[Fairleigh Dickinson University Press series in communication studies] Ronald C. Arnett, Patricia Arneson, Brenda Allen, Austin S. Babrow, Isaac E. Catt, Andreea Deciu Ritivoi, Gina Ercolini, Janie Harden Fritz, Pat .pdf
[Fairleigh Dickinson University Press series in communication studies] Ronald C. Arnett, Patricia Arneson, Brenda Allen, Austin S. Babrow, Isaac E. Catt, Andreea Deciu Ritivoi, Gina Ercolini, Janie Harden Fritz, Pat .pdf
[Fairleigh Dickinson University Press series in communication studies] Ronald C. Arnett, Patricia Arneson, Brenda Allen, Austin S. Babrow, Isaac E. Catt, Andreea Deciu Ritivoi, Gina Ercolini, Janie Harden Fritz, Pat .pdf
Ronald C. Arnett and Pat Arneson (eds.), Philosophy of Communication Ethics: Alterity
and the Other (2014)
Pat Arneson, Communicative Engagement and Social Liberation: Justice Will
Be Made (2014)
Erik A. Garrett, Why Do We Go to the Zoo?: Communication, Animals, and the Cultural-
Historical Experience of Zoos (2013)
Philip Dalton and Eric Kramer, Coarseness in U.S. Public Communication (2012)
Catherine Creede, Beth Fisher-Yoshida, and Placida Gallegos (eds.), The Reflective,
Facilitative, and Interpretive Practices of the Coordinated Management of Meaning
(2012)
Jolanta Aritz and Robyn C. Walker, Discourse Perspectives on Organizational
Communication (2011)
S. Alyssa Groom and J. M. H. Fritz, Communication Ethics and Crisis: Negotiating
Differences in Public and Private Spheres (2011)
R. C. MacDougall, Digination: Identity, Organization, and Public Life (2011)
Deborah Eicher-Catt and Isaac E. Catt (eds.), Communicology: The New Science of
Embodied Discourse (2010)
Dan Cassino and Yesamin Besen-Cassino, Consuming Politics: Jon Stewart, Branding,
and the Youth Vote in America (2009)
Unit A, Whitacre Mews, 26-34 Stannery Street, London SE11 4AB, United Kingdom
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any form or by any
electronic or mechanical means, including information storage and retrieval systems,
without written permission from the publisher, except by a reviewer who may quote
passages in a review.
Philosophy of communication ethics : alterity and the other / edited by Ronald C. Arnett and Pat
Arneson.
pages cm.—(The Fairleigh Dickinson university press series in communication studies)
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 978-1-61147-707-8 (cloth : alk. paper)—ISBN 978-1-61147-708-5 (electronic)
1. Other (Philosophy) 2. Communication—Moral and ethical aspects. I. Arnett, Ronald C., 1952-
editor.
BD460.O74P45 2914
175—dc23
2014029267
TM
The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of American
National Standard for Information Sciences Permanence of Paper for Printed Library
Materials, ANSI/NISO Z39.48-1992.
Acknowledgments vii
Introduction ix
v
vi Contents
vii
viii Acknowledgments
Arnett for inviting me to work with him on this project and to Susan Carr for
her diligent and careful assistance. Thanks also to the contributors of this
volume for the care taken in expressing their ideas.
I dedicate this work to my Grandma, who taught me more than words can
say.
Introduction
ix
x Introduction
This project is composed of thoughtful chapters that speak clearly for them-
selves on the value and necessity of meeting Otherness. The intent of this
preamble is to assist the reader in understanding our stress on alterity as
radical otherness. We offer a brief glimpse of the subject of each chapter and
end by underscoring the connections between philosophy of communication
and communication ethics in the meeting of the Other. Radical differences
begin, accompany, and transform our communication with one another in a
time of otherness and offer a pragmatic reminder to learn from difference.
The chapters are grouped into three theoretical gatherings. The first series
of chapters addresses “Otherness: Place and Space.” The second sequence
turns to “Otherness and Justice,” and the third moves to “Otherness and
Contextual Divergence.” We understand questions of place, space, justice,
and contextual divergence as ways of interrogating an existential communi-
cative fact: Content and values matter, and they are inherent in our diverse
conceptions of what is of communicative importance. Before offering an
initial overture on each chapter, we pause to offer thanks to our colleagues
for their participation and their willingness to invite readers into the Philoso-
phy of Communication Ethics: Alterity and the Other. The rationale for this
shorthand is to offer an overt counter to the normative assumption that com-
munication is centered on process. Contention begins with differences that
arise from dissimilar content and value positions and standpoints.
Introduction xiii
expectation. Holba takes the reader to the doing of content and value that
contrasts with a culture bent on recreation and consumerism.
Andreea Deciu Ritivoi, in “Saving the Nation: Redemptive Ethos and the
Moral Figure of the Refugee,” takes us to an otherness that reveals the
complexity of hypertextuality in human lives. Ritivoi details a world of
multiple identity formations and linkages. She situates her theoretical expli-
cation in the moral crisis of Nazi Germany and post–World War II Germany.
We witness in the chapter a redemptive ethos of identity reformation. This
chapter exposes a postmodern reality of hypertextuality. Ritivoi reminds us
of an existential authenticity—identity is not singular; it involves multiple
places of content and values, oftentimes at odds with one another.
Isaac E. Catt, in “Communicology and the Ethics of Selfhood under the
Regime of Antidepressant Medicine,” suggests an alternative reading of the
pharmaceutical industry’s reliance upon mood-altering substances. He thinks
otherwise than the immediacy of a Western culture bent on imposition of
change. He reminds us of our communal responsibilities in discourse with
one another, which can summon hope and realignment of persons in commu-
nity. Catt’s chapter is an open challenge to content and values solidified in
smug self-assurance and then marketed within a mantra of progress that
rejects questioning.
We now invite you into conversation with our colleagues and Gerard A.
Hauser’s “Machiavelli’s Question Mark and the Problem of Ethical Commu-
nication.” We leave the last word to Hauser; he is an exemplar of philosophy
of communication and communication ethics thoughtfulness. His career has
been an ongoing examination and, when needed, challenge to reified content
and values within Western society. His afterword is an archetype of thought-
generating scholarship. We should expect no less from a colleague whose
most recent book, Prisoners of Conscience: Moral Vernaculars of Political
Agency, was the recipient of two major awards: the James A. Winans and
Herbert A. Wichelns Memorial Award for Distinguished Scholarship in
Rhetoric and Public Address from the National Communication Association
and the Rhetoric Society of America’s 2013 Book Award. 5 Good colleagues
and good chapters remind us that there is much to learn—diversity matters,
and our meeting of Otherness is the creative heart of this historical moment.
The content of philosophy of communication and the values of communica-
tion ethics matter; we do not agree on them, but they fuel our communicative
lives. Meeting the Other begins as we acknowledge the otherness all around
us housed in content and values that matter ever so differently to many of us.
NOTES
1. Alasdair MacIntyre, A Short History of Ethics: A History of Moral Philosophy from the
Homeric Age to the Twentieth Century (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, Ltd., 1967).
Introduction xvii
2. Seyla Benhabib, Situating the Self: Gender, Community, and Postmodernism in Contem-
porary Ethics (New York: Routledge, 1992); Ronald C. Arnett, Communication Ethics in Dark
Times: Hannah Arendt’s Rhetoric of Warning and Hope (Carbondale: Southern Illinois Univer-
sity Press, 2013).
3. Richard L. Johannesen, “Diversity, Freedom, and Responsibility in Tension,” in Com-
munication Ethics in an Age of Diversity (155–86), edited by Josina M. Makau and Ronald C.
Arnett (Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1997).
4. Emmanuel Levinas, Entre Nous: Thinking-of-the-Other (London: Continuum, 1998/
2006).
5. Gerard A. Hauser, Prisoners of Conscience: Moral Vernaculars of Political Agency
(Columbia: University of South Carolina Press, 2012).
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Arnett, Ronald C. Communication Ethics in Dark Times: Hannah Arendt’s Rhetoric of Warn-
ing and Hope. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 2013.
Benhabib, Seyla. Situating the Self: Gender, Community, and Postmodernism in Contemporary
Ethics. New York: Routledge, 1992.
Hauser, Gerard A. Prisoners of Conscience: Moral Vernaculars of Political Agency. Columbia:
University of South Carolina Press, 2012.
Johannesen, Richard L. “Diversity, Freedom, and Responsibility in Tension.” In Communica-
tion Ethics in an Age of Diversity, 155–86. Edited by Josina M. Makau and Ronald C.
Arnett. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1997.
Levinas, Emmanuel. Entre Nous: Thinking-of-the-Other. London: Continuum, 1998/2006.
MacIntyre, Alasdair. A Short History of Ethics: A History of Moral Philosophy from the
Homeric Age to the Twentieth Century. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, Ltd., 1967.
I
G. L. Ercolini
itinerary and life of its own as Spinozism, played a central role. While the
notion of radicality carries with it an undergirding evaluative authenticity
that can be problematic, radical also indicates the root, the fundamental. In
this sense, the early figure of Spinoza serves as a central character in later
conversations about enlightenment thought, particularly through the con-
structed or animated figure of pantheism that invariably arose in late-
eighteenth-century debates about enlightenment.
The Pantheism Controversy (Pantheismusstreit), on its face a debate
about whether renowned author Gotthold Ephraim Lessing was a Spinozist,
involved many luminaries of the time. Active participants included Lessing’s
close friend Moses Mendelssohn and Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi, the leader of
the charges against Lessing. 5 The controversy later drew in Immanuel Kant
and Johann Gottfried Herder, among others. Of course, the stakes of the
debate extend far beyond Lessing’s personal beliefs, addressing at heart both
the radical thought of Spinoza and the broader considerations central to the
German Enlightenment, particularly the relation between reason and religion,
between philosophy and theology. The Pantheism Controversy in the context
of Enlightenment Germany provides an interesting moment by which to
examine rhetoric’s place, scope, and role. This general context and period—
oft characterized as one of many nadirs in rhetoric’s history, particularly
from a vantage point presupposing the golden age of ancient oratory as
zenith—was replete with lively public debates and exchanges oriented to-
ward a broader, popular audience. While at first appearing as an esoteric
literary feud, this moment not only provides a way to reevaluate the practices
that constitute rhetoric in accounts of its history but also opens the reevalua-
tion of the broader relation between enlightenment and rhetoric.
This chapter examines the Pantheism Debate, including the initial person-
al correspondence between Mendelssohn and Jacobi after Lessing’s death,
the making public of the exchange in popular publication, and the eventual
drawing in of a somewhat reluctant Immanuel Kant. These three moments,
the core and early elements of an even wider-ranging controversy, provide an
opportunity to interrogate the conventional wisdom that rhetoric in this time
and context not only wanes but becomes entirely subsumed by the imminent
Romantic turn toward aesthetics and poetics. The Pantheism Controversy
serves as a particular site in which the lively embodied practices of rhetoric
in public debate and exchange not only concern the stakes of a historical
period examining its own present through the question, “What is enlighten-
ment?” but also further carry out, demonstrate, enact, and perform those very
considerations before a broader interested public audience. In sketching out
these contours, I start with a brief examination of the underlying question of
rhetoric in the German Enlightenment and then move to a brief overview of
the subject matter on which the debate is focused: the figure of Spinoza and
one reductive version of his thought that goes by the name of Spinozism.
The Pantheism Controversy 5
Mendelssohn and Lessing, both key players in the Enlightenment and central
characters in the Pantheism Controversy, not only forged a close and impor-
tant friendship (an important relationship undergirding the controversy) but,
furthermore, can be read as rhetorically inflected thinkers on their own. I
then turn from select key moments of the Pantheism Controversy proper
toward the twin implications of a more robust role for rhetoric in the German
Enlightenment and (borrowing from Stephen H. Browne) an ending accent
upon the texture of memory. 6
While this characterization prompts debate on many accounts (as some re-
cent scholarship has addressed, particularly on the characterization of Kant’s
attitudes toward rhetoric), Kennedy’s specific characterization of rhetoric’s
subsumption under poetics in the German Enlightenment provides an inter-
esting point for further reexamination. Not only was rhetoric a continuing
field of pedagogy at this time, but if we count as rhetoric the public practices
of lively exchange, debate, and controversies taking place through popular
journals and publications, then rhetoric not only survived but perhaps even
flourished in the context of the German Enlightenment.
Thomas Conley notes that between 1750 and 1850, over two hundred
handbooks on declamation and elocution appeared in German. 9 Even if one
restricted examination to handbooks, treatises, and courses in rhetoric during
the German Enlightenment, rhetoric hardly slips away quietly, overtaken by
poetics. While rhetoric oftentimes appears as a fine art, alongside poetry, it
exists (and persists) as a subject with distinct form, function, and operation.
Courses in Germany and Prussia were titled “rhetoric,” professorship lines
6 G. L. Ercolini
In many ways, we are still trying to come to terms with the writings of
Baruch Spinoza—despite (or even exemplified by) Slavoj Žižek’s exasperat-
ed rejoinder to Gilles Deleuze, “Is It Possible Not to Love Spinoza?” 17 This
question only emerges intelligibly rather recently—a product of a turn in
contemporary continental theory—with Deleuze’s work Spinoza: Practical
Philosophy, in particular, at the helm. 18 For centuries the question was quite
the inverse—“How could anyone (at least publicly) associate themselves
with such a dangerous thinker?” In certain circles, an epithet hardly could
take a more pointed form than Spinozist. Spinoza was always an outlaw
8 G. L. Ercolini
and criticized from an array of positions, all at the same time. Not incidental
to the question at hand, the radical thinking of Spinoza—in particular, as
Michael Mack writes, his “questioning of theology as political obfuscation,
which serves to cover up social injustices” 28—precisely helps to pave the
way for the Jewish Enlightenment’s critique of rabbinic elite and hierarchical
politics.
Mendelssohn, albeit not at his initiation, became embroiled in a few pub-
lic debates and controversies. The Lavater affair 29 involved Johann Caspar
Lavater’s challenge to Mendelssohn’s enlightened theology and the attempt
to convert him to Christianity. A debate on the civil rights and status of
Jewish people inspired Mendelssohn to contribute, resulting in another chal-
lenge to his Judaism and another attempt to claim that his thinking is closer
to Christianity, resulting in Mendelssohn’s masterpiece, Jerusalem (pub-
lished in 1783). 30 Another pivotal work, Morning Hours, emerged from
within the context of the Pantheism Controversy. 31 By all accounts, these
hardly civil public controversies took quite a toll on Mendelssohn’s health
and well-being (reportedly he developed a nervous ailment of sorts, plaguing
him from the Lavater affair until his death). These events provide a caution-
ary note to both the idealization of civil public debates and the exaltation of
the sometimes acrimonious nature of the exchanges. Mendelssohn was a
formidable participant and opponent in all three of these important public
controversies, but not to his own physical and psychological benefit.
No stranger to rhetoric and public debate, Mendelssohn even wrote of
rhetoric explicitly in the essay “On the Main Principles of the Fine Arts and
Sciences” 32 in the 1761 collection Philosophical Writings. In sketching out
the nature and relation between the fine arts and sciences, which all move us
in profound ways, Mendelssohn’s first order of division distinguishes the
fine sciences (belles lettres) as ones trafficking in arbitrary signs, and the fine
arts (beaux arts), natural signs. 33 Signs are natural, in Mendelssohn’s ac-
count, “if the combination of the sign with the subject matter signified is
grounded in the very properties of what is designated” and, furthermore,
involve the expression of “emotion by means of the sounds, gestures, and
movements appropriate to it.” 34 Signs are arbitrary when such a natural con-
nection is absent, when they have “nothing in common with their designated
subject matter, but have nonetheless been arbitrarily assumed as signs.” 35
The passage on rhetoric, not without complexity, difficulty, and influence of
its own that will have to be merely glossed here, is intriguing, bearing direct-
ly not only on this question of rhetoric in Enlightenment Germany but also
on the connection to the central practices of debate and exchange in the
learned journals:
As belles lettres, both poetry and rhetoric concern a liveliness, evoking many
senses and attributes at once, one oriented toward entertainment, the other
toward persuasion. Not only was Mendelssohn a lively participant in many
public debates and controversies, but also his philosophical thought actually
included explicit treatment of the topic of rhetoric.
If Mendelssohn is named the father of modern Jewish philosophy, then
Gotthold Ephraim Lessing (1729–1781) is credited as the father of modern
German theater. A few key aspects of his biography indeed call Spinoza to
mind: an early path of theological studies; a turning away from the expected
course of life; a restless movement from locale to locale, having trouble in
finding a place, a home, a suitable and enduring living; an untimely end to a
life replete with controversy, and so on. This hardly makes one a Spinozist,
however. Lessing’s legacy emanates from a tremendous corpus of comedies,
dramas, poetry, and aesthetic treatises forged, through Hannah Arendt’s
phrase, in “dark times,” surrounded by a sense of vexatious, evil misfor-
tune. 37 He sought to make the theater his pulpit, much to the dismay of his
family and other members of the clergy since the theater was considered a
powerful, dangerous, and potentially corrupting force.
Lessing and Mendelssohn met in 1754, “and it was through Lessing that
Mendelssohn profited not a little as a writer, critic, and as a man.” 38 After
Mendelssohn provided Lessing with a manuscript for comments, Lessing
surprised him with a published copy, having secured its publication in secret.
This work, in part inspired by Lessing and Mendelssohn’s collaborative read-
ing and conversations about Spinoza, includes two dialogues defending Spi-
noza as mediary between Descartes and Leibniz (these dialogues Mendels-
sohn later revised and published with other works in the aforementioned
volume, Philosophical Writings 39). The following year, the two collaborated
on the essay entitled “Pope: A Metaphysician!,” which in some sense ridi-
culed the Berlin Academy’s prompt as to whether Alexander Pope was a
metaphysician.
Lessing furthermore encouraged Mendelssohn to translate one of Rous-
seau’s essays, helping him along the path toward the role of popular philoso-
pher in the sense of making available, through translation and review essays,
the works of enlightened thinkers in different languages. Mendelssohn,
whose first language was Yiddish and who studied biblical Hebrew from his
youth, was also accomplished in Latin, German, French, and English, among
12 G. L. Ercolini
other languages, and was known for his brilliant style. According to Zeydel,
Lessing “set Mendelssohn on his feet as a German author and publicist and
called his attention to the advantages of the modern languages.” 40 Lessing
did not stay in any one place too long, but to Berlin (Mendelssohn’s perma-
nent residence from an early age to his death), Lessing returned several
times. Their close friendship persisted largely through correspondence when
not in each other’s direct company. Often noted is Lessing’s portrait of
Mendelssohn, surely the model for Nathan the Wise. 41
Lessing was always shrouded in controversy, not the least due to his
polemical mode of engagement. He wrote essays for Voss’s Gazette, attack-
ing the imitation and exaltation of all things French. A longtime critic of
Lessing erroneously attacked him on account of an ostensible mistake con-
cerning an archaeological matter, provoking a controversy “that was waged
fast and furiously for some months, until at last Lessing silenced his adver-
sary.” 42 While librarian for the Court of Brunswick at Wolfenbüttel, Lessing
published and edited some work of Hermann Samuel Reimarus known as the
Wolfenbüttel Fragments. 43 According to Zimmern, the “publication drew
down upon Lessing a fury of rancorous abuse, and involved him in a vortex
of controversy that lasted till his death.” 44 Leading the charge against Less-
ing, insisting that Lessing was the author hiding behind someone else’s
name, J. M. Goeze attacked Lessing while his wife lay dying. Lessing’s
relentless response, a series of fourteen letters known as Anti-Goeze, 45 out-
maneuvers his opponent in just about every way.
Lessing: “I took no offense. I did that long ago, and at first hand.”
I (Jacobi): “In its own way, I do too; otherwise I would have not shown it
to you.”
I (Jacobi): “In that case you would be more or less in agreement with
Spinoza.”
Lessing: “If I should name myself after someone, then I know no one
else.”
I (Jacobi): “Spinoza is good enough for me, but what poor salvation we
find in his name!”
The account continues the next morning when Lessing senses Jacobi’s dis-
comfort about the Spinoza conversation but basically depicts his forthright-
ness and intellectual honesty with admiration. Jacobi insists on defending a
personal God and recourse to faith, the mortal leap. After the account of the
confession and ensuing lively discussion, Jacobi summarizes his own posi-
tion in the following postulates:
1. Spinozism is atheism.
2. The Kabbalistic philosophy . . . is, as philosophy, nothing but underde-
veloped or newly confused Spinozism.
3. The Leibnizian-Wolffian philosophy is no less fatalistic than the Spin-
ozistic philosophy and leads the persistent inquirer back to the first
principles of the latter.
4. Every path of demonstration ends in fatalism.
5. We can only demonstrate similarities. Every proof presupposes some-
thing that has already been proven, the principle of which is revela-
tion.
6. The element of all human knowledge and activity is faith. 54
theological matters, the charge that such rationalism invariably strips away
the tenets of true theology (revelation, faith), and corresponding rejection of
the enlightenment synthesis of reason and theology (which in Protestant
Germany took the particular form of reconciling the Leibniz-Wolffian ration-
alism into “enlightenment theology” from the Christian side). Of course, it is
telling that Jacobi’s work concludes with an extensive quote from Lavater
(one of Mendelssohn’s early antagonistic interlocutors).
Mendelssohn, by all accounts unaware of the appearance of Jacobi’s
work, proceeded with Morning Hours, or Lectures on the Existence of God,
with an ending tribute to Lessing and without mentioning the exchange with
Jacobi. Part of Morning Hours is an elegant paean to common sense, which
provides a general orientation to Mendelssohn’s approach. In Lecture X,
after an allegorical dream in which the figure of Reason adjudicates disputes
between Common Sense (sensus communis) and Contemplation (contempla-
tio), Mendelssohn summarizes,
Whenever my speculation seems to carry me too far off the high road of
common sense, I stop and try to orient myself. I look back at the point at which
we started and I try to comprehend my two guides. Experience has taught me
that common sense tends to be right in most cases, and that reason must speak
quite decisively in favor of speculation if I am to forsake the former and follow
the latter. Indeed, it must be clear to me how common sense could have
strayed from the truth and taken the wrong track if I am to be convinced that its
persistence is mere obstinacy. 55
all things are mere modifications of the infinite substance. No thought of the
infinite can attain reality in and apart from its being. . . . God, says the
Spinozist, is the single necessary, and also the only possible, substance. Every-
thing else lives, moves, and is not outside God. Rather it is a modification of
the divine being. One is all and all is one. 57
Such is Mendelssohn’s take on hen kai pan, which he admits has adherents
but also goes against the common sense, and furthermore fails to make an
internal distinction from within substance (conflating self-supporting and
16 G. L. Ercolini
Our friend, who may well have gotten wind of Mr. Jacobi’s sincere purpose
quite quickly, was roguish enough to confirm the opinion that Mr. Jacobi had
formed of him. He may have also taken some pleasure in the ingenuity with
which Jacobi was able to expound and defend Spinoza’s doctrine. . . . There-
fore he played the attentive pupil with consummate skill, never contradicting,
agreeing with everything, and only seeking to get things going again by means
of some sort of joke when the discussion seemed to be coming to an end. . . .
Hence the affectations, platitudes, the pleasure in bad verse that was so unnat-
ural to Lessing. 66
ON MEMORY
Lessing, however, rejoiced in the very thing that has ever—or at least since
Parmenides and Plato—distressed philosophers: that the truth, as soon as it is
uttered, is immediately transformed into one opinion among many, is con-
20 G. L. Ercolini
NOTES
1. Roy Porter and Teich Mikulas, eds., The Enlightenment in National Context (Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981).
2. Jonathan Israel, Radical Enlightenment: Philosophy and the Making of Modernity
1650–1750 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001).
3. Israel, Radical Enlightenment, 7.
4. Ibid., 4.
5. Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi (1743–1819), a figure of the Counter-Enlightenment, took
issue with the Enlightenment defense of rational theology. Frederick Beiser summarizes Jaco-
bi’s general position: “Reason . . . was not supporting but undermining all the essential truths of
morality, religion, and common sense. If we were consistent and pushed our reason to its limits,
then we would have to embrace atheism, fatalism, and solipsism. . . . In short, we would have to
The Pantheism Controversy 21
deny the existence of everything, and we would have to become . . . ‘nihilists.’” According to
Jacobi, the only way to evade nihilism was to take a leap of faith. See The Fate of Reason:
German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), 47.
His relationship with Lessing dates to his publication of Woldemar in 1779, which brought
about a meeting between the two. (See B. A. Gerrish, “The Secret Religion of Germany:
Christian Piety and the Pantheism Controversy,” Journal of Religion 67, no. 4 (1987): 437–55.)
6. Stephen H. Browne, “Review: Reading, Rhetoric, and the Texture of Public Memory,”
Quarterly Journal of Speech 81 (1995): 237–65.
7. George A. Kennedy, Classical Rhetoric & Its Christian and Secular Origins from An-
cient to Modern Times, 2nd ed. (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1999), 3, 14,
45, 130, 294.
8. Kennedy, Classical Rhetoric, 275.
9. Thomas M. Conley, Rhetoric in the European Tradition (New York: Longman, 1990),
244.
10. Immanuel Kant, “An Answer to the Question: What is Enlightenment?” in Politics of
Truth, trans. Lewis White Beck, ed. Sylvere Lotringer and Lysa Hochroth, 7–20 (New York:
Semiotext(e), 1997), 31.
11. Moses Mendelssohn, “On the Question: What Is Enlightenment?” trans. James Schmidt,
in What is Enlightenment?: Eighteenth Century Answers and Twentieth Century Questions,”
ed. James Schmidt, 53–57 (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1996).
12. James Schmidt, “Introduction: What is Enlightenment? A Questions, Its Context, and
Some Consequences,” in What Is Enlightenment?: Eighteenth Century Answers to Twentieth
Century Questions, ed. James Schmidt, 1–44 (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press,
1996), 2.
13. Immanuel Kant, “On the Wrongfulness of Unauthorized Publication of Books,” in Prac-
tical Philosophy, trans. and ed. Mary J. Gregor, 23–35, The Cambridge Edition of the Works of
Immanuel Kant (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 30.
14. Joachim Whaley, “The Protestant Enlightenment in Germany,” in The Enlightenment in
National Context, 106–17 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), 110.
15. While seemingly an esoteric exchange on an ephemeral topic, Beiser notes the tremen-
dous influence of the Pantheism Controversy in three areas: an increased popularity of Spinoz-
ism in Germany, an increasing accessibility and popularity of Kantianism, and the creation of a
fracture in the Aufklärung (see The Fate of Reason, 44–45).
16. Hannah Arendt, prologue to The Human Condition (Chicago: The University of Chicago
Press, 1958), 5.
17. Slavoj Žižek, “Is It Possible Not to Love Spinoza?” in Organs Without Bodies, 29–36
(New York: Rutledge, 2004).
18. Gilles Deleuze, Spinoza: Practical Philosophy, trans. Robert Hurley (San Francisco:
City Lights Books, 1988).
19. Ibid., 6.
20. Steven Nadler, A Book Forged in Hell: Spinoza’s Scandalous Treatise and the Birth of
the Secular Age (Princeton University Press, 2011), 8.
21. Baruch Spinoza, Theological-Political Treatise, 2nd edition, trans. Samuel Shirley (In-
dianapolis: Hackett Publishing, 2001).
22. For a thorough discussion of the context and reception of Spinoza’s Treatise, see Nadler,
A Book Forged in Hell, xi, 239.
23. Benedictus de Spinoza, Ethics, in The Collected Writings of Spinoza, vol. 1, trans.
Edwin Curley (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1985).
24. Deleuze, Spinoza, 17.
25. Ibid., 17.
26. Israel, Radical Enlightenment, 12–13.
27. Michah Gottlieb, introduction to Moses Mendelssohn: Writings on Judaism, Christian-
ity, and the Bible, by Moses Mendelssohn (Waltham, MA: Brandeis University Press, 2011).
28. Michael Mack, “The Fate of Political Theology: Reflections on Shmuel Fiener’s ‘The
Jewish Enlightenment,’” Journal of Religion 81, no. 1 (2007): 78–89.
22 G. L. Ercolini
29. Michah Gottlieb explains in his prefatory note to Moses Mendelssohn: Writings on
Judaism, Christianity, and the Bible that on February 26, 1764, Johann Casper Lavater and
friends went to Moses Mendelssohn’s home seeking to make clear his view of Christianity.
After expressing his desire to keep the conversation private, Mendelssohn expressed respect for
Jesus on the grounds that Jesus did not claim to be divine. In 1769, shortly after reading Charles
Bonnet’s (1720–1793) Palingenesis, in which the divine revelation of Jesus’s miracles were
used as a basis to argue in favor of the immortality of the soul, Lavater publicly called upon
Mendelssohn to refute Bonnet’s argument. Embarrassed by this call, which placed him in the
delicate situation of having either to refute Christianity or renounce his Judaism, Mendelssohn
turned the argument back to Lavater with a “masterful” public letter in which he contrasted
Lavater’s “intolerant Christianity” with “tolerant Judaism,” 3–4.
30. Moses Mendelssohn, Jerusalem, or On Religious Power and Judaism, trans. Allan Ar-
kush (Hanover, NH: University Press of New England, 1983).
31. Moses Mendelssohn, Morning Hours, or Lectures on the Existence of God, in Moses
Mendelssohn: Writings on Judaism, Christianity, and the Bible, ed. Michael Gottlieb, 140–52
(Waltham, MA: Brandeis University, 2011).
32. Moses Mendelssohn, “On the Main Principles of the Fine Arts and Sciences,” in Philo-
sophical Writings, ed. Daniel O. Dahlstrom, 169–91 (New York: Cambridge University Press,
1997).
33. Ibid., 177.
34. Ibid.
35. Ibid.
36. Ibid., 178.
37. Hannah Arendt, “On Humanity in Dark Times: Thoughts on Lessing,” in Men in Dark
Times, 3–31 (New York: Mariner Books, 1970).
38. Edwin H. Zeydel, “Moses Mendelssohn, 1729–1929,” German Quarterly 3 (1930): 56.
39. Moses Mendelssohn, Philosophical Writings, ed. Daniel O. Dahlstrom (New York:
Cambridge University Press, 1997).
40. Ibid.
41. Gotthold Ephram Lessing, Nathan the Wise, trans. Adophus Reich (London: A. W.
Bennett, 1860).
42. Helen Zimmern, “Lessing,” in The Dramatic Works of G. E. Lessing (London: George
Bell and Sons, York Street, 1878), xxiii.
43. Hermann Samuel Reimarus, Fragments, ed. Charles H. Talbert (Minneapolis, MN: For-
tress Press, 1970).
44. Zimmern, “Lessing,” xxviii.
45. Ibid., xxix.
46. Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi, “From Jacobi’s On the Doctrine of Spinoza in Letters to Mr.
Moses Mendelssohn,” in Moses Mendelssohn: Writings on Judaism, Christianity, and the
Bible, ed. Michael Gottlieb (Waltham, MA: Brandeis University, 2011), 127–39.
47. Mendelssohn, Morning Hours, 140–52.
48. Moses Mendelssohn, “From To Lessing’s Friends,” in Moses Mendelssohn: Writings on
Judaism, Christianity, and the Bible, ed. Michael Gottlieb (Waltham, MA: Brandeis Univer-
sity, 2011), 153–71.
49. Immanuel Kant, “On the Philosophers’ Medicine of the Body,” in Anthropology, Histo-
ry, Education, ed. Gunter Zoller and Robert B. Louden, trans. Mary Gregor (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2007), 182–91.
50. Immanuel Kant, “What Does it Mean to Orient Oneself in Thinking,” in Religion and
Rational Theology, trans. and ed. Allen Wood (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996).
51. Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. and ed. Paul Guyer and Allen N. Wood
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999).
52. Jacobi, On the Doctrine of Spinoza.
53. Ibid., 132.
54. Ibid., 137.
55. Mendelssohn, Morning Hours, 143.
56. Ibid., 150.
The Pantheism Controversy 23
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Arendt, Hannah. “On Humanity in Dark Times: Thoughts about Lessing.” Translated by Clara
and Richard Winston. In Men in Dark Times, 3–31. New York: Mariner Books, 1970.
———. Prologue to The Human Condition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958.
Beiser, Frederick C. The Fate of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 1987.
Browne, Stephen H. “Review: Reading, Rhetoric, and the Texture of Public Memory.” Quar-
terly Journal of Speech 81 (1995): 237–65.
Conley, Thomas M. Rhetoric in the European Tradition. New York: Longman, 1990.
Deleuze, Gilles. Spinoza: Practical Philosophy. Translated by Robert Hurley. San Francisco:
City Lights Books, 1988.
Gerrish, B. A. “ The Secret Religion of Germany: Christian Piety and the Pantheism Controver-
sy.” Journal of Religion 67, no. 4 (1987): 437–55.
Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von. Satyros and Prometheus. Edited by Alexander Tille. Translated
by John Gray. Glasgow: Glasgow Goethe Society, 1898.
Gottlieb, Michah. Introduction to Moses Mendelssohn: Writings on Judaism, Christianity, and
the Bible, by Moses Mendelssohn. Edited by Michah Gottlieb. Translated by Curtis Bow-
man, Elias Sacks, and Allan Arkush. Waltham, MA: Brandeis University Press, 2011.
———. Prefatory Note to Selections 1, 2, and 3 of Moses Mendelssohn: Writings on Judaism,
Christianity, and the Bible, by Moses Mendelssohn. Edited by Michah Gottlieb. Translated
by Curtis Bowman, Elias Sacks, and Allan Arkush. Waltham, MA: Brandeis University
Press, 2011.
Israel, Jonathan. Radical Enlightenment: Philosophy and the Making of Modernity 1650–1750.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001.
Jacobi, Friedrich Heinrich. “From Jacobi’s On the Doctrine of Spinoza in Letters to Mr. Moses
Mendelssohn.” In Moses Mendelssohn: Writings on Judaism, Christianity, and the Bible,
edited by Michael Gottlieb, 127–39. Waltham, MA: Brandeis University, 2011.
Kant, Immanuel. “An Answer to the Question: What Is Enlightenment?” In Politics of Truth,
edited by Sylvere Lotringer and Lysa Hochroth, 7–20. Translated by Lewis White Beck.
New York: Semiotext(e), 1997.
24 G. L. Ercolini
———. Critique of Pure Reason. Edited and translated by Paul Guyer and Allen N. Wood.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.
———. “On the Philosophers’ Medicine of the Body.” In Anthropology, History, Education,
edited by Gunter Zoller and Robert B Louden, 182–91. Translated by Mary Gregor. The
Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2007.
———. “On the Wrongfulness of Unauthorized Publication of Books.” In Practical Philoso-
phy, edited and translated by Mary J. Gregor, 23–35. The Cambridge Edition of the Works
of Immanuel Kant. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
———. “What Does it Mean to Orient Oneself in Thinking?” In Religion and Rational Theolo-
gy, edited by Allen Wood, 1–18. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
Kennedy, George A. Classical Rhetoric and Its Christian and Secular Origins from Ancient to
Modern Times. 2nd ed. Chapel Hill: The University of North Carolina Press, 1999.
Lessing, Gotthold Ephram. Nathan the Wise. Translated by Adolph Reich. London: A. W.
Bennett, 1860.
Mack, Michael. “The Fate of Political Theology: Reflections on Shmuel Feiner’s ‘The Jewish
Enlightenment.’” Journal of Religion 81, no. 1 (2007): 79–89.
Mendelssohn, Moses. “From Morning Hours, Or Lectures on the Existence of God.” In Moses
Mendelssohn: Writings on Judaism, Christianity, and the Bible, edited by Michael Gottlieb,
140–52. Waltham, MA: Brandeis University, 2011.
———. “From To Lessing’s Friends.” In Moses Mendelssohn: Writings on Judaism, Chris-
tianity, and the Bible, edited by Michael Gottlieb, 153–71. Waltham, MA: Brandeis Univer-
sity, 2011.
———. Jerusalem, or On Religious Power and Judaism. Translated by Allan Arkush. Han-
over, NH: University Press of New England, 1983.
———. “On the Main Principles of the Fine Arts and Sciences.” In Philosophical Writings,
edited by Daniel O. Dahlstrom, 169–91. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
———. “On the Question: What is Enlightenment?” Translated by James Schmidt. In What is
Enlightenment?: Eighteenth Century Answers and Twentieth Century Questions, edited by
James Schmidt, 53–57. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1996.
———. Philosophical Writings. Edited by Daniel O. Dahlstrom. New York: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, 1997.
Moore, Evelyn. The Passions of Rhetoric: Lessing’s Theory of Argument and the German
Enlightenment. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1993.
Nadler, Steven. A Book Forged in Hell: Spinoza’s Scandalous Treatise and the Birth of the
Secular Age. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2011.
Porter, Roy and Mikulas Teich. Introduction to The Enlightenment in National Context. Edited
by Roy Porter and Mikulas Teich. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981.
Reimarus, Hermann Samuel. Fragments. Edited by Charles H. Talbert. Minneapolis, MN:
Fortress Press, 1970.
———. Ethics. In The Collected Writings of Spinoza, vol. 1. Translated by Edwin Curley.
Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1985.
Spinoza, Baruch. Theological-Political Treatise. 2nd ed. Translated by Samuel Shirley. Indi-
anapolis: Hackett Publishing, 2001.
Whaley, Joachim. “The Protestant Enlightenment in Germany.” In The Enlightenment in Na-
tional Context, 106–17. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981.
Zeydel, Edwin H. “Moses Mendelssohn, 1729–1929.” German Quarterly 3 (1930): 55–60.
Zimmern, Helen. “Lessing.” In The Dramatic Works of G. E. Lessing. London: George Bell
and Sons, York Street, 1878.
Žižek, Slavoj. “Is It Possible Not to Love Spizona?” In Organs Without Bodies, 29–36. New
York: Routledge, 2004.
Chapter Two
A Rhetoric of Sentiment
The House the Scots Built
Ronald C. Arnett
INTRODUCTION
25
26 Ronald C. Arnett
life within three major cities that nourished communities of creative thought
and application: Glasgow, Aberdeen, and Edinburgh.
In order to explicate this distinctive context of the Scottish Enlighten-
ment, I offer four perspectives that illuminate the importance of this peerless
orientation. First, I review Immanuel Kant’s classic essay, which opens the
conversation on the Enlightenment writ large. 4 Second, I recount a review by
C. Jan Swearingen of one of Alexander Broadie’s works, published in Phi-
losophy and Rhetoric; 5 Swearingen announces important communication
discipline connections to the Scottish Enlightenment. Third, I examine Alex-
ander Broadie’s book, The Scottish Enlightenment. 6 Finally, I turn to James
Buchan’s popularized description of the lived experience of a people at a
given time in Scottish history, Crowded with Genius: The Scottish Enlighten-
ment. 7 Buchan’s work offers dramatic insight into the Edinburgh community
of the eighteenth century that performed as a warrant for claims that gave
birth to a creative moment termed the Scottish Enlightenment. I have separat-
ed the discussions on works by Kant, Swearingen, Broadie, and Buchan in
order to render distinctly different impressions of this particular time and
place. The notion of the Scottish Enlightenment is best understood as an
inventive era, textured with multiple facets and dimensions. However, what-
ever the perspective on this historic period, there is agreement that the geo-
graphical context legitimized the rhetorical prowess of that moment, giving
rise to what we now call the Scottish Enlightenment.
This chapter serves as an overture to the Scottish Enlightenment, provid-
ing an impressionistic image of the sensations, sentiments, and feelings that
constitute this particular historical context. The heart of the Scottish Enlight-
enment rests in sensations and sentiments that shaped a given people and
their ideas, generating innovation in economics, church life, governance, and
ethics. The Scottish Enlightenment displays the rhetorical power of theory
and practice in action, offering witness to the unity of philosophy and practi-
cality. The Scottish Enlightenment yielded enlightened hope without falling
prey to a conception of progress that is oblivious to unintended conse-
quences, the inevitable shadow side of change.
KANT’S ESSAY
Immanuel Kant (1724–1804), in his classic essay “An Answer to the Ques-
tion: What is the Enlightenment?” offers a recipe for the coordinates of an
enlightened good life or, put differently, the elimination of a non-enlightened
life of laziness, cowardice, and self-incurred immaturity. Kant stressed the
practice of independent thinking and internal self-dialogue that precludes
blind allegiance to authority. Kant wrote:
A Rhetoric of Sentiment 27
Kant framed the Enlightenment as a demand that human beings “finally learn
to walk.” 9 For Kant, thinking is not only what defines humanness; it is the
essential “vocation” of every human being. 10 Revolutions seek to unseat
autocratic despotism, making room for freedom that entails public space for
thinking and rational discernment. Such a world necessitates reading, civic
participation, discussion of ideas, and a desire to keep the public domain a
home of multiple opinions. Kant’s understanding of the Enlightenment in-
cluded the civic duty of paying taxes to the government; only unjust actions
of a government that deny the organization of free discussion can legitimize
acts of rebellion.
Guardians of the people must discard thoughtless immaturity and commit
themselves to reasoned thought in the public square, forgoing the temptation
of “Imperial Diets.” 11 Authority, particularly law, must rest in “the collective
will of the people.” 12 Religious issues, human freedom, and the space for
multiple ideas in the public domain must be protected and energized by the
metaphor of “tolerance” that endorses a struggle against the “barbarity” of
lack of patience for any position that is not one’s own. 13 Kant ends his classic
essay with an emphasis on freethinking, reasoning that enlightens the public
sphere and ensures civic freedom. Such thinking assumes that the human
being, in the time of the Enlightenment, “is now more than a machine.” 14
The human must exercise the dignity of autonomous thought, acting and
thinking freely within an Enlightenment conception of the world. For Kant,
the Enlightenment was not an era; it was a space that was filled with illumi-
nation resulting from ongoing independence of thinking. Unrestricted action
and freedom in one’s thinking are human responsibilities; we are caretakers
of the public domain.
Enlightenment thinking embraced a heightened awareness about the im-
portance of diverse ideas required in the shaping of the public domain and
the necessity of autonomy of thought. For example, Kant and Jean-Jacques
Rousseau (1712–1778) wrote as supportive-thinking spectators about the ide-
as that gave rise to the French Revolution in 1789. Both Rousseau and Kant
are historically central to the Enlightenment, which according to most
sources began around 1650, shortly after the conclusion of the Thirty Years
War and the Peace of Westphalia in 1648. Spain was then less protected and
eventually lost northern territory to France in the Treaty of the Pyrenees in
28 Ronald C. Arnett
SWEARINGEN’S COMMUNICATION
PERSPECTIVE ON BROADIE
Swearingen reminded her readers that some contend that the Scottish
Enlightenment impacted the framers of the Declaration of Independence.
Controversy continues around Gary Wills’s Inventing America, which argues
that Francis Hutcheson, not John Locke, influenced Jeffersonian thinking and
language. 33 This assertion underscores Broadie’s contention that the com-
mon sense philosophy of Hutcheson, Smith, and Reid filled philosophical
gaps in early American intellectual thought, Broadie asserting that there was
a Scottish accent in early intellectual and structural documents that framed
the emerging country. 34
Swearingen concludes with Broadie’s argument against an unsophisticat-
ed understanding of Adam Smith’s achievements. 35 Some state that Adam
Smith’s Theory of Moral Sentiments (published in 1759) is centered on a
concept of “sympathy” that is then abandoned in The Wealth of Nations
(published in 1776) in favor of the notion of “self-interest.” 36 Such an analy-
sis is unduly simple, missing the interplay of self-interest and sympathy in
common sense philosophy. Swearingen’s review concludes with an emphasis
on the relationship between aesthetics and moral theory in the Scottish En-
lightenment, preparing the way for our further discussion of Broadie’s work,
The Scottish Enlightenment, as a counter to the primacy of the French En-
lightenment. 37 The French grounded the Enlightenment in universal lan-
guage, whereas the Scots grounded it on local soil, offering an intellectual
contribution to the West that was otherwise than universal abstraction.
Two concepts, morality and civic life, were driving forces in the Scottish
Enlightenment and can be found in the works of Hutcheson, Hume, and
Smith—all known for their work in the realm of morality, along with Adam
Ferguson and John Millar (1735–1801) who stressed the importance of civil
society. The literati of the Scottish Enlightenment had two principle models:
Thomas Hobbes of England and Jean-Jacques Rousseau of France, with the
former understanding the nature of human life as defined by perpetual war
and the latter understanding the human being as an innocent left to grapple
with a problematic State.
The danger of war and the cautions about the power of the State led to
what was called experimental method of reasoning. 59 Ferguson and Smith
provide concrete examples of this approach, framing experiment as direct
observation of social life. They recognized both the fragility of human life
and the necessity of a civil society charged with eradicating, or at least
managing, corruption. Ferguson was cognizant of Scotland’s distrust of Eng-
land and England’s suspicion about Scotland, particularly after the Jacobite
Rebellion (1745–1746), 60 as he was writing Essay on the History of Civil
Society. Distrust of authority was carried forward in argument between Smith
and Ferguson on the question of the military. Ferguson contended that civic
virtue requires a standing militia with an expectation that each man must give
service time to the militia. This communal commitment to a militia gave
clarity to patriotism as a shared higher ideal, a more cosmopolitan perspec-
tive than the commercial hope of self-interest alone. 61
Smith wrote in the time of Kant and during an emphasis on “sympathy”
of “spectators.” 62 Kant articulated a trilateral relation of “spectator,” “agent,”
and “recipient,” with each dependent upon the importance of “sympathy,” a
feeling or passion toward the other. 63 The notion of an impartial spectator
was necessary in the creation of human imagination, providing distance from
ideas that we advocate as agents or encounter as recipients. In order to
nourish the notion of sympathy between and among persons in the interplay
between spectator, agent, and recipient in the making of good judgments, the
Scottish Enlightenment turned increasingly to education and discussion of
civic virtue. Dugald Stewart (1753–1828) was a central figure in the articula-
tion of well-rounded education.
34 Ronald C. Arnett
Hume advanced the argument that polytheism was more appropriate for the
Enlightenment than monotheism, due to its multiplicity of perspectives.
Hume’s most significant work on religion was Dialogues Concerning Natu-
ral Religion, which appeared in 1779, three years after his death. Hume did
not deny the existence of God or of miracles; he repeatedly stated that there
is no rational proof for either. Even at the point of his death, Hume continued
to annoy many who contended that his positions represented blatant heresy
against the Church. To the chagrin of many, Hume seemingly died happy.
Hume also angered some conservative churchmen with his friendships with
William Robertson and Hugh Blair (1718–1800), both moderate clergy-
men. 67 “One might even see their [Hume, Robertson, and Blair’s] friendship
as a celebration of the Enlightenment virtue of tolerance, for the credulity
A Rhetoric of Sentiment 35
that Hume found in Blair and the incredulity that Blair found in Hume could
not shake the bond of affection.” 68 Friendship among persons of differing
views was central to the Enlightenment value of tolerance and congruent
with the Scottish Enlightenment stress on human sentiment.
The Scottish Enlightenment was the home of sentiment, offering a dwell-
ing for the creative expression of painters, writers, architects, gardeners, and
musicians. 69 For instance, creative attention toward everyday existence
shaped the work of painters such as Gavin Hamilton (1723–1798), who
followed Hutcheson’s efforts to dismiss the supernatural. Hamilton engaged
the arts with direct reliance upon lived experience. The Scottish Enlighten-
ment also stressed a rhetorical connection to sentiment. George Campbell’s
work on the Philosophy of Rhetoric, published in 1776, reminded us of great
orators who brought ideas and actions together. To a degree, the historians of
the Scottish Enlightenment were rhetoricians propelled by ideas and lived
experience, which, when understood together, constituted public evidence.
Thomas Reid proposed clarity between the sign and the signified, assisting
with knowledge of experiential public evidence. 70 He articulated the neces-
sity of distance to keep sign and signifier from collapsing into one another.
Akin to the interplay between Hutcheson and Hamilton, the paintings of Sir
Henry Raeburn represented the philosophical insights of Reid. 71 There was a
consistent theme in the Scottish Enlightenment—the uniting of theory and
practice within a framework of human sentiment.
Hutcheson was a major leader in moving the notion of sentiment into
university life. He was elected to the philosophy chair at Glasgow in 1729,
where he emphasized aesthetic and moral senses. Following this stress on
sentiment, Hume’s understanding, “Of the Standard of Taste,” framed issues
of affection and elegance in moral judgment, giving us five standards of a
critic functioning in the role of a spectator attentive to the following senti-
ments: (1) practiced understanding of taste, (2) practiced use of critical pow-
ers, (3) practiced differentiation of similar objects, (4) practiced rejection of
relational connections that can taint judgment, and finally (5) practiced en-
gagement of good sense. 72 For Hume, a “good critic” offers “the true stan-
dard of taste and beauty” through the following qualities: “strong sense,
united to delicate sentiment, improved by practice, perfected by comparison,
and cleared of all prejudice.” 73 In each one of Hume’s standards for senti-
ment, we discern practices akin to “picturesque,” ideas that connect to lived
life and bypass the safety of abstraction. 74
The emphasis on lived experience additionally manifested itself in major
scientific inventions during the Scottish Enlightenment—for example, James
Watt’s improved version of the steam engine, Thomas Reid’s work with non-
Euclidian geometry, and James Hutton’s understanding of geological
change. 75 The Scottish Enlightenment united the practical and the philosoph-
ical, engaging human nature via sentiment. From the work of Reid, to Hume,
36 Ronald C. Arnett
to Adam Smith, sentiment is a major guide. Broadie argues that the Scottish
Enlightenment can be defined by “the drum beat of sentiment.” 76 Another
concrete metaphor for describing the Scottish Enlightenment is “the age of
the earth.” 77 In an era of natural philosophy, the integration of the practical
and the theoretical framed understanding of lived experience.
The nineteenth century, according to Broadie, brought us close to what
we call the Scottish Enlightenment. He refers to this time as a “sad anti-
climax,” a time that lost the ambiance necessary for nourishing a dispropor-
tionate number of geniuses. 78 For Broadie, what drove the Scottish Enlight-
enment was not just intellectual geniuses, but a “close-knit unity” of per-
sons. 79 As people found increased space between one another, the creative
energy dissipated and then died. Broadie’s critique recounts how a pragmatic
magic perishes when families no longer stand together at a kitchen sink and
wash dishes. The mechanical assistance of the dishwasher loses an un-
scripted creative space, leaving the household with one less location that
offers an opportunity to rub shoulders; common places assist in generating
ideas for potential genius in the everyday of human life. Such an emphasis on
sociality of the Scottish Enlightenment is otherwise than the unquenched
desire for individual autonomy. The emphasis on the importance of sociality
continues with the work of James Buchan’s stress on “crowded with gen-
ius.” 80
Buchan provides a dramatic look at daily life in Edinburgh during the Scot-
tish Enlightenment, continuing the theme of creative spatiality with his title,
Crowded with Genius. Buchan begins his story with a depiction of the High-
land Rebellion of 1745 and the French Revolution of 1789, in an era when
Edinburgh “ruled the Western intellect.” 81 Edinburgh, a city once known
primarily for bigotry, violence, and poverty, became an intellectual power
during the Scottish Enlightenment. John Buchan called the battle of Culloden
Moor (1746) 82 the “last fight of the Middle Ages;” 83 this confrontation began
Edinburgh’s entrance into the modern world defined by international com-
merce, good laws, loyalty, and virtue among persons. Edinburgh was peopled
with intellectual celebrities: David Hume, Adam Smith, William Robertson,
Adam Ferguson, and Hugh Blair. Interestingly, in 1755 the famous Ency-
clopédie of French philosophers, edited by Denis Diderot (1713–1784) and
Jean Le Rond d’Alembert (1717–1783), was contemptuous of Scotland;
however, by 1762, Voltaire considered Scotland a center of taste in all arts. 84
Edinburgh had become more important than Oxford and Cambridge com-
A Rhetoric of Sentiment 37
bined. Indeed, the city was a place crowded with genius and rapidly chang-
ing.
In the year 1745, the city of Edinburgh had forty thousand people without a
royal court (lost to London in 1603), had combined Scottish and English
parliaments since 1707, and had developed little manufacturing. Edinburgh
was principally a city of lawyers and churchmen, with the attorneys attending
the Court of Session and the clergymen joining the General Assembly of the
Church of Scotland. There were nine Presbyterian churches, each with two
ministers. There were also two banks, both of which survive today, as well as
two newspapers—one Whig and the other Jacobite. In 1708, the parliamen-
tary Union with England destroyed the formal administration of Scotland and
politically empowered the Edinburgh Town Council, which was run as an
oligarchy 85 ever since James VI (1473–1513). The purpose of the council
was to maintain peace among three groups: the guilds, the Kirk, and the
Presbytery. 86 The confines of Lawnmarket and High Street were densely
populated; the sight of wood burning and peat smoke provided impetus for
the area’s nickname—Auld Reekie, or Old Smokey—a place of few public
buildings and little bread to eat; it remained, at that time, a city with Medie-
val character and smell. The intellectual foundations of Edinburgh, however,
were present years prior. The courts, the Kirk, and the college provided a
threefold foundation for the intellectual ascendance of Edinburgh. There was
political debate in Scotland when the Whigs rejected authority from the
Crown and wanted influence to come from the public itself. 87 The city had
been mainly Protestant since John Knox, a leader of the Scottish Reforma-
tion, imported both the creed and doctrines of John Calvin from Geneva,
Switzerland, to St. Giles, Scotland, in the 1560s. This set of theological
commitments was set against the royal House of Stuart since the time of
Mary, Queen of Scots (1542–1587). 88 John Knox and Edinburgh contended
against monarchs of divine-right and the Roman Catholic Church. 89 The
other political side of Edinburgh was composed of the Jacobites (named from
the Latin for James), who supported the House of Stuart and their “sacramen-
tal and eternal right” to rule over Scotland. 90 The Revolution of 1688 ended
Stuart government in Edinburgh and put the Stuart court in exile. After the
revolution, the Episcopalian church was disestablished. The former Episco-
palians became Jacobites. London was determined to punish Edinburgh,
leading Lord Provost George Drummond (1687–1766) to state that Edin-
burgh was held together by fear and hatred. The Jacobite/Whig debate con-
tinued with David Hume contending that the city, without a merchant class,
38 Ronald C. Arnett
could only prosper by defeating both the Jacobites and Whigs, with the
former being a political defeat and the latter requiring a religious downfall.
The tension between Britain and Scotland continued to increase after the
revolution. Charles Edward Stuart (1720–1788), the grandson of James VII
of Scotland and II of England and leader of the Jacobite Rebellion, was living
in exile under the protection of the French court in 1743. He led the Jacobites
who were landing from France in 1745 under the direction of the Earl of Mar.
Former Lord Provost George Drummond was in charge of the defense party.
This effort by Drummond, at the age of fifty-eight, launched his political
career as Lord Provost of Edinburgh once again. 91 The Lord Provost, Archi-
bald Stewart (elected in 1744), did not know what to do in the midst an
invasion. Drummond, on the other hand, took his volunteers and marched to
the castle in a political gesture that stopped the invasion.
The Jacobite rebellion of 1745, led by Prince Charles Edward Stuart, could
not take the castle. On October 31, Prince Charles Edward left, demoralized,
and abandoned his expedition. Then, on November 26, 1746, Drummond
once again became Lord Provost, with the old Provost Stewart being tried for
neglect of office. The Jacobite rebellion transformed Edinburgh and brought
forth names such as Adam Ferguson and Hugh Blair, 92 who stressed “union-
ism.” 93 Societally, the rebellion simultaneously invited acts of romantic nos-
talgia and philosophical pessimism. David Hume wondered if civilized life
was “unfit for the Use of Arms.” 94
The fight for Edinburgh was not just against the Stuarts but in the name of
intellectual and religious freedom, as well. For example, on December 23,
1696, Thomas Aikenhead, a student at the college, was indicted by the Court
of Justiciary for blasphemy. The Lord Advocate claimed that Aikenhead
repeatedly spoke of Christian theology as a “rapsodie of feigned and ill-
invented nonsense.” 95 This eighteen-year-old boy in Presbyterian Edinburgh
was hanged until dead on January 8, 1697. This case haunted Edinburgh for a
century, calling into question responsive attention to the privacy of con-
science—an ongoing political controversy between the Jacobites and Whigs.
The ecclesiastical wars initiated conflict between a “rigid Calvinism which
saw any deviation in doctrine or conduct as a mortal threat to the whole
community, and a new conviction of the privacy and variety of conscious-
ness.” 96 An emphasis on privacy of conscience privileged skepticism over
knowledge “revealed through scripture” 97—such thinking led to the effort to
excommunicate David Hume and Henry Home (1696–1782) by the General
Assemblies of 1755 and 1756. At that time, the Kirk had assumed many civil
and judicial functions and worked from an agenda of religious strictness. 98
Lord Provost Drummond was dispirited until the General Assembly was
A Rhetoric of Sentiment 39
joined by a new generation of leaders born after 1690. One could finally
sense the possibility of bridging the gap between Presbyterianism and the
new ideas emerging out of the college. For instance, Robert Wallace
(1697–1746) suggested that the way to repel the power of the Deists was
with their own weapon––reason. 99 Wallace was at first persecuted for this
perspective, but then, in 1742, he became the moderator of the General
Assembly. He brought the famed English evangelist George Whitefield 100
(1714–1770) to Scotland; such actions of public tension and debate revealed
the seemingly restless power of change in Scotland.
At the University of Glasgow, Andrew Carlyle (1722–1805), in 1743,
found his liberal sentiments gaining ground under the influence of Francis
Hutcheson, who brought a preoccupation with issues of virtue, a perspective
contrary to Thomas Hobbes’s view that human beings were totally selfish.
Hutcheson claimed that the human’s principle virtue was “disinterested be-
nevolence.” 101 Hutcheson was a utilitarian who connected good conduct to
the beautiful and the pleasurable, which he associated with the greatest hap-
piness for the greatest number. Buchan understood Hutcheson’s system as
more akin to “aesthetic imagination” and “reasoning intellect,” unlike “the
philosophy of the sentimental novelist.” 102 Some felt Hutcheson abandoned
the modern project by underestimating the power of reason; in actuality, he
assisted with a Scottish stamp on the Enlightenment with his emphasis on the
senses, both moral and aesthetic.
One of those countering Hutcheson’s continuing commitment to philoso-
phy that was attentive to God’s world was Hume, an emerging intellectual
hero willing to plumb “the darkness of intellectual despair.” 103 Hume was
known for his commitment to skepticism and suspicion. He founded no
school, left no major successor, and was denied the privilege of a professor-
ship. He offered an alternative to the common sense school that he deemed
too dependent upon a “benevolent deity” and “disreputable prejudices.” 104
Hume sought to rediscover the importance of human emotion. He seemed to
be working, in some strange way, out of a tradition more akin to Francis
Bacon or Sir Isaac Newton, who had rejected and abandoned a priori argu-
ments that constituted the Middle Ages. Bacon and Newton embraced an
experimental method that intrigued Hume, who was interested in establishing
a new science of ethics, which he connected to a “New Scene of Thought.” 105
Hume believed the human mind could be completely known. Hume was
interested in knowledge and causation connected to a sense felt by the mind.
Reason had been given a heightened importance that Hume wanted to de-
throne. On this matter, Hume and Hutcheson had significant kinship.
Hume’s A Treatise of Human Nature: Being an Attempt to Introduce the
Experimental Method of Reasoning into Moral Subjects was published in
three books or volumes—the first two were published in 1739 and the third
in 1740, followed by a cool and hostile reception; he then decided to follow
40 Ronald C. Arnett
ever, began to assume more power, finding power from London. In 1762,
Blair was installed in the High Kirk; his sermons were a necessary part of a
visitor’s trip to Edinburgh. He was appointed to the position of professor of
rhetoric and belles lettres at the college. David Hume stayed in Scotland, as
did William Robertson, who in 1762 was installed as the principal of the
college. Robertson then had control over both the Kirk and the college until
the late 1770s when civil rights questions arose in regard to Scottish Catho-
lics. 110 Creative change and debate defined Edinburgh.
Fifty years after the union with London, Edinburgh was prospering, and
the Jacobites were a spent force. Prince Charles Edward Stuart had retreated
and was in exile, comforted by drink and “undignified attachments.” 111 In
Edinburgh, the argument for union had been won in Scotland; problems were
moving to London as Scotland became a place of economic, intellectual, and
civic life shaped by the sentiments of the Scottish Enlightenment.
Buchan suggests that perhaps the last and greatest of the major works of the
era was Adam Smith’s Theory of Moral Sentiments; the book appeared in
1759, the year a number of British military victories over the French in both
Europe and North America occurred. The book was more accessible than
Hume’s Treatise and less “precious” than Hutcheson’s Inquiry. 112 By the
time of Smith’s death on August 4, 1790, it was stated that he had moved
from the chair of moral philosophy at the University of Glasgow into a focus
on trade and finance. Both David Hume and Adam Smith privileged the
notion of human instinct over reason. Smith is best known for The Wealth of
Nations; however, throughout his life, he was concerned with the practices of
morality within an emerging commercial society. Buchan, like Broadie,
argued against those who suggested that the Theory of Moral Sentiments
concerned sympathy and The Wealth of Nations centered on selfishness. In
particular, H. T. Buckle (1821–1862) made such a suggestion, which has not
held scholarly water. There is unity in Smith’s thought; one must understand
the ongoing unity between sympathy and selfishness.
Smith was born June 5, 1723, at Kirkcaldy, never knew his father, and
was often sick; at the University of Glasgow, Smith found himself under the
spell of Francis Hutcheson’s lectures. Smith’s agile mind was equipped with
knowledge of Latin, Greek, French, and Italian. His first major essay dealt
with astronomy; he understood philosophy as an effort to make sense out of
chaos and to hold things together––“philosophy as tranquilizer.” 113 Many of
Smith’s major metaphors were more literary than social scientific: “impartial
spectator,” “invisible hand,” and “propensity to barter and truck.” 114 By
1751, Smith was appointed professor of logic and rhetoric at Glasgow. He
was not only a brilliant mind but also a graduate of Oxford University, which
42 Ronald C. Arnett
IN SEARCH OF FREEDOMS
The first freedom that was sought in Scotland was economic; during the
Jacobite occupation in Edinburgh in 1745, the Highlanders would hold up
pedestrians for a penny. 129 The new Scotland was becoming an argument
between those who understood the importance of luxury and opulence and
those like Sir James Steuart Denham (1712–1780), 130 who called for a Sparta
of frugal needs, a “Spartan communism.” 131 Steuart’s position did not ro-
mantically view commerce as a magic solution. “Public authority . . . must
intervene to protect the fragility of modern systems.” 132 Steuart was im-
pressed by the Spartan system of “longevity, consistency and simplicity.” 133
Steuart’s work was quoted by Hegel and Marx and applauded by Adam
Ferguson, who spent many of his adult years as a military chaplain. Ferguson
understood that conflict and society go hand in hand. Provost George Drum-
mond, in 1759, appointed Ferguson to the chair of natural philosophy, after
44 Ronald C. Arnett
which Ferguson mastered physics in three months in order to teach it. 134
Ferguson was deeply committed to Scotland, defending the play Douglas and
promoting Ossian poetry; he understood the fragility of institutions and soci-
eties and the importance of local soil. Ferguson’s work on An Essay on the
History of Civil Society was an effort to bring forth a moral public and virtue
that recognized the pragmatic necessity of connection with Britain. Ferguson
became a kind of Scottish Cato in his later years. On the other hand, Adam
Smith acknowledged the modern fact of commercial life of luxury and opu-
lence and was greatly influenced by Hume and Hutcheson, more so than
Ferguson, whose commitment to a Spartan world shaped his commitments to
both Scotland and Britain.
The diversity of positions within the public domain made Edinburgh alive
with concern for ideas and others: conversations shaped by ideas and senti-
ment. Buchan offers the example of the changes between Dr. Samuel John-
son and James Boswell (1740–1795) during Johnson’s visits to Edinburgh. 135
The two were like oil and water; Johnson disliked Adam Smith and loathed
David Hume and particularly detested Boswell, who was deeply committed
to Scotland and regretted its union with Britain. Yet, at the end of his life,
Johnson, in one of his narratives, discussed his visit to Scotland and talked
about the “college for the deaf and dumb” that was operated by Thomas
Braidwood. 136 Johnson was hard of hearing; he was so impressed with their
work that when he talked about the experience, he was moved to tears.
Edinburgh was crowded with genius that extended into concern for others.
As Edinburgh entered the eighteenth century, people like Adam Smith
and David Hume reflected a “bachelor society.” 137 However, the eighteenth
century was also “the women’s century” within Scotland. 138 In retrospect,
one witnesses the role of Jacobite women in the Forty-Five Rebellion as
“brilliant” and “striking.” 139 The admission of women was understood as an
emerging maturity of Edinburgh. Women were admitted to the college lec-
tures in 1745; in 1710, public dancing was introduced in Edinburgh. Into this
world of increasing inclusion came gaiety and social improvement. Women
began to alter their appearance from the national plaid of yesteryear. Under
the philosophical influence and the insights of Montesquieu and Rousseau,
Edinburgh began to take seriously the importance of a proper education for
young women. 140 John Millar, in his book Origin of the Distinction of Ranks,
also assisted in bringing women into the discussion of Scottish philosophy.
Additionally, the French Revolution in 1789 further altered the public posi-
tion of women. The Scottish sentiment included ideas of inclusion and atten-
tiveness to practical advancement.
A Rhetoric of Sentiment 45
ed his work. Burns was considered an example of pure genius. However, Sir
Walter Scott (1771–1832), the final romantic author from Edinburgh, who
had seen Burns with luminaries such as Adam Ferguson, John Home, and
James Hutton, stated that Burns was no genius, just an exemplar of a life-
style. Sentiment had moved from a noble philosophical heritage, to literary
pulp fiction, to the invitation of a lifestyle that was destructive of self and
other.
The Scottish Enlightenment—an invitation to an egalitarian democratic
world and a world of ideas put into action was, at best, a paradox. Even in
1779, the Whigs were still at their mean-spirited best, attempting to relieve
the Roman Catholics of civil rights that they had labored for under the
Reformation, giving rise to the so-called Gordon riots. The excesses of terror
in France came close to Scotland; even romantic radicals like Robert Burns
had to recant “liberal sentiment” with the rise of Jacobinism. 145 In 1793, the
British Convention of Delegates of the People came to Edinburgh; their task
was to press for universal suffrage and, at the same time, “Lord Braxfield
invented a crime of unconscious sedition [stating] . . . ‘Let them bring me
prisoners, and I’ll find them law.’” 146 Scotland was increasingly becoming a
myth. It took Sir Walter Scott, an architect of modern Edinburgh, to catapult
Scotland and its ancient capital into the romantic center of the world—
“Through him it is possible the experience the history of Edinburgh twice:
once as disaster, and once as daydream.” 147 Great ideas and action had
morphed into literary myth.
The creative genius of the Scottish Enlightenment came from the doing;
the rhetorical warrant for change emerged from a community of poverty,
desire for social change, and commitment to general education that included
the highest percentage of literacy in Europe. The rhetorical warrant for con-
ceptual and practical change died when the gaze of too many turned to the
task of reifying the genius of a previous moment and past accomplishments.
This rhetorical solidification of a myth became a death gaze, moving Scot-
land from the creative application of theory and practice to celebratory rheto-
ric about Scottish Enlightenment accomplishments. Self-congratulatory rhet-
oric led the shift from crowded with genius to a place crowded with rhetoric,
of self-affirmation based on lineage and heritage. The rhetorical death of
genius comes from a rhetoric based upon pedigree that bypasses the needed
creative work that seeks to turn creative otherness into the banality of the
expected, the predictable, the routine. Rhetorically, what is lost is a commit-
ment to a dwelling that is crowded with innovative productivity that demands
meeting local, creative, and cosmopolitan insights. The rhetoric shifts from
learning and doing to telling, leaving only an antiquarian understanding of
genius and creative productivity. The rhetoric of telling and the desire to
control, to colonize a creative moment, moves a people from learning from
the Other into a milieu that atrophies into acts of possession and posturing—
A Rhetoric of Sentiment 47
NOTES
1. James Buchan, Crowded with Genius, the Scottish Enlightenment: Edinburgh’s Moment
of the Mind (New York: HarperCollins, 2003).
2. Stephen E. Toulmin, The Uses of Argument (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University
Press, 1958/2003).
3. Calvin O. Schrag, Communicative Praxis and the Space of Subjectivity (Bloomington,
IN: Indiana University Press, 1986); Schrag, Philosophical Papers: Betwixt and Between (Al-
bany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1994); Schrag, The Resources of Rationality: A
Response to the Postmodern Challenge (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1992);
Schrag, The Self After Postmodernity (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1997). Also see,
Ronald C. Arnett, “Civic Rhetoric––Meeting the Communal Interplay of the Provincial and the
Cosmopolitan: Barack Obama’s Notre Dame Speech, March 17, 2009.” Rhetoric & Public
Affairs 14, no. 4 (2011).
4. Immanuel Kant, “An Answer to the Question: What Is the Enlightenment?” in What Is
Enlightenment: Eighteenth-Century Answers and Twentieth-Century Questions, ed. James
Schmidt (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1784/1996).
5. C. Jan Swearingen, review of A History of Scottish Philosophy, by Alexander Broadie,
Philosophy and Rhetoric 43, no. 2 (2010).
6. Alexander Broadie is the first scholar whose scholarship covers the full seven centuries
of Scottish philosophy. Broadie is professor of logic and rhetoric at the University of Glasgow,
the first Henry Duncan Prize lecturer (1990–1993) in Scottish Studies at the Royal Society of
Edinburgh, and a Gifford Lecturer at Aberdeen (1994). In 1991, Broadie was both elected to
the Fellowship of the Royal Society of Edinburgh and was appointed chair of Philosophy at
The University of Glasgow—the same chair that had been occupied by Adam Smith. In 2007,
he was awarded an honorary doctorate degree from Blaise Pascal University for his contribu-
tions to Franco-Scottish relations in the field of the history of philosophy. See “Alexander
Broadie,” from the Gifford Lectures website, accessed May 10, 2013, www.giffordlectures.org/
Author.asp?AuthorID =213; Alexander Broadie, The Scottish Enlightenment (Edinburgh: Bir-
linn, 2007).
7. Buchan, Crowded with Genius.
8. Kant, “Answer to the Question,” 58.
9. Ibid., 59.
10. Ibid.
11. Ibid., 61.
12. Ibid., 62.
13. Ibid.
14. Ibid., 63, emphasis added.
15. Susanne Kord, Women Peasant Poets in Eighteenth-Century England, Scotland, and
Germany: Milkmaids on Parnassus (Rochester, NY: Camden House, 2003), 40.
16. Franklin E. Cort, The Scottish Connection: The Rise of English Literary Study in Early
America (Syracuse, NY: Syracuse University Press, 2001), 2.
17. Swearingen, Review.
18. David Hume is intentionally not in this list as he was denied chairs at both the University
of Edinburgh in 1744 and the University of Glasgow in 1764. See Encyclopædia Britannica,
s.v. “David Hume,” accessed May 10, 2013, www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/276139 /
David-Hume.
19. Swearingen, “Review.”
20. Broadie notes that David Hume, along with Adam Smith, was one of the most well-read
and influential scholars of the Republic of Letters, a group of writers who committed their work
to the public domain. Additionally, Hume was a leading Scottish historian of the eighteenth
48 Ronald C. Arnett
century alongside Smith, Kames, Turnbull, and Ferguson. See Broadie, History of Scottish
Philosophy, 14, 44.
21. John Duns Scotus was a Franciscan philosopher, scholar, realist, and theologian who
introduced the doctrine of the Immaculate Conception, which argues that Mary, the mother of
Jesus, was conceived without original sin. Additionally, Scotus contended that “Incarnation
was not dependent on the fact that man had sinned, that will is superior to intellect and love to
knowledge, and that the essence of heaven consists in beatific love rather than the vision of
God.” See Encyclopædia Britannica, s.v. “Blessed John Duns Scotus,” accessed May 10, 2013,
www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/173846/Blessed-John-Duns-Scotus.
22. The Declaration of the Clergy (1310) declared Scotland in favor of King Robert Bruce.
The document, which repeatedly stresses leadership determined by the Scottish citizenship,
argues that England, or more specifically the king of England, does not have the authority to
declare the Scottish king. See Broadie, History of Scottish Philosophy, 28. The four versions of
the Declaration of the Clergy, preceding The Declaration of Arbroath, made between 1309 and
1310, were written in an effort to persuade European clergy and monarchs of Robert I’s royalty.
Roland J. Tanner, “Cowing the Community? Coercion and Falsification in Robert Bruce’s
Parliaments, 1309–1318,” in The History of Scottish Parliament, ed. Keith M. Brown and
Roland J. Tanner, vol. 1 (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2004), 59.
23. The Declaration (or Letter) of Arbroath argued for papal recognition of Scotland’s right
to name its own leaders. See Swearingen, Review, 189. The Declaration of Arbroath asserted
the independence of Scotland following Robert the Bruce’s victory over the English at Ban-
nockburn in 1314. The declaration was composed by the Scottish Parliament in Arbroath
Abbey, a historic county in Scotland founded in 1178 by King William I, and sent to the pope
at Avignon, France. See Encyclopædia Britannica, s.v. “Arbroath,” accessed May 10, 2013,
www.britannica.com /EBchecked/topic/32366/Arbroath.
24. Controversy surrounding the Declaration of Arbroath is due to its “hype” rather than its
“reality.” Since it has become the modern motto for the Scottish Nationalist Party, “moderates
in Scotland today often respond with reserve to its invocation.” See Swearingen, Review, 189.
25. Although not stressed by Swearingen, Scotus offered an alternative reading to Augus-
tine’s understanding of will. See Swearingen, “Review.”
26. Ibid., 190.
27. Ibid.
28. Ibid., 189.
29. Michel de Montaigne was the French writer whose Essais (Essays ) marked a “new
literary form.” His Essays are among the “most captivating and intimate self-portraits ever
given, on a par with Augustine’s and Rousseau’s.” See Encyclopædia Britannica, s.v. “Michel
de Montaigne,” accessed May 10, 2013, www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/390476 /
Michel-de-Montaigne.
30. Swearingen, “Review.”
31. Francis Hutcheson designed the new curriculum in moral philosophy while he was a
professor at Glasgow, a curriculum which was adopted by all of Scotland’s universities. It
replaced the dark view of human nature with “doctrines of humankind’s innate love of virtue
and liberty.” See Swearingen, “Review,” 193–94.
32. Ibid., 195. Common sense philosophy, as framed by Hutcheson, Smith, and Reid, chal-
lenged Rousseau. These philosophers defied the state of nature defined by Rousseau on the
grounds that it was unscientific because, according to their own historical and scientific obser-
vations, humans have always, first and foremost, by their nature, formed societies for their
individual betterment and collective good.
33. Gary Wills, Inventing America: Jefferson’s Declaration of Independence (New York:
Houghton Mifflin, 1978/2002).
34. Broadie, History of Scottish Philosophy.
35. Swearingen, “Review.”
36. Buchan, Crowded with Genius, 121.
37. Swearingen, “Review”; Broadie, Scottish Enlightenment.
38. Some argue that the Scottish Enlightenment consisted solely of the eighteenth-century
Scottish contributions to political economy, history, and moral philosophy; others claim that
A Rhetoric of Sentiment 49
mathematics and the natural sciences were crucial as well. See Broadie, Scottish Enlighten-
ment.
39. Broadie notes that Hume, Smith, and Ferguson are leading eighteenth-century Scottish
historians; additionally, they made leading contributions to the philosophical culture of Scot-
land. See History of Scottish Philosophy, 44. Broadie credits Thomas Reid, professor of moral
philosophy at Glasgow and a member of Aberdeen’s Philosophical Society, as the “deepest of
the philosophers of the Scottish Enlightenment.” See Broadie, Scottish Enlightenment, 30. Reid
was both a mathematician and a writer of the nature of the mind and human action, as well as a
scholar of rhetoric and jurisprudence. James Hutton, the “father of modern geology,” earned a
Doctorate of Medicine from the University of Leiden in 1749. Hutton’s leading contribution
was his research on the age of the heart, which he defined, against religious scrutiny, as having
no beginning and no end. See Broadie, History of Scottish Philosophy, 209–11. Sir Henry
Raeburn, one of the best portraitists in Europe alongside Allan Ramsey, reflected a distinction
between “what we see and what we know”; Raeburn was influenced by the writings of Thomas
Reid and represented human nature as “individuated” to each person. See Broadie, History of
Scottish Philosophy, 174.
40. Broadie, Scottish Enlightenment, 13.
41. Some international institutions include the Republic of Letters, the Moderate Party—
which disapproved of the traditional harshness of Scottish Calvinism—and the Rankenian Club
in 1717.
42. Broadie, Scottish Enlightenment, 14.
43. Ibid., 20.
44. Ibid., 42.
45. George Buchanan, a Scottish humanist and educator, critiqued the Church during the
Reformation for its corruption and inefficiency. See Encyclopædia Britannica, s.v. “George
Buchanan,” accessed May 10, 2013, www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/82825/George-
Buchanan.
46. John Knox, considered the leader of the Scottish Reformation, set the moral tone for the
Church of Scotland and shaped Scotland’s democratic government. See Encyclopædia Britan-
nica, s.v. “John Knox,” accessed May 10, 2013, www.britannica.com/EBchecked /topic/
320580/John-Knox.
47. William Robertson, a Presbyterian minister and Scottish historian, is regarded, along
with David Hume and Edward Gibbon, as one of the most important British historians of the
eighteenth century. Robertson completed his studies at the University of Edinburgh in 1741 and
was ordained a minister in the Church of Scotland. He became a member of the church’s
General Assembly in 1746, holding a leading position in the moderate party for many years.
His reputation as a historian emerged with his first major work, The History of Scotland,
During the Reigns of Queen Mary and of King James VI, published in 1759. He was appointed
principal of the University of Edinburgh and historiographer royal for Scotland. His works
reflect his interest in social theory, stressing the importance of material and environmental
factors in determining the course of civilization. Although influential in the nineteenth century,
his writings received little attention during the twentieth century. See Encyclopædia Britanni-
ca, s.v. “William Robertson,” accessed May 10, 2013, www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/
505591/William-Robertson.
48. Broadie, Scottish Enlightenment, 47.
49. Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgment, trans. J. H. Bernard (New York: Hafner Press,
1790/1951), 136–37.
50. Broadie, Scottish Enlightenment, 72.
51. Dugald Stewart, under the influence of Thomas Reid, became a major exponent of the
Scottish common sense school. Stewart was educated and taught at the University of Edin-
burgh, where he was appointed professor of philosophy in 1785, replacing Adam Ferguson in
the chair of Moral Philosophy at Edinburgh, holding this position until 1820. Stewart’s major
works include Elements of the Philosophy of the Human Mind, (published in three volumes
emerging in 1792, 1814, and 1827), Outlines of Moral Philosophy (published in 1793), Philo-
sophical Essays (published in 1810), and Philosophy of the Active and Moral Powers of Man
50 Ronald C. Arnett
(published in 1828). See Encyclopædia Britannica, s.v. “Dugald Stewart,” accessed May 10,
2013, www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/566015/Dugald-Stewart.
52. Broadie, Scottish Enlightenment, 72–73.
53. Ibid., 69.
54. Ibid., 75.
55. Ibid.
56. Ibid.,76.
57. Ibid., 77.
58. Ibid.
59. Ibid., 81.
60. The Jacobite Rebellion, often referred to as the Forty-Five Rebellion, was the final
rebellion in a series of such in support of exiled Stuart King James II and his followers after the
Glorious Revolution. See Encyclopædia Britannica, s.v. “Jacobite,” accessed May 10, 2013,
www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/299035/Jacobite. English distrust lasted nearly a decade
after the Jacobite Rebellion. In Scotland, this distrust seemed to be misplaced, and Adam
Ferguson wrote on the subject as part of a wide debate among the literati. See Broadie, History
of Scottish Philosophy, 91.
61. Smith was not completely opposed to militias but disagreed with Ferguson, who charged
that a replacement of militia with a standing army would threaten civil liberty. Rather, Smith
saw the standing army as a “category of ‘division of labor.’” See Broadie, History of Scottish
Philosophy, 92.
62. Broadie, Scottish Enlightenment, 101.
63. Immanuel Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals, ed. M. Gregor (Cambridge, UK: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1797/1996).
64. Broadie, History of Scottish Philosophy, 109.
65. Broadie, Scottish Enlightenment, 115.
66. Broadie, History of Scottish Philosophy, 136
67. William Robertson, alongside William Cullen, John Robinson, Hugh Blair, Adam Fer-
guson, and Adam Smith, founded the Philosophical Society of Edinburgh in 1783. See Broadie,
History of Scottish Philosophy, 57. Hugh Blair was the first occupant of the chair of rhetoric
and belles lettres at Edinburgh University and was minister of the Hugh Kirk of St. Giles,
providing intellectual underpinnings for the Enlightenment. See Broadie, History of Scottish
Philosophy, 22. Both Blair and Robertson served as members of the Select Society in 1754, a
debating society on the principles of Jacobitism. See Broadie, History of Scottish Philosophy,
26–27.
68. Broadie, Scottish Enlightenment, 150.
69. Ibid., 151.
70. Ibid., 169.
71. Hamilton was a pupil of Hutcheson’s at the University of Glasgow. Hutcheson’s philos-
ophy was naturalistic—Hutcheson believed in God but believed that it was possible to con-
struct human virtues without resorting to revelation. Hamilton’s paintings depicted the super-
naturalism of the Homeric narratives, which was thought to be intentional according to Hutche-
son. Hamilton and Hutcheson both fit into a secular and humanistic orientation. See Broadie,
History of Scottish Philosophy, 155–56.
72. Broadie, Scottish Enlightenment, 178.
73. Ibid., 184.
74. Ibid., 185.
75. Ibid., 186.
76. Ibid., 198.
77. Ibid., 209.
78. Ibid., 218.
79. Ibid., 219.
80. Buchan, Crowded with Genius.
81. Ibid., 1.
82. The Battle of Culloden Moor (April 16, 1746) was the last battle of the Forty-Five
Rebellion. The Jacobites, under Prince Charles Edward, were defeated by British forces under
A Rhetoric of Sentiment 51
William Augustus, Duke of Cumberland. The battle lasted only forty minutes and resulted in
bitter defeat for the heavily outnumbered Jacobites; as many as one thousand of five thousand
Highlanders were killed by the nine thousand Redcoats, who lost only fifty men. The Highland-
ers fled, and British troops killed another one thousand men during the following weeks. Prince
Charles wandered over Scotland for five months before escaping to France. See Encyclopædia
Britannica, s.v. “Battle of Culloden,” accessed May 10, 2013, www.britannica.com /
EBchecked/topic/146084/Battle-of-Culloden.
83. Buchan, Crowded with Genius, 1.
84. Ibid., 2.
85. An oligarchy is a government ruled by the few where power is despotic. See
Encyclopædia Britannica, s.v. “Oligarchy,” accessed May 10, 2013, www.britannica.com/
EBchecked/topic/427558/oligarchy.
86. A hierarchy of courts controls the Church of Scotland. Beginning with the Kirk sessions,
congregation affairs are governed. The Presbytery covers the group of parishes, and finally the
General Assembly hosts clergy and lay representatives annually to discuss key issues. See
Encyclopædia Britannica, s.v. “Scotland,” accessed May 10, 2013, www.britannica.com/
EBchecked/topic/529440/Scotland/44556/Languages.
87. Buchan, Crowded with Genius, 17.
88. Mary Queen of Scots (1542–1567) whose “unwise marital and political actions” were
the cause of rebellion among the Scottish nobles. Mary was forced to flee to England, where
she was deemed a threat to the English throne and was eventually beheaded. See Encyclopædia
Britannica, s.v. “Mary,” accessed May 10, 2013, www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/
367467/Mary.
89. Buchan, Crowded with Genius, 18.
90. Broadie, History of Scottish Philosophy, 19.
91. Drummond was elected Lord Provost in 1725, 1746, 1750, 1754, 1758, and 1762; each
term lasted two years.
92. Hugh Blair was a Scottish minister and university professor best known for his four-
volume Sermons, the first of which was published in 1777, and for his lectures on rhetoric and
fine arts. He was licensed to preach in 1741 and began ministering at the Canongate church in
Edinburgh in 1743. In 1757, he was given an honorary doctorate from the University of St.
Andrews and in 1758 was promoted to the cathedral of St. Giles (the High Kirk of Edinburgh),
the most important charge in Scotland. In 1759, he began, under the patronage of Henry Home,
Lord Kames, to deliver a successful course on composition, which led to his appointment as
chair of rhetoric and belles lettres at the University of Edinburgh in 1762. See in Encyclopædia
Britannica, s.v. “Hugh Blair,” accessed May 10, 2013, www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/
68746/Hugh-Blair.
93. Buchan, Crowded with Genius, 54.
94. Ibid., 55.
95. Ibid., 56.
96. Ibid., 57.
97. Ibid.
98. Henry Home, Lord Kames, was appointed a judge in the Court of Session in 1752. He
became a lord of justiciary in 1763. Home is best known for his three-volume work Elements of
Criticism (published in 1762). See Encyclopædia Britannica, s.v. “Henry Home,” accessed
May 10, 2013, www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/310597/Henry-Home-Lord-Kames.
99. Buchan, Crowded with Genius, 65.
100. George Whitefield was a famous English evangelist in mid-century Edinburgh who
reignited a preaching style that was popular during the persecution of the later Stuarts. See
Buchan, Crowded with Genius, 67.
101. Ibid., 70.
102. Ibid., 71.
103. Ibid., 75.
104. Ibid., 76.
105. Ibid., 80.
106. Ibid., 85–86.
52 Ronald C. Arnett
107. Samuel Johnson is regarded as one of the “greatest figures of eighteenth-century life and
letters.” See Encyclopædia Britannica, s.v. “Samuel Johnson,” accessed May 10, 2013, www.
britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/305432/Samuel-Johnson. Johnson was critical of Adam
Smith and disliked David Hume. See Buchan, Crowded with Genius, 232.
108. Buchan, Crowded with Genius, 108–9.
109. Ibid., 110.
110. Ibid., 116.
111. Ibid., 118.
112. Ibid., 119.
113. Ibid., 125.
114. Ibid., 126.
115. Ibid., 131.
116. Ibid., 136.
117. Ibid.
118. Ibid., 138.
119. Ibid., 139.
120. Ibid., 141.
121. Ibid., 142.
122. Ibid., 145.
123. Ibid., 160.
124. Ibid, 163.
125. Ibid., 174.
126. Ibid., 176.
127. Ibid., 183.
128. Ibid., 206.
129. Ibid., 208.
130. Sir James Steuart Denham was a “leading Scottish economist who was the leading
expositor of mercantilist views.” See Encyclopædia Britannica, s.v. “Sir James Steuart Den-
ham, 4th Baronet,” accessed May 10, 2013, www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/157672/Sir-
James-Steuart-Denham-4th-Baronet. Unlike Smith and Hume, Steuart explores three divisions
of society—pastoral, agrarian, and commercial—which progress due to rising population and
surpluses in trade. See Buchan, Crowded with Genius, 215.
131. Buchan, Crowded with Genius, 212.
132. Ibid., 215.
133. Ibid., 216.
134. George Drummond, six-time Lord Provost of Edinburgh, became a commissioner of
customs in 1715 and city treasurer by 1717. He worked to establish the medical school at the
college and helped to found the Royal Bank of Scotland while managing the General Assembly
of the Church.
135. Samuel Johnson’s visit to Edinburgh left an impression on posterity, but he had little to
say about Scotland. Boswell, who had met Johnson in 1763, had wanted to establish and
introduce Johnson to the Scottish people as well as vice versa. For twelve weeks, Johnson and
Boswell, along with one of Boswell’s servants, Joseph Ritter, traveled Scotland.
136. Buchan, Crowded with Genius, 240.
137. Ibid., 241.
138. Ibid.
139. Ibid., 243.
140. Beginning with Montesquieu and then Rousseau, Edinburgh made contributions to the
philosophy of women, including God’s purpose for women, the proper education for women,
the differences between men and women, and the institution of marriage. See Buchan,
Crowded with Genius, 260.
141. Buchan, Crowded with Genius, 287.
142. Rousseau was exiled from France in early 1766 on account of his atheist beliefs. See
Buchan, Crowded with Genius, 304.
143. Buchan, Crowded with Genius, 304.
A Rhetoric of Sentiment 53
144. Tacitus was a “Roman orator and public official, probably the greatest historian and one
of the greatest prose stylists who wrote in the Latin language. Among his works are the
Germania, describing the Germanic tribes, the Historiae (Histories ), concerning the Roman
Empire from ad 69 to 96, and the later Annals , dealing with the empire in the period from ad
14 to 68.” See Encyclopædia Britannica, s.v. “Tacitus,” www.britannica.com/EBchecked/
topic/579997/Tacitus.
145. Buchan, Crowded with Genius, 337.
146. Ibid., 338.
147. Ibid., 340
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Arnett, Ronald C. “Civic Rhetoric—Meeting the Communal Interplay of the Provincial and the
Cosmopolitan: Barack Obama’s Notre Dame Speech, March 17, 2009.” Rhetoric & Public
Affairs 14, no. 4 (2011): 631–71.
Broadie, Alexander. A History of Scottish Philosophy. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press,
2009.
———. The Scottish Enlightenment. Edinburgh: Birlinn, 2007.
Buchan, James. Crowded with Genius, the Scottish Enlightenment: Edinburgh’s Moment of the
Mind. New York: HarperCollins, 2003.
Cort, Franklin E. T he Scottish Connection: The Rise of English Literary Study in Early
America. Syracuse, NY: Syracuse University Press, 2001.
Kant, Immanuel. “An Answer to the Question: What Is the Enlightenment?” In What Is En-
lightenment: Eighteenth-Century Answers and Twentieth-Century Questions, 58–64. Edited
by J. Schmidt. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1784/1996.
———. Critique of Judgment. Translated by J. H. Bernard. New York: Hafner Press, 1790/
1951.
———. The Metaphysics of Morals. Edited by M. Gregor. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, 1797/1996.
Kord, Susanne. Women Peasant Poets in Eighteenth-Century England, Scotland, and Germa-
ny:Milkmaids on Parnassus. Rochester, NY: Camden House, 2003.
Schrag, Calvin O. Communicative Praxis and the Space of Subjectivity. Bloomington: Indiana
University Press, 1986.
———. Philosophical Papers: Betwixt and Between. Albany, NY: State University of New
York Press, 1994.
———. The Resources of Rationality: A Response to the Postmodern Challenge. Bloomington,
IN: Indiana University Press, 1992.
———. The Self after Postmodernity. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1997.
Swearingen, C. Jan. Review of A History of Scottish Philosophy, by Alexander Broadie. Phi-
losophy and Rhetoric 43, no. 2 (2010), 186–99.
Tanner, Roland J. “Cowing the Community? Coercion and Falsification in Robert Bruce’s
Parliaments, 1309–1318.” In The History of the Scottish Parliament, edited by K. M. Brown
and R. J. Tanner, 50–73. Vol. 1. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2004.
Toulmin, Stephen E. The Uses of Argument. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press,
1958/2003.
Chapter Three
Pat J. Gehrke
This chapter argues that the dominance of philosophies of One has pro-
duced the current crisis and that the turn to philosophies of the Other, such as
that of Emmanuel Levinas, will not provide satisfactory redress. Instead, I
turn toward a highly restrained minimalist ontology of community, offering
an alternative path for the study of ethics, politics, and communication.
55
56 Pat J. Gehrke
PHILOSOPHIES OF ONE
Philosophies of the Other find their grounds in encounters with another (or
the Other). While sometimes also labeled philosophies of alterity, I want to
reserve the possibility of distinguishing these particular philosophies from
those that may make alterity central but do not find their grounding in refer-
ence to the Other or an other. One of the most influential and recognized
philosophies of the Other is the work of Levinas. The dominance of the
encounter with the Other in Levinas and his insistence upon not fusing others
or the two (the other who approaches me and the me called out by the other)
into one make his work a particularly prime example of a philosophy of the
Other. In such philosophies of communication and ethics, a perhaps phenom-
enal, perhaps counterfactual dyadic encounter becomes the model for ethics
(the encounter of two, of the Other and me). Contrary to the theorization of
dyads in philosophies of One, Levinas’s philosophy of the Other operates
through the priority of the Other as an infinitely alterior Other before which
one inclines. 9 Rather than emphasize or rely upon the unitary vision of a
philosophy of One, Levinas’s philosophy of the Other places all emphasis on
the prioritization of the Other in a dyadic alterity that, by his argument,
interrupts the fusion that would make these two into One. In Levinas and
similar philosophies of the Other, the entire experience of ethics relies upon
the Other that confronts me and the priority of the Other. This asymmetry
and the unidirectional obligation (I am obligated for the Other, but there is no
reciprocal obligation) 10 may enable philosophies of the Other to avoid re-
turning to a philosophy of One, but also models all further considerations of
politics, community, and justice on this original dyad.
Scholars appealing to philosophies of the Other often reference dissatis-
faction with philosophies of One as the reason for their consideration. 11 In
many cases philosophies of the Other do indeed avoid many of the criticisms
leveled against philosophies of One, but they do so at a significant cost.
Communication ethicists and theorists grappling with the thinking of ethics
under philosophies of the Other find it particularly difficult to extend the
philosophy to include the simple fact that life is not lived in dyads. As T. A.
Carlson notes, Levinas’s ethic “actually resists an articulation of commu-
nity.” 12 While Levinas does attempt an explication of community and justice,
he calls them the limit of responsibility and the introduction of a contradic-
tion that always risks integrating the Other into a “we.” 13 Positing justice and
community as the emergence of a third (the other to the Other), as an adden-
dum to the first dyad of the Other and me, creates a philosophy of community
and justice that makes every relation always a dyad or some combination of
dyads. Thus, the ethics of the Other as this other before me becomes the
model for thinking of justice and community. 14 Even in the third, the rela-
tions between the three are figured as an incomplete triangle composed of
Before the One and the Other 59
only two dyads: the Other and me; the other-to-the-Other and me. Justice for
Levinas is thus the problem of competing incommensurable dyads.
Additionally, philosophies of the Other most often require particular qual-
ities or characteristics of the two persons in the encounter (the Other and me).
Levinas, for example, insists that the Other must be human and cannot be
animal or any other substance. 15 Such an insistence is difficult to understand
if not predicated upon something that is innately or at least uniquely human.
What is it about the approach of a human other that so uniquely sets it apart
from the approach of a nonhuman other? If it is to be found in a unique
quality of that approach, then there seems little way to avoid falling back into
either a philosophy of One that would imbue every human with some unique
quality manifest in the approach of a human Other (such as reasoned autono-
my in Immanuel Kant) or a dialectical philosophy in which a third term or
operation sublates the approach, the Other, and me into an organization or
specified relationship. In moments of Levinas’s writing that fold together the
approach of the specific Other before me and the approach of the face of
God, there is a hint that a dialectical movement has sublated alterity and
unicity to a divine alterior or perhaps an alterior divine. Scholars of Levinas
have been struggling for years with these dimensions of his work, and it
remains one of the most problematic elements of his philosophy. 16
Philosophies of One certainly provide little salve to those who find such
faults with philosophies of the Other, and likewise contemporary critics of
philosophies of One have been attracted to philosophies of the Other, but
often find that their reliance upon a dyadic model leaves them unable to
address the fact that life occurs in disparate multiplicity. Where this leaves us
today is with two largely unsatisfactory philosophies grounding the majority
of communication ethics and theory.
being-in-the-world as being-together 17
out that the Kantian moral system gives priority to autonomy and the central-
ity of that priority to the moral philosophy of perhaps Kant and certainly
most Kantians, 19 the more important observation is that Kant’s establishment
of noumenal principles for both metaphysics and ethics is predicated first
upon phenomenal necessities, one of which is the phenomenal necessity that
being in the world is being-together. To put it in plainer language, before one
can establish ideal principles, even in Kantian terms, one must begin with the
simple fact of being-in-the-world. If Stroud is correct that Kant and the
Kantians attempted a divide between his theoretical and practical philoso-
phies that would make this conclusion untenable, then this may do much to
explain the detriment that much modern philosophy has inherited from the
Kantians.
This observation, however, does not tell us much about that simple fact of
being, though it does place the simplicity of mundane being as antecedent to
all our theories and philosophies of Being. Risking some repetition of my
previous work, let us begin with Kant’s three analogies of experience: dur-
ability of substance, causation, and community. Kant begins not with the
noumenal or ideal structure of the world but with the fact of experience, or
perhaps more precisely, the facticity of being without presumption of any
particular form or content of being. This simplest of facts—there is being, or
more simply, there is—precedes any knowing or seeing, 20 but this does not
make being into the arche of the world. Quite to the contrary, as Kant’s
metaphysics argues, any particular being is only possible as being-together.
Since I have already worked this issue out at length in the previous essay,
I will only briefly review its operation here. A being in the world can only be
as a result of its distinction from not just another being and not an Other
being, but a multiplicity of other beings in time and space. A being requires
being, which is not so much a tautology as the necessity of a sheer status as
being. Every thing, a word, a thought, a rock, a person, must have a sheer
status of being in order to become a thing and then that thing. If a being
requires a sheer status of being, then also it requires a position in time and
space. All beings (objects, things, people, thoughts) can only be by virtue of
being then and being there. A being must be in the world, or perhaps more
accurately we should say in a world, even the being of a thought or experi-
ence.
Yet, as Kant noted, we have no direct experience of either time or space,
so in order for something to have a position in time and space, its reference
cannot be time or space themselves. To place a specific being in time and
space with reference only to time qua time and space qua space would
require that time and space as themselves become beings, that they would
become things in the world. Instead, we depend upon the relative positioning
of beings to other beings for any particular being to have its position in time
or space. Any being that exists can exist because it is given a position in time
Before the One and the Other 61
and space by virtue of being coexistent but not identical with other beings in
the world. The blue shirt that floats by is on the man wearing it, who is now
further to my right than three minutes ago, when the draft slightly ruffled the
papers on my desk as I typed, and as I was typing a few lines earlier, the
woman in red was whispering something to the man beside her, who sat in
the chair ahead of me while I thought how to end this sentence. No being,
material or otherwise, nothing that is, was, or will be, can be except as being
in distinction and coexistence with other beings, and this distinction and
coexistence gives each its very possibility for being, including the possibility
of the being of experience. 21
This requisite fact of phenomenal coexistence Kant called community,
but the term community here carries none of the baggage that would bind it to
the common, the shared, or the bond of blood. It was not until much later in
his groundwork for agency and morals that Kant would propose a particular
type of rational community of beings imbued with moral agency. Even in the
work of Kant, a figure often championed as the strongest advocate of the
foundational nature of the ideal rational agent in ethical thought, there is a
being that must precede rational agency as the necessary condition of all
beings—animal, vegetable, mineral, ephemeral. Being is the simple fact that
being is being-in-the-world, but the world and being are only given by the
multiplicity of beings that give each being its position in time and space.
By now the importance of the lowercase of being as discussed here is
already clear. This is no grand, foundational, or prescriptive Being. This is
not a being with any particular substance, form, nature, or quality. This
certainly is not a rational Being or a shared Being or even a human Being but
is instead first and foremost sheer being. This is being that precedes every
attempt to give to beings some Being that would define, separate, bond,
gather, or organize them. This is the sheer being of being-together in the
world.
The emphasis on the sheer reflects my attempt to distinguish this being
from all those theories of Being that would seek to insert some quality or
content at the origin of beings. Indeed, even the event of death or alienation
from the self or the separation of man from the divine rely first on the
possibility of experience, the possibility of sheer existence, which can only
occur as being-together. To place it in terms of the philosophies of One and
the philosophies of the Other, before there can be a unifying principle or the
establishment of dyads, there is first an anarchic multiplicity. Language here
fails us, for even multiplicity would imply multiplication from, as if there
was an operation of reproduction (multiplication is, after all, an operation
that produces a product from multipliers) or perhaps an operation of division
(such as multiplication through division, as with mitosis). 22
While multiplicity is a popular word to describe being-together, we might
likewise use a phrase such as dispersed beings or a term like community.
62 Pat J. Gehrke
back into a philosophy of One or, at best, a philosophy of the Other, then we
cannot start with the Human. We likewise cannot start with humans or a
human. Prior to being a human, one is first a being that is being-together. The
co-creation of the Human and humans, a human and another human, makes
every human a human by virtue of (and hence in debt to) being-together with
the not-human. The human and nonhuman are posterior inventions of beings
parsing out and organizing relations in response to the first condition of
anarchic community: the facticity of being as being-together.
Many philosophers of ethics and communication are struggling today to
think of an ethic that starts with this simplest and most minimal ontological
claim: being is being-together. If this basic claim holds merit, then this most
simple and mundane minimal ontology is not an ethic (i.e., one among oth-
ers) but the answer to why there is ethics at all. The question is not one of
ethics before ontology or ontology before ethics but understanding that the
simplest requirement of being is relationality, the condition of being together,
being-as-relation, owing to this first community one’s very possibility not
only to say “I” but to exist in the world, to be called you or thou or it. The
first obligation, the obligation that at every moment is the beginning of
being, is being obligated by this debt, by owing being to being-together, by
owing being to every other being, every moment and event in time and space,
without exception and without measure.
Thus, before any ontology of Being, there is first the ethics-ontology/
ontology-ethics of being-together. Prior to a notion of finitude, prior to a
calling of the divine in the face of another human, prior to the instantiation of
a category of rational beings, prior to ecological interdependence, there is the
ontological obligation that my possibility of being is owed to an anarchic
community—being is owed to being-together. This is not any particular com-
munity or even a philosophy of community but the basic simple community
that every object in space and time requires for its position in space and time.
At his best, Kant taught us that while objects in space and time must exist
in space and time, we cannot know much of anything about the structure of
space or time. We might make pragmatic philosophies for the navigation or
measurement of things and their changing relationships in space and time,
but space and time themselves cannot become objects of experience. Kant
did not even promise that the three analogies of experience (durability, caus-
ation, community) would reveal any substantive content. 24 In fact, he argued
that it only matters that something like durability exists, not what is durable
or how durability is maintained. Similarly, the analogy of causation stated
only that something like causation or change must occur, not that causation
or change are governed by any greater principles or structures that would
give them a logic or substance. So also with community, we can only know
that something like community must exist, not that there is any necessary
structure, function, or content to that coexistence.
64 Pat J. Gehrke
every other thing in space and time, then every position in space and time
must be occupied by only one particular, and no other particular can occupy
that moment of space and time. Every particular in space and time at every
moment is unique and singular. This fleeting thing, this thing here and now,
can only be now and here, and no other thing can be at this place and this
time. Thus, each thing at each moment is irreplaceable, owing its irreplace-
able uniqueness to its being-together with every other unique, irreplaceable
thing in every other moment of time and space.
The obligation of being-together is thus an obligation not only to commu-
nity but also to the community of singular beings being-together without any
necessary structure, order, or philosophy to that together. We are each of us
bound to every other thing (animal, vegetable, mineral, ephemeral) irredu-
cibly, inextricably, infinitely, and again at every moment. My obligation
emerges at every moment, every instance, again and again, never ceasing and
never subsiding, as my being is given to me over and over by the community
of singular beings-together.
If the ethics of being-together sounds entirely impractical, it is because
the practical always presumes a particular relation, a dividing up of this
obligation, weighing out its contradictions, and making choices. The problem
is not so much with being-together as with the fact that ethics demands
choosing, and choosing only occurs in the face of specific contested options.
By virtue of the fact that we are always infinitely obligated by the very
possibility of being and that this infinite obligation makes no distinction
between our obligation to any particular thing, and that there is no organizing
principle or philosophy for either the together of being-together or the obli-
gation intrinsic to being, we are bestowed with the necessity of choosing
without a calculus or philosophy for choice. The contradictions, the tensions,
the doubling-backs that make ethics impractical are what make ethics both
necessary and possible. Ethics emerges by virtue of the fact that nothing is
decided by ontology, that there is no guiding principle to being-together, that
we must choose, we must make choices, take leaps into the world for which
we are always responsible and we can never know to be ethical.
If ethics were practical, then it would not be ethics at all. If it were merely
a matter of following a credo, obeying a set of rules, operating along a
calculus, approximating a normative principle, then ethics and life would
never be a question of choice but only a question of knowledge and applica-
tion. Epistemology would conquer ethics. We have inherited this error in our
philosophies and our language. Consider that the term right holds for us so
many functions that would connect truth, morality, and obligation together as
one idea: To be right about something, to do the right thing, and to have a
right are conflated in the history of Western philosophy from even before
Socrates’s reasoning soul.
66 Pat J. Gehrke
Yet, ethics are at the same time all about practice; they are about nothing
other than being-together in the action of the everyday, in the simplest being
of being-together, here and now. As such, the overwhelming ethical call of
community is the call of every moment of being. There is not an instant in
which being is not given to us again by virtue of being-together. I am always
dependent and always owing this moment of being to the being-together of
every instance in time and space, and so every action is always a response to
this basic ontological fact. Ethics is in every second of practice, every small
move, choice, gesture, word, and thought. As such, the ethics of being-
together is nothing but an ethics of practice in the everyday, even if it is in
some sense impossible.
situation but always first reaction to infinite anarchic community. The re-
sponsive “I” comes in Levinas’s thought from the approach of the Other, 27
but prior to the Other’s approach is the anarchic community, the sheer being
of being-together. In every moment, when we respond, we respond to, as, in,
and for this infinite community of singular beings, even before the approach
of the Other. There is, then, no less a call to this moment here than to any
other moment, nor to this other before me as to every other. At every mo-
ment, we are called to respond, or more accurately, to be responsible for this
community of singular beings being-together.
The traditional ethicist would place before us now some dilemma or
situation that requires us to come to an ethical choice: Nazis come knocking
on the door while the Jewish family hides in my basement; the pharmacist
who withholds the medicine that I cannot afford to buy my dying child, and
so on. Each of these scenarios mistakes ethics for a set of specific relation-
ships that are deployed in an effort to generate or test a model for ethical
action. Is there a contract or a universal rationality that obligates me simulta-
neously to tell the truth to this Nazi and to protect this Jewish family; to
provide the medicine to my child and not to steal from the pharmacist? The
ethical is masked in such considerations of contracts and axioms, but also
recedes in the thinking of obligation and response in an abstracted locality,
even if every response and every obligation requires its locality to occur.
When the ethicist builds such a scenario, the counterfactual structure sets
aside the very thing that imbues us with responsibility: the infinite commu-
nity of singular beings. Lived experience never confronts one with these
scenarios because we always live in the disparate multiplicity of all, to which
we bear an infinite and unyielding obligation. Every smile, every gesture,
every small choice, every move evokes the entirety of our obligation to
being-together.
An act of communication, a saying, a choosing of what is said, is thus a
choosing of the mode of response to the community of singular beings—a
response as much to that which gives us the very possibility of response as to
the persons and circumstances found in locality. When we say “yes,” or even
a simple “please,” or when we orate on matters of grand public affairs and
international politics, in all these cases and every other, we engage the entire-
ty of the community of all beings in time and space, even those that we will
never know or encounter. Each response, then, is a living of the responsibil-
ity, an ethos, an ethic, a choosing of living and responding that is at that
moment the particular making of a world. The question is not which response
is ethical but which ethic is in the response, which living and being, what
world is in the making of that response.
Today we face ethics of response that would cover over everything that
makes being and choosing possible, replacing the absolute obligation of an-
archic community with a contract, an identification, a unity, a bond, a dialec-
68 Pat J. Gehrke
tic, Humanity, reason, the divine, and all those other expressions of philoso-
phies of One and philosophies of the Other. Can there be anything more
urgent right now than to interrogate this repetition of the general horizon of
our age that has hurled us into a world in which everything is in danger and
nothing exists except in the service of such tyrannies?
Tyranny is not the most accurate word, but it does spur the consideration
of the ethico-political at stake in this discussion. Nancy’s depiction of the
ethico-political, of a community-politics without telos or arche, gives us one
narrative of how we can live together and make necessary and impossible
choices. 28 Under philosophies of One, the political is guided by the theologi-
cal (or at least pseudo-theological, as in humanist ontology). This theologico-
politics makes all singular beings and all life slave to the extension and
repetition of a philosophy of One. Whether it be a philosophy of human
essence, an interpretation of divine will, or the expansion and reproduction of
“market democracy,” each turn returns to the philosophy and feeds all things
to it, without exception and without any choosing or ethical struggle, except
to overcome the resistance offered by the excess of the existent.
Communism and Nazism are but two examples of the theologico-political
in operation, but no less so is the operation of current Western market de-
mocracies and all their dreams of the end of history and the liberation of man,
from the progressive disciples of John Dewey to the neoconservatives in-
spired by Francis Fukuyama. In the politics of these philosophies, all things
yield to the articulation of an ideal, a telos, or a unity. To contrast the ethico-
political to the theologico-political is to contrast a politics without telos or
unity to all those systems of relations that grind the community of singular
beings being-together into one substance, into a community of commonality.
The question, however, is not how to hold everything apart as monads. Each
is always already dependent on every other, but being-together in every
moment emerges again and again, asking us to take up the political anew
each time, without reservation, without hesitation, and without reliance upon
what might have come before.
Contrary to philosophies of the Other, an ethico-politics of community
ties up singular being with singular-being in being-together at every moment;
each tying and unraveling at the same moment, calling us to take up the act
of tying once again. Every choice, every little motion of the eye, each small
word, is another chance to take up the tying again. The ethico-political takes
up the tying in each moment—not to tie us together with knots, not to give us
a common bond, but to tie again and to tie only for that moment and in that
moment, in response to all being-together.
Such a politics refuses justification for ideologies, projects, and agendas
in a way that might appear contrary to many cherished and vital political
projects of the twenty-first century. The problem is not that being-together is
insensitive to the immediate material suffering of beings in the world. To the
Before the One and the Other 69
movement and this moment that would not demand the interrogative? Is the
next step in this process a case study that would exemplify this operation?
Does any such opportunity exist today, or is there no politics without telos in
circulation? Could such a case study be done without the fantasy of produc-
ing a model for that which is without model? Is communication inextricably
connected to the theologico-political philosophies of One? Here, on the brink
of social and ecological collapse, on a planet tortured by unitary visions and
theologico-politics, what more important question could communication
ethicists and theorists ask than this: Can we think differently from that which
has led us to this dangerous precipice?
NOTES
10. For an explication of Levinas’s critique of reciprocity, see Arne Johan Vetlesen, “Rela-
tions with Others in Sartre and Levinas: Assessing some Implications for an Ethics of Proxim-
ity,” Constellations 1, no. 3 (1995): 358–82.
11. For example, Ronald C. Arnett, “The Responsive ‘I’: Levinas’s Derivate Argument,”
Argumentation and Advocacy 40 (2003): 39–50; Michael J. Hyde, The Call of Conscience:
Heidegger and Levinas, Rhetoric and the Euthanasia Debate (Columbia, SC: University of
South Carolina Press, 2001); Lisbeth Lipari, “Listening for the Other: Ethical Implications of
the Buber-Levinas Encounter,” Communication Theory 14 (2004): 122–41.
12. T. A. Carlson, “Ethics, Religiosity, and the Question of Community in Emmanuel Levi-
nas,” Sophia 37 (1998): 42.
13. Emmanuel Levinas, Otherwise than Being or Beyond Essence (Boston: Kluwer Aca-
demic Publishers, 1991), 157–61.
14. For a more detailed explication, see Pat J Gehrke, “Being for the Other-to-the-Other:
Justice and Communication in Levinasian Ethics,” Review of Communication 10 (2010): 5–19.
15. See Emmanuel Levinas, Difficult Freedom: Essays on Judaism, trans. Seán Hand (Balti-
more: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1990), 152–53; Tamra Wright, Peter Hughes, and
Alison Aimley, “The Paradox of Morality: An Interview with Emmanuel Levinas,” trans.
Andrew Benjamin and Tamra Wright, in The Provocation of Levinas: Rethinking the Other, ed.
Robert Bernasconi and David Wood, 169–73 (New York: Routledge, 1988).
16. See Silvia Benso, The Face of Things: A Different Side of Ethics (Albany, NY: SUNY
Press, 2000), 200; Diane Davis, “Greetings: On Levinas and the Wagging Tail,” JAC: A
Journal of Composition Theory 29, no. 1 (2009): 711–48; Christina Diehm, “Facing Nature:
Levinas Beyond the Human,” Philosophy Today 44 (2000): 51–59; Pat J. Gehrke, “The Ethical
Importance of Being Human: God and Humanism in Levinas’s Philosophy,” Philosophy Today
50 (2006): 428–36.
17. The grammatically inappropriate use of the lower case here and elsewhere emphasizes
the reference to the simple fact of phenomenal being and sets apart the term from the sense of
Being that would imply a grander or more unifying ontology than this chapter pursues.
18. Pat J. Gehrke, “Turning Kant against the Priority of Autonomy: Communication Ethics
and the Duty to Community,” Philosophy and Rhetoric 35 (2002): 1–21.
19. Scott Stroud, “Kant on Community: A Reply to Gehrke,” Philosophy and Rhetoric 39
(2006): 157–65.
20. Even if one insists upon the possibility of the middle voice (“knowing knows” and
“seeing sees”), which would distinguish knowing from a being that knows, the knowing still
must exist; the seeing still is in its seeing, which is to say that even without the prerequisite of a
subject, there is the prerequisite of being (sheer existence), though this does not require any
particular type or form of being. The middle voice merely avoids the idea that there must be a
subject, but not that something must be, that is, that there must be being. Language makes this
difficult to say, as the middle voice is anathema to our way of speaking and thinking, but I
struggle for some (over)simplicity in saying that seeing sees still relies on the being of seeing.
21. It might be more accurate here to say the possibility of anything other than undifferen-
tiated uniformity, but this point is quite trivial since a constant and undifferentiated experience
would be impossible to distinguish from no experience at all. Additionally, the experience of
undifferentiated uniformity is logically problematic, as such an experience already requires the
distinction of an experiencing being from the experienced uniformity, which would deny that
the experience was purely of undifferentiated uniformity in the first place.
22. In biology, the term mitosis describes the process of one cell dividing into two cells with
identical genomes.
23. For an excellent discussion of the problems of noncount nouns, mass, and stuff, see
Thomas J. McKay, “‘Critical Notice’ of Words without Objects,” Canadian Journal of Philos-
ophy 38 (2008): 301–24. For a more abbreviated introduction, see Laycock, Henry, “Object,”
in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2011 edition), published October 1, 2002,
revised August 4, 2010, ed. Edward N. Zalta, accessed May 26, 2013, plato.stanford.edu/
entries/object/.
24. See Kant’s Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics, ed. Paul Carus (Chicago: The
Open Court Publishing Company, 1912).
72 Pat J. Gehrke
25. Norman Fischer, “The Concept of Community in Kant’s Architectonic,” Man and World
11 (1978): 372-91; Susan Meld Shell, The Embodiment of Reason: Kant on Spirit, Generation,
and Community (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996).
26. Jean Luc Nancy, The Inoperative Community (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press, 1991), 60.
27. See Arnett, “Responsive ‘I.’”
28. See Phillipe Lacoue-Labarthe and Jean Luc Nancy, Retreating the Political (New York:
Routledge, 1997); Jean Luc Nancy, The Sense of the World (Minneapolis: University of Minne-
sota Press, 1998); also Pat J. Gehrke, “Community at the End of the World,” in Communication
Ethics: Between Cosmopolitanism and Provinciality, ed. Kathleen Glenister Roberts and Ro-
nald C. Arnett (New York: Peter Lang, 2008).
29. Henry W. Johnstone, “Toward an Ethics of Rhetoric,” Communication 6 (1981):
305–14.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Arnett, Ronald C. “The Responsive ‘I’: Levinas’s Derivate Argument.” Argumentation and
Advocacy 40 (2003): 39–50.
Baird, Craig A. “Speech and the New Philosophies.” Central States Speech Journal 13 (1962):
241–46.
Benso, Silvia. The Face of Things: A Different Side of Ethics. Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 2000.
Campbell, Karlyn Kohrs. “The Rhetorical Implications of the Axiology of Jean Paul Sartre.”
Western Speech 35 (1971): 155–61.
Carlson, T. A. “Ethics, Religiosity, and the Question of Community in Emmanuel Levinas.”
Sophia 37 (1998): 42–71.
Davis, Diane. “Greetings: On Levinas and the Wagging Tail.” JAC: A Journal of Composition
Theory 29, no. 1 (2009): 711–48.
Dickens, Milton. “Discussion, Democracy, Dictatorship.” Quarterly Journal of Speech 33
(1947): 151–58.
Diehm, Christina. “Facing Nature: Levinas Beyond the Human.” Philosophy Today 44 (2000):
51–59.
Fischer, Norman. “The Concept of Community in Kant’s Architectonic.” Man and World 11
(1978): 372–91.
Gehrke, Pat J. “Being for the Other-to-the-Other: Justice and Communication in Levinasian
Ethics.” Review of Communication 10 (2010): 5–19.
———. “Community at the End of the World.” In Communication Ethics: Between Cosmopol-
itanism and Provinciality. Edited by Kathleen Glenister Roberts and Ronald C. Arnett. New
York: Peter Lang, 2008.
———. “The Ethical Importance of Being Human: God and Humanism in Levinas’s Philoso-
phy.” Philosophy Today 50 (2006): 428–36.
———. The Ethics and Politics of Speech: Communication and Rhetoric in the Twentieth
Century. Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press, 2009.
———. “Turning Kant against the Priority of Autonomy: Communication Ethics and the Duty
to Community.” Philosophy and Rhetoric 35 (2002): 1–21.
Heidegger, Martin. “Letter on ‘Humanism’ (1946).” Translated by Frank A. Capuzzi. In Path-
marks, 239–76. Edited by William McNeill. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
Hyde, Michael J. The Call of Conscience: Heidegger and Levinas, Rhetoric and the Euthanasia
Debate. Columbia: University of South Carolina Press, 2001.
Johnstone, Christopher Lyle. “Ethics, Wisdom, and the Mission of Contemporary Rhetoric:
The Realization of Human Being.” Central States Speech Journal 38 (1981): 177–88.
Johnstone, Henry W. “Toward an Ethics of Rhetoric.” Communication 6 (1981): 305–14.
Kant, Immanuel. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics. Edited by Paul Carus. Chicago: The
Open Court Publishing Company, 1912.
Lacoue-Labarthe, Phillipe and Jean Luc Nancy. Retreating the Political. New York: Routledge,
1997.
Before the One and the Other 73
Lisbeth Lipari
language habits may lead us to think more about ethics than with ethics. In
particular, I investigate how the spatial metaphors we use to talk about time
and dialogue may, inadvertently, curtail our ethical horizons.
If, as Levinas writes, “the relationship with alterity is neither spatial nor
conceptual,” then what could it be? 4 In what follows, I tentatively respond to
Levinas with an idea about the relationship with alterity being temporal and
embodied rather than spatial and conceptual. But this temporality must be
understood as a nonlinear phenomenon that is accomplished in relation to
and with the other. That is, unlike binary conceptual models of time, such as
the pairings of chronos/kairos, diachrony/synchrony, objective/subjective,
and quantitative/qualitative time, here we will address time not as “the
achievement of an isolated and lone subject, but . . . [as] the very relationship
of the subject with the other.” 5 Such a relational and generative way of
thinking may thereby enable us to relinquish linear, spatial, and mechanical
models of communicative interaction in favor of nonlinear, musical, and
embodied models wherein temporality and communication ethics are en-
acted, and perhaps even accomplished, by speakers and listeners in concert.
TIME
or imagine a future that is yet to exist. Was time always understood in largely
spatial terms?
In the Euro-American tradition, the conflation of time and space may be
traced back to the ancient Greeks’ inquiry into the relationship between time,
motion, and change. Time became important for the Eleatics when the ques-
tion of whether, how, and why things change led to an argument between
Parminedes and Heraclitus about being versus becoming—was the universe
always in flux, in a state of ever-changing becoming in time, or is the uni-
verse and everything in it a vast, unchanging, and timeless still-point? Ever
since Aristotle, Western thinking about time has been rendered spatially,
conceived as a succession of nows that flow unidirectionally from past to
present to future. In the words of Aristotle, the present time is the indivisible
“extremity of the past (no part of the future being on this side of it) and also
of the future (no part of the past being on the other side of it).” 6 The now
stands still like a stone in the river of time. For Aristotle, time was “merely
the way we ‘measure motion,’ the way we ‘measure the difference between
before and after,’ that is, reduce our descriptions of motions to statements of
the sequence of change.” 7 And with the invention of calendars and sundials
that measured time by movements in space, the spatial model of time was
complete.
During the Enlightenment, however, things got a bit more complicated,
and for Kant, as perhaps for Descartes, the question of time was more com-
plex. For Kant, time and space were not simply concepts that describe ob-
jects—such as the quantity or quality of flowers in the garden. Rather, the
concepts of time and space were the a priori formal conditions of all phe-
nomena that could not be derived from external experience. Time, for exam-
ple, could not be perceived as passing or calculated as a measurement were it
not for the already existing conception of time in consciousness. Similarly,
space must exist prior to the named objects that exist within it. Because both
time and space were presupposed in the core pure concepts, Kant argued that
time and space were super pure concepts upon which everything else de-
pended. He wrote, “In order that certain sensations should be related to
something outside me (i.e., to something in another place of space from that
which I find myself) . . . the representation of space must already be there.” 8
Similarly, Kant argued that “time is not an empirical concept that is some-
how drawn from an experience. For simultaneity or succession would not
themselves come into our perception if the representation of time were not
given a priori.” 9 As an example, Kant describes how the concept of causality
could not exist without a prior idea of time in the form of a beforehand and
an afterward. According to Charles Sherover, Kant was perhaps influenced
by previous conceptions of time—such as Newton’s differentiation between
an absolute and a relative time and Descartes’s 57th principle, which distin-
guished time and duration. Kant suggested a third form of time that was
78 Lisbeth Lipari
the prevailing linear, spatialized notion of time: linguistic diachrony was the
horizontal x axis of time that moves from left to right, and linguistic synchro-
ny was the vertical y axis of structural elements that cohabitate a given
moment of time. Today, we live in Saussure’s rather than Bergson’s world,
and the temporality of dialogue is implicitly, if not explicitly, thought of in
diachronous spatial terms wherein utterances “follow one another” in a linear
stream of discourse. But was the temporality of dialogue always thus?
KAIROS
Two concepts from the ancient Greek language give us insight into the rela-
tion of ethics and temporality: the words kairos—most superficially under-
stood as right timing or the opportune moment—and akroasis—translated as
listening and invoking the idea of secret, esoteric teachings. Although both
terms kairos and akroasis were important to the Pythagoreans and other pre-
Socratics, and both are related to ideas of harmony and balance, only the
term kairos remains a part of the Western rhetorical apparatus. But as we will
explore below, thinking about kairos as a relation with alterity that accom-
plishes temporality enables us to consider kairos as an ethical response that
arises from akroasis—from a listening attunement that transcends binary
oppositions and the presumed spatial linear progressions of past, present, and
future. From this perspective, kairos is a nonlinear way of synchronous lis-
tening and speaking, a dialogic midwifery that, as an ethics, can give birth to
speech. 14 Thus, in the ethical encounter, listening does not merely follow
speech; it also draws speech forth. The ethical relation is thus a temporal,
embodied, and intersubjective process, an achievement accomplished by
weaving the weft of kairos into the warp of akroasis.
The pre-Socratic concept of kairos seems to have originated in the con-
text of two ancient art forms: archery and weaving. 15 The former use of
kairos pertained to a narrow passage for or wound from an arrow, and the
latter pertained to the passage of threads (the weft) through strands (or warp)
of fiber in the making of cloth. The term is also found in the works of ancient
Greek poets Homer, Pindar, and Hesiod and is defined variously as “‘sym-
metry,’ ‘propriety,’ ‘occasion,’ ‘due measure,’ ‘fitness,’ ‘tact,’ ‘decorum,’
‘convenience,’ ‘proportion,’ ‘fruit,’ ‘profit,’ and ‘wise moderation.’” 16 Later,
the term kairos made its way into the heart of rhetorical theory, first through
Isocrates’s and later Aristotle’s school of rhetoric. 17
As an ethics, calling kairos an “opportune moment” seems to cultivate a
flavor of opportunism that would violate an ethics of alterity that demands
we renounce our claims and prerogatives. Similarly, some scholars relate
kairos to ethics via the idea of prepon, or propriety and decorum, in a way
that may sound to modern ears more calculating than virtuous. Isocrates, for
80 Lisbeth Lipari
example, called upon speakers to “always monitor your speech and actions
so that you make the fewest mistakes possible. It is best to make use of
perfect opportunities, but since these are hard to identify, elect to fall short
rather than overstep the mark.” 18 Isocrates claimed kairos was difficult to
learn because the goodness of speech stems from its having “a share in what
is opportune [kairos], appropriateness of style, and originality.” 19 The em-
phasis on propriety and right timing has led some scholars to conclude that
kairos is a kind of situational, pragmatic, or relativist ethics. 20 Laurent Per-
not, for example, describes kairos as a Greek idea of situational ethics that
varies depending on context. 21 This is perhaps what leads Pernot to lament a
lack of “truth or justice defined once and for all” for rhetoric in the classical
age. 22 In the Roman era, kairos, like so many other rhetorical concepts, took
on an ethically questionable form of strategic instrumentalism as a techne, or
skill to be honed. 23
Toward the late-mid-twentieth century, however, American scholars of
rhetoric came to develop a more nuanced conception of kairos as “a concept
far richer and complex than saying the right thing at the right time.” 24 To
Michael Carter, for example, ethics was crucial to the kairos of the pre-
Socratics who sought to produce ethical judgments in “a relativistic uni-
verse . . . Gorgias and the other sophists were not the skeptics and opportu-
nists that the Platonic tradition has painted them.” 25 Similarly, Sheri Helsley
describes “a generative kairos” that “exhibits rich ethical implications in
addition to its epistemological and rhetorical facets.” 26 To Michael Harker,
“kairos is a term that reminds us of the ethical responsibility that accompa-
nies the project of evaluating context.” 27 Because of the improvisational and
generative dimensions of kairos, some scholars link it to Lloyd Bitzer’s
concept of exigence in the rhetorical situation. 28 Focusing here on Bitzer’s
beautiful conception of discourse as being called forth by exigence, we will
leave aside the question of whether an ethics of urgency can indeed be an
ethics. 29
As had Isocrates done with kairos, Bitzer identifies exigency as drawing a
“fitting response” from the rhetor, a speaking that is timely, appropriate,
proper, and in keeping with the circumstances. To Bitzer, exigency is “an
imperfection marked by urgency” that calls forth speech. 30 Exigence works
in combination with audience and other constraints such as beliefs, facts,
traditions, interests, motives, and so on, to call forth what Bitzer calls a
“fitting response.” 31 Bitzer gives us Lincoln’s Gettysburg Address and asks
us to imagine the speech without the exigence of the situation (i.e., blood-
stained ground from a civil war that caused terrible losses on both sides).
Such a “groundless” speech would, in Bitzer’s mind, “lose its profound rhe-
torical value.” 32 It is not clear, however, whether there might not be numer-
ous fitting responses to any given exigence, and whether each would yield a
comparably ethical response. Indeed, we might ponder the question of
Ethics, Kairos, and Akroasis 81
AKROASIS
Like kairos, the term akroasis (from the Greek for hearing, Ακρόασις) also
received attention by the Pythagoreans. Unlike kairos, however, it received
far less attention from either classical or modern rhetoricians. A stray trace of
its existence is preserved, however, in several versions of the Progymnasma-
ta, one of the early preparatory manuals of classical rhetoric. 39 According to
Pernot, “the rhetorical exercises are an ancient practice” that can be traced to
the Sophists. 40 One extant version of the Progymnasmata dates from the first
or second century CE and is attributed to Ailios Theon. In addition to exer-
cises in such familiar forms as narrative, topos, encomium, and so forth,
there are an additional five supplementary exercises that include reading,
82 Lisbeth Lipari
Mortals hear the thunder of the heavens, the rustling of woods, the gurgling of
fountains, the ringing of plucked strings, the rumbling of motors, the noises of
the city—only and only so far as they always already in some way belong to
them and yet do not belong to them. . . . So long as we only listen to the sound
of a word, as the expression of a speaker, we are not yet even listening at
all. . . . We have heard when we belong to the matter addressed. 48
One of the few scholars to follow Heidegger into the elusive mysteries of
listening is the Italian philosopher Fiumara, who calls listening “the other
84 Lisbeth Lipari
sciousness wherein the initial stages of speech are an integrated gestalt with-
out temporal sequence or differentiated parts. Luria’s model does not depict
speech as a simple conversion of thoughts into words. Rather, it describes
how complex, nonlinguistic conceptual intuitions are gradually transformed
into full-blown, grammatically correct, speech. As he describes it, “There is
every reason to agree with Vygotsky that thought is completed, rather than
embodied in speech and that the transition from thought into speech involves
several stages.” 73 Thus, rather than merely reflecting preexisting thoughts,
the Soviet psychologists saw language as a process that transforms a gestalt
of nonlinear consciousness (not unlike Bergson’s dureé) into the linear, se-
quenced expressions of speech. Vygotsky gives a wonderful example of the
instantaneous flash-like intuition of meaning that arises conterminous with
speaking:
Thought, unlike speech, does not consist of separate units. When I wish to
communicate the thought that today I saw a barefoot boy in a blue shirt
running down the street, I do not see every item separately: the boy, the shirt,
its blue color, his running, the absence of shoes. I conceive of all this in one
thought, but I put it into separate words. 74
of both time and language as largely linear and spatial phenomena continues
to limit and condition us to thinking about (rather than with) ethics. What
follows is an illustration of kairos as an ethical achievement enacted by the
openness and attunement of akroasis.
EXEMPLUM
IMPLICATIONS
NOTES
Portions of this chapter have been excerpted from chapters six and eight of Lisbeth Lipari,
Listening, Thinking, Being: Toward an Ethics of Attunement (University Park, PA: Penn State
University Press, 2014).
1. Ronald C. Arnett, Communication Ethics in Dark Times: Hannah Arendt’s Rhetoric of
Warning and Hope (Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press, 2013); Michael J.
Hyde, Openings: Acknowledging Essential Moments in Human Communication (Waco, TX:
Baylor University Press, 2012); George Cheney, Daniel J. Lair, Dean Ritz, and Brenden E.
Kendall, Just a Job?: Communication, Ethics, and Professional Life (Oxford: Oxford Univer-
sity Press, 2009).
2. Emmanuel Levinas, Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority, trans. Alphonso
Lingis (Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press, 1969), 216.
90 Lisbeth Lipari
3. George Lakoff and Mark Johnson, Metaphors We Live By, 2nd ed. (Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 2003); Cheney, Just a Job.
4. Levinas, Time and the Other, 84.
5. Ibid., 39.
6. Aristotle, Physics, in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon, 214–394 (New
York: Modern Library, 2001), 321.
7. Charles M. Sherover, Are We In Time? And Other Essays on Time and Temporality, ed.
Gregory R. Johnson (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 2003), 8–9.
8. Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood (Edin-
burgh: Cambridge University Press, 1998), version B, sec. 38, p. 157
9. Ibid., B, 46, 162.
10. Sherover, Are We In Time?, 50.
11. Henri Bergson, Time and Free Will: An Essay on the Immediate Data of Consciousness.
Translated by R. L. Pogson. Mineola, NY: Dover, 2001, 50.
12. Ibid., 100.
13. Ferdinand Saussure, Course in General Linguistics, ed. Charles Bally and Albert Seche-
haye, trans. Wade Baskin (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1959), 232, 18.
14. Nelle Morton, The Journey Is Home (Boston: Beacon Press, 1985); G. C. Fiumara, The
Other Side of Language: A Philosophy of Listening (New York: Routledge, 1990); Lisbeth
Lipari, “The Vocation of Listening: The Other Side of Dialogue,” in After You, ed. Axel
Liégeois, Jozef Corveleyn, and Marina Riemslagh, 15–36, Bibliotheca Ephemeridum Theolog-
icarum Lovaniensium CCLVIII (Leuven: Uitgeverij Peeters, 2013).
15. Eric Charles White, Kaironomia: On the Will to Invent (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University
Press, 1987); Debra Hawhee, Bodily Arts: Rhetoric and Athletics in Ancient Greece (Austin:
University of Texas, 2004).
16. Phillip Sipiora, “Introduction: The Ancient Concept of Kairos,” in Rhetoric and Kairos:
Essays in History, Theory and Praxis, ed. Phillip Sipiora and James S. Baumlin, 1–22 (Albany,
NY: State University of New York Press, 2002), 1.
17. James L. Kinneavy, “Kairos: A Neglected Concept in Classical Rhetoric,” in Rhetoric
and Praxis, ed. John D. Moss, 79–105 (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America,
1986), 80.
18. David Mirhady and Yun Lee Too, trans. Isocrates I (Austin: University of Texas, 2000),
164.
19. Ibid., 64.
20. White, Kaironomia; Michael Carter, “Stasis and Kairos: Principals of Social Construc-
tion in Classical Rhetoric,” Rhetoric Review 7, no. 1 (1988): 97–112; Sipiora, “Introduction.”
21. Laurent Pernot, Rhetoric in Antiquity, trans. W. E. Higgins (Washington, DC: Catholic
University of America, 2005), 13.
22. Ibid.
23. Dale L. Sullivan, “Kairos and the Rhetoric of Belief,” Quarterly Journal of Speech 78
(1992): 317–32.
24. Sheri L. Helsley, “Kairos,” in The Encyclopedia of Rhetoric and Composition from
Ancient Times to the Information Age, ed. Theresa Enos (New York: Garland, 1996), 371.
25. Carter, “Stasis and Kairos,” 105.
26. Helsley, “Kairos,” 371.
27. Michael Harker, “The Ethics of Argument: Rereading Kairos and Making Sense in a
Timely Fashion,” College Composition and Communication 59, no. 1 (2007): 94.
28. Lloyd F. Bitzer, “The Rhetorical Situation” Philosophy and Rhetoric 1, no.1 (1968): 2.
29. As Žižek notes, a sense of urgency often “necessitates a suspension of ordinary ethical
concerns.” Slavoj Žižek, “Jack Bauer and the Ethics of Urgency,” In These Times, January 27,
2006, inthesetimes.org/article/2481/jack_bauer_and_the_ethics_of_urgency.
30. Bitzer, “Rhetorical Situation,” 6.
31. Ibid.
32. Ibid., 10.
33. Abraham Lincoln, “The Gettysburg Address,” Abraham Lincoln Online, accessed July
23, 2013, www.abrahamlincolnonline.org/lincoln/speeches/gettysburg.htm.
Ethics, Kairos, and Akroasis 91
34. Ibid.
35. John Poulakos, “Toward a Sophistic Definition of Rhetoric,” Philosophy and Rhetoric
16, no. 1 (1983): 40–41.
36. Sipiora, “Introduction,” 17n1.
37. James Kinneavy and Catherine R. Eskin, “Kairos in Aristotle’s Rhetoric,” Written Com-
munication 17, no. 3 (2000): 432–44.
38. Harker, “The Ethics of Argument.”
39. Malcolm Heath, “Theon and the History of the Progymnasmata,” Greek, Roman, and
Byzantine Studies 43, no. 3 (2002): 129–60.
40. Pernot, Rhetoric in Antiquity, 146.
41. Ibid., 138.
42. C. Jan Swearingen, “Song to Speech: The Origins of Early Epitaphia in Ancient Near
Eastern Women’s Lamentations,” in Rhetoric Before and Beyond the Greeks, ed. Carol S.
Lipson and Roberta A. Binkley, 213–25 (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press,
2004).
43. Fiumara, The Other Side of Language.
44. Martin Heidegger, Early Greek Thinking, trans. David Farrell Krell and Frank Capuzzi
(New York: Harper & Row, 1984).
45. Jonathan Barnes, ed., Early Greek Philosophy (New York: Penguin Classics, 1987), 50.
46. Heidegger, Early Greek, 67.
47. Ibid., 65.
48. Ibid., 65–66.
49. Ibid., 73.
50. Sullivan, “Kairos and the Rhetoric of Belief.”
51. Hawhee, Bodily Arts, 71.
52. Carolyn Eriksen Hill, “Changing Times in Composition Classes: Kairos, Resonance,
and the Pythagorean Connection,” in Rhetoric and Kairos: Essays in History, Theory and
Praxis, ed. Phillip Sipiora and James S. Baumlin, 211–25. (Albany, NY: State University of
New York Press, 2002), 216.
53. Fiumara, The Other Side of Language.
54. Ibid., 30.
55. Ibid., 19.
56. Ibid., 67
57. Ibid., 90.
58. Ibid., 122.
59. Ibid., 158.
60. Morton, The Journey Is Home, 128.
61. Levinas, Totality and Infinity, 214.
62. Morton, The Journey Is Home, 206.
63. Martin Buber, Between Man and Man (New York: Macmillan, 1975), 39.
64. Morton, The Journey is Home, 209.
65. Fiumara, The Other Side of Language, 144.
66. Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson (Mal-
den, MA: Blackwell Publishers, 1962), 197; Martin Heidegger, The Concept of Time, trans.
Ingo Farin and Skinner (New York: Continuum, 2011), 47.
67. Levinas, Time and the Other, 81.
68. Ibid., 33.
69. Lisbeth Lipari, “Rhetoric’s Other,” Philosophy and Rhetoric 45, no. 3 (2012): 242.
70. Edward Holmes, The Life of Mozart, Including His Correspondence (New York: Harp-
ers, 1845), 267–68.
71. Bergson, Time and Free Will, 59.
72. Mikhail Bakhtin, Problems of Dostoevsky’s Poetics, trans. R.W. Rotsel (Ann Arbor, MI:
Ardis, 1973); V. N. Voloshinov, “The Word and Its Social Function,” in Bakhtin School
Papers, ed. Ann Shukman, trans. Joe Andrew, 139–52 (Oxford: RPT, 1983).
73. Alexander R. Luria, Language and Cognition, ed. James V. Wertsch (New York: John
Wiley & Sons, 1981), 151.
92 Lisbeth Lipari
74. Lev Vygotsky, Thought and Language, trans. Alex Kozulin (Cambridge, MA: Massa-
chusetts Institute of Technology, 1986), 251.
75. William Faulkner, Requiem for a Nun (New York: Vintage Books, 1975), 73.
76. Roy Schafer, “Narration in the Psychoanalytic Dialogue,” in On Narrative, ed. W. J. T.
Mitchell, 25–50 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980), 48.
77. Wallace Martin, Recent Theories of Narrative (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press,
1986), 127.
78. Fiumara, The Other Side of Language, 134.
79. Heidegger, The Concept of Time, 49.
80. Bitzer, “Rhetorical Situation,” 8.
81. Carter, “Stasis and Kairos”; Hawhee, Bodily Arts; Helsley, “Kairos,” 371.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Aristotle. Physics. In The Basic Works of Aristotle, edited by Richard McKeon, 214–394. New
York: Modern Library, 2001.
Arnett, Ronald C. Communication Ethics in Dark Times: Hannah Arendt’s Rhetoric of Warn-
ing and Hope. Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press, 2013.
Bakhtin, Mikhail. Problems of Dostoevsky’s Poetics. Translated by R.W. Rotsel. Ann Arbor,
MI: Ardis, 1973.
Barnes, Jonathan, ed. Early Greek Philosophy. New York: Penguin Classics, 1987.
Bergson, Henri. Time and Free Will: An Essay on the Immediate Data of Consciousness.
Translated by R. L. Pogson. Mineola, NY: Dover, 2001.
Bitzer, Lloyd F. “The Rhetorical Situation.” Philosophy and Rhetoric 1, no. 1 (1968): 1–14.
Buber, Martin. Between Man and Man. New York: Macmillan, 1975.
Carter, Michael. “Stasis and Kairos: Principals of Social Construction in Classical Rhetoric.”
Rhetoric Review 7, no. 1 (1988): 97–112.
Cheney, George, Daniel J. Lair, Dean Ritz, and Brenden E. Kendall. Just a Job?: Communica-
tion, Ethics, and Professional Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009.
Eliot, T. S. “Burnt Norton.” In The Four Quartets, 13–20. New York: Harcourt Brace, 1943.
Faulkner, William. Requiem for a Nun. New York: Vintage Books, 1975.
Fiumara, Gemma Corrida. The Other Side of Language: A Philosophy of Listening. New York:
Routledge, 1990.
Harker, Michael. “The Ethics of Argument: Rereading Kairos and Making Sense in a Timely
Fashion.” College Composition and Communication 59, no. 1 (2007): 77–97.
Hawhee, Debra. Bodily Arts: Rhetoric and Athletics in Ancient Greece. Austin: University of
Texas, 2004.
Heath, Malcolm. “Theon and the History of the Progymnasmata.” Greek, Roman, and Byzan-
tine Studies 43, no. 3 (2002): 129–60.
Heidegger, Martin. Being and Time. Translated by John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson.
Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishers, 1962.
———. Early Greek Thinking. Translated by David Farrell Krell and Frank Capuzzi. New
York: Harper & Row, 1984.
———. The Concept of Time. Translated by Ingo Farin, with Alex Skinner. New York: Contin-
uum, 2011.
Helsley, Sheri L. “Kairos.” In The Encyclopedia of Rhetoric and Composition from Ancient
Times to the Information Age, edited by Theresa Enos, 371. New York: Garland, 1996.
Hill, Carolyn Eriksen. “Changing Times in Composition Classes: Kairos, Resonance, and the
Pythagorean Connection.” In Rhetoric and Kairos: Essays in History, Theory and Praxis,
edited by Phillip Sipiora and James S. Baumlin, 211–25. Albany, NY: State University of
New York Press, 2002.
Holmes, Edward. The Life of Mozart, Including His Correspondence. New York: Harpers,
1845.
Hyde, Michael J. Openings: Acknowledging Essential Moments in Human Communication.
Waco, TX: Baylor University Press, 2012.
Ethics, Kairos, and Akroasis 93
Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Pure Reason. Translated by Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood.
Edinburgh: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
Kinneavy, James L. “Kairos: A Neglected Concept in Classical Rhetoric.” In Rhetoric and
Praxis, edited by John D. Moss, 79–105. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America,
1986.
Kinneavy, James, and Catherine R. Eskin. “Kairos in Aristotle’s Rhetoric.” Written Communi-
cation 17, no. 3 (2000): 432–44.
Lakoff, George, and Mark Johnson. Metaphors We Live By. 2nd ed. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 2003.
Levinas, Emmanuel. Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority. Translated by Alphonso
Lingis. Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press, 1969.
———. Time and the Other. Duquesne University Press, 1987.
Lipari, Lisbeth. “Rhetoric’s Other.” Philosophy and Rhetoric 45, no. 3 (2012): 227–45.
———. “The Vocation of Listening: The Other Side of Dialogue.” In After You, edited by Axel
Liégeois, Jozef Corveleyn, and Marina Riemslagh, 15–36. CCLVIII. Leuven: Uitgeverij
Peeters, 2013.
Luria, Alexander, R. Language and Cognition. Edited by James V. Wertsch. New York: John
Wiley & Sons, 1981.
Martin, Wallace. Recent Theories of Narrative. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1986.
Mirhady, David, and Yun Lee Too, trans. Isocrates I. Austin: University of Texas, 2000.
Morton, Nelle. The Journey Is Home. Boston: Beacon Press, 1985.
Pernot, Laurent. Rhetoric in Antiquity. Translated by W. E. Higgins. Washington, DC: Catholic
University of America, 2005.
Poulakos, John. “Toward a Sophistic Definition of Rhetoric.” Philosophy and Rhetoric 16, no.
1 (1983): 35–48.
Saussure, Ferdinand. Course in General Linguistics. Edited by Charles Bally and Albert Seche-
haye. Translated by Wade Baskin. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1959.
Schafer, Roy. “Narration in the Psychoanalytic Dialogue.” In On Narrative, edited by W. J. T.
Mitchell, 25–50. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980.
Sherover, Charles M. Are We In Time? And Other Essays on Time and Temporality. Edited by
Gregory R. Johnson. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 2003.
Sipiora, Phillip. “Introduction: The Ancient Concept of Kairos.” In Rhetoric and Kairos: Es-
says in History, Theory and Praxis, edited by Phillip Sipiora and James S. Baumlin, 1–22.
Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 2002.
Sullivan, Dale L. “Kairos and the Rhetoric of Belief.” Quarterly Journal of Speech 78 (1992):
317–32.
Swearingen, C. Jan. “Song to Speech: The Origins of Early Epitaphia in Ancient Near Eastern
Women’s Lamentations.” In Rhetoric Before and Beyond the Greeks, edited by Carol S.
Lipson and Roberta A. Binkley, 213–225. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press,
2004.
Voloshinov, V. N. “The Word and Its Social Function.” In Bakhtin School Papers, edited by
Ann Shukman, translated by Joe Andrew, 139–52. Oxford: RPT, 1983.
Vygotsky, Lev. Thought and Language. Translated by Alex Kozulin. Cambridge, MA: Massa-
chusetts Institute of Technology, 1986.
White, Eric Charles. Kaironomia: On the Will to Invent. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press,
1987.
Žižek, Slavoj. “Jack Bauer and the Ethics of Urgency.” In These Times, January 27, 2006.
II
scenarios at the beginning of this essay, imagine how they might have un-
folded if group members and their colleagues had applied this approach. The
college committee might not only have recognized the viability of the
African American candidate during their discussion but, if they had been
proactive, might also have entered the process with clear diversity-affirming
criteria that would have informed their deliberation from the start.
Similarly, a diversity ethic might have directed the college committee on
academic dishonesty to engage in dialogue with the foreign students under
review to understand their rationale for their behaviors. Even better, a diver-
sity ethic might have guided the committee and their colleagues to analyze
processes that professors use to educate students about plagiarism to ensure
that faculty members understand cultural differences and that they speak to
those differences explicitly in their policies, provide clear examples, ac-
knowledge the potential for cultural differences, and refer students to on-
campus resources. The committee also could develop and implement re-
courses that rehabilitate rather than punish students. The committee’s work
functions as an exemplar of the academy’s need to engage in decision-mak-
ing processes that recognize the value of diversity ethics. The academy must
take proactive measures to optimize the creative potential resulting from the
interplay of attentiveness to ethics and diversity.
NOTES
1. I will not name the country because I do not want to stigmatize it.
2. Richard L. Henderson, Absael Antela, and Norman St. Clair, “Ethics and Values in the
Context of Teaching Excellence in the Changing World of Education,” Journal of College
Teaching and Learning 7, no. 3 (2010).
3. Antonette Aragon and Edward J. Brantmeier, “Diversity-Affirming Ethics and Critical
Epistemology: Institutional Decision Making in Community Colleges,” New Directions for
Community Colleges 148 (2012): 40.
4. National Communication Association, “NCA Credo for Ethical Communication,” www.
natcom.org/uploadedFiles/About_NCA/Leadership_and_Governance/Public_Policy_Platform/
PDF-PolicyPlatform-NCA_Credo_for_Ethical_Communication.pdf.
5. Josina Makau and Ronald Arnett, Communication Ethics in an Age of Diversity (Illinois:
University of Illinois, 1997), 336.
6. Chronicle of Higher Education, College 2020: Students (Washington, DC: Chronicle of
Higher Education, 2009).
7. Pond, Allison, Gregory Smith, and Scott Clement, “Religion Among the Millennials,”
Pew Forum on Religion & Public Life, February 17, 2010, www.pewforum.org/Age/Religion-
Among-the-Millennials.aspx.
8. Aragon and Brantmeier, “Diversity-Affirming Ethics,” 40.
9. Ibid.
10. Ibid.
11. Ibid., 41.
12. Ibid., 49.
13. National Communication Association, “Credo.”
14. Ibid.
15. Aragon and Brantmeier, “Diversity-Affirming Ethics.”
102 Brenda J. Allen
16. Uma Jayakumar et al., “Racial Privilege in the Professoriate: An Exploration of Campus
Climate, Retention, and Satisfaction,” Journal of Higher Education 80, no. 5 (2009).
17. Richard Anderson, Kenneth N. Cissna, and Ronald C. Arnett, The Reach of Dialogue:
Confirmation, Voice, and Community (Cresskill, NJ: Hampton Press, 1994), 2.
18. Marvin T. Brown, “Concepts and Experience of the ‘Valuing Diversity and Ethics
Workshops’ at Levi Strauss and Company,” in Ethics in International Management, edited by
Brij Nino Kumar and Horst Steinmann, 243–58 (New York: de Gruyter, 1998), www.
workingethics.com/valuesanddiversity.html.
19. Aragon and Brantmeier, “Diversity-Affirming Ethics,” 40.
20. For example, see Exploring Communication Ethics: Interviews with Influential Scholars
in the Field, ed. Pat Arneson (New York: Peter Lang, 2007); Makau and Arnett, Communica-
tion Ethics.
21. Craig E. Johnson, Ethics in the Workplace: Tools and Tactics for Organizational Trans-
formation (Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications, 2007).
22. Communication, Diversity, and Ethics in Higher Education, “A Framework for Think-
ing Ethically,” Santa Clara University. Revised May 2009. www.scu.edu/ethics/practicing/
decision/framework.html.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Anderson, Richard, Kenneth N. Cissna, and Ronald C. Arnett. The Reach of Dialogue: Confir-
mation, Voice, and Community. Cresskill, NJ: Hampton Press, 1994.
Aragon, Antonette, and Edward J. Brantmeier. “Diversity-Affirming Ethics and Critical Episte-
mology: Institutional Decision Making in Community Colleges.” New Directions for Com-
munity Colleges 148 (2009): 39–51.
Arneson, Pat, ed. Exploring Communication Ethics: Interviews with Influential Scholars in the
Field. New York: Peter Lang, 2007.
Arnett, Ronald C. “Dialogic Civility as Pragmatic Ethical Praxis: An Interpersonal Metaphor
for the Public Domain.” Communication Theory 11, no. 3 (2001): 315–38.
Brown, Marvin T. “Concepts and Experience of the ‘Valuing Diversity and Ethics Workshops’
at Levi Strauss and Company.” In Ethics in International Management, edited by Brij Nino
Kumar and Horst Steinmann, 243–58. New York: de Gruyter, 1998. www.workingethics.
com/valuesanddiversity.html.
Chronicle of Higher Education. College 2020: Students. Washington, DC: Chronicle of Higher
Education, 2009.
Henderson, Richard L., Absael Antelo, and Norman St. Clair. “Ethics and Values in the Con-
text of Teaching Excellence in the Changing World of Education.” Journal of College-
Teaching & Learning 7, no. 3 (2010): 5–12.
Jayakumar, Uma M., Tyrone C. Howard, Walter R. Allen, and June C. Han. “Racial Privilege
in the Professoriate: An Exploration of Campus Climate, Retention, and Satisfaction.” Jour-
nal of Higher Education 80, no. 5 (2009): 538–63.
Johnson, Craig E. Ethics in the Workplace: Tools and Tactics for Organizational Transforma-
tion. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications, 2007.
Makau, Josina M., and Ronald C. Arnett. Communication Ethics in an Age of Diversity.
Illinois: University of Illinois, 1997.
Markkula Center for Applied Ethics. “A Framework for Thinking Ethically.” Santa Clara
University. Revised May 2009. www.scu.edu/ethics/practicing/decision/framework.html.
National Communication Association. “NCA Credo for Ethical Communication.” Approved by
the NCA Legislative Council, November 1999. www.natcom.org/uploadedFiles/About_
NCA/Leadership_and_Governance/Public_Policy_Platform/PDF-PolicyPlatform-NCA_
Credo_for_Ethical_Communication.pdf.
Pond, Allison, Gregory Smith, and Scott Clement. “Religion Among the Millennials.” Pew
Forum on Religion & Public Life. February 17, 2010. www.pewforum.org/Age/Religion-
Among-the-Millennials.aspx.
Chapter Six
Tymieniecka’s Benevolent
Sentiment as Ground for
Communication Ethics
Juliette Hampton Morgan’s
Advocacy for Racial Justice
Pat Arneson
Many authors approach the study of moral discourse from a purely theoreti-
cal perspective, identifying intellectual theories that are then to be applied in
behavioral practice by human actors. Viewing communication ethics as an
abstract theory to be applied hides the myriad demands within any particular
situation. Dating back to antiquity, Aristotle realized that a theoretically dis-
tanciated view of virtue was misguided. In the ancient tradition, ethike prag-
matia was essentially a form of practical wisdom (phronesis), a manner of
being ethical rather than simply knowing the theories that one may choose to
engage or not engage. 1 In a similar manner, Joseph Kockelmans asserts that
the study of ethics is “an attempt to come to a critical understanding of our
basic moral experiences from the perspective of our most primordial human
experience.” 2 One’s morality is communicated in one’s conjoined linguistic
and corporeal expressivity.
Anna-Teresa Tymieniecka proposed an ontopoietic cosmology, or a phe-
nomenology of life, in her works, an approach that is necessarily interwoven
with the possibilities of human communication. Daniela Verducci explains
that Tymieniecka offered a phenomenology united with a hermeneutics of
development. She clarifies that Tymieniecka presented a “pre-ontological
position of being, that in which being generates itself and regenerates; from
this point of view, she untangled the logos, which presides over the evolution
103
104 Pat Arneson
of the life of being, indicating it, with a term of her own coinage, as ‘onto-
poiesis,’ that is ‘production/creation of being.’” 3 Within phenomenology,
apprehending “new spheres of givenness is a necessary step in the progres-
sion of intuitive attunement.” 4 This avoids an emphasis on inner subjectivity
as separate from societal and ethical realms. Tymieniecka posited an ethical
position that takes the vital impulse of human creativity, rather than cogni-
tion or belief, to be the organizing principle for human interaction with the
lifeworld. 5 In so doing, she offered ground for understanding human commu-
nication ethics.
This chapter begins with a brief overview of Tymieniecka’s scholarship,
identifying the genesis of the moral sense within her work. Her ethical posi-
tion is grounded in the creativity of the benevolent sentiment, which drives
the moral sense. Reading her work through the lens of human communica-
tion reveals that a person’s experience is compelled by aesthetic, moral, and
intellectual meaning-bestowing faculties. The moral sense promotes commu-
nal life, in which moral valuation and judgment emerge. The social sphere
provides a space in which to deliberate for the common good. Being true to
oneself requires reflection upon the constraints that compel or restrain one’s
moral behavior. Tymieniecka provides philosophical insight into a communi-
cation ethics that theoretically illuminates Juliette Hampton Morgan’s advo-
cacy for racial justice in Montgomery, Alabama, during the bus protest of
1955 through 1956. Hampton exhibited a moral sensibility driven by the
benevolent sentiment in her interactions with others.
1971 until her death. Extending the work of Edmund Husserl and Maurice
Merleau-Ponty, Tymieniecka reached beyond intentional consciousness and
the preconscious lived-body to discern how constitutive systems of meaning
emerge. She inscribed meaning within the entire expansion of life, not sim-
ply attributing meaning to the human realm. Tymieniecka examined the
sense-bestowing capacities of life in its evolutional construction, delving into
ontopoiesis (first makings).
Tymieniecka asserted that the inner workings of life are expressed in the
creative function that emerges from the vital sphere. The creative function in
the human condition is the hinge to logos. The fundamental creative function
has been covered over by a bias on cognition. Covering over the creative
function masks the genesis of meaning. Her approach recognizes the onto-
poietic generation of all life at various stations. The human station cannot be
separated from how humans are embedded in the givenness of life. Given-
ness cannot be limited to a cognitive process; givenness is the constructivity
of life that flows through the creative forge of humans.
In the 1990s, Tymieniecka intensified her scrutiny of the sciences and
articulated a complementarity between her articulation of ontopoiesis and the
scientific paradigm of self-organizing, dynamic systems. She combined the
language of ontopoiesis (phenomenological meanings) with the language of
open dynamic systems in her metaphysic. In the 2000s, she articulated her
phenomenology of life with particular attention to the spiritual sphere and
role of the sacred in her cosmology.
Tymieniecka explained life as the expansion of logos. In short, recursive-
ly the vital sphere (Imaginatio Creatrix) initiates logos, forcing the existen-
tial sphere, concurrently prompting the social sphere of the human condition.
The human station reveals meaning-bestowing functions: The creative-imag-
inative origin urges the aesthetic, moral, and intellective senses. At the peak
or human crown of life, life recedes through an individual quest for spiritual
(the sacred, enfolding back to include the moral) development, inspired by a
desire for transcendence. Drawing from her work, an embodied communica-
tion ethic emerges from the benevolent sentiment, which drives the moral
sense.
Meaning-Bestowing Faculties
While, as Martin Heidegger noted, the human being may be thrown into the
life-world without having a choice, Tymieniecka allowed that a person indi-
vidualizes oneself in one’s ever-unfolding faculties within circumambient
life-conditions. This occurs in four functions of the human station in her
logos of life: vital (creative/imaginative origin) and the meaning-bestowing
faculties of aesthetic, moral, and intellective 8 (which I read as comprising
multiple modes of awareness). Verducci explains, “The nature of meaning of
106 Pat Arneson
significance to be concerned with what we call the ‘good’ of the Other, our
own good, or the Good in general.” 27 Benevolence activates the moral sense
toward goodness.
The benevolent sentiment spontaneously associates with the interpretive
function of the aesthetic sense; benevolent subjects find the sentiment “en-
joyable.” 28 Some people may cognitively think that surrendering one’s own
interests to the interests of others would not bring fuller corporeal enjoyment.
However, Tymieniecka asserts that there is a counterbalancing experiential
factor that is essential to establishing the moral interpretation within human
interaction. What one loses in the “existential transactional circuit” is gained
in the moral enjoyment of benevolence, “which surpasses all other types of
joys by giving value to our own being as experienced by us and thereby
strengthening our existential force by self-confidence, self-reliability, and
ultimately self-worthiness.” 29 Communicators strengthen their existential
force in benevolence!
Benevolence can take either a constructive or a malefic orientation. The
moral enjoyment that accompanies the exercise of moral sense is identified
as either positive or negative enjoyment. Positive enjoyment is “benevolence
as oriented for the ‘good’ of the Other.” 30 In a morally benevolent sentiment,
the human is penetrated by “‘self-contentment,’ ‘self-satisfaction,’ [and]
‘self-respect.’ These moral sentiments generated by the exercise of the moral
sense are amplified by releasing the sentiments of ‘self-reliance,’ ‘security,’
and self-‘worthiness’ deposited in one’s own inaccessible and autonomous,
indestructible moral force.” 31 The positive orientation of the benevolent sen-
timent promotes constructiveness; the negativity of the malefic orientation
obstructs the constructive course of the Other.
Negative enjoyment is a “malefic deviation from the promptings of be-
nevolence, which turns against the life-interest of the Other.” 32 Evil is ac-
companied by negative enjoyment. “The malefic propensity in the sentiment
and its exercise produces also an aesthetic enjoyment, but of a negative
sort,” 33 resonating with Schadenfreude (pleasure derived from the misfor-
tunes of others). Tymieniecka recognized that “the moral subject, in benevo-
lent acting finds his own reward! In evil-doing, his own punishment.” 34 She
acknowledged recursive consequences in one’s actions (e.g., what goes
around comes around, a person reaps what he sows, etc.).
Communication ethics scholars often lament the loss of sensitivity to the
moral sense within people’s everyday interactions. Within the entire spec-
trum of the human condition, the moral sense is the most vulnerable. The
expansion or shrinking of the moral sense does not spontaneously emerge.
Tymieniecka asserted that this is a complex issue, driven by a question of
one’s “inward struggle to preserve and cultivate” moral enjoyment in the
midst of “all the other adverse inclinations and propulsions.” 35 The cultiva-
110 Pat Arneson
For ethics, you cannot talk about principles and norms of behavior unless you
find a measure against which these principles and rules should be distributed.
Whether it be justice, honesty, sincerity, or whatever, there will be the need to
measure its degree. The great question is the question of measure. This is what
we have completely lost amidst our marvelous technological progress . . . the
principles of measure can be in life itself through self-individualization in
existence. 38
Humans are able to inscribe change within the natural order through creativ-
ity. The self-in-the-world begins with self-awareness and extends into the
world by articulating one’s will, judgments, acts, and choices in the construc-
tion of one’s life-project. The basic moral experience is fundamentally relat-
ed to consciousness in corporeal performance; moral experience is only sec-
ondarily cognitive.
Deliberation. Tymieniecka punctuated (“knots” 45) the exercise of judg-
ment in communicative engagements within the human station of her phe-
nomenology of life. Communal life is promoted in the moral sense; commu-
nal networks rejuvenate a person’s identity. The benevolent sentiment spurs
deliberation, which provides justifying reasons to the moral sense. The jus-
tifying reasons within a conflict are balanced within “the axis of right/
wrong.” 46 On my reading, the sentient body is the moral axis.
Social consensus does not ground morality; neither does an individual’s
position of social power. Social morality is grounded in discerning valuation.
The interactions in which people generate rules about how to take others into
consideration through valuation ground social morality. A person exists as
“self-individualization-within-a-communal-network,” 47 the primary social
structure within Tymieniecka’s cosmology. Although individuals seek to
control social conditions, an interesting paradox emerges.
There is a stress in the social world upon autonomy and independence of
individuals. This is seen in the emphasis on freedom of choice, self-direction,
and respect for individual needs. People seek to have their rights recognized
and also require that the conditions for exercising those rights be available.
These rights “form the operative ‘nervous system’ of social life.” 48 An elab-
orate legal system (laws, regulations, procedures) protects these rights across
public and private spheres. Societal institutions including education, religion,
and politics have pledged to honor and perpetuate these rights as valid social
structures.
Paradoxically, this prerogative is undermined in actual practices when
societal institutions are perceived as limiting one’s choices. People within
institutions, “while pretending to implement these laws, are in fact intent on
ignoring, abusing, and violating them; that is, there is a widespread effort to
neglect the moral axis upon which the very essence of intersubjective soci-
ability is suspended.” 49 The average person is “caught in a dilemma between
dutiful obedience to the law and the voice of moral conscience denying its
validity.” 50 In this form of moral dilemma, the poietic qualities of possibility
are limited by extant social structures.
Although moral valuation occurs within the intersubjective context, moral
valuation is “operated by the innermost core of the individual’s conjoined
meaning-bestowing faculties.” 51 A person’s aesthetic, moral, and intellective
faculties are interwoven to introduce a “moral point of view” into one’s
interpretation of others’ actions and life-events. 52 Self-interest may hinder
112 Pat Arneson
of other beings.” 68 With surrender comes risk: One takes a risk each time she
enters into communication with another person.
The most immediate contact a person can have with a topic, situation, or
other person is surrender. Kurt Wolf explains that surrender implies total
involvement, including cognition, love, “identification, the importance of
everything that comes to the attention of a person in such a state, the suspen-
sion of received notions, and the risk of being hurt.” 69 Surrender is not
achievable by an effort of the will and can work in two ways—as “surrender
to morality” or “the morality of surrender.” 70 The morality of surrender
refers to a theory of the idea of surrender. Drawing from Tymieniecka, Wolff
advocates that a person be true to herself and surrender to morality as her
morality of surrender. 71 Tymieniecka requires that “To be true to ourselves
means we must seek the hidden reasons that prevented us from acting moral-
ly so that we can tighten the knots of our beingness.” 72 Virtue is the exercise
of this capacity. In virtue, the subliminal moral ideal is united with delibera-
tions of the will carried out in behavioral engagements within the social
complex.
Within Tymieniecka’s phenomenology of life, the moral sense endows
“the human intersubjective matrix of actions with moral meaningfulness.” 73
A person’s experience is compelled by one’s aesthetic, moral, and intellectu-
al meaning-bestowing faculties. The benevolent sentiment inspires moral
sense (meaning-bestowing) and drives people to contribute to the social
world. Interactants often communicate from different valuative standpoints,
requiring them to work together to draw from the benevolent sentiment to
discern a good. One may accept a moral code defined by society but not
enact the tenets of that prescribed morality in one’s everyday life. Humans
are free to make individual choices. This freedom strengthens and encour-
ages the autonomy of the individual. At the same time, life is lived out in
networks of connectivity guided by deliberation. “The intersubjective pro-
vides ballast for the self-individuating principles.” 74 Theoretical speculation
from a scientific distance insufficiently accounts for the richness of one’s
contingent experience and the genesis of moral sense, which is expressed in
one’s corporeal and linguistic expressivity. Morgan’s embodied communica-
tion ethic may be understood as emerging from Tymieniecka’s benevolent
sentiment.
And then I saw—on the bus I think—Jane Addams’ classic question, “Who if
not you? When if not now?” So I went at it. 75
—Juliette Hampton Morgan
114 Pat Arneson
Figure 6.1. Juliette Hampton Morgan. Source: Birmingham, Alabama, Public Li-
brary Archives.
Zygmunt Baumann writes that life has become liquid. 76 The implication for
philosophers of communication is that we have to grasp our understandings
of humanity in a dynamic and integrated way. A person must be compre-
hended in the whole-of-life; one’s self-individualizing reveals aspects of the
social complex as well as other aspects of life. Bauman notes that “History is
philosophy’s fulfillment; the truth of philosophy finds its ultimate test and
confirmation in its acceptance and recognition, in the words of philosophers
becoming the flesh of the polity.” 77 This section examines the situation of
Juliette Hampton Morgan (1914–1957) in Montgomery, Alabama, drawing
upon ideas constituting Tymieniecka’s benevolent sentiment, which provides
ground for Morgan’s communication ethics. Specific attention is paid to the
period of 1955 through 1957, surrounding the bus protest by African
Americans in her community.
Morgan was a seventh-generation Southerner and a third-generation Ala-
bamian, born into a prominent family in the Montgomery community. 78 Like
most affluent Southern white women in the 1940s and 1950s, she enjoyed
entertaining, had many friends, and loved literature, theater, and music. Mor-
gan also had a passion for politics. “She was an educated and conscientious
person who took exception to the racial customs into which she was born.” 79
Leslie W. Dunbar, director of the Southern Regional Council during that
time, observed “it is difficult to convey to persons who did not live in the
South [in the 1950s] . . . a feeling of how it was.” 80 Reverend Robert S.
Graetz wrote, “It’s hard to imagine that simply going to a meeting could be
Tymieniecka’s Benevolent Sentiment as Ground for Communication Ethics 115
an act of courage. But in the mid 1950s, a white person taking part in an
integrated organization in the South defied all social mores and jeopardized
the principles that controlled every aspect of life.” 81 Morgan’s understanding
of equality was ahead the socio-cultural practices of that time.
A vocal proponent of civil rights, Morgan was the first white woman in
Alabama to persistently and publicly speak out against racial segregation. 82
She believed that “white privilege constituted moral evil as well as political
injustice.” 83 As a scholar of the humanities, she understood that the creative
function is the hinge to logos. If she could convey meaning in a creative way,
she could aid in the ontopoietic generation of life.
At the level of humanity in Tymieniecka’s phenomenology of life, “life
attains a degree of individualization by which it gains consciousness of itself
and explicates itself as capacity,” including “the capacity to recognize, select,
and bring to realization his own ontological virtualities.” 84 Morgan felt that
her voice could make a difference in the way humans beings acted toward
and responded with one another. As early as 1939, she was writing letters to
the editor of the Montgomery Advertiser regarding civil injustices. She
worked against passage of the Boswell Amendment in 1946, designed to
restrict Negro voting in Alabama by requiring, in part, that voter registration
be limited to “those who can read and write, understand and explain any
article of the Constitution of the United States in the English language” 85 to
the satisfaction of a county registrar. In 1953, Morgan wrote a letter to the
Montgomery Advertiser protesting the white supremacy slogan printed on
ballots in Alabama, referring to the slogan as “an insult to the colored races
and a disgrace to the white.” 86 When asked by a friend what compelled her to
write that letter, Morgan shared some ideas from recent reading she had
done, adding, “And then I saw—on the bus I think—Jane Addams’ classic
question, ‘Who if not you? When if not now?’ So I went at it.” 87
Morgan went at it in all areas of her life, whether she was acting as a
member of the Fellowship of the Concerned, 88 the Alabama Human Rela-
tions Council, 89 or alone. Morgan advocated freedom of speech for all
views, 90 and during World War II she urged people to get involved in the
political system. 91 She wrote letters to influential people, acknowledging “I
do not expect you to agree with me in these views, but I do want you to know
them.” 92 In her place of work, Morgan supported the effort against “stand up
integration.” 93 This practice of de jure segregation in public libraries re-
moved all tables and chairs from the building to minimize interactions of the
races in reading areas. 94 The aesthetic, moral, and intellective meaning-be-
stowing activities of the city fathers would not go unmatched by the onto-
poietic sense-making capacities of the city mothers. The creativity of the
benevolent sentiment drives the moral sense, compelling one to reflect upon
constraints that compel or restrain moral behavior.
116 Pat Arneson
the bus. Her own mother told her she was making a fool of herself and
tarnishing the family’s good name.” 101 A constructive orientation toward the
benevolent impulse guided Morgan; she sought to expand her moral sense to
fulfill her beingness and struggled to cultivate moral enjoyment in the midst
of adversity. Moral valuation emerges in the communal life as a deliberative
process that then directs one’s decisions. Her letters prompted contemplation
in others.
Martin Luther King Jr. explained that initially “the Sermon on the Mount,
rather than a doctrine of passive resistance . . . inspired the Negroes of
Montgomery.” 102 Then on December 12, 1955, seven days after the protest
began, the Montgomery Advertiser printed a letter by Juliette Morgan, a
“reclusive and normally private librarian.” 103 She wrote,
I have heard some bus drivers use the tone and manners of mule drivers in the
treatment of Negro passengers. . . . Three times I’ve gotten off the bus because
I could not countenance treatment of Negroes. . . . I should have gotten off on
several other occasions. Twice I have heard a certain driver with high seniority
mutter quite audibly “black ape.” I could not tell whether the Negro heard or
not, but I did and felt insulted. 104
In her letter, Morgan compared the bus protest to Mahatma Gandhi’s Salt
March. 105 King and his colleagues began to reflect on Morgan’s comments
about Gandhi. 106 In Stride Toward Freedom: The Montgomery Story, King
credited Morgan with a shift in people’s thinking about the protest. He wrote,
[I]n the first days of the protest . . . the phrase most often heard was ‘Christian
love.’ . . . As the days unfolded, however, the inspiration of Mahatma Gandhi
began to exert its influence. . . . About a week after the protest started, a white
woman who understood and sympathized with the Negroes’ efforts wrote a
letter to the editor of the Montgomery Advertiser comparing the bus protest
with the Gandhian movement in India. . . . Nonviolent resistance had emerged
as a technique of the movement, while love stood as the regulating idea. 107
Historian Lawrence Reddick noted: “Up until that time expressions from
white people had been to belittle the protest. . . . They said it wouldn’t last
long and didn’t mean anything. Her letter grasped the significance of it [the
protest] and helped give many people a sense of history.” 108 Morgan called
for a public discussion of moral valuation in her letter.
Morgan’s letter communicatively foregrounded deliberation: “we ought
to be working out plans to span the gap between segregation and integration
to extend public services—schools, libraries, parks—and transportation to
Negro citizens.” 109 She acknowledged her self-individuation but also pressed
others to realize that moral valuation emerges in communal life. She wrote,
“This may be a minority report, but a number of Montgomerians not entirely
118 Pat Arneson
private; scarcely anyone outside of white Montgomery knew what was oc-
curring. Morgan’s mother, Lila Bess Olin Morgan, shared with a friend that
her daughter had become a “complete Pariah.” 142 Anxiety and depression
weakened Morgan’s nerves, and she was granted a temporary leave from her
job at the library. 143
Morgan wrote a postcard to her aunt, reflecting “I wish there were things I
could have added or worded more tactfully [in the January 14, 1957, letter],
but I’m trying to forget that for now and profit by it next time.” 144 At the
same time, she “loved Montgomery and resented being ostracized for obey-
ing [her] . . . conscience.” 145 In Tymieniecka’s phenomenology of life, “hu-
manity is principally entrusted to his creative acts.” 146 Morgan found herself
“faced with the task of conceiving of a new horizon of meaning.” 147 Given
Morgan’s state of depression, she faced a daunting task in determining how
to craft meaning that would be interpreted by others as innovative with
respect to racial equality.
On the night of July 15, 1957, a cross was burned on Morgan’s front
lawn. This was a terrifying experience for Morgan, who lived with her moth-
er. Stanton explains, “Flaming crosses were known to be the Klan’s ‘first
warning.’ Visits from ‘wrecking crews’ were subsequently scheduled if first
warnings went unheeded.” 148 On July 17, 1957, Morgan’s mother called the
library to resign Morgan from her position. That night, Morgan, leaving a
note on which she had written “I can’t go on,” took her own life with an
overdose of sleeping pills. 149 Although the exact circumstances of her death
are unknown, “the city’s black citizens, including King, and its sympathetic
whites, believed that Juliette Morgan had been persecuted to death.” 150
After Morgan’s death, Mary Y. Dobbins, one of her friends, described her
as a “rare spirit” who was “alive to the cause of justice.” 151 Her resistance
was a “sensitive barometer, or conscience, for people like you and me.” 152
Morgan “brought joy into any gathering she attended. It is significant that she
was loved and admired by many who did not share her views on segrega-
tion.” 153 She brought a sense of aliveness to others. One writer shared that
since Morgan “took the teachings of Christianity seriously, it was perhaps
inevitable that she should cry out against racial injustice.” 154 Tymieniecka’s
understanding of benevolent sentiment offers insight into Morgan’s commu-
nicative ethic, conveyed in her linguistic and corporeal expressivity.
IMPLICATIONS
Tymieniecka offered an ethical ground that emerges with the vital impulse of
human creativity. The creativity of the benevolent sentiment drives the moral
sense, which is expressed both corporeally and linguistically. She asserted
that aesthetic, moral, and intellective meaning-bestowing faculties shape life
122 Pat Arneson
in the human station. Moral valuation and judgment emerge through deliber-
ation to promote a good in communal life. The benevolent sentiment drives
people to contribute to the social world.
This ground for communication ethics is recognizable in the life of Juli-
ette Morgan, who expressed her right to free speech in Montgomery, Ala-
bama. She attended to the benevolent sentiment in her expression of moral-
ity. This ethical ground prompted her efforts to creatively change the mean-
ing of equality in her public and private communication with others. People
respond to the call for communication ethics in postmodernity by being
attentive to threats of injustice to Others, exposed by the benevolent senti-
ment.
NOTES
1946) in Lila Bess Olin Morgan (1895–1977) Family Papers, Alabama Department of Archives
and History, Montgomery, Alabama.
92. Juliette Morgan, letter to Senator John Bankhead, U.S. Senate, Washington, DC (Janu-
ary 30, 1946) in Lila Bess Olin Morgan (1895–1977) Family Papers, Alabama Department of
Archives and History, Montgomery, Alabama.
93. Graham, A Right to Read, 3.
94. Ibid.; Stanton, Journey toward Justice, 153.
95. Verducci, “Examining Development,” 21.
96. Charles Erwin Wilson, To Secure These Rights: The Report of the President’s Commit-
tee on Civil Rights (Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1947), 139.
97. Joe Azbell, “5,000 at Meeting Outline Boycott; Bullet Clips Bus,” Montgomery Adver-
tiser, December 6, 1955, 1.
98. Taylor Branch, Parting the Waters: America in the King Years, 1954–1963 (New York:
Simon and Schuster, 1988), 144.
99. Graham, A Right to Read, 130.
100. “Juliette Hampton Morgan: A White Woman Who Understood.”
101. Ibid.
102. “A Southern Profile,” n.p.
103. Graham, A Right to Read, 101.
104. Juliette Morgan, letter to the editor [“Lesson from Ghandi”], Montgomery Advertiser,
December 12, 1955, 4.
105. Ibid.
106. Stephen B. Oates, Let the Trumpet Sound: The Life of Martin Luther King, Jr. (New
York: HarperCollins, 1994), 77.
107. Martin Luther King, Jr., Stride Toward Freedom: The Montgomery Story (New York:
Harper and Row, 1958), 67.
108. Stanton, Journey Toward Justice, 2.
109. Morgan, letter to the editor [“Lesson from Ghandi”], 4.
110. Ibid.
111. Jean Read, letter to Juliette Morgan (ca. December 12, 1955), in Lila Bess Olin Morgan
(1895–1977) Family Papers, Alabama Department of Archives and History, Montgomery,
Alabama.
112. Juliette Morgan, draft letter [“Revised Letter”], June 9, 1952, in Lila Bess Olin Morgan
(1895–1977) Family Papers, Alabama Department of Archives and History, Montgomery,
Alabama.
113. Will T., letter to Juliette Morgan, Heflin, Alabama (July 7, 1949), in Lila Bess Olin
Morgan (1895–1977) Family Papers, Alabama Department of Archives and History, Mont-
gomery, Alabama.
114. Juliette Morgan [pseudonym, Mrs. J. J. Cough], letter to the editor [“Unto the Least of
These”], Montgomery Advertiser, May 8, 1956, in Lila Bess Olin Morgan (1895–1977) Family
Papers, Alabama Department of Archives and History, Montgomery, Alabama.
115. Ibid.
116. Tymieniecka, “The Moral Sense,” 73n15.
117. Buford Boone, “Editorial: What a Price for Peace,” Tuscaloosa News, February 7, 1956,
1.
118. Wyn Craig Wade, The Fiery Cross: The Ku Klux Klan in America (New York: Oxford
University Press, 1998), 300.
119. Buford Boone, “Editorials: Segregation and Integration,” Tuscaloosa News, January 6,
1957, 4.
120. Boone, “Editorials,” 4; see Stanton, Journey Toward Justice, 194.
121. Boone, “Editorials,” 4.
122. Buford Boone, letter to Juliette Morgan, Montgomery, Alabama, January 11, 1957, in
Lila Bess Olin Morgan (1895–1977) Family Papers, Alabama Department of Archives and
History, Montgomery, Alabama.
123. Stanton, Journey Toward Justice, 121, 136, 161.
124. “Juliette Hampton Morgan: A White Woman Who Understood.”
126 Pat Arneson
BIBLIOGRAPHY
———. Logos and Life, Book 2: The Three Movements of the Soul. In Analecta Husserliana:
The Yearbook of Phenomenological Research 25. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers,
1988.
———. Logos and Life, Book 3: The Passions of the Soul and the Elements in the Ontopoiesis
of Culture: The Life Significance of Literature. In Analecta Husserliana: The Yearbook of
Phenomenological Research 28, 4–141. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1990.
———. “Interview with Anna-Teresa Tymieniecka.” By Ivanka Rainova. The World Phenom-
enology Institute, 1993. Updated December 1, 1999. www.phenomenology.org/inter-
view.html.
———. Logos and Life, Book 4: Impetus and Equipoise in the Life-Strategies of Reason. In
Analecta Husserliana: The Yearbook of Phenomenological Research 70. Dordrecht: Kluwer
Academic Publishers, 2000.
———. “Theme: The Triumph of Imagination in the Critique of Reason.” In Analecta Husser-
liana: The Yearbook of Phenomenological Research 83, xi–xviii. Dordrecht: Kluwer Aca-
demic Publishers, 2004.
———. “Logos’ Timing in Life—Fabulating History.” In Analecta Husserliana: The Year-
book of Phenomenological Research 90, xiii–xix. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers,
2006.
Verducci, Daniela. “Examining Development from the Ontopoietical Perspective.” Translated
by Sheila Beatty. Phenomenological Inquiry: A Review of Philosophical Ideas and Trends
31 (2007): 17–22.
Wade, Wyn Craig. The Fiery Cross: The Ku Klux Klan in America. New York: Oxford Univer-
sity Press, 1998.
Wilson, Charles Erwin. To Secure These Rights: The Report of the President’s Committee on
Civil Rights. Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1947.
Wolff, Kurt H. “Surrender to Morality as the Morality of Surrender.” In Analecta Husserliana:
The Yearbook of Phenomenological Research 15, 495–99. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic
Publishers, 1983.
Chapter Seven
“Every art and every inquiry, and similarly every action and pursuit, is
thought to aim at some good; and for this reason the good has rightly been
declared to be that at which all things aim.” 1 If Aristotle was correct—
descriptively or prescriptively—in his formulation of the ethical basis of
human life, why is so much of our experience not merely dreary, but punish-
ing? Material reality places profound constraints on our ability to realize the
good. We age, get sick, and die. But why is achieving the good in human
relationships so difficult? Why is it so hard for us to get along with our
friends and neighbors?
In this chapter we use a movie, The Three Burials of Melquiades Estrada
(hereafter, Three Burials), to examine the ethics of friendship, primarily in
the interpersonal realm, but also, and necessarily, in the political sphere. 2
The aim of this analysis is to illuminate some of the possibilities and chal-
lenges of achieving these values, as well as the meanings of the values at
stake. We are guided in this enterprise by insights gleaned from Austin
Babrow’s Problematic Integration theory and by writings on communication
and ethics, particularly works by William Rawlins and Ronald C. Arnett,
Janie M. Harden Fritz, and Leeanne M. Bell. 3 Following Herbert Blumer’s
notion of sensitizing concepts and Victoria Chen and W. Barnett Pearce’s
view of case study, we hope to unpack the relational and ethical significance
129
130 Austin S. Babrow and Lindsey M. Rose
of Three Burials at the same time that the film deepens and thickens our
appreciation for ideas drawn from the several theoretical schemes. 4
Rawlins argues that “becoming and remaining friends with others is an on-
going voluntary achievement that involves the continual exercise of moral
will by each friend.” 30 In other words, friendship is neither biologically de-
termined by blood relations nor compelled by legal covenants such as mar-
riage. 31 It is a voluntary choice, involving the free expression of reason and
intention. As noted in the quotation from Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics
that opened this chapter, actors’ conceptions of the good guide freely chosen
actions. Volitional actions, such as those composing voluntary relationships
like friendship, are thus inherently moral acts; they express, constitute and
embody actors’ understandings of the good. As enduring relationships,
friendships require ongoing moral action.
Friendship’s embodiment of choice as an expression of moral will is a
significant theme in Three Burials. Choices are particularly significant be-
cause they so often involve actions that defy substantial counterforces. For
instance, the expression of moral will is illustrated in Mel’s and Pete’s
choices to become friends despite the hierarchy of a supervisor-worker rela-
tionship, the obstacles of their cultural differences, and Mel’s tenuous resi-
dency as an illegal alien. Although nontrivial, these obstacles are small in
contrast to many others Mel and Pete surmount as friends. To appreciate the
latter, they must be seen in the context of the political economy of the
Mexican-U.S. borderlands.
Mel’s gift to Pete of a wonderful horse (Pete attests, “It’s the best horse I
ever saw.”) perfectly contradicts values that are commonly taken for granted
on the U.S. side of the borderlands with Mexico: the avarice and acquisitive-
ness of consumer culture. Homeless and living outside the law, Mel nonethe-
less gives his more secure and affluent friend the vaquero’s most valuable
possession. His gift is all the more poignant as an inversion of values because
of Mel’s grace, the palpable ease with which he bestows the gift; Mel tells his
136 Austin S. Babrow and Lindsey M. Rose
friend not to return the horse after a ride because Pete’s name is already
branded on the animal’s mind.
Although Mel’s gift to Pete is great, the most significant exercise of moral
will in the film is Pete’s attempt to honor his friend’s wish to be buried in his
hometown in Mexico. This undertaking is unusually powerful even at a
superficial level; Mel must disinter his friend’s corpse for a second time, well
over a week after the killing. 32 But more importantly, this decision sets Pete,
his friend’s corpse, and Mel’s killer, the captive Border Patrol agent, Mike,
on a journey that inverts many elements of the typical illegal border crossing
narrative: from the United States to Mexico, eluding U.S. agents intent on
keeping the fugitives within the United States, for friendship and family (and
ultimately for justice; more on this below) rather than for work (and despite
the legal system), and ultimately resulting in the repatriation and redemption
of the Mexican at the cost of everything for the U.S. citizen, Pete. 33 By the
end of this journey, Pete has not only lost his friend, but he is also a stateless
fugitive who has given away his friend’s wonderful gift and has lost the
fantasy that he was “the only one” for his lover. In short, Pete exercises
incredible moral will at every step of the journey to return his friend to his
home. As in many other ways, some discussed below, Pete’s exercise of
moral will involves so many reversals of the typical narrative of illegal
immigration that passive viewing and complacency are impossible. The
viewer is impelled toward ethical deliberation.
The inversions of the typical narrative and the exercise of extraordinary
moral choice challenge us to rethink the meaning of our friendships. If, as
Rawlins argues, the ethics of the relationship are rooted in the choice to be
friends, Mel and Pete’s example prompts us to ask what our friendships
actually reveal about our moral will. 34 To the extent that we become friends
because of proximity, similarity of outlook, and shared leisure pursuits, these
relationships reveal an easy virtue. In other words, it takes little moral will to
be friends with those with whom it is easy to forge such bonds. These
relationships take on substantial ethical meaning to the extent that they con-
front PI, such as surmounting ambivalence in choices between weighty, com-
peting values, or acting in the face of uncertain or highly unlikely success.
significant act toward Pete is, as we have said, the gift of his horse. In this, it
might be asserted that Mel does not so much show concern for Pete as
generosity, giving Pete the pleasure of a marvelous horse; as we have said,
from one vaquero to another, there can be no greater gift. But someone in the
reduced circumstances of an illegal alien has relatively little scope—neither
opportunity nor motive—for enacting concern for a U.S. citizen. Moreover,
in terms of the arc of the story, when Mel’s life is cut short, he is deprived of
the time and the opportunities a longer life would have provided to show
caring and concern for his friend.
By contrast, Pete shows concern and caring for Mel in many ways. He is
apparently devastated by his friend’s death, sitting alone in his room, brush-
ing off a visitor who brings condolences and .223 shells found near the scene
of Melquiades’s shooting. Pete asks to have Mel’s body released to him for
burial, pursues evidence (the bullet shells) that might reveal the identity of
the killer, confronts the sheriff several times about his investigation, and
ultimately kidnaps the killer when it is clear that the authorities are uninter-
ested in justice. But, even in comparison to these strong reactions to his
friend’s killing, Pete’s efforts to return Mel to his home show exceptional
caring.
Somehow, although he gives every appearance of being at home in west
Texas, Pete must recognize the significance to Mel of being far from home
and family, in alien land and culture. Pete must not merely understand, but
care about, Mel’s wishes. The meaning of friendship—and of a friend’s
request—provides the grounds for this empathic concern. Moreover, Pete
cares for Mel’s corpse in several scenes that do not merely challenge, but
overturn, our ordinary understandings of devotion and propriety. In so doing,
they add urgency to the ethical questions at the heart of the film.
Images of the treatment of Mel’s corpse are gruesome, but they are partic-
ularly striking when Pete unearths the corpse that has been decomposing,
without refrigeration, for well over a week, picks foraging ants off of the
moldering body, sets the corpse’s head on fire to dislodge remaining ants,
infuses the corpse with antifreeze to preserve it, and combs hair from the
rotting scalp. Audience members cannot help being repulsed by these im-
ages, but they also cannot easily doubt the loving concern that motivates
Pete’s actions. PI theory suggests that strong ambivalence prompts reflection
on both expectation and desire. In this case, the jarring contrast of loving and
abhorrent action, the confrontation of goodness and evil, requires us to con-
front the question of right and wrong. In other words, Pete’s treatment of his
friend’s corpse pushes us outside the role of passive, complacent viewers to
active judges of morality.
In the spirit of this push, the film can also be taken as a challenge to an
important element of Rawlins’s analysis of the ethics of friendship. Specifi-
cally, he argues that “the giving of friends is not a matter of self-sacrifice—a
138 Austin S. Babrow and Lindsey M. Rose
denial of our self and our well-being in helping our friend. The giving of
friends simultaneously reflects self . . . and other’s interests.” 36 Through the
act of giving, he says, one more fully realizes oneself as friend and so
achieves greater fulfillment of one’s humanity. 37 But Three Burials raises the
question of whether it is always possible to be friends without self-sacrifice.
Moreover, it demands us to consider whether “friendship” would be an espe-
cially valued relationship without self-sacrifice. In this we are reminded of
Arnett and colleagues’ insistence that distance is essential to relational con-
cern, and Levinas’s insistence that the very alterity is the seed of our respon-
sibility. 38 Willing self-sacrifice for the benefit of the Other constitutes un-
sparing responsibility through the embrace of distance, valuing the Other
completely by ignoring the value of the self.
These considerations lead us to agree with Rawlins’s analysis of the self’s
fulfillment through giving to a friend, but to demur on the issue of self-
sacrifice. Especially in situations involving unequal resources, when one
friend has much more than the other, it is hard to see friendship in anything
other than sharing and at least some self-sacrifice on the part of the person
with more assets. It is also hard to see anything particularly significant in
such sharing.
The act of giving is meaningful to the extent that what is given has value
for both recipient and benefactor. In other words, no matter how valuable the
gift is to the recipient, if it costs the benefactor nothing, its meaning as a gift
is diminished. This is precisely the reason that Melquiades’s gift of his horse
to Pete is so significant. It is also precisely why Pete’s gift to Mel is so
significant; Pete loses everything, except perhaps his life, to bring Mel’s
body to his home. But there is a deeper gift in this journey. Pete does not risk
everything simply by exhuming his friend and crossing the border illegally.
In terms of the law, his most significant act is kidnapping a federal agent.
This act is also the basis for the most profound caring he shows for Melqui-
ades.
Pete puts Mike through an ordeal in which the killer is beaten several
times; is forced to disinter his victim; eats, sleeps, and shares a horse with the
rotting corpse; vainly attempts to escape from his captor by running for hours
across the scorching desert sand with nothing to protect his bare feet except
pieces of his pant legs; continually fears for his life at the hands of his
kidnapper; and nearly dies from a rattlesnake bite. Mike, the young, strong,
overenthusiastic representative of U.S. border policy, is completely un-
manned by the much older Pete. His nose is broken by the woman who saved
his life after the snakebite (and whose nose Mike had broken earlier in the
film as he beat her to the ground after an illegal crossing into the United
States). And this Border Patrol agent, brimming with testosterone and brutal-
ity, is himself forced by circumstances to cross the border, but from the
The Ethical Challenges of Friendship 139
United States to Mexico, to return his victim’s body to his home and to beg
for forgiveness.
Why does Pete subject Mike to this ordeal? Is it merely for revenge or
punishment? In the end, Pete brings Mike to sincere remorse. When Mike
finally apologizes, kneeling at the foot of an ancient tree where Mel’s picture
is hung, it is as if he is at the foot of the cross, begging forgiveness of the
innocent savior who died for Mike’s sins. Pete evidently believes in Mike’s
redemption, calling Mike “son” as he leaves him Mel’s fabulous horse and
rides away on a donkey. Mike’s redemption also is evident in the concern he
shows for Pete, calling out after him, “You gonna be alright?”
Mike’s salvation has two deeper meanings, we believe. One has to do
with the idea that friendship is the continual exercise of moral will (see
above), the other with the caring shown for a friend. Consider first Pete’s
choice to bring Mike to repentance and redemption. The act of killing is, of
course, antithetical to acts of friendship. How are we to respond to such an
act? Is it a greater good to condemn or to forgive? The choice marks out
antithetical pathways following a grievous breach. Condemnation leads to
the complete severing of human relationship. Forgiveness redeems the vital
human bond. Although Three Burials depicts the latter, it ends only after
Pete gives Mel’s horse to his killer and rides away with nothing remaining of
his former life except the donkey he rides. Aside from this, the ending is
open. Once again, we are pushed out of the role of passive viewers and into
the position of having to arrive at our own moral stance. In friendship, we
must often act in highly ambiguous situations and often in the face of great
ambivalence. By acting in the face of powerful PI, we do not merely choose,
but embody, and thereby constitute the good.
In addition to the question of choice and the exercise of moral will, the
story of Mike’s redemption has another vital meaning having to do with the
value of caring for our friends. In bringing Mike to sincere remorse for
killing Mel, Pete cares for his friend by resurrecting the meaning of his life
and death. How is this so? Mel’s life and death are threatened with meaning-
lessness because of his invisibility as an illegal alien. A host of factors
contributes to such invisibility: the need to take on a false identity, a deval-
ued native language, a life of constant movement in pursuit of agricultural or
other low-wage jobs, and the conspiratorial indifference of local and federal
officials in response to an illegal immigrant’s killing. 39 On the latter point,
recall Mel’s second burial, by governmental authority, in an incompletely
marked grave (“Melquiades—Mexico”). Here we are reminded of a Woody
Guthrie and Martin Hoffman song about illegal farm workers who died
nameless during deportation, to be remembered only as “deportees.” 40
The invisibility of migrant agricultural workers threatens to erase the very
meaning of Mel’s life and death. But his friend, Pete, cares about him; Pete
cares enough to act against the complacency that would erase the meaning of
140 Austin S. Babrow and Lindsey M. Rose
In the night one family camps in a ditch and another family pulls in and the
tents come out. The two men squat on their hams and the women and children
The Ethical Challenges of Friendship 141
listen. Here is the node, you who hate change and fear revolution. Keep these
two squatting men apart; make them hate, fear, suspect each other. Here is the
anlage of the thing you fear. This is the zygote. For here “I lost my land” is
changed; a cell is split and from its splitting grows the thing you hate—“we
lost our land.” The danger is here, for two men are not as lonely and perplexed
as one. And from this first “we” there grows a still more dangerous thing: “I
have a little food” plus “I have none.” If from this problem the sum is “We
have a little food,” the thing is on its way. 42
Readers who have seen Three Burials know that the foregoing has understat-
ed the moral complexity at the heart of the film. They know Pete eventually
learns that Mel’s hometown, Jimenez, as well as his wife and family, may
have been fantasies, much as the reality of Mexico as a home is fantasy for
the millions who are forced into the life of illegal immigration by economic
privation. This revelation profoundly challenges any calculations about
Pete’s caring and sacrifices for his friend. It also asks us to think about yet
another ethical precept.
Rawlins argues that another “ethical requirement of friendship involves
ongoing learning about each other.” 44 But Pete and Mel have limited time to
get to know one another. We as viewers know little of what Mel learns about
Pete, but we watch as Pete learns that Mel appears not to have had the wife
142 Austin S. Babrow and Lindsey M. Rose
and family he claimed and that Jimenez, too, appears to have been a fiction.
Was Mel lying? Or was his truth obscured by the distortions forced on his
life, identity, and relationships by illicit residency and migrant life? These
constraining dynamics necessarily limited what these friends could learn
about one another, thus constraining the chances for their mutual understand-
ing.
This raises vital questions about the ethical potential of friendship. As
Rawlins says, “creating understandings and ongoing learning is a relational
and ethical necessity to remain connected and to meet our friends on their
own terms where they are in their own lives.” 45 But it is impossible for
people forced across the border as illegals to be experienced by U.S. friends
in the context of the formers’ home lives in Mexico. It is also impossible for
U.S. citizens to experience Mexican illegal immigrants in the context of their
life in the United States because people forced into this situation have ex-
tremely limited scope for living life on their own terms. American citizens
can meet and get to know only people who are living outside of themselves,
just as they are living outside their home.
Rawlins’s analysis allows us to see that the constraint in situations like
these raises a significant moral challenge for friendships:
If Pete cannot ever experience his friend on his own terms because Mel can
never live life completely on his own terms, Pete can never understand Mel’s
needs. Pete’s capacity to act on behalf of Mel’s well-being is thus limited.
Perhaps Mel’s fantasy life is as real as any he might have in such a soul-
depriving marginal existence. By the same logic, U.S. citizens, too, have
only a limited context for understanding the life and being of an immigrant
living illegally in this country, not only because of the obvious issue of
mobility, but more fundamentally because of the profound constraints on the
immigrant’s being. U.S. natives, too, appear to be stymied even if we want to
befriend, know, and act on behalf of illegal immigrants.
Absent access to Mel’s life, both because of his being an illegal alien
immigrant and because he has died, Pete has little on which to base his
judgments of how to act on behalf of justice for Mel. Here again we are
reminded of Arnett and colleagues’ insistence on the Levinasian idea that
difference is essential to the ethics of relationships. 47 For Levinas, the Face
of the Other is emblematic of an existent that is forever beyond our compre-
hension, and this very difference is the wellspring of responsibility. 48 In stark
The Ethical Challenges of Friendship 143
contrast to the parallel relationship that currently exists between the United
States and Mexico, despite the profound limits on his understanding of his
friend, Pete adopts an extremely self-sacrificing path to justice and redemp-
tion. In so doing, Pete redeems not only the meaningfulness of Mel’s life; he
brings Mike to recognize something of the meaning of the life he had taken
and thereby fosters Mike’s reborn humanity. And even more striking than the
contrast between the way that Pete acts on behalf of his friend and the
relationship between the United States and Mexico, Pete acts not merely
despite the insurmountable limits in his understanding of Mel; Pete acts in
pursuit of what may be a fantasy, perhaps a lie, even after the apparent
illusion is revealed.
Rawlins argues that, interwoven with the other ethical qualities of their rela-
tionship, friends are honest; they behave in trusting and trustworthy ways
with each other. 49 Was Mel dishonest in telling Pete about his home and
family in Mexico? Was he unethical in asking Pete to return him to a fiction-
al hometown? The film treats Mel’s (dis)honesty ambiguously. PI theory
suggests that, just as in the case of ambivalence, uncertainty prompts ethical
reflection. For example, in the broader context of the film, we might ask,
“What are the facts in a borderland so rife with dishonesty?” Indeed, there is
little apparent honesty in the depicted borderlands, save for that of Mel’s gift
to Pete and Pete’s redemption of Mel and his killer. Another way to say this
is that the only certain truth in the film is the two friends’ generosity toward
one another despite their difference. 50
Along these lines, another stark contrast or inversion suggests itself. Until
the very end of the film, when he seems to have broken with reality at the
location he deems Mel’s home, Pete consistently acts with perfect certainty
or assurance, despite what appear to be striking uncertainties, value conflicts,
and the like. Perhaps the only way to act ethically in situations as fraught
with irreducible uncertainty and ambivalence as this one is to make a choice
and embody it to its fullest. By contrast, if one hesitates, one diminishes the
uncertain or conflicting values. Perhaps moral deliberation beyond the point
at which one has given due consideration to each potential value or choice is
moral evacuation. Truth and honesty are acts of will or joint enactments of
relationships such as friendship, rather than mere reflections of something
external to the self or the relationship. In other words, the film seems to ask,
“Is the possibility of friendship negated by the dishonesty of the borderlands
(and by extension, the Mexican-U.S. relationship)? Or is friendship only
possible in such a land through acts of generosity or pure selflessness?”
144 Austin S. Babrow and Lindsey M. Rose
Rawlins ends his analysis of the moral compass of friendship by arguing that,
in living up to the other specific ethical values, “friendship is a conscien-
tiously interested relationship.” 51 In other words, “we are partial to our
friends. We regard and treat them in thoughtful and special ways as they do
us, which creates a distinctive ‘ethical pull.’” 52 This caring and concern for
friends “goes beyond what is characteristic and expected of people general-
ly.” 53 Importantly, however, Rawlins notes that showing special regard for
our friends is not without limits. Although “genuine devotion to a particular
group—family, neighborhood, ethnic community, ethnic group, club—is in
itself morally good, . . . [it] becomes morally suspect . . . when it involves a
deficient stance towards others.” 54 In other words, partiality toward friends
should not cause us to disregard others’ needs or deprive them of what is
good.
It is vital to note the unclarity and potential moral conflict here: Precisely
who merits our partiality? This question is especially significant in light of
arguments against partiality. For example, ethicist Peter Singer challenges us
to extend the circle of our “caring to encompass Mother Earth and all her life
forms.” 55 But if we are to draw borders that locate those who will receive our
partiality, they are not easily drawn. Moreover, how ought this partiality to
be expressed? What is meant by “a deficient stance” toward others? How
does one show partiality, which is morally good, without depriving others
not among our favored group? The very “finitude” that “typically limits our
concrete opportunities for devoted service to particular others” sharpens the
ethical tension between partiality to our family, friends, or community and
fairness to all. 56
Three Burials encourages viewers to reflect on the above questions relat-
ed to the ethic of partiality to our friends. The film’s depiction of the pro-
found devotion of a friendship provides a stark contrast to the relationship
between the United States and Mexico. Mel asks Pete to return his body to
his homeland, and Pete elevates this commitment to satisfying his friend’s
desire above all other considerations, including national borders, laws, per-
sonal security, love, and a host of other social mores or demands. Contrast
this with the relationship of the United States to illegal immigrants from
Mexico. National policy demands that aspiring immigrants (and migrants)
arrive legally and enforces substantial barriers to illegal entry, with the result
that crossing the border is physically arduous and often quite expensive and
dangerous. Those who are able to cross successfully, but illegally, must live
in hiding until they can develop a false identity and must work at quite
undesirable jobs, often as temporary workers (e.g., the traditional stoop labor
following maturing crops), for low and often subminimum wages, without
benefits, all the while vulnerable to unscrupulous labor practices, raids by
The Ethical Challenges of Friendship 145
CONCLUSION
The main purpose of this chapter was to examine the ethics of friendship in
the interpersonal realm by applying to a recent film insights drawn from
writings about ethics and about the challenges of valuative orientations.
Through these efforts, we have tried to remain mindful of a lesson in the
recently published Handbook of Communication Ethics; George Cheney and
colleagues point out that many of the chapters challenge the notion that
ethics is a “sphere of thought, discussion, and practice” separate from other
realms of communication theory and praxis. 58
Our analysis of Three Burials understands the film as ethical provocation.
At the level of interpersonal relationships, it asks the viewer to consider the
ethics of friendship in a world of permeable boundaries, profound inequal-
ities, and systemic injustice. For these reasons, as we have tried to suggest in
much of the foregoing, Three Burials challenges us to understand that the
ethics of interpersonal friendship are bound with those of international
friendship. Of course, there are reasons to be wary of the latter idea. One
might well ask whether it makes sense to think of the associations between
two nations as a friendship. Conservative analysts often reject the idea, para-
phrasing Lord Palmerston’s 1848 speech in the House of Commons: “Na-
tions have no permanent friends and no permanent enemies but only perma-
nent interests.” 59 But what are permanent interests, and how ought they to be
pursued? Do they have invariant meaning in an ever-changing world? Might
efforts to cleave inflexibly to one construction of national interest undermine
that very interest? One obvious example of this is the argument that a narrow
and inflexible commitment to freedom for its own citizens puts the United
States in the position of endangering freedom elsewhere in the world, which
in turn engenders hostility and threat to freedom at home.
146 Austin S. Babrow and Lindsey M. Rose
Even more concretely, U.S. policy toward illegal immigrants from eco-
nomically troubled Mexico is thought to protect domestic jobs and national
law, but it also creates an underclass of worker-residents without rights. And
what do we make of national interests when they conflict? For instance, the
United States is committed not only to freedom but also to justice. These
twin values are thought to be mutual guarantors, or perhaps mutual require-
ments. Can the United States claim to uphold the value of justice when so
much of its economy (e.g., agriculture, construction, service) is heavily reli-
ant on the labors of illegal immigrants whose lives are profoundly, inhu-
manely constrained by the realities of illegal residence?
Three Burials raises even more fundamental ethical questions than those
noted above. In its depiction of Mel and Pete’s friendship, it asks us to reflect
on several related questions: Who is a friend? To whom can I show partial-
ity? Is partiality possible, and in particular, is it advisable in an era of global-
ization? When borders, traditional nation-states, traditional ways of organiz-
ing are challenged by globalizing economic, social, political, and communi-
cation structures, what are we to make of relationships? In a constantly
evolving reality of permeable, flexible, dynamic borders, when the pace and
scope of change are accelerating, who can we call a friend, and what can
friendship mean? Can we afford to be partial, or should we treat the entire
globe as our friend? Can we afford to let the meaning of friendship wash
away in the global ocean of others when so much is at stake? Is the meaning,
the significance of friendship, all the more profound in the new global real-
ity? In these ways and more, Three Burials provokes us to meditate on who
and what we will be to one another.
Three Burials is also a provocation to action. Pete’s actions on behalf of
his friend ultimately redeem Melquiades. They also appear to redeem his
friend’s killer. 60 Without Pete’s actions, both men appear to be lost. Superfi-
cially, the film might be taken to ask us to choose between the amoral
indifference of the sheriff and its counterpoint in the ideal of Pete’s heroic
sacrifice. This false choice is as self-defeating as is the reduction of Mexican-
U.S. relations to a conflict between the sovereignty of national borders and,
say, the basic human right to fair working conditions. A more promising
response is suggested in Jonsen and Toulmin’s defense of casuistry:
At the end of the day, then, all reflective moral traditions keep it in mind that
the kernel of moral wisdom consists, not in a hardline commitment to princi-
ples which we accept without qualification, but in understanding the human
needs and relations that are nurtured by a life of reflective moral action. With
that preoccupation, the practical task is to apply general moral rules, and other
ethical considerations, to new and more complex sets of circumstances, in
ways that respect these human needs. 61
The Ethical Challenges of Friendship 147
NOTES
1. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics: Book I, trans. W. David Ross (Oxford: Oxford Univer-
sity Press, 2009), 3. An earlier draft of this paper was presented at the National Communication
Association conference, Washington, DC, November, 2013. The authors thank Ronald C.
Arnett for helpful comments on an earlier draft.
2. The Three Burials of Melquiades Estrada, directed by Tommy Lee Jones (New York:
Sony Classics, 2005), DVD.
3. Ronald C. Arnett, Janie M. Harden Fritz, and Leeanne M. Bell, Communication Ethics
Literacy: Dialogue and Difference (Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage, 2008); Austin S. Babrow,
“Communication and Problematic Integration: Understanding Diverging Probability and Val-
ue, Ambiguity, Ambivalence, and Impossibility,” Communication Theory 2, no. 1 (1992);
Austin S. Babrow, “Problematic Integration Theory,” in Explaining Communication: Contem-
porary Theories and Exemplars, ed. Brian B. Whaley and Wendy Samter (Mahwah, NJ: Law-
rence Erlbaum, 2007); William K. Rawlins, “Embracing Ethical and Political Potentials of
Friendship,” in The Compass of Friendship: Narratives, Identities, Dialogues (Thousand Oaks,
CA: Sage, 2009), 175–200.
4. Herbert Blumer, Symbolic Interactionism: Perspectives and Method (Engelwood Cliffs,
NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1969), 147–52; Elizabeth B. Gill and Austin S. Babrow, “To Hope or to
Know: Coping with Uncertainty and Ambivalence in Women’s Magazine Breast Cancer Arti-
cles” Journal of Applied Communication Research 35, no. 2 (2007); Victoria Chen and W.
Barnett Pearce, “Even if a Thing of Beauty, Can a Case Study Be a Joy Forever? A Social
Constructionist Approach to Theory and Research,” in Social Approaches to Communication,
ed. Wendy Leeds-Hurwitz (New York: Guilford Press, 1995).
5. Babrow, “Communication and Problematic Integration”; Austin S. Babrow, “Uncertain-
ty, Value, Communication, and Problematic Integration,” Journal of Communication 51, no. 3
(2001).
6. Babrow, “Communication and Problematic Integration”; Babrow, “Uncertainty, Value,
Communication.”
7. Aristotle, Aristotle’s Metaphysics, trans. W. David Ross (Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1924/rev. 1958), 1: Book I, chapter 1; The Internet Classics Archive, classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/
metaphysics.html.
8. See the brief discussion of the universal-particular and global-local in George Cheney et
al., “Encountering Communication Ethics in the Contemporary World: Principles, People, and
Contexts,” in The Handbook of Communication Ethics, ed. George Cheney, Steve May, and
Debashish Munshi (New York: Routledge, 2011), 4–7.
9. Immanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. H. J. Paton (New
York: Harper & Row, 1964).
10. Albert R. Jonsen and Stephen Toulmin, The Abuse of Casuistry: A History of Moral
Reasoning (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1990), see especially chapter 1, 13,
16–17.
11. Babrow, “Uncertainty, Value, Communication”; Babrow, “Problematic Integration The-
ory.”
12. For example, labels for criminal and beneficent acts; see Hilary Putnam, “The Entangle-
ment of Fact and Value,” The Collapse of the Fact-Value Dichotomy and Other Essays (Cam-
bridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2004), 28–45.
13. See Michael J. Hyde, “Ethics, Rhetoric, and Discourse,” in The Handbook of Communi-
cation Ethics, ed. George Cheney, Steve May, and Debashish Munshi (New York: Routledge,
2011): 31–44; W. Barnett Pearce, Communication and the Human Condition (Carbondale, IL:
Southern Illinois University Press, 1989).
148 Austin S. Babrow and Lindsey M. Rose
14. Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2nd ed., trans. Joel Weinsheimer and Donald
G. Marshall (London: Continuum, 2004).
15. Also see Austin S. Babrow, “Using Problematic Integration Theory, a Perspective on
Communication and Human Suffering, to Promote Dialogue Across Spiritual and Other World
Views” (paper presented at the annual meeting of the National Communication Association,
Chicago, 2007).
16. One way to appreciate the latter issue is by analogy to the cross-contextuality of “knowl-
edge”: value relativism is like the condition of having no long-term memory. Each moment is a
new context, each encounter unlike any before. Experiencing the world in this way is profound-
ly debilitating. See Oliver Sacks, The Man Who Mistook His Wife for a Hat (New York:
Touchstone, 1998).
17. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, chapter 9; Hyde, “Ethics, Rhetoric, and Discourse”;
Chaїm Perelman and L. Olbrechts-Tyteca, The New Rhetoric: A Treatise on Argumentation
(South Bend, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1969).
18. Sally Planalp and Julie Fitness, “Interpersonal Communication Ethics,” in The Hand-
book of Communication Ethics, ed. George Cheney, Steve May, and Debashish Munshi (New
York: Routledge, 2011).
19. Leslie A. Baxter and Barbara M. Montgomery, Relating: Dialogues and Dialectics
(New York: Guilford, 1996); Sandra Petronio, Boundaries of Privacy: Dialectics of Disclosure
(Albany: SUNY Press, 2002); William K. Rawlins, Friendship Matters: Communication, Di-
alectics, and the Life Course (New York: Aldine De Gruyter, 1992).
20. Arnett, Fritz, and Bell, Communication Ethics Literacy, 119–33.
21. Ibid., 126.
22. Rawlins, Compass.
23. Arnett, Fritz, and Bell, Communication Ethics Literacy, 123–26.
24. Rawlins, “Embracing Ethical,” 27.
25. Arnett, Fritz, and Bell, Communication Ethics Literacy.
26. Arnett, Fritz, and Bell, Communication Ethics Literacy; Rawlins, Compass.
27. Rawlins, “Embracing Ethical,” 175–76.
28. For further discussion of the co-construction of ethics and cosmopolitanism, also see K.
Anthony Appiah, Cosmopolitanism (New York: W. W. Norton & Company, 2006); Pearce,
Communication.
29. George Cheney, Steve May, and Debashish Munshi, eds., The Handbook of Communi-
cation Ethics (New York: Routledge, 2011).
30. Emphasis in original; Rawlins, “Embracing Ethical,” 176.
31. See also Rawlins, Friendship.
32. The scene’s power is enhanced by its contrast with a twilight baseball game in the
background. America’s wholesome pastime is thus juxtaposed with what are abhorrent and
surely criminal acts.
33. There are also inversions in Mike’s story: the irredeemable is saved through genuine
repentance (but more on this below); the brutal enforcer of U.S. border-crossing policy must
himself cross the border into Mexico as a prisoner and return his victim to his homeland to be
saved.
34. Rawlins, “Embracing Ethical,” 176–77.
35. Emphasis in original; Ibid., 177.
36. Ibid., 177.
37. Also see Martin Buber, I and Thou, trans. Walter Kaufmann (New York: Touchstone,
1971); Gregory J. Shepherd, “Communication as Transcendence,” in Communication As Per-
spectives on Theory, ed. Gregory Shepherd, Jeffrey St. John, and Ted Striphas (Thousand Oaks,
CA: Sage, 2006), 22–30.
38. Arnett, Fritz, and Bell, Communication Ethics Literacy; Emmanuel Levinas, Totality
and Infinity (Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press, 1969).
39. Elva T. Hart, Barefoot Heart: Stories of a Migrant Child (Tempe, AZ: Bilingual Review
Press, 1999).
40. Woody Guthrie, music by Martin Hoffman, “Deportee” (also known as “Plane wreck at
Los Gatos”), The Official Woody Guthrie Website (Woody Guthrie Publications, Inc. and The
The Ethical Challenges of Friendship 149
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Aristotle. Metaphysics. Translated by W. David Ross. The Internet Classics Archive, 1994.
classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/metaphysics.html.
———. Nicomachean Ethics. Translated by W. David Ross. New York: Oxford University
Press, 2009.
Arnett, Ronald C., Janie M. Harden Fritz, and Leeanne M. Bell Communication Ethics Litera-
cy: Dialogue and Difference. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage, 2008.
Arriaga, Guillermo. The Three Burials of Melquiades Estrada. Directed by Tommy Lee Jones.
New York: Sony Classics, 2005. DVD.
Babrow, Austin S. “Communication and Problematic Integration: Understanding Diverging
Probability and Value, Ambiguity, Ambivalence, and Impossibility.” Communication Theo-
ry 2, no. 1 (1992): 95–130.
———. “Communication and Problematic Integration: Milan Kundera’s ‘Lost Letters.’ in The
Book of Laughter and Forgetting.” Communication Monographs 62, no. 2 (1995): 283–300.
———. “Uncertainty, Value, Communication, and Problematic Integration.” Journal of Com-
munication 51, no. 3 (2001): 553–73.
———. “Problematic Integration Theory.” In Explaining Communication: Contemporary The-
ories and Exemplars, edited by Brian B. Whaley and Wendy Samter, 181–200. Mahwah,
NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum, 2007.
150 Austin S. Babrow and Lindsey M. Rose
Resolutions of Regret
The Other in the Evolution of a State Apology for Slavery
John B. Hatch
In 2007, 141 years after slavery was abolished through the ratification of
the Thirteenth Amendment, Virginia led four Southern states in passing reso-
lutions to apologize for slavery. 2 These resolutions constituted a decisive
turnaround from the widespread rejection of a one-sentence slavery apology
resolution proposed at the national level by U.S. Representative Tony Hall a
decade earlier. 3 Apparently, the times had changed. Indeed, the Maryland
resolution claimed, “It is time . . . to acknowledge the role the State played in
maintaining the institution of slavery and its attendant evils.” 4 But how, the
rhetorical analyst must wonder, did it finally become time (kairos) to ac-
knowledge the evils of an institution that ended more than a century ago—
and what are we to make of these collective resolutions of regret? Through
the lens of contemporary apologia theory, such apologies typically are
viewed as devices for damage control or crisis management, responses to the
exigence of a marred public image or degraded reputation—in short, a rheto-
ric of (self-)defense. However, despite the perennial utility and prolific pro-
ductivity of this ever-expanding generic tradition, apologia offers too myop-
ic a view of these resolutions in two respects. First, it assumes a relatively
clear and present crisis of image that requires damage control or defense in
the courts of public opinion; yet no such exigence is apparent in the case of
the state slavery resolutions. Second, apologia per se too readily margi-
153
154 John B. Hatch
The potential shift from Self to Other at the center of apology invites rhetori-
cal critics to shift the balance of attention from ontology (effects) to axiology
(ethics). In Race and Reconciliation, I characterize public reconciliation
apologies as a kind of epideictic performance, enacting and producing re-
deemed character (ethos), restoring integrity between avowed communal val-
ues and actual practices by denigrating the wrongful actions, taking respon-
sibility for them, and paying due respect to those who have been wronged. 21
Thus, the values that need to be restored in practice among the parties to an
apology are the standards against which its strategic rhetorical choices ought
to be measured. Certainly, an “apology” bearing signs that its core aim is
self-defense or restoring the image of the represented party may be read as a
pseudo-apology (apologia masquerading as apology). However, even an
apology that is “genuine” (in its conscious intention) may fall short of that
aim by failing to adequately address one or more value that has been violated
and needs restoration. By what values, then, might recipients of apologies for
egregious offenses judge the adequacy of such apologies as speech acts of
would-be restoration? How should critics assess such apologies?
Hearit and Borden identify the following ethical standards by which to
judge apologetic discourse: truthfulness, sincerity, timeliness, voluntariness,
inclusiveness (addressing all stakeholders), and contextual appropriateness. 22
This list is particularly apropos to Hearit’s focus on crisis management cases.
However, in rhetorical efforts to reconcile groups divided by a historical
legacy of oppressive and dehumanizing actions, other values come into focus
as well. In my study of popular and scholarly reconciliation discourse, I
identified the following “tetrad” of broad, polysemic values (or value-con-
stellations) that recur in tension, controversy, and conversation: truth, agen-
cy, justice, and peace. 23 These appear to be constitutive values—an ethical
grammar of reconciliation—that must together motivate a reconciling apolo-
gy if it is to be fully satisfactory in the long run. 24 Each value pertains
especially to one of four rhetorical thrusts in an historical apology. That is,
recipients expect such apologies to (1) reflect and produce a thoroughly
truthful acknowledgment of history, (2) honor their agency through proper
recognition of their wronged ancestors and acknowledgment of their voices
in the present, (3) offer a just atonement that regrets and corrects old wrongs,
158 John B. Hatch
and (4) reconcile their relationship in a way that engenders substantial peace
(which entails a sense of well-being in community and ultimately depends on
truth, justice, and inclusive agency—as in the Hebrew notion of shalom).
Each of these four values constitutes a desired good (or aim) in reconcili-
ation; each of them may also frame its project rhetorically. Drawing upon the
work of Kenneth Burke and Northrop Frye, 25 I have argued that apologies,
forgiveness, and other constituents of reconciliation may be framed realisti-
cally (or “ironically” in Frye’s parlance), romantically, tragically, or com-
ically. 26 While a realistic orientation treats truth about history and present
circumstances as the consummate value to pursue, the romantic sees the
moral exigence of conflict primarily through a desire to promote heroic agen-
cy (the power of free choice and creative action transcending circum-
stances). 27 Moreover, while the tragic frame measures actions against inflex-
ible standards of justice or universal rights that govern human interaction, the
comic apprehends and values a harmonious oneness or interconnectedness of
(human) beings, which belies their misguided enmity and cruelty toward one
another and warrants peace. 28
Although the four value-constellations—truth (factuality, historicity, sin-
cerity, and so on), agency (responsibility, freedom, grace, etc.), justice (fair-
ness, right, law), and peace (unity, harmony, civility, and the like)—frequent-
ly come to be at odds in the wake of a serious violation, on closer examina-
tion, they are interdependent and each intrinsic to the common good in soci-
ety. 29 Ethically coherent apologies, then, should attend to all four values and
be informed by each; reconciliation is as much a project of knitting together
disparately framed narratives as it is a matter of bringing together parties in a
kind of relational healing. 30 For example, reconciliation in the fullest sense
transforms a tragic view of injustice (measured against laws or principles)
into a tragicomic understanding, in which injustice is as much the harming of
concrete persons with whom one is humanly connected as it is a violation of
abstract rights. 31 Like the restorative justice movement, reconciliation re-
places a fixation on offenders’ guilt or innocence and potential punishment
with a focus on victims’ needs for acknowledgment of harm (by offenders)
and negotiated restitution to repair the harm. 32 That being the case, reconcili-
ation calls for an apology that attends to the harms suffered by the offended
party more than an apologia for the damaged or threatened image of the
offenders.
Combining this tetrad of values with the triad of personal/relational en-
tities that an apology may restore, we have a sevenfold set of ends by which
to judge the ethics of a historical, collective apology. It would be more
accurate, however, to combine them multiplicatively, as there are three pri-
mary subjects/agents to which—and from whose perspective—each of the
four values may be applied: self, Other, and relationship. I have previously
gestured in this direction, arguing that the parties to past injuries and con-
Resolutions of Regret 159
past and move on”; “forgive and forget”), an ethically coherent apology
honors any constructive, conciliatory expressions of agency shown by the
victims/survivors—as a gracious gift. 38 Such recognition provides a kind of
symbolic justice since it restores the intrinsic human dignity of those whose
social dignity was formerly stripped away: it not only acknowledges their
victimization but also recognizes their survival—indeed, their triumph—as
moral agents.
elective office.” 48 Here Virginia is a heroic agent of liberty and equality, first
by propagating these ideals and then by affirming them in practice. Clearly,
then, image restoration is one of the goals toward which the apology aims. If
the white-supremacist Virginia of bygone days was guilty of crimes against
African Americans, those crimes are a departure from its true self: a leading
agent of liberty and equality.
That the resolution thus uses bolstering as a strategy to restore Virginia’s
image is no news; indeed, it is par for both commemoration and apologia.
Rather, what renders the resolution morally and rhetorically significant is
that the preponderance of its content recalls actions contrary to Virginia’s
espoused ideals and frames these actions in tragic terms as flagrant viola-
tions of universal principles. This is a significant move for a legislative body
addressing its past. While public apology has recently come into vogue in the
United States as a way for individuals and organizations to address their
failures and wrongful actions (as many observers have noted), 49 the domi-
nant individualism and present-future orientation of American culture have
presented a formidable barrier to apologizing for collective actions by past
generations, particularly so historically distant a transgression as slavery.
Virginia partly breaks through this barrier by rendering judgment on its pat-
tern of oppression and discrimination toward African Americans (and Native
Americans, who were added to the resolution after the House received the
Senate-approved version).
Since the second Whereas clause celebrates Virginia’s seminal role in
American democracy, the stage now needs to be set for denigrating Virgin-
ia’s sins. The third clause does this by rehearsing the principles that its most
celebrated son, Thomas Jefferson, is famed for declaring: human equality
and the “‘unalienable rights’” to “‘life, liberty, and the pursuit of happi-
ness.’” 50 Then, the fourth Whereas clause turns to the tragic truth: “despite
the ‘self-evident’ character of these fundamental principles, the moral stan-
dards of liberty and equality have been transgressed during much of Virgin-
ia’s and America’s history.” The next clause, in turn, names the transgres-
sions (“the maltreatment and exploitation of Native Americans and the im-
moral institution of human slavery”) and characterizes them in tragic terms
as “directly antithetical to and irreconcilable with the fundamental principles
of human equality and freedom.” 51
One would now expect some recounting of these offenses; however, the
resolution here pivots from collective Self (the state of Virginia) to the first
Others who were wronged: Native Americans. Virginia recognizes them as
the first Americans and honors them as agents, over the course of four
Whereas clauses. The resolution recalls their early encounters with the
Jamestown settlers, their kindness in providing them food and then aiding
their survival over the first winter, and later Native American leaders’ dili-
gent efforts “to preserve and protect their heritage, history, and culture,” even
164 John B. Hatch
predominantly white state. Admittedly, it does leave the door wide open to
read this symbolic act, at bottom, as apologia in the service of image restora-
tion. It would be more precise, however, to characterize the resolution as
embodying a rhetorical dance of deferral that its African American sponsors
found necessary to disarm white colleagues’ resistance and edge Virginia
toward becoming the first state to officially apologize (in some form) for
slavery.
Yamazaki contends that apologies aimed at reconciliation require negoti-
ation among apologists and recipients. 63 Villadsen shows that rhetorical
agency in representative apologies is problematized by the uncertainty and
complexity of audience mandate among those represented. 64 Virginia’s slav-
ery resolution exhibits both complications. The General Assembly purport-
edly represents all of Virginia’s citizens; through its black and other minority
members, it represents diverse peoples as well. It was the white majority of
the past that perpetrated atrocities against Virginia’s politically and socially
disempowered minorities; it is their descendents, if anyone, who should ten-
der an apology. Yet white representatives’ agency to speak on direct behalf
of those descendants is diluted by the large numbers of white constituents
who disclaim collective or trans-generational responsibility, particularly
those whose ancestors immigrated after abolition or even after segregation.
Nonetheless, the General Assembly itself can coherently apologize to
African Americans (and Native Americans), for it was the laws of Virginia
that kept race-based slavery and segregation in force; the Virginia govern-
ment, and especially its legislature, is an enduring body that bears definitive
responsibility for the oppressions of the past. Yet that Assembly now consists
of blacks as well as whites, and it was blacks who introduced the apology
resolution into the Senate and House (potent support for Yamazaki’s claim
that an apology’s recipient may, in fact, act as its “co-producer”). 65
That is why this resolution cannot be treated primarily as image-restora-
tion rhetoric. While it does incorporate image restoration for the tacit white
majority (the collective political agent of Virginia’s past oppressions), it also
embodies a distinct, irreducible aim toward recognition of, and reconciliation
with, the Other who was oppressed. Like the Truth and Reconciliation Com-
mission in South Africa, 66 Virginia’s apology resolution is a product of polit-
ical compromise, expressing ugly truths and seeking to promote reconcilia-
tion while still making concessions to a white majority. Below, I examine
that compromise more closely, albeit indirectly, by comparing the final ver-
sion of the resolution (discussed above) with the original Senate-approved
version (submitted by Senator Marsh) and the substitute version written by
Representative O’Bannon for the House.
Resolutions of Regret 167
despite the acute hardship, conflict, cruelty, and oppression that characterized
those first encounters and interactions, Virginians of native, European, and
African descent persevered and made indispensible contributions to the survi-
val of the colony, the founding of our good Commonwealth and nation, and
the forging of our national character and culture. 69
for it. In its twelfth Whereas clause, Marsh and McEachin’s version accus-
ingly laments:
Furthermore, in its sixteenth Whereas clause, the original version warns that
“the story of the enslavement of Africans and their descendants, the human
carnage, and the dehumanizing atrocities committed during slavery should
not be purged from Virginia’s history or discounted.” 77 Thus, the original
thoroughly conveys a victim’s passion for truth, acknowledgment, and ac-
countability on the part of the perpetrator, as well as the fear that the heirs of
past oppression would gladly forget or deny the history of their wrongdoing
in a comic-romantic rush to a guilt-free future unhindered by debts from the
past. (This concern proved to be justified, as Delegate Frank Hargrove re-
sponded to the proposed resolution by saying that blacks needed to “get
over” slavery.) 78 By contrast, the final version—a product of negotiation
between those who do prefer to leave the past behind and those whose vision
is fixed on it (as well as legislators at points in between)—heads off these
accusations and warnings by simply doing the right thing: acknowledging
“with profound regret” the wrongs of the past and calling for ongoing re-
membrance both of the “dehumanizing atrocities” and the definitively human
contributions made by those who were so oppressed. 79
At the same time that the legislators “do the right thing” in this regard,
their resolution thoroughly dilutes a significant implication of Marsh and
McEachin’s version: a need for reparation to the descendants of African
American slaves (i.e., material restoration for the Other). Without calling for
reparation directly, the original version establishes warrants for it by citing
the economics of slavery and racism and their effects up to the present: “The
Atlantic slave trade was a lucrative enterprise, and African slaves, a prized
commodity to support the economic base of plantations in the colonies;”
“after emancipation . . . African Americans soon saw the political, social, and
economic gains they made during Reconstruction dissipated by virulent and
rabid racism;” and “the vestiges of slavery are ever before African American
citizens.” 80 We have seen that this version refers to the broken promise of
“40 acres and a mule” and originally stated that Virginia’s legislators “hereby
atone for” slavery (a word taken by opponents to signify reparation). 81 The
potential demand for reparations is the specter that has haunted slavery apol-
ogies ever since Tony Hall introduced his resolution in 1997 and President
Resolutions of Regret 171
against black people occupied their full attention and buried any impulse to
bolster the state’s image by praising its ideals or its achievements in propa-
gating those ideals. Thus, their resolutions are purer exemplars of the collec-
tive, historical reconciliation apology. 90 For instance, rather than tying the
timing of its acknowledgment to a commemorative occasion, the Maryland
resolution simply states that “it is time” to acknowledge its role in slav-
ery 91—implying that it is high time to attend to the yawning gap between its
espoused values and its historical practices. The North Carolina and Alabama
apologies not only retain this relative purity of focus and aim but also greatly
magnify the historical litany of slavery and its legacy, describing both in
much greater detail. North Carolina even broaches the A-word, daring to say
that it apologizes to African Americans, literally.
These facts, I would argue, indicate a de facto shift from image restora-
tion to Other restoration as the primary task—the center of gravity—of the
slavery apology. Before the pendulum of a state’s epideictic discourse on
race can come to a relative rest at reconciliation between parties, it must
swing from self-regarding commemoration to Other-regarding acknowledg-
ment. Apologizing is a necessary, but not sufficient, element in this discourse
of reconciliation. Its effectuality for reconciliation depends on an ongoing
willingness to engage the Other in meaningful dialogue concerning further
acknowledgments that may be needed, reparations that would most meaning-
fully lend substance to the apology and redress the injustice, 92 and conditions
that may facilitate forgiveness. In response to the successful passage of the
Maryland resolution he sponsored, Senator Nathaniel Exum spoke of his
desire to promote racial reconciliation and commented: “‘I hope this leads to
some dialogue, because that’s what we really need.’” 93 When Florida issued
its own slavery apology early in 2008, its white Republican governor, Char-
lie Crist, made a more daring (and surprising) comment—suggesting that his
state should consider offering reparations to African Americans. 94 Both of
these statements indicate awareness that an apology is only one move in a
negotiated, open process of healing and restoration. Apologies go awry, how-
ever, when they present reconciliation as a virtually foregone conclusion. As
we have seen, the House Committee version of Virginia’s apology almost
assumed reconciliation by presenting a comic portrayal of multicultural to-
getherness (and shared suffering/oppression) at Jamestown. The final resolu-
tion emerged as a compromise between this version (grounded in a misty
myth of origins) and the original version, which recounted the original sin of
slavery in stark historical detail.
Nonetheless, just as Virginia bears the distinction of being the first Eng-
lish colony, with the first permanent English settlement in North America, it
also gained the distinction of being the first state to apologize for slavery. In
that sense, Virginia’s resolution may be the most important apology for
slavery in the United States 95—capturing and combining America’s dispar-
174 John B. Hatch
NOTES
1. Acknowledging with Profound Regret the Involuntary Servitude of Africans and the
Exploitation of Native Americans, and Calling for Reconciliation among All Virginians, S J
Res. 332 [ER], 2007 Va. Gen. Assem., leg1.state.va.us/cgi-bin/legp504.exe?071+ful+
SJ332ER.
2. The other states that passed resolutions in 2007 are Maryland, North Carolina, and
Alabama. Arkansas’s Legislative Council, which oversees state government between legisla-
tive sessions, also passed a resolution.
3. See John B. Hatch, “Reconciliation: Building a Bridge from Complicity to Coherence in
the Rhetoric of Race Relations,” Rhetoric & Public Affairs 6 (2003).
4. A Senate Joint Resolution Concerning Slavery in Maryland, S J Res. 6, 2007 Md. Gen.
Assem., mgaleg.maryland.gov.
5. North Carolina was an exception in that a prominent white legislator (Senate Majority
Leader Tony Rand) introduced its resolution. See Lynn Bonner and Benjamin Niolet, “Senator
Proposes Slavery Apology; Rands Resolution Gains Swift Support,” News & Observer, April
4, 2007, A1.
6. John B. Hatch, “Beyond Apologia: Racial Reconciliation and Apologies for Slavery,”
Western Journal of Communication 70 (2006); Jason A. Edwards, “Community-Focused Apo-
logia in International Affairs: Japanese Prime Minister Tomiichi Murayama's Apology,” Ho-
ward Journal of Communications 16 (2005); Jason A. Edwards, “Apologizing for the Past for a
Better Future: Collective Apologies in the United States, Australia, and Canada,” Southern
Communication Journal 17 (2010); Jane W. Yamazaki, “Crafting the Apology: Japanese Apol-
ogies to South Korea in 1990,” Asian Journal of Communication 14 (2004); Keith Michael
Resolutions of Regret 175
lor University Press, 2007); Robert C. Rowland and John M. Jones, “Recasting the American
Dream and American Politics: Barack Obama’s Keynote Address to the 2004 Democratic
National Convention,” Quarterly Journal of Speech 93 (2007).
28. See Burke, Attitudes, 4–5, 37–43, 166–75; Barry Brummett, “Burkean Comedy and
Tragedy, Illustrated in Reactions to the Arrest of John Delorean,” Central States Speech Jour-
nal 35 (1984).
29. See Hatch, Race and Reconciliation, 136–41.
30. Ibid.
31. Hatch, “Reconciliation.”
32. For a brief explication of the concept of restorative justice by one of its seminal theo-
rists, see Howard Zehr, “Restorative Justice: The Concept,” Corrections Today, December
1997. For a more in-depth examination, see Howard Zehr, Changing Lenses: A New Focus for
Crime and Justice (Scottsdale, PA: Herald Press, 1990). The work of South Africa’s Truth and
Reconciliation Commission was premised on restorative justice principles: see Elizabeth Kiss,
“Moral Ambition within and Beyond Political Constraints: Reflections on Restorative Justice,”
in Truth v. Justice: The Morality of Truth Commissions, ed. Robert I. Rotberg and Dennis
Thompson (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2000).
33. Hatch, Race and Reconciliation, 153–54. For a detailed discussion of the social-psycho-
logical effects of victimization and how they influence perceptions of ethical exigencies in
reconciliation, see also pp. 95–98.
34. Ibid.
35. Robert D. Enright, Suzanne Freedman, and Julio Rique, “The Psychology of Interper-
sonal Forgiveness,” in Exploring Forgiveness, ed. Robert D. Enright and Joanna North (Madi-
son: University of Wisconsin Press, 1998), 53–54.
36. For an outstanding treatment of what makes for morally coherent and effective (victim-
healing and relationship-reconciling) apologies, see Aaron Lazare, On Apology (New York:
Oxford University Press, 2004).
37. In other words, forgiveness is a choice that victims may make when they are ready, a
choice that should be healing and empowering for the victim; it is a gift, not an obligation owed
to an offender (even if the offender is repentant). See Robert D. Enright, Forgiveness Is a
Choice: A Step-by-Step Process for Resolving Anger and Restoring Hope (Washington, DC:
APA LifeTools, 2001); Everett L. Worthington Jr., “The Pyramid Model of Forgiveness: Some
Interdisciplinary Speculations about Unforgiveness and the Promotion of Forgiveness,” in
Dimensions of Forgiveness: Psychological Research & Theological Perspectives, ed. Everett
L. Worthington Jr. (Philadelphia: Templeton Foundation Press, 1998).
38. Such honoring is richly exemplified in Hall’s 1999 apology for slavery in West Africa;
see Hatch, “Beyond Apologia.”
39. For example, after the passage of Maryland’s apology, its black sponsor, Senator Na-
thaniel Exum said, “‘I hope this leads to some dialogue, because that’s what we really need. . . .
This is just a start.’” On introducing the resolution, Exum had admitted that he would have
preferred to pursue reparations, but was “being practical” given the unpopularity of the idea.
Kelly Brewington, “‘Profound Regret’: House of Delegates Passes Resolution Acknowledging
State’s Part in Slavery,” Baltimore Sun, March 27, 2007; Jill Rosen, “Slavery: African-
Americans in Maryland and Elsewhere Are Seeking a Formal Apology for Its Painful Legacy,”
Baltimore Sun, February 25, 2007: F1.
40. Atoning for the Involuntary Servitude of Africans and Calling for Reconciliation among
All Virginians, S J Res. 332, 2007 Va. Gen. Assem., leg1.state.va.us/cgi-bin/legp504.exe?071+
ful+SJ332; Jenny Jarvie, “Formal Slavery Apologies Debated,” Los Angeles Times, March 19,
2007: A7.
41. Atoning for the Involuntary Servitude.
42. Tyler Whitley, “Slavery Apology Language Altered: ‘Contrition’ Replaces ‘Atone’;
Potential for Reparations Is Issue,” Richmond Times-Dispatch, January 30, 2007.
43. Acknowledging the Contributions of Varied Races and Cultures to the Character of the
Commonwealth of Virginia, and Expressing Profound Regret for Slavery and Other Historic
Wrongs, S J Res. 332 [H1]: Amendment in the nature of a substitute, 2007 Va. Gen. Assem.,
leg1.state.va.us/cgi-bin/legp504.exe?071+ful+SJ332H1.
Resolutions of Regret 177
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Alabama Legislature. Apologizing for the Wrongs of Slavery; Expressing Profound Regret for
Alabama's Role in Slavery; and Expressing Intent That This Resolution Shall Not Be Used
in, or Be the Basis of, Any Type of Litigation. H J Res. 321. 2007 Ala. Legis. www.
legislature.state.al.us/Searchableinstruments/2007RS/Resolutions/HJR321.htm.
Resolutions of Regret 179
Benoit, William L. Accounts, Excuses, and Apologies: A Theory of Image Restoration Strate-
gies. SUNY Series in Speech Communication. Albany: State University of New York Press,
1995.
Benoit, William L. “Another Visit to the Theory of Image Restoration Strategies,” Communica-
tion Quarterly 48 (2000): 40–44.
Bonner, Lynn, and Benjamin Niolet. “Senator Proposes Slavery Apology; Rands Resolution
Gains Swift Support.” News & Observer, April 4, 2007, A1.
Brewington, Kelly. “‘Profound Regret’: House of Delegates Passes Resolution Acknowledging
State’s Part in Slavery.” Baltimore Sun, March 27, 2007.
Brooks, Roy L. “The Age of Apology.” In When Sorry Isn't Enough: The Controversy over
Apologies and Reparations for Human Injustice, edited by Roy L. Brooks, 3–11. New York:
New York University Press, 1999.
———. Atonement and Forgiveness: A New Model for Black Reparations. Berkeley: Univer-
sity of California Press, 2004.
Brophy, Alfred L. Reparations: Pro and Con. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006.
Brummett, Barry. “Burkean Comedy and Tragedy, Illustrated in Reactions to the Arrest of John
Delorean.” Central States Speech Journal 35 (1984): 217–27.
Burke, Kenneth. Attitudes Toward History. 3d ed. Berkeley: University of California Press,
1984.
———. A Grammar of Motives. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1969.
———. Permanence and Change: An Anatomy of Purpose. 3rd ed. Berkeley: University of
California Press, 1984.
———. The Rhetoric of Religion: Studies in Logology. Berkeley: University of California
Press, 1970.
“Clinton Opposes Slavery Apology.” In When Sorry Isn't Enough: The Controversy over
Apologies and Reparations for Human Injustice, edited by Roy L. Brooks, 352. New York:
New York University Press, 1999.
Doxtader, Erik. “Making Rhetorical History in a Time of Transition: The Occasion, Constitu-
tion, and Representation of South African Reconciliation.” Rhetoric & Public Affairs 4
(2001): 223–60.
Edwards, Jason A. “Apologizing for the Past for a Better Future: Collective Apologies in the
United States, Australia, and Canada.” Southern Communication Journal 17 (2010): 57–75.
———. “Community-Focused Apologia in International Affairs: Japanese Prime Minister To-
miichi Murayama's Apology.” Howard Journal of Communications 16 (2005): 317–36.
Enright, Robert D. Forgiveness Is a Choice: A Step-by-Step Process for Resolving Anger and
Restoring Hope. Washington, DC: APA LifeTools, 2001.
Enright, Robert D., Suzanne Freedman, and Julio Rique. “The Psychology of Interpersonal
Forgiveness.” In Exploring Forgiveness, edited by Robert D. Enright and Joanna North,
53–54. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1998.
Frye, Northrop. Anatomy of Criticism: Four Essays. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press,
1957.
Gibson, Bob. “Lawmakers Pass Roads, Slavery Bills.” Daily Progress, February 5, 2007.
———. “Slavery Resolution Rewritten: Committee Passes Statement of ‘Regret.’” Clover
Herald, February 1, 2007.
Hafenbrack, Josh, and John Kennedy. “Florida Legislature Makes Formal Apology for Slav-
ery.” South Florida Sun-Sentinel.com, March 26, 2008.
Hall, Tony P. “Defense of Congressional Resolution Apologizing for Slavery.” In When Sorry
Isn’t Enough: The Controversy over Apologies and Reparations for Human Injustice, edited
by Roy L. Brooks, 350–51. New York: New York University Press, 2003.
Hatch, John B. “Beyond Apologia: Racial Reconciliation and Apologies for Slavery.” Western
Journal of Communication 70 (2006): 186–211.
———. Race and Reconciliation: Redressing Wounds of Injustice. Lanham, MD: Lexington,
2008.
———. “Reconciliation: Building a Bridge from Complicity to Coherence in the Rhetoric of
Race Relations.” Rhetoric & Public Affairs 6 (2003): 739–66.
180 John B. Hatch
Yamazaki, Jane W. “Crafting the Apology: Japanese Apologies to South Korea in 1990.” Asian
Journal of Communication 14 (2004): 156–73.
———. “The Failure of Japanese Apologies for World War II.” International and Intercultural
Communication Annual 27 (2004): 169–90.
Zehr, Howard. Changing Lenses: A New Focus for Crime and Justice. Scottsdale, PA: Herald
Press, 1990.
———. “Restorative Justice: The Concept.” Corrections Today, December 1997, 68–70.
Chapter Nine
Lester C. Olson
183
184 Lester C. Olson
superior pretensions with wit, wry humor, and, at times, grace, by mirroring
them symbolically in the homosexual character of George, who sometimes
mischievously reverses them against his interlocutors.
George’s character is suffused with what Joan Didion describes in her
classic 1961 essay “On Self-Respect” as a “certain toughness, a kind of
moral verve.” Self-respect should not be confused with convictions concern-
ing one’s own merits nor even self-esteem. Rather, self-respect, as Didion
describes it, entails a mindfulness of one’s frailties and limitations as well as
strengths and potential. “People with self-respect have the courage of their
mistakes,” she explains, adding that “they display what was once called
character.” Didion notes, “The dismal fact is that self-respect has nothing to
do with the approval of others—who are, after all, deceived easily enough;
has nothing to do with reputation, which, as Rhett Butler told Scarlett
O’Hara, is something people with courage can do without.” Didion sum-
marizes, “To have that sense of one’s intrinsic worth which constitutes self-
respect is potentially to have everything: the ability to discriminate, to love
and to remain indifferent.” On the other hand, Didion observes, “If we do not
respect ourselves, we are . . . forced to despise those who have so few
resources as to consort with us, so little perception as to remain blind to our
fatal weaknesses.” 3 During the 1960s and 1970s, a self-respecting homosex-
ual would have been an oxymoron or a performative contradiction to most
readers because of commonplace stigmas attending homosexuality—stigmas
imposed by religion as sinful, by legal systems as criminal, and by psycho-
logical institutions as pathological. This central oxymoron animates
George’s transgressions against public heterosexuality.
Today, in 2013, at least thirty-five years after Isherwood wrote that mem-
orable line on a paper scrap, possibly to be tossed away, his naming of a
“heterosexual dictatorship” could still be considered an accurate character-
ization of the predominant political circumstances confronting gay men in
the United States, where I have written this chapter concerning Isherwood’s
original novel, A Single Man (published in 1964), a theatrical performance of
it (produced in 1990), and Tom Ford’s film ostensibly “based on” it (pro-
duced in 2009). The contours of heterosexism and homophobia have changed
during the intervening decades, most notably with regard to state-level legis-
lation concerning both nondiscrimination and bias crime laws as well as an
increasing acceptance of same-sex marriage. In 1964, there were no such
laws anywhere in the United States for homosexuals. Only as recently as
2009 has the federal government enacted bias crime laws, however, and it
has yet to enact nondiscrimination laws in employment. These political
circumstances make precarious the lives of homosexuals. Isherwood’s ap-
proach in the novel was not merely a reaction pressing back against the
heterosexual dictatorship, but rather a firm, gentle affirmation of the homo-
Public Memory of Christopher Isherwood’s Novel, A Single Man 185
sexual’s life despite it. The overall spirit of the work is to assert a homosexu-
al presence in a life-affirming way despite oppressive, hostile conditions.
In this chapter, I must risk offending public heterosexuality as an inherit-
ed hegemonic ideology with all of its diversity, while endeavoring to expli-
cate the powerful rhetoricity of Isherwood’s brilliant novel because it ex-
poses, ridicules, and mocks this ideology with wry, sardonic, and merciless
humor. In other words, I must negotiate recurring rhetorical problems of
communicating about an acknowledged literary masterpiece in gay history
and culture under the watchful eyes, or surveillance, of the very ideology that
Isherwood confronted via his novel at a time when its contours were even
more severe than they are today, however still oppressive and sadistically
cruel. So I should mention the capacity of public heterosexuality to project its
own hostility onto gay authors in ways that can trivialize the work, as exem-
plified by one contemporaneous reviewer’s shallow commentary that Isher-
wood’s portrait of the Strunks demonstrates his dislike of people, even
though George eventually demonstrates a model of compassion for Mrs.
Strunk, so apparently lacking in her self-serving performances toward him.
So permit me to ask, as a gay scholar living under this “heterosexual dictator-
ship,” whose disgraceful misrepresentations of homosexuals in film was ex-
tensively documented in The Celluloid Closet in 1987, 4 what does it mean
when an apparently well-intentioned homosexual filmmaker does our ene-
mies’ work for them by reproducing damaging stereotypes and other con-
tours of heterosexism and homophobia? Who profits in what specific ways
from the film ostensibly based on A Single Man?
Although the popular 2009 film version of A Single Man suggests that it
was based on the original 1964 novel with the same title by Christopher
Isherwood, the film, almost a half century later, does consequential symbolic
violence to Isherwood’s achievement in the novel in ways that constitute a
false and potentially harmful memory of it. While I do not doubt that the
filmmaker presented his work as an homage to Isherwood’s novel, such
rhetorical recognition is what makes the film’s symbolic violence, in Pierre
Bourdieu’s sense, appear legitimate, however insidious on inspection. 5 Spe-
cifically, the film introduces invidious stereotypes of homosexual men that
do not appear anywhere in the novel and that Isherwood was careful to avoid
in his literary works, as exemplified by A Single Man. Arguably, it was
precisely Isherwood’s endeavor to portray a life-affirming homosexuality
that diminished his novel’s appeal for popular audiences beyond a diverse
gay readership, who have tended to recognize his novel as a brilliant literary
achievement, as indeed it is. It could be argued, moreover, that the film
detracts from Isherwood’s artistic legacy in a way that falsely represents his
work and defames his literary sensibility. Yet the Gay and Lesbian Alliance
Against Defamation recognized the film with a national award. The recurring
homage by homosexuals makes the symbolic violence, which consequential-
186 Lester C. Olson
want to center on the rhetoricity of each work by noticing how key revisions
during adaptation of the novel into a film constructed a fundamentally differ-
ent set of rhetorical appeals to active audiences. Isherwood’s novel was not
written to please public heterosexuality, but rather to embarrass it for its not-
necessarily-deliberate cruelties and foibles, much to the pleasure of its pre-
dominantly homosexual readership. In contrast, the film was directed more
broadly to a diffuse audience whose members are called upon regardless of
sexuality to engage “a love story” across consequential social differences as
somehow universal to humankind. 15 To be sure, certain components of the
original novel do this, too, dealing as all these works do with aging, mortal-
ity, anger, love, and compassion.
To explore the rhetoricity of these works, I focus primarily on their com-
municative relationships to diverse audiences by asking, for example, What
specific rhetorical techniques do these works employ to play on their audi-
ences’ sensibilities? How do each of these works position their audiences as
spectators, witnesses to, and vicarious participants in the narrative action?
What sorts of potential critical responses, attitudes, and personal engage-
ments—both thoughtful and affective—do these works endeavor to elicit
from diverse audiences? Let me begin with my experience of the novel as a
brilliant literary achievement before turning to a theatrical rendition and then
the recent film to explore how differences among them could warrant my
concerns about the film’s retrograde politics and its exploitation of a usable
past, however exceptional the acting by Colin Firth, Matthew Goode, and
Nicholas Hoult and however beautiful the cinematography. In the conclu-
sion, I speculate on how to interpret the recent revisionist uses of the novel as
public memory by moving beyond a simple factor of profit, which surely
mattered for addressing a broad range of contemporary audiences, to contem-
plate the film’s specific cultural, ideological treatment of a mis-usable past.
Why, I wonder, do so many contemporary commentaries from gay, lesbian,
and queer viewers applaud the 2009 film, given what I will argue are its
serious failings vis-à-vis the 1964 novel?
I first encountered Isherwood’s novel, A Single Man, twenty years after its
initial 1964 publication in London and New York. So, I cannot render an
account of how, as a reader, I experienced it at the time of its initial release in
1964. I would have been nine years old, ancient though I now appear to my
students. However, in late winter 1984, while I was a graduate student, I read
Isherwood’s novel for the first time on a flight returning from a research trip
to London. As Isherwood’s biographer, Peter Parker, explains, “George,” the
central character, is “a single man in the legal sense that he is unmarried, in
Public Memory of Christopher Isherwood’s Novel, A Single Man 189
geles Times in 1964 with the demeaning title, “Disjointed Limp Wrist Saga.”
Hubler uses words like “retchings” [sic] and “resentment” to describe
George’s inner life and “perverted lebensraum” for his expectations. Hubler
characterizes the “defense mechanism built up for the homosexual” as being
“both feeble and disgusting.” He describes Isherwood’s literary stature as
“virtually invisible” and his writing as “little more than competent.” 36
Experienced homosexuals might know that when public heterosexuality
endeavors in such sustained, hostile ways to trivialize an author’s literary
work, as did Jacobs, Bradbury, and Hubler, it is possible that the novel is
doing something exceptionally well. Such hostile commentaries serve as a
testament today to Isherwood’s courage. In Isherwood’s novel, George is
projecting his precise perceptions of public heterosexuality’s self-serving
delusions back onto the ideology, making its pervasive commonplaces and
failings both evident and public, not his self-loathing. It could be argued
perhaps that George evades genuine intimacy or friendship with his neigh-
bors by not expressing his disagreeable views directly to them, unwilling to
risk conflict. Instead, he carefully contains them beneath his generally stoic,
amiable exterior and ironic detachment. George does not confront them via
parrhēsia by speaking his truth to their power. 37 Rather, for survival, he only
engages them with politeness while challenging them internally though a rich
and self-sustaining inward life. In other words, an interpretation that George
evades intimacy and enacts hypocrisy would be simplistic in underestimating
the cruel power of the “heterosexual dictatorship” within which George has
learned to live and survive, because direct confrontation more often than not
results in heterosexuals’ misuses of privilege and power to retreat behind a
fragile facade of guilt, hurt feelings, and defensiveness, if not much worse.
It is tempting to suggest that A Single Man is powerful, in part, because it
gives access to what could be considered one early 1960s homosexual man’s
double consciousness, an expression first articulated by W. E. B. DuBois in
The Souls of Black Folk in 1907 and thus usually associated specifically with
the racial oppression of black people in the United States. Yet the idea of
double consciousness has been developed and extended by many intellectu-
als from minority communities. “Double consciousness,” as James Darsey
notes, “implies a complexity of vision, the necessity for members of subordi-
nate subcultures always to know the rules of the dominant culture as well as
of their subculture.” 38 George’s thoughts shift between specific views that he
ascribes to public heterosexuality and his own critical engagement with this
ideology, between the public rules for civility and his annoyances because of
them.
Alternatively, perhaps George’s sensibility might be called subjugated
knowledge, an expression advanced by Michel Foucault, whose second sense
of subjugated knowledge defines it as “a whole set of knowledges that have
been disqualified as inadequate to their task or insufficiently elaborated:
Public Memory of Christopher Isherwood’s Novel, A Single Man 193
naïve knowledges, located low down on the hierarchy, beneath the required
level of cognition or scientificity.” He adds, “it is through the re-appearance
of this knowledge, of these local popular knowledges, these disqualified
knowledges, that criticism performs its work.” Yet George’s inner knowl-
edge is that of a homosexual professor, whose views as a college teacher are
not disqualified, as evidenced by his lively classroom interactions with stu-
dents. But his views as a homosexual could be dismissed inasmuch as they
are not adapted to public heterosexuality—he is unapologetic, rebellious, and
spirited in his defiance. 39 In this regard, there might be an odd, rough parallel
with the life of Foucault, whose works are oftentimes celebrated and evoked
critically as a result, in part, of his professorial prestige, usually without any
mention of his homosexuality, which was surely a vital fount for his rich
insights. Yet Foucault made few public comments concerning his homosexu-
ality, characterizing it euphemistically in public as “friendship as a way of
life,” as in his 1981 interview. 40
George’s stance is not so much passive alienation as it is an active dis-
identification from public heterosexuality, 41 or an ongoing, internalized in-
surrection against it informed by his subordinated knowledge of public
heterosexuality and its perils for himself and, laterally, for others who are
similarly situated within the dictatorship. In other words, because Isher-
wood’s novel was addressed to a predominantly homosexual readership in
the 1960s and 1970s, George’s inner life is not merely fulfilling an ego-
function directed only to himself to sustain himself, 42 as a sort of silent
protest rhetoric. More fundamentally, through George’s character, Isherwood
offered his audiences a perspective on political and social oppression that he
shared with others within an oftentimes vilified, criminalized, and patholo-
gized minority. In the 1960s and 1970s, a diverse homosexual readership was
invited to participate vicariously in George’s comprehension of his oppres-
sive situation, his skillful negotiation of it, and his anger.
A few years later, in late summer 1990, I was back in London for another
research trip. I learned that A Single Man was being performed as a play at a
theater located on the outskirts of London. As I used mass transit to travel to
the performance in Greenwich Theatre at Croons Hill, London, I pondered
how A Single Man could be staged, since so much of its potency depends on
accessing George’s inner life, the privileged audience’s vantage so vital to
the comic frame. According to Burke, “The comic frame should enable peo-
ple to be observers of themselves, while acting. Its ultimate would not be
passiveness, but maximum consciousness.” 43 As Isherwood expressed it, the
limited omniscient narrator’s voice is that of George’s “Id, or by God. It
194 Lester C. Olson
knows things about him which he does not know.” 44 Throughout the novel,
this vantage provides the audience with access to George’s resilient sensibil-
ity, especially his anger of a specific variety that is only possible for a man
with confidence in his own intrinsic worth, or what Didion describes as “self-
respect.” 45
Part of what I love about George, in fact, is his anger suffused with his
self-respect and his mindfulness of its perils. With incisive wit and merciless
humor, he rants, he fumes, he seethes in response to heterosexism and the
rampant consumer capitalism of his time (e.g., see 36–38, 83), and I love him
for it. His outrage extends even to the college or university as a clean “mod-
ern factory.” As another instance, a bemused George ponders a local news-
paper editor’s campaign against “sex deviants,” like George: “They are eve-
rywhere, he says; you can’t go into a bar any more, or a men’s room, or a
public library, without seeing hideous sights. And they all, without excep-
tion, have syphilis” (36). Today, of course, they would all have HIV-AIDS.
George punctures inherited stereotypes that homosexual means diseased or
pathological. In Isherwood’s novel, a sustained target for laughter and
wicked humor consists of the worries, fears, and delusions of public hetero-
sexuality as projected onto homosexuals, not George.
Throughout the novel, George enacts in his musings varied symbolic
reversals suggesting tacitly, in the process, that homosexuals can live moral
and fulfilling and spiritual lives, 46 despite the perils of public heterosexual-
ity’s narcissism, superficiality, and psychological dysfunctions, which
George notices sometimes with evident pleasure. In other words, George
gives back to public heterosexuality for its ownership some demeaning
stereotypes projected so routinely and ruthlessly onto homosexual men, rec-
ognized as scapegoats for public heterosexuality’s failings. Isherwood under-
stood something about the dominant group’s capacity for authoritarian pro-
jectivity and its sometimes cruel misuses for others. Instead of characterizing
such conduct as evil or sadistic, however, he eviscerated it with bemused
insight and various symbolic reversals rendering the stereotypes not only
ludicrous but also revelatory of the profoundly mistaken views he firmly
ascribed to public heterosexuality. In a symbolic reversal, which mirrored
public heterosexuality’s tolerance of homosexuality, George reflects, “Not
that one isn’t broad-minded, of course; let them write about heterosexuality if
they must, and let everyone read it who cares to. Just the same, it is a deadly
bore and, to be frank, a wee bit distasteful” (85). Substitute the word homo-
sexuality for heterosexuality in George’s archly ironic thought and the ex-
pression becomes a familiar commonplace in liberal tolerance, which George
mirrors to mock it. Such symbolic reversals of public heterosexuals’ tolerant
attitudes, in aside after delightfully naughty aside, endear George to a homo-
sexual readership weary of heterosexism and homophobia. I will illustrate
and support this claim concerning George’s reversals and mirroring more
Public Memory of Christopher Isherwood’s Novel, A Single Man 195
Think of two people, living together day after day, year after year, in this small
space, standing elbow to elbow cooking at the same small stove, squeezing
past each other on the narrow stairs, shaving in front of the same small bath-
room mirror, constantly jogging, jostling, bumping against each other’s bodies
by mistake or on purpose, sensually, aggressively, awkwardly, impatiently, in
rage or in love—think what deep though invisible tracks they must leave,
everywhere, behind them! (12)
While I was researching this chapter, I learned that Alec McCowen, who
played George, viewed his performance as his coming out play and that his
partner, Geoffrey Burridge, had died a few years earlier in 1987 from com-
plications of AIDS.
As I sat in the theater after that performance, I experienced a poignant
realization that, in my mid-thirties, I had for the first time in my life experi-
enced a respectful play centering on a homosexual man’s life. George was
not rendered in a way that reproduced any convenient, demeaning stereo-
196 Lester C. Olson
types for homosexual men so commonplace in public life at that time and
even now. I cannot express now how powerful—both upsetting and mean-
ingful—that realization was for me. The audience does not laugh at George
as clown-like or ineffectual (as in Tea and Sympathy, Some Like It Hot,
Vanishing Point, or Birdcage). George is neither deranged nor psychologi-
cally dysfunctional (as in Rebecca, Rope, Suddenly Last Summer, or A Beau-
tiful Mind). George is not isolated and almost totally without friendship (as in
Brokeback Mountain). Nor does George tragically end his own life by sui-
cide (as in Advise and Consent, Victim, or The Children’s Hour). The ending
of George’s life is not a sadistically cruel murder in ways that are so formula-
ic and apparently gratifying to public heterosexuality, to judge from myriad
films and novels that pander to the ideology (as in Rebel Without a Cause,
Walk on the Wild Side, The Detective, Freebie and the Bean, and especially
Cruising). George is neither hypersexualized and amoral (like Brian in Queer
as Folk) nor nearly devoid of any evident sexuality (like Will in Will &
Grace). The novel and the play both consist simply of one mundane day of
George’s life while he was grieving the loss of his partner, taking stock of
what it means to face midlife suddenly alone, but with friends, and, ultimate-
ly, in moments, rekindling his capacity for renewed sexuality and possibly a
new love.
Later, as I learned more about Isherwood’s life and works, I came to
appreciate that this firm refusal of familiar stereotypes was almost certainly
deliberate on his part. In 1947, Isherwood wrote a letter to Gore Vidal criti-
cizing the manuscript’s conclusion of The City and the Pillar, written in 1946
and published in January 1948, for its tragic ending in which the homosexual
character suffers greatly. The original version of Vidal’s novel ends catas-
trophically with a homosexual murder of a former lover. Isherwood’s entire
December 19, 1947, letter to Vidal deserves to be read, but here I will note
that Isherwood pressed firmly on the matter of the political ramifications of
literary representations as “propaganda” and the potential harms from repro-
ducing demeaning stereotypes of homosexuals to gratify mainstream audi-
ences. Then, having endeavored to raise Vidal’s consciousness concerning
the disconcerting ramifications of his novel’s formulaic conclusion, Isher-
wood asserts: “Homosexual relationships can be and frequently are happy.
Men live together for years and make homes and share their lives and their
work, just as heterosexuals do. This truth is particularly disturbing and
shocking even to ‘liberal’ people, because it cuts across the romantic, tragic
notion of a homosexual’s fate.” 51 Having criticized Vidal’s work, Isherwood
adds, “I am really lecturing myself, because I, too, have been guilty of
subscribing to the Tragic Homosexual myth in the past, and I am ashamed of
it.” 52
In light of this correspondence, it is noteworthy that Isherwood dedicated
A Single Man to Vidal, which Vidal reciprocated later with a dedication to
Public Memory of Christopher Isherwood’s Novel, A Single Man 197
detail of literature, as though fidelity or, more generally, being true to the
spirit of the work, is of paramount importance. It is possible to consider each
work for its own artistic merits, or lack thereof. However, if there is a depar-
ture from the literary work in the process of translating it into film as a
medium with its distinctive resources (a process that Tom Gunning refers to
as “textual transformations”), 59 presumably it would be for the purpose of
strengthening rather than diminishing a literary work’s achievement. Gun-
ning details several components of this process of “textual transformations,”
which I elide here in the interest of concentrating, above all, on character,
narrative, and framing.
Filmgoers likewise have artistic latitude for appreciation of the producers’
sometimes disappointing efforts with great literature. Dudley Andrew ob-
serves, “Fidelity is the umbilical cord that nourishes the judgments of ordi-
nary viewers as they comment on what are effectively aesthetic and moral
values. . . . If we tuned in on these discussions, we might find ourselves
listening to a vernacular version of comparative media semiotics.” 60 As one
such ordinary viewer, I was so dissatisfied with the film ostensibly based on
A Single Man that, after the initial viewing, a hapless friend who had gone to
see it with me found himself discussing it with me over dinner for more than
an hour and a half. He thought the film was wonderful. In contrast, I recog-
nized it as a travesty. So, our dialog was heartfelt and sustained. Though my
friend is almost a decade older than me, he had not read Isherwood’s novel
(despite my having made a gift to him of one of my few cherished, hardback,
first editions). So, I infer that part of the differences in our engagements with
the film had to do with expectations for the film insofar as they were in-
formed by having read the novel or not. But I do not believe that factor
accounts entirely for the differences in our critical commentary on the film.
Certainly, it is accurate that the acting in the film was exceptional, the cine-
matography was aesthetically pleasing, and the leading men were sensuous
and handsome.
Yet both the character of George and the narrative were deeply disturbing
as rendered in the film when juxtaposed with the novel. There is no reason to
believe that George in the novel is in the closet, though he apparently is in
the film. In the novel, George does not linger over a female secretary’s
perfume appreciatively, as he does in the film. More important, George’s
relationship to Charlotte, who goes by Charley, is friendship, not a frustrated
heterosexual romance (as rendered at too much length in the film in ways
that astute critics have accurately characterized as having “de-gayed” the
novel). The film’s promotional materials—both the initial poster and the
trailers—featured George’s relationship, not to Jim, but to Charley. Peter
Knegt observes, “While the heterosexualized poster for Tom Ford’s not-so-
heterosexual ‘A Single Man’ caused a wee stir last week, it seems the recent-
ly released trailer has just re-enforced those complaints.” 61 Ben Walters,
Public Memory of Christopher Isherwood’s Novel, A Single Man 199
whose review encapsulates several discrepancies between the novel and the
film, notes that “this is not Isherwood’s Charley, though it might be some-
thing like how she would fantasize about her life.” 62 Among other discrepan-
cies, Walters notes George’s palatial home (“a capacious modernist construc-
tion, by the architect John Lautner”), which Andrew Holleran has likewise
described as a significant change: “In Isherwood’s novel, the house George
inhabits with Jim is so small two people cannot enter the kitchen side by side;
in the movie he lives in something out of Architectural Digest and drives a
beautiful Mercedes.” 63
In the novel, moreover, readers encounter George’s anger at the arrogant
narcissism that public heterosexuals sometimes bring to their interactions
with self-respecting homosexuals, exemplified by George’s neighbors, Mr.
and Mrs. Strunk, each of whom represents a different strand of liberal toler-
ance for the homosexual. Mr. Strunk, in George’s imaginings, “tries to nail
him down with a word. Queer, he doubtless growls. But, since this is after all
the year 1962, even he may be expected to add, I don’t give a damn what he
does just as long as he stays away from me” (27). After lingering over what
psychologists might make of such a remark, George mischievously savors “a
photograph” of a youthful Mr. Strunk in his football uniform, when he “used
to be what many would call a living doll” (27). In contrast, Mrs. Strunk’s
self-serving beneficence concerning what she views as his pitiable homosex-
uality triggers George’s well warranted, yet bemused rage, intensified and
suffused by his grieving (see 27–29). As George sees it, “she is trained in the
new tolerance, the technique of annihilation by blandness. Out comes her
psychology book—bell and candle are no longer necessary” (27). George
incisively caricatures Mrs. Strunk’s affectation of acceptance, which is sel-
dom more than a fragile facade: “Here we have the misfit, debarred forever
from the best things in life, to be pitied, not blamed . . . it’s so sad; especially
when it happens, as let’s face it[,] it does, to truly worthwhile people, people
who might have had so much to offer” (28).
In the novel, George believes Mrs. Strunk to be a hypocrite, who elevates
her own worth by diminishing his. The reader has no available resources to
size up the accuracy of George’s perceptions, while in the film, in contrast,
he is so emotionally unstable that viewers are likely to align themselves with
her heartfelt concerns for his well-being. In the novel, George continues at
some length to inhabit a worldview that he ascribes to Mrs. Struck to mock
her liberal tolerance via his naughty ventriloquism of her: “Let us even go so
far as to say that this kind of relationship can sometimes be almost beauti-
ful—particularly if one of the parties is already dead, or, better yet, both”
(28). Ultimately, George muses defiantly, “Your exorcism has failed, dear
Mrs. Strunk. . . . The unspeakable is still here—right in your very midst”
(29). At least one book reviewer misunderstood Isherwood’s critique of Mr.
and Mrs. Strunk’s liberal tolerance. In a 1964 review by Sir Thomas Willes
200 Lester C. Olson
ocean and is nearly pulled by an undertow into its depths, and, through it all,
experiences a mutually flirtatious reawakening of his capacity for sexual
desire and possibly love. George becomes momentarily vulnerable. These
scenes in the film are among the most powerful and sensually portrayed,
rendering both Kenny’s apparently ready availability for sex and George’s
struggles with his temptations, which he restrains with evident reflection and
sensible effort. It is one of the few, well-rendered erotic moments in the film,
made more powerful by the intricate interplay of taboos, stemming from their
roles as teacher and student, as well as the intergenerational chasm separating
them, plus the nakedness and frank homosexual attraction.
instead, on his merely personal, individual crisis. Even the beauty of the
scenic cinematography mitigates George’s recognition of his bleak predica-
ment, specifically as a homosexual, though it is possible that the contrast
heightens differences between his emotional state and the landscape.
It is as though the film decapitated the novel by reducing George to his
handsome surfaces and excising most of his interior life. The filmmaker’s
endeavor to universalize a love story is consequently more vulnerable than
was the novel to Richard Jacobs’s criticism about making the political mere-
ly personal. It should be acknowledged that Isherwood was also somewhat
concerned that his novel not be treated simply as a gay novel. But rather than
universalize it, he sought to shape the novel to represent a life predicament of
minorities within an ostensibly democratic culture, whose practical politics
with a tyranny of the majority were de facto dictatorships for racial minor-
ities, Jews, and homosexuals. 77 It is precisely that position, as severely op-
pressed, that the film’s universalization of a love story erases, to its detri-
ment.
More generally, what does it mean today that so many of the finest gay
novels, not only Isherwood’s A Single Man but also James Baldwin’s Gio-
vanni’s Room and E. M. Forester’s Maurice, were written before Stonewall
in 1968, which is routinely represented in queer histories today as the wa-
tershed moment in gay liberation struggles? How could it be even remotely
plausible that a watershed of sea-changing proportions could have happened
only after such landmark literary achievements? Does this observation sug-
gest anything about atemporality as well as the virtual absence of a historical
and cultural sensibility among recent generations? Might viewers be suscep-
tible to misrepresentations of a past because educational systems have done a
poor job of familiarizing people of diverse sexualities with an inclusive and
accurate history—not only of literature, but of diverse lives? Would faulting
the audiences be simplistic and misplaced criticism?
As a possibly related matter, why has there been—with the few excep-
tions usually written by gay men of my generation or the one before mine—
such a general outpouring of enthusiasm within diverse queer communities
for the film “based on” A Single Man? 78 What does it mean that the Gay and
Lesbian Alliance Against Defamation has recognized the film with an award,
when the film may well detract from the reputation of an accomplished gay
author? 79 Should self-respecting gay men and our apparent allies applaud a
film that, as I have suggested, may have done our enemies’ work for them?
Should we applaud a film that has transformed a brilliant literary achieve-
ment in 1964 into a series of demeaning stereotypes and formulaic narrative
techniques almost fifty years later in 2009?
These are difficult, unpleasant questions to consider even briefly—be-
cause I believe enthusiasm for the film may reveal something disconcerting
about public memory loss and what, in a playful rephrasing of a now popular
206 Lester C. Olson
NOTES
3. Joan Didion, “On Self-Respect,” in Slouching Towards Bethlehem (New York: Simon &
Schuster, 1968), 142–48, quotations on 145, 143, and 147; the essay was originally published
in 1961 in Vogue.
4. Vito Russo, The Celluloid Closet: Homosexuality in the Movies, rev. ed. (New York:
Harper & Row, 1987), which became the basis for a documentary, The Celluloid Closet (Cul-
ver City, CA: Columbia TriStar Home Video, 2001).
5. On symbolic violence, see Pierre Bourdieu, Language & Symbolic Power (Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 1991); John B. Thompson, “Symbolic Violence,” Studies in the
Theory of Ideology, 42–72.
6. For a sample of germane rhetoric scholarship on public memory, see Kendall Phillips’s
Framing Public Memory (Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press, 2008); Stephen Howard
Browne, “Reading, Rhetoric, and the Texture of Public Memory,” Quarterly Journal of Speech
81, no. 2 (1995): 237–50; Greg Dickinson, “Memories for Sale: Nostalgia and the Construction
of Identity in Old Pasadena,” Quarterly Journal of Speech 83, no. 1 (1997): 1–27; Bradford
Vivian, “Neoliberal Epideictic: Rhetorical Form and Commemorative Politics on September
11, 2002,” Quarterly Journal of Speech 92, no. 1 (2006): 1–26; Thomas R. Dunn, “Remember-
ing Matthew Shepard: Violence, Identity, and Queer Counterpublic Memories,” Rhetoric &
Public Affairs 13, no. 4 (2010): 611–52; Brent Allen Saindon “A Doubled Heterotopia: Shifting
Spatial and Visual Symbolism in the Jewish Museum Berlin’s Development,” Quarterly Jour-
nal of Speech 98, no. 1 (2012): 24–48.
7. Andrew Holleran, “The Sloth of Sadness,” Gay and Lesbian Review Worldwide 17, no.
2 (2010): 48–49; Ben Walters, “The Trouble with Perfume,” Film Quarterly 63, no. 4 (2010):
14–17.
8. Kenneth Burke, “Comic Correctives,” in Attitudes Toward History, 3rd ed. (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1937, reprinted 1959 and 1984), 166–75.
9. For a concise commentary on the comic frame, see Anne Theresa Demo, “The Guerrilla
Girls’ Comic Politics of Subversion,” Women’s Studies in Communication 23, no. 2 (2000):
133–57; reprinted in Lester C. Olson, Cara A. Finnegan, and Diane S. Hope, Visual Rhetoric: A
Reader in Communication and American Culture (Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage, 2008): 241–56,
quotation on 242; Adrienne E. Christiansen and Jeremy J. Hanson, “Comedy as a Cure for
Tragedy: Act Up and the Rhetoric of AIDS,” Quarterly Journal of Speech 82, no. 2 (1996):
157–70.
10. Colin MacCabe, “Introduction,” in Colin MacCabe, Kathleen Murray, and Rick Warner,
eds., True to the Spirit: Film Adaptation and the Question of Fidelity (New York: Oxford
University Press, 2011), 8.
11. I touch on this critical practice in Lester C. Olson, “Concerning Judgment in Criticism of
Rhetoric,” Review of Communication 12, no. 3 (2012): 251–56, though analogs can be drawn
among works that are not adaptations, as is the case in the instance of the novel and film based
on A Single Man.
12. Christopher Isherwood, A Single Man (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1964), 27.
13. Edward J. Ingebretsen, “Monster-Making: A Politics of Persuasion,” Journal of
American Culture 21, no. 2 (1998): 25–34, quotations on 25 and 29. Thanks to Thomas R.
Dunn for calling my attention to this essay many years ago.
14. On realism in cinema studies, especially in André Bazin, see Daniel Morgan, “Rethink-
ing Bazin: Ontology and Realist Aesthetics,” Critical Inquiry 32, no. 3 (2006): 443–81.
15. Gregg Shapiro, “A Singular Man: Tom Ford Talks to the B.A.R. [Bay Area Reporter],”
Bay Area Reporter, Dec. 24, 2009. www.ebar.com/arts/art_article.php?sec=film&article=704.
16. Parker, Isherwood, 623.
17. David Garnes, “A Single Man, Then and Now,” in The Isherwood Century: Essays on
the Life and Work of Christopher Isherwood, ed. James J. Berg and Chris Freeman, foreword
Armistead Maupin (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 2000), 196–202, quotations on
196 and 198.
18. Edmund White, “Tale of Two Kitties” [Review of Peter Parker’s biography], Times
Literary Supplement (London), June 4, 2004, Issue 5279, pg. 3; quoted in James J. Berg,
“Introduction,” Isherwood on Writing: Christopher Isherwood, ed. James J. Berg (Minneapo-
208 Lester C. Olson
lis: University of Minnesota Press, 2007), 27. Edmund White, “A Love Tormented but Trium-
phant,” New York Times Book Review, Dec. 12, 2010, p. 15.
19. White, “Tale of Two Kitties,” 3.
20. Carolyn G. Heilbrun, Christopher Isherwood (New York: Columbia University Press,
1970), 13.
21. John Lehmann, Christopher Isherwood: A Personal Memoir (New York: Holt, 1987),
102 and 103.
22. Isherwood, as quoted in Berg and Freeman, see interview with Winston Leyland,
“Christopher Isherwood Interview [1973],” in Conversations, 107, xiv, similarly 66 and 87.
23. James J. Berg with Chris Freeman, “Isherwood the Multiculturalist,” Chronicle of High-
er Education 56, no. 18 (2010): B13–15.
24. Berg and Freeman, see interview with Derek Hart, “A Fortunate, Happy Life [An inter-
view of Isherwood in 1970]” in Conversations, 54.
25. Berg and Freeman, see interview with Winston Leyland, “Christopher Isherwood Inter-
view [1973],” in Conversations, 107. On this matter, see also Berg, “Introduction,” Isherwood
on Writing, 8.
26. For instance, see White, “A Love Tormented,” 15.
27. Lehmann, Christopher Isherwood, 102–3.
28. Holleran, “The Sloth of Sadness,” 48.
29. The lowest assessment that I am aware of was at number 33 of 100 by Triangle Publish-
ing, “The 100 Best Lesbian and Gay Novels,” www.publishingtriangle.org/100best.asp. This
ranking was published in the June 22, 1999, issue of The Advocate and has been widely
circulated by numerous outlets. I recall, but cannot locate, an earlier assessment in the top 6
along with James Baldwin’s Giovanni’s Room.
30. Mary Vaughan Cuddon, “Tragi-comic Tale of a Saint and Sinner,” Catholic Herald,
Nov. 27, 1964, 6. The reviewer does not even list the book’s title among those considered in the
review.
31. Richard Jacobs, Penguin History of Literature (London: Penguin, 1994), 7: 240; quoted
by Berg in Isherwood on Writing, 16.
32. Berg, Isherwood on Writing, 17.
33. Jacobs, Penguin History, 7: 242–43. Both comments by Jacobs and Berg are in Berg,
Isherwood on Writing, 17.
34. Malcolm Bradbury, The Modern British Novel (London: Secker & Warburg, 1993), 232.
35. Both comments by Bradbury and Berg are in Berg, Isherwood on Writing, 18.
36. Richard G. Hubler, “Disjointed Limp Wrist Saga,” Los Angeles Times, Aug. 2, 1964,
B15.
37. Michel Foucault explores parrhēsia in The Courage of Truth, ed. Frédérick Gros, trans.
Graham Burchell (New York: Palgrave MacMillan, 2011).
38. James Darsey, “‘The Voice of Exile’: W. E. B. DuBois and the Quest for Culture,” in
Rhetoric and Community: Studies in Unity and Fragