement”, Center for European Studies, Harvard University, Working Paper
No. 97.
Morgan, P. (1993) “Multilateralism and Security: Prospects in Europe”, in J.G. Ruggie
(ed.) Multilateralism Matters: The Theory and Praxis of an Institutional Form,
New York: Columbia UP, pp. 327–64.
Morris, N. (1999) “UNHCR and Kosovo: A Personal View from within UNHCR”,
Forced Migration Review 5(August): 14–17.
Morris, P. (1999) “Humanitarian Interventions in Macedonia: an NGO Perspective”,
Forced Migration Review 5(August): 18–19.
Morrow, J. (1994) Game Theory for Political Scientists. Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP.
Moustakis, F. and Sheehan, M. (2000) “Greek Security Policy after the Cold War”,
Contemporary Security Policy 21(3): 95–115.
Muller, H. (1993) “The Internalization of Principles, Norms, and Rules by Govern-
ments: The Case of Security Regimes”, in V. Rittberger (ed.) Regime Theory and
International Relations, Oxford: Oxford UP, pp. 361–90.
Muller, H. (2003) Terrorism, Proliferation: a European Threat Assessment, Chaillot
Paper No. 58, Paris: Institute for Security Studies.
Nabers, D. (2003) “The Social Construction of International Institutions: The Case of
ASEAN +3”, International Relations of the Asia-Pacific 3(1): 113–36.
Nagel, T. (1988) “War and Massacre”, in S. Scheffer (ed.) Consequentialism and Its
Critics, Oxford: Oxford UP, pp. 51–73.
Narine, S. (1998) “ASEAN and the Management of Regional Security”, Pacific Affairs
71(2): 195–214.
Nathan, J.A. and Oliver, J.K. (1994) Foreign Policy Making and the American Political
System, 3rd edn, Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins Press.
Nau, H.R. (2002) At Home Abroad. Identity and Power in American Foreign Policy,
Ithaca, NY: Cornell UP.
Nielson, D. and Tierney, M. (2003) “Delegation to International Organizations:
Agency Theory and World Bank Environmental Reform”, International Organiza-
tion 57(2): 241–76.
Noutcheva, G. (2003) “Europeanisation and Conflict Resolution”, Europa South-East
Monitor, CEPS, no. 49, October.
Noutcheva, G. (2004) “The EU and the Western Balkans”, Europa South-East Monitor
CEPS, no. 58, September.
Nye, J.S. (1990) Bound to Lead: The Changing Nature of American Power, New York:
Basic Books.
Nye, J.S. (2002) The Paradox of American Power: Why the World’s Only Superpower
Can’t Go It Alone, Oxford: Oxford UP.
346 References
Nye, J.S. (2003) “US Power and Strategy After Iraq”, Foreign Affairs 82(4): 60–73.
Nyers, P. (1999) “Emergency or Emerging Identities? Refugees and Transformations in
World Order”, Millennium 28(1): 1–26.
O’Brien, P. (2004) “Politicized Humanitarianism: A Response to Nicolas de Torrente”,
Harvard Human Rights Journal 17: 31–9.
O’Neill, B. (1997) “Power and Satisfaction in the Security Council”, in B. Russett
(ed.), The Once and Future Security Council, New York: St. Martin’s Press,
pp. 59–82.
Office of the President see US President’s Office
Ogata, S. (2005) The Turbulent Decade, New York: Norton Press.
Oguzlu, H.T. (2004) “The Promise of NATO in the Construction of Cooperative
Turkish-Greek Relations”, Review of International Affairs 3(3): 458–78.
Oneal, J.R. and Russett, B.M. (1997) “The Classic Liberals were Right: Democracy,
Interdependence, and Conflict, 1950–1985”, International Studies Quarterly 41(2):
267–93.
Onis, Z. (2003) “Domestic Politics, International Norms and Challenges to the State:
Turkey-EU Relations in the Post-Helsinki Era”, Turkish Studies 4(1): 9–34.
Orbinski, J. (1999) “Kosovo: Aid Under Siege Once Again: The Principles, Roles, and
Responsibilities of Humanitarian Action were Challenged at a Fundamental Level
During the Kosovo Crisis”, Online at <http:// nato.int>.
Orru, M., Biggart, N.W. and Hamilton, G. (1991) “Organizational Isomorphism
in East Asia”, in W. Powell and P. DiMaggio (eds) The New Institutionalism in
Organizational Analysis, Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP, pp. 361–89.
Osgood, R.E. (1953) Ideals and Self-Interest in America’s Foreign Relations. The Great
Transformation of the Twentieth Century, Chicago: Chicago UP.
Overseas Development Institute, Disasters Emergency Committee, et al. (2000)
Independent Evaluation of Expenditure of DEC Kosovo Appeal Funds. Phases I and
II, April 1999–January 2000. London: Disasters Emergency Committee.
Owen, J.M. (1994) “How Liberalism Produces the Democratic Peace”, International
Security 19(1): 87–125.
Owen, J.M. (1997) Liberal Peace, Liberal War. American Politics and International
Security, Ithaca, NY: Cornell UP.
Pace, M. (2005) “EU Policy-Making Towards Border Conflicts”, Working Paper Series
in EU Border Conflicts Series, No. 15, University of Birmingham.
Page, S. (2006) “Path Dependence”, Quarterly Journal of Political Science 1(1):
87–115.
Paris, R. (2002) “International Peacebuilding and the “Mission Civilisatrice” ”, Review
of International Studies 28(4): 637–56.
Paris, R. (2004) At War’s End, Cambridge: Cambridge UP.
Patrick, S. (2002) “Multilateralism and Its Discontents: The Causes and Consequences
of US Ambivalence” in S. Patrick and S. Forman (eds) Multilateralism and U.S.
Foreign Policy: Ambivalent Engagement, Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner, pp. 1–44.
Payne, R.A. (2001) “Persuasion, Frames and Norm Construction”, European Journal
of International Relations 7(1): 37–61.
Penn, W. (1693/1993) An Essay towards the Present and Future Peace of Europe,
London: Everyman.
Perlo-Freeman, S. and Stålenheim, P. (2003) “Military Expenditure in South Caucasus
and Central Asia” in A.J.K. Bailes et al., Armament and Disarmament in the Cauca-
sus and Central Asia, Stockholm: SIPRI, pp. 7–20.
References 347
Petritsch, Wolfgang (1999) “Report to the PIC Steering Board Meeting in Brussels”,
October, Brussels: Peace Implementation Council.
Pevehouse, J.C. (2002) “Democracy from the Outside-In? International Organizations
and Democratization”, International Organization 56(3): 515–49.
Pew Research Center (2002) Americans and Europeans Differ Widely on Foreign Policy
Issues, Washington, DC: Pew Research Center for the People and the Press, April.
Pew Research Center (2002) What the World Thinks in 2002, Pew Global Attitudes
Project, Washington, DC: Pew Research Center for the People and the Press.
Pew Research Center (2003) Views of a Changing World. Report, Pew Global Atti-
tudes Project, Washington, DC: Pew Research Center for the People and the Press,
June.
Pew Research Center (2004) A Year after Iraq War. Mistrust of America in Europe
Ever Higher, Muslim Anger Persists, Pew Global Attitudes Project, Washington,
DC: Pew Research Center.
Pew Research Center (2005) Trends 2005, Washington, DC: Pew Research Center for
the People and the Press.
Pfeffer, J. and Salancik, G. (2003) The External Control of Organizations: A Resource
Dependence Perspective, Stanford, CA: Stanford UP.
PIC (2000) “Declaration of the Peace Implementation Council”, 24 May, Brussels:
Peace Implementation Council.
Pictet, J. (1979) The Fundamental Principles of the Red Cross, Geneva: Henry Dunant
Institute.
Pierson, P. (2000) “Increasing Returns, Path Dependence, and the Study of Politics”,
American Political Science Review 94(2): 251–67.
Plato (c.360 bc 1941) “The Allegory of the Cave”, trans. F. MacDonald Cornford,
The Republic of Plato, Oxford: Oxford UP.
Pogge, T. (2002) World Poverty and Human Rights, Cambridge: Polity.
Pollack, M. (1997) “Delegation, Agency, and Agenda Setting in the European Com-
munity”, International Organization 51(1): 99–134.
Pond, E. (2004) Friendly Fire. The Near-Death of the Transatlantic Alliance, Pittsburgh,
PA and Washington, DC: European Union Studies Association/Brookings Institu-
tion Press.
Porter, T. (1999) “Coordination in the Midst of Chaos: The Refugee Crisis in Albania”,
Forced Migration Review 5: 20–3.
Porter, T. (2000) “The Partiality of Humanitarian Assistance – Kosovo in Comparative
Perspective”, Journal of Humanitarian Assistance, Online at <http://www.jha.ac/
articles/a057.htm>.
Posen, B. (2003) “Command of the Commons: The Military Foundation of US
Hegemony”, International Security 28(1): 5–46.
Powell, R. (1991) “Absolute and Relative Gains in International Relations Theory”,
American Political Science Review 85(4): 1303–20.
Power, S. (2002) A Problem from Hell: America and the Age of Genocide, New York:
Basic.
Pridham, G. (2002) “EU Enlargement and Consolidating Democracy in Post-
Communist States – Formality and Reality”, Journal of Common Market Studies
40(1): 953–73.
Pridham, G., Herring, E. and Sanford, G. (eds) (1997) Building Democracy: the
International Dimension of Democratisation in Eastern Europe, Leicester: Leicester
UP.
348 References
Przeworski, A., Alvarez, M., Cheibub, J. and Limongi, F. (2000) Democracy and
Development: Political Institutions and Well-being in the World, 1950–1990, New
York: Cambridge UP.
Pugh, M. (2002) “Peacekeeping and Critical Theory”, paper presented at the BISA
Conference, LSE, London, 16–18 December.
Pugh, M. (2004) “Rubbing Salt into War Wounds. Shadow Economies and Peace-
building in Bosnia and Kosovo”, Problems of Post Communism 51(3):
53–60.
Pupavac, V. (2001) “Therapeutic Governance: Psycho-Social Intervention and Trauma
Risk Management”, Disasters 25(4): 358–72.
Putnam, R.D. (1988) “Diplomacy and Domestic Politics”, International Organization
42(3): 427–61.
Putnam, T. (2002) “Human Rights and Sustainable Peace”, in S.J. Stedman, D.
Rothchild and E. Cousens (eds) Ending Civil Wars: The Implementation of Peace
Agreements, New York: Lynne Rienner, pp. 237–71.
Randel, J. and German, T. (2002) “Trends in the Financing of Humanitarian Assist-
ance”, in J. McRae (ed.) The New Humanitarianism: A Review of Trends in Global
Humanitarian Action, Humanitarian Policy Group Report, London: Overseas
Development Institute, pp. 12–28.
Regan, P. (1996) “Conditions for Successful Third Party Interventions”, Journal of
Conflict Resolution 40(1): 336–59.
Regan, P. (2000) Civil Wars and Foreign Powers: Outside Interventions and Intrastate
Conflicts, Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.
Regan, P. (2002) “Third-Party Interventions and the Duration of Intrastate Conflict”,
Journal of Conflict Resolution 46(1): 55–73.
Reisman, M. (1993) “The Constitutional Crisis in the United Nations”, American
Journal of International Law 87(1): 83–100.
Reljić, D. (2005) “The Western Balkans without a Plan for the Future”, SWP Com-
ments, 31 July.
Report of the Secretary-General’s High Level Panel on Threats, Challenges, and
Change (2004) New York: United Nations.
Richmond, O. (2002) Maintaining Order, Making Peace, London: Palgrave.
Richmond, O. (2004a) “The Globalisation of Approaches to Conflict”, Cooperation
and Conflict 39(2): 129–50.
Richmond, O. (2004b) “UN Peace Operations and the Dilemmas of the Peacebuilding
Consensus”, International Peacekeeping 10(4): 83–101.
Richmond, O. (2005) The Transformation of Peace, London: Palgrave.
Rieff, D. (2002) A Bed for the Night: Humanitarianism in Crisis, New York: Simon and
Schuster.
Riesman, W.M. (1999) “Kosovo’s Antimonies”, American Journal of International Law
93(4): 860–2.
Risse, T. (2000) “Let’s Argue!: Communicative Action in World Politics”, International
Organization 54(1): 1–39.
Risse, T. (2002) “U.S. Power in a Liberal Security Community”, in J. Ikenberry (ed.)
America Unrivaled. U.S. Unipolarity and the Future of the Balance of Power, Ithaca,
NY: Cornell UP, pp. 260–83.
Risse, T. (2003) “Beyond Iraq: The Crisis of the Transatlantic Security Community”,
Die Friedens-Warte 78(2–3): 173–93.
Risse, T. (2006) “The Crisis of the Transatlantic Security Community”, in I. Peters
References 349
(ed.) Transatlantic Tug-of-War: Prospects for US–European Cooperation, Berlin:
LIT Verlag, pp. 11–141.
Risse, T., and Sikkink, K. (1999) “The Socialization of International Human Rights
Norms into Domestic Practice”, in T. Risse, S. Ropp and K. Sikkink (eds) The
Power of Human Rights: International Norms and Domestic Change, Cambridge:
Cambridge UP, pp. 1–38.
Risse, T., Ropp, S. and Sikkink, K. (1999) The Power of Human Rights, New York:
Cambridge UP.
Risse-Kappen, T. (1988) The Zero Option. INF, West Germany, and Arms Control,
Boulder, CO: Westview.
Risse-Kappen, T. (1995) Cooperation among Democracies. The European Influence on
U.S. Foreign Policy, Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP.
Risse-Kappen, T. (1996) “Collective Identity in a Democratic Community: The Case
of NATO”, in P. Katzenstein (ed.) The Culture of National Security: Norms and
Identity in World Politics, New York: Columbia UP, pp. 357–99.
Roberts, A. (1999) “NATO’s “Humanitarian War” Over Kosovo”, Survival 41(3):
102–23.
Roggo, B. (2000) “After the Kosovo Conflict, a Genuine Humanitarian Space: A
Utopian Concept or an Essential Requirement?”, International Review of the Red
Cross, 837: 31–47.
Rotberg, R.I. and Thompson, D. (eds) (2000) Truth vs. Justice: The Morality of Truth
Commissions, Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP.
Roth, K. (2001) “The Case for Universal Jurisdiction”, Foreign Affairs 80(5):
150–4.
Ruggie, J.G. (1992) “Multilateralism: The Anatomy of an Institution”, International
Organization 46(3): 561–98.
Ruggie, J.G. (ed.) (1993a) Multilateralism Matters. The Theory and Praxis of an Insti-
tutional Form, New York: Columbia UP.
Ruggie, J.G. (1993b) “Multilateralism: The Anatomy of an Institution”, in J.G. Ruggie
(ed.) Multilateralism Matters, New York: Columbia UP, pp. 3–47.
Ruggie, J.G. (1994) “America and Multilateralism after the Cold War”, Political
Science Quarterly 109(4): 553–70.
Ruggie, J.G. (1998) Constructing the World Polity, London: Routledge.
Rumelili, B. (2003) “Liminality and Perpetuation of Conflicts: Turkish-Greek Rela-
tions in the Context of Community-Building by the EU”, European Journal of
International Relations 9(2): 213–48.
Rumelili, B. (2004a) “The European Union’s Impact on the Greek–Turkish Conflict:
A Review of the Literature”, Working Paper Series in EU Border Conflicts Series,
no. 6.
Rumelili, B. (2004b) “The Microprocesses of Hegemonic Influence: The Case of EU
and Greece/Turkey”, EUBORDERCONF Project, Bogazici University/University
of Birmingham.
Rumelili, B. (2005) “Civil Society and the Europeanization of Greek–Turkish Cooper-
ation”, South European Society and Politics 10(1): 43–54.
Rupnik, J. (2005) European Parliament, Committee on Foreign Affairs, 25 January,
Centre d’Etudes et de Recherches Internationales, Online at <http://europa-eu-
un.org/articles/sl/article_4265_sl.htm>.
Russett, B. (1993) Grasping the Democratic Peace, Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP.
Russett, B. (2005) “Security Council Expansion: Can’t and Shouldn’t”, in Reforming
350 References
the United Nations for Peace and Security, New Haven, CT: Yale Center for the
Study of Globalization, pp. 153–66.
Russett, B. and Oneal, J. (2001) Triangulating Peace. Democracy, Interdependence, and
International Organizations, New York and London: W.W. Norton.
Russett, B., O’Neil, B. and Sutterlin, J. (1997) “Breaking the Restructuring Logjam”,
in B. Russett (ed.) The Once and Future Security Council, London, Macmillan:
pp. 153–69.
Sambanis, N. (2002) “Do Ethnic and Non-Ethnic Civil Wars Have the Same Causes?
Organization and Interests in Ethnic Insurgency”, Working Paper, Yale University,
17 October.
Sambanis, N. (2004) “What Is A Civil War? Conceptual and Empirical Complex-
ities of an Operational Definition”, Journal of Conflict Resolution 48(6):
814–58.
Schachter, O. (1989) “Self-Defense and the Rule of Law”, American Journal of Inter-
national Law 83(2): 259–77.
Scheffer, D.J. (2000) “The U.S. Perspective on the ICC,” in S.B. Sewall and C. Kaysen
(eds) The United States and the International Criminal Court, New York: Rowman
& Littlefield, pp. 119–36.
Schelling, T. (1960) The Strategy of Conflict, Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP.
Schimmelfennig, F. (2000) “International Socialization in the New Europe: Rational
Action in an Institutional Environment”, European Journal of International Rela-
tions 6(1): 109–39.
Schimmelfennig, F. (2001) “The Community Trap: Liberal Norms, Rhetorical Action
and the Eastern Enlargement of the European Union”, International Organization
55(1): 47–80.
Schimmelfennig, F. (2002) “Introduction: The Impact of International Organizations
on the Central and Eastern European States – Conceptual and Theoretical Issues”,
in R. Linden (ed.) Norms and Nannies. The Impact of International Organizations
on the Central and East European States, Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield,
pp. 1–29.
Schimmelfennig, F. (2003) The EU, NATO and the Integration of Europe. Rules and
Rhetoric, Cambridge: Cambridge UP.
Schimmelfennig, F. (2005) “The International Promotion of Political Norms in
Eastern Europe: a Qualitative Comparative Analysis”, Harvard University, Center
for European Studies /Central and Eastern Europe, Working Paper 61.
Schimmelfennig, F. (2006) “Strategic Calculation and International Socialization:
Membership Incentives, Party Constellations, and Sustained Compliance in Cen-
tral and Eastern Europe”, International Organization 59(4): 827–60.
Schimmelfennig, F. and Sedelmeier, U. (2004) “Governance by Conditionality: EU
Rule Transfer to the Candidate Countries of Central and Eastern Europe”, Journal
of European Public Policy 11(4): 661–79.
Schmitt, C. (1996) The Concept of the Political, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Schneckener, U. (2002) Netzwerke des Terrors. Charakter und Strukturen des transna-
tionalen Terrorismus, Berlin: Stiftung Wissenschaft und Politik, December.
Schöllgen, G. (2003) Der Auftritt. Deutschlands Rückkehr auf die Weltbühne, Berlin:
Propyläen Verlag.
Schulz, W.F. (2001) In Our Own Best Interest: How Defending Human Rights Benefits
Us All, Boston: Beacon.
SCO (Shanghai Co-operation Organization) (2001a) Declaration on the Creation of
References 351
the Shanghai Cooperation Organization, Online at <http://russia.shaps.hawaii.edu/
fp/russia/sco_1_20010620.html> [accessed on 5 May 2005].
SCO (Shanghai Co-operation Organization) (2001b) Charter of Shanghai Coop-
eration Organization, Online at <http://www.sectsco.org/news_detail.asp?id=96&
LanguageID=2> [accessed on 5 May 2005].
SCO (Shanghai Co-operation Organization) (2001c) Shanghai Communiqué, Online
at <http://www.missions.itu.int/~kazaks/eng/sco/sco04.htm> [accessed on 5 May
2005].
SCO (Shanghai Co-operation Organization) (2004) Tashkent Declaration of the Heads
of the States Participating in the Shanghai Co-operation Organization, Online at
<http://www.sectsco.org/news_detail.asp?id=119&LanguageID=2> [accessed on
5 May 2005].
Scott, W.R. (1987) “The Adolescence of Institutional Theory”, Administrative Studies
Quarterly 32(4): 493–511.
Scott, W.R. (1995) Institutions and Organizations, Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Scott, W.R. and Meyer, J. (1993) Organizational Environments: Ritual and Rationality,
Beverly Hills, CA: Sage.
Scott-Flynn, N. (1999) “Coordination in Kosovo: The Challenge for the NGO Sector”,
Humanitarian Practice Network.
Searle, J.R. (1999) “I married a computer”, New York Review of Books, 8 April, pp. 37–8.
Segal, G. (1996) “East Asia and the “Constrainment” of China”, International Security
20(4): 107–35.
Setear, J.K. (2002) “The President’s Rational Choice of a Treaty’s Preratification
Pathway: Article II, Congressional-Executive Agreement, or Executive Agree-
ment?”, Journal of Legal Studies 31(1): 5–39.
Sewall, S.B. and Kaysen, C. (eds) (2000) The United States and the International
Criminal Court, New York: Rowman & Littlefield.
Shambaugh, D. (2004–5) “China Engages Asia: Reshaping the Regional Order”, Inter-
national Security 29(1): 64–99.
Shanghai Co-operation Organization see SCO
Shklar, J. (1964) Legalism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP.
Simma, B. (1999) “NATO, The UN and the Use of Force: Legal Aspects”, European
Journal of International Law 10(1): 1–22.
Simmons, B.A. (2000) “International Law and State Behavior: Commitment and
Compliance in International Monetary Affairs”, American Political Science Review
94(4): 819–35.
Simmons, B.A. and Martin, L.L. (2002) “International Organizations and Institu-
tions”, in W. Carlsnaes, T. Risse, and B.A. Simmons (eds) Handbook of Inter-
national Relations, London: Sage.
Simon, H. (1951) “A Formal Theory of the Employment Relationship”, Econometrica
19(3): 299–305.
Simon, S. (1996) “Alternative Visions of Security in the Asia Pacific”, Pacific Affairs
69(3): 381–96.
Simon, S. (1998) “The Limits of Defense and Security Cooperation in Southeast
Asia,” in J. Sperling Y. Malik and D. Louscher (eds) Zones of Amity, Zones of
Enmity: The Prospects for Economic and Military Security in Asia, Leiden: Brill,
pp. 62–75.
Siquiera, K. (2003) “Conflict and Third-Party Intervention”, Defence and Peace
Economics 14(6): 389–400.
352 References
Slim, H. (1997) “Doing the Right Thing: Relief Agencies, Moral Dilemmas, and
Moral Responsibility in Political Emergencies and War”, Disasters 21(3): 244–57.
Slim, H. (2002a) “By What Authority? The Legitimacy and Accountability of
Non-governmental Organisations”, Journal of Humanitarian Assistance, Online at
<http://www.jha.ac/articles/a082.htm>.
Slim, H. (2002b) “Claiming a Humanitarian Imperative: NGOs and the Cultivation
of Humanitarian Duty”, paper presented at the Seventh Annual Conference of
Webster University on Humanitarian Values for the 21st Century, Geneva, 21–22
February.
Slim, H. (2002c) “Military Intervention to Protect Human Rights: The Humanitarian
Agency Perspective”, Journal of Humanitarian Assistance, Online at <http://
www.jha.ac/articlesa084.htm>.
Slim, H. (2004a) “Politicizing Humanitarian Action According to Need”, presentation
to the 2nd International Meeting on Good Humanitarian Donorship, Ottawa,
21–22 October.
Slim, H. (2004b) “Protecting Civilians: Putting the Individual at the Humanitarian
Centre”, in Office of the Co-ordinator of Humanitarian Assistance (ed.) The
Humanitarian Decade: Challenges for Humanitarian Assistance in the Last Decade
and into the Future, vol. II, New York: United Nations Press, pp. 154–70.
Slomp, G. (1996) “Hobbes, Feminism, and Liberalism”, Political Studies Association
Conference, University of Glasgow.
Smith, A. and Stam, A. (2003) “Mediation and Peacekeeping in a Random Walk
Model of Civil and Interstate War”, International Studies Review 5(4): 115–35.
Smith, K.E. (2003) European Union Foreign Policy in a Changing World, London:
Polity Press.
Smith, M. (1996) “The EU as an International Actor,” in J.J. Richardson (ed.) European
Union: Power and Policy-Making, London: Routledge, pp. 247–62.
Smith, M.G. (2003) Peacekeeping in East Timor, Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner.
Smith, T. (1994) America’s Mission: The United States and the Worldwide Struggle for
Democracy in the Twentieth Century, Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP.
Snyder, G.H. (1984) “The Security Dilemma in Alliance Politics”, World Politics 36(4):
461–95.
Snyder, J. (2000) From Voting to Violence, London: W.W. Norton.
Snyder, J. (2002) “Anarchy and Culture: Insights from the Anthropology of War”,
International Organization 56(1): 7–46.
Snyder, J. and Vinjamuri, L. (2003–4) “Trials and Errors: Principle and Pragmatism in
Strategies of International Justice”, International Security 28(3): 5–44.
Solana, J. (2005) “Dayton @ 10: Drawing Lessons from the Past”, Policy Dialogue
organised by EPC and King Baudouin Foundation, Brussels, 25 November,
S382/05.
Solingen, E. (1998) Regional Orders at Century’s Dawn: Global and Domestic Influ-
ences of Grand Strategy, Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP.
Soutou, G.H. (2000) “Was there a European Order in the Twentieth Century? From
the Concert of Europe to the End of the Cold War”, Contemporary European
History 9(3): 329–33.
Spiro, P.J. (2001) “Treaties, Executive Agreements, and Constitutional Method”, Texas
Law Review 79(5): 961–1033.
Stålenheim, P., Omitoogun, W., and Perdomo, C. (2005) “Military Expenditures,” in
SIPRI, SIPRI Yearbook 2005, Oxford: Oxford UP, pp. 307–44.
References 353
Stanley, H.W. and Niemi, R.G. (2001) Vital Statistics on American Politics, 2001–2002,
Washington, DC: CQ Press.
Stearns, M. (1992) Entangled Allies: US Policy towards Greece, Turkey and Cyprus,
New York: Council on Foreign Relations.
Stedman, S.J. (1997) “Spoiler Problems in Peace Processes”, International Security
22(2): 5–53.
Steinbruner, J.D. (2000) Principles of Global Security, Washington, DC: Brookings
Institution Press.
Stephanou, C. and Tsardanides, C. (1991) “The EC Factor in the Greece–Turkey–
Cyprus Triangle” in D. Constas (ed.) The Greek–Turkish Conflict in the 1990s:
Domestic and External Influences, New York: St. Martin’s Press, pp. 207–30.
Stockton, N. (1998) “In Defence of Humanitarianism”, Disasters 22(4): 352–60.
Stockton, N. (2002) “Strategic Coordination in Afghanistan”, ECHO/ Afghanistan
Research and Evaluation Unit, August.
Stockton, N. (2004) “The Changing Nature of Humanitarian Crises”, in Office of
the Co-ordinator of Humanitarian Assistance (ed.) The Humanitarian Decade:
Challenges for Humanitarian Assistance in the Last Decade and into the Future,
vol. II, New York: United Nations Press, pp. 15–38.
Stoddard, A. (2002) “Trends in US Humanitarian Policy”, in J. Macrae, The New
Humanitarianisms: A Review of Trends in Global Humanitarian Action, Humani-
tarian Policy Group Report, 11, London.
Stone Sweet, A. and Brunell, T.L. (1998) “Constructing a Supranational Constitution:
Dispute Resolution and Governance in the European Community”, American Pol-
itical Science Review 92(1): 63–81.
Strand, J., Rapkin, D. and Scales, P. (2005) Weighted Voting, Relative Voting Power,
and UN Security Council Reform, paper presented in the annual meeting of the
International Studies Association, Honolulu, 1–5 March.
Suchman, M. (1995) “Managing Legitimacy: Strategic and Institutional Approaches”,
Academy of Management Review 20(3): 571–610.
Suhrke, A. (2001) “Peacekeepers as Nation-builders: Dilemmas of the UN in East
Timor”, International Peacekeeping 8(4): 1–20.
Suhrke, A., Barutciski, M., Sandison, P. and Garlock, R. (2000) The Kosovo Refugee
Crisis: An Evaluation of UNHCR’s Emergency Preparedness and Response, Gen-
eva: UNHCR, February.
Sumner, G.W. (1911) War and Other Essays, New Haven, CI: Yale UP.
Sutterlin, J. (1997) “The Past as Prologue”, in B. Russett (ed.) The Once and Future
Security Council, London and New York: Macmillan, pp. 1–13.
Talbott, S. (1984) Deadly Gambits, New York: A. Knopf.
Talbott, S. (1988) The Master of the Game: Paul Nitze and the Nuclear Arms Race,
New York: A. Knopf.
Tallberg, J. (2002) “Paths to Compliance: Enforcement, Management, and the
European Union”, International Organization 56 (3): 609–43.
Terry, F. (2002) Condemned To Repeat?, Ithaca, NY: Cornell UP.
Thatcher, M. and Stone Sweet, A. (2002) “Theory and Practice of Delegation to
Non-Majoritarian Institutions”, West European Politics 25(1): 1–22.
Towell, P. (1998) “Aspiring NATO Newcomers Face Long Road to Integration”,
Congressional Quarterly 56(6): 275.
Tribe, L.H. (1995) “Taking Text and Structure Seriously: Reflections on Free-Form
Method in Constitutional Interpretation”, Harvard Law Review 108(6): 1221–303.
354 References
Trofimov, D. (2003) “Arms Control in Central Asia”, in A.J.K. Bailes et al. Armament
and Disarmament in the Caucasus and Central Asia, Stockholm: SIPRI, pp. 46–56.
Tsakonas, P. (2001) “Turkey’s Post-Helsinki Turbulence. Implications for Greece and
the Cyprus Issue”, Turkish Studies 2(2): 1–40.
Tsakonas, P. (2007) A Breakthrough in Greek-Turkish Relations? Understanding
Greece’s Socialization Strategy, Basingstoke and New York: Palgrave, forthcoming.
Tsakonas, P. and Tournikiotis, A. (2003) “Greece’s Elusive Quest for Security Pro-
viders: The ‘Expectations–Reality Gap’ ”, Security Dialogue 34(3): 301–14.
Tsebelis, G. (1990) Nested Games,: University of California Press.
Tsebelis, G. (2002) Veto Players: How Political Institutions Work, Princeton, NJ:
Princeton UP.
Tuschoff, C. (1999) “Alliance Cohesion and Peaceful Change in NATO”, in H.
Haftendorn, R.O. Keohane, and C.A. Wallander (eds) Imperfect Unions: Security
Institutions over Space and Time, Oxford: Oxford UP, pp. 140–61.
Ugur, M. (1999) The European Union and Turkey: An Anchor/Credibility Dilemma,
Aldershot, Hants: Ashgate.
United Nations Development Programme (2004) Human Development Report 2004,
New York: Oxford UP.
United Nations High-Level Panel on Threats, Challenges, and Change (2004) A More
Secure World: Our Shared Responsibility. New York: United Nations, A/59/565,
2 December.
United Nations (2005) Year in Review 2004: United Nations Peace Operations,
New York: United Nations Dept of Public Information.
Urquhart, B. (2005) “Brief Notes on the Report of the High-level Panel on Threats,
Challenges and Change” in Reforming the United Nations for Peace and Security
New Haven, CT: Yale Center for the Study of Globalization, pp. 183–5.
US President’s Office (2002) The National Security Strategy of the United States of
America, Washington, DC: The White House, September. (Also online at http://
whitehouse.gov/nsc/nss.html)
US President’s Office (2006) The National Security Strategy of the United States of
America, 2006, Washington, DC: White House.
Vachudova, M.A. (2003) “Strategies for Democratization and European Integration in
the Balkans”, in M. Cremona (ed.) The Enlargement of the European Union,
Oxford: Oxford UP, pp. 141–60.
Valinakis, Y. (1997) With Vision and Program: Foreign Policy for a Greece with Self-
Confidence, Thessaloniki: Paratiritis [in Greek].
Vamvakas, P.I. (2001) “States in Transition and Defensive Alliances: Greece and
Turkey in NATO” (Unpublished PhD thesis, Boston University, Graduate School
of Arts and Sciences).
Vaughan, D. (1996) The Challenger Launch Decision, Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Vaux, T. (2001) The Selfish Altruist, Sterling, VA: Earthscan Publishing.
Vedby Rasmussen, M. (2003) The West, Civil Society, and the Construction of Peace,
London: Palgrave.
Vejvoda, I. (2004) US Policy towards Southeast Europe: Unfinished Business in the
Balkans, Testimony to the US Senate Committee on Foreign Relations, 14 July.
Voeten, E. (2000) “Clashes in the Assembly”, International Organization 54(2): 185–217.
Voeten, E. (2001) “Outside Options and the Logic of Security Council Action”,
American Political Science Review 95(4): 845–58.
References 355
Voeten, E. (2005) “The Political Origins of the United Nations Security Coun-
cil’s Ability to Legitimize the Use of Force”, International Organization 59(3):
527–57.
Voeten, E. (n.d.) “A Strategic Approach to Understanding Security Council Author-
ity”, in in B. Cronin and I. Hurd (eds) International Authority and the UN Security
Council, Cambridge: Cambridge UP, forthcoming.
de Waal, A. (1997) Famine Crimes, Bloomington: Indiana UP.
Wæver, O. (1998) “Insecurity, security, and asecurity in the West European non-war
Community”, in E. Adler and M. Barnett (eds) Security Communities, Cambridge:
Cambridge UP, pp. 69–118.
Walker, R.B.J (1992) Inside/Outside: International Relations as Political Theory, Cam-
bridge: Cambridge UP.
Wallander, C.A. (2000) “Institutional Assets and Adaptability: NATO After the Cold
War”, International Organization 54(1): 705–35.
Wallensteen, P. (1997) “Representing the World: A Security Council for the 21st Cen-
tury”, in R. Dahl (ed.) The Politics of Global Governance, Boulder, CO: Lynne
Rienner, pp. 103–15.
Walt, S.M. (1987) The Origins of Alliances, Ithaca, NY: Cornell UP.
Walter, B.F. (1997) “The Critical Barrier to Civil War Settlement”, International Organ-
ization 51(3): 335–64.
Waltz, K. (1978) Theory of International Politics, New York: Random House.
Waltz, K. (1979) Theory of International Politics, Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
Waltz, K. (1993) “The Emerging Structure of International Politics”, International
Security 18(2): 44–79.
Wanandi, J. (2005) “Towards an Asian Security Community”, Asia-Europe Journal
3(3): 323–32.
Ward, M.D. and Gleditsch, K.S. (1998) “Democratizing for Peace”, American Political
Science Review 92(1): 51–61.
Warner, D. (1999) “The Politics of the Political/Humanitarian Divide”, International
Review of the Red Cross 833: 109–18.
Weber, S. (1993) “Shaping the Postwar Balance of Power: Multilateralism in NATO”,
in J.G. Ruggie (ed.), Multilateralism Matters: The Theory and Praxis of an Insti-
tutional Form, New York: Columbia UP, pp. 233–92.
Weber, S. (1994) “Origins of the European Bank for Reconstruction and Develop-
ment”, International Organization 48(1): 1–38.
Weiss, T. (1999) “The Humanitarian Identity Crisis”, Ethics and International Affairs
13: 1–42.
Weiss, T. (2003) “The Illusion of UN Security Council Reform”, Washington Quarterly
26(4): 147–61.
Weiss, T., Forsythe, D. and Coate, R. (2004) The United Nations and Changing World
Politics, 4th edn, Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Wendt, A. (1994) “Collective Identity Formation and the International State”, Ameri-
can Political Science Review 88(2): 391–425.
Wendt, A. (1996) “Identity and Structural Change in International Politics”, in Y. Lapid
and F. Kratochwil (eds) The Return of Culture and Identity in IR Theory, Boulder,
CO: Lynne Rienner, pp. 47–66
Wendt, A. (1999) Social Theory of International Politics, Cambridge: Cambridge
UP.
Wendt, A. and Duvall, R. (1989) “Institutions and International Order” in E. Czempiel
356 References
and J. Rosenau (eds) Global Changes and Theoretical Challenges: Approaches to
World Politics for the 1990s, Lexington, MA: Lexington Books, 51–74.
Weschler, L. (2000) “Exceptional Cases in Rome: The United States and the Struggle
for an ICC,” in S.B. Sewall and C. Kaysen (eds) The United States and the Inter-
national Criminal Court, New York: Rowman & Littlefield, pp. 85–111.
Wessels, W. (1997) “An Ever Closer Fusion? A Dynamic Macropolitical View on
Integration Processes”, Journal of Common Market Studies 35(2): 267–99.
Wheeler, N. (2000) Saving Strangers, New York: Oxford UP.
White House see US President’s Office
White, N.D. (1993) Keeping the Peace, Manchester: Manchester UP.
Wichmann, N. (2004) “The Hand that Rocks the Cradle: Do Norms Matter?” Inter-
national Studies Review, 6(1): 129–30 [book review].
Wiener, A. (2004) “Contested Compliance: Interventions on the Normative Struc-
ture of World Politics”, European Journal of International Relations 10(2): 189–
234.
Wiles, P. (2001) “The Kosovo Emergency: The Disasters Emergency Committee
Evaluation”, paper presented at Kosovo and the Changing Face of Humanitarian
Action Conference, Uppsala, Sweden, May.
Wilmer, F. (1998) “The Social Reconstruction of Conflict and Reconciliation in the
Former Yugoslavia”, Social Justice 25(4): 90–113.
Wilson, W. (1983) Address to the Senate, 22 January 1917, in Arthur S. Link et al.
(eds), The Papers of Woodrow Wilson, vol. 40, Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP,
pp. 533–9.
Winter, E. (1996) “Voting and Vetoing”, American Political Science Review 90(4):
813–24.
Wohlforth, W.C. (1999) “The Stability of a Unipolar World”, International Security
24(1): 5–41.
Wolfers, A. (1962) “Collective Security versus Collective Defense” in A. Wolfers (ed.)
Discord and Collaboration: Essays on International Politics, Baltimore, MD: Johns
Hopkins UP, pp. 181–216.
Woodward, B. (2002) Bush at War, New York: Simon & Schuster.
Woodward, B. (2004) Plan of Attack. New York: Simon & Schuster.
WorldAudit.org (n.d.) “World Audit Democracy Statistics”, Online at http://
www.worldaudit.org/statpage.htm [accessed on 2 February 2006].
Worldviews 2002 (2002) Chicago: The Chicago Council on Foreign Relations and the
German Marshall Fund of the United States.
Wright, Q. (1964) The Study of War, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Yom, S.L. (2002) “The Future of the Shanghai Cooperation Organization”, Online at
<http://www.fas.harvard.edu/-asiactr/haq/200204/0204a003.htm> [accessed on 23
October 2004].
Yoo, J.C. (2001) “Laws as Treaties? The Constitutionality of Congressional-Executive
Agreements”, Michigan Law Review 99(4): 757–852.
Young, O. (1967) The Intermediaries: Third Parties in International Crises, Princeton,
NJ: Princeton UP.
Young, O. (1992) “The Effectiveness of International Institutions: Hard Cases and
Critical Variables” in J. Rosenau and E.O. Czempiel (eds) Governance Without
Government: Order and Change in World Politics, Cambridge: Cambridge UP,
pp. 160–94.
Zacher, M. (2003) “The Conundrums of Power Sharing: The Politics of Security
References 357
Council Reform”, Paper prepared for the Conference on the United Nations and
Global Security, University of British Columbia, 18–19 September.
Zielonka, J. and Pravda, A. (eds) (2001) Democratic Consolidation in Eastern Europe:
International and Transnational Factors, vol. 2, Oxford: Oxford UP.
Zurn, M. and Joerges C. (eds) (2005) Law and Governance in Postnational Europe:
Compliance Beyond the Nation-State, New York: Cambridge UP.
Index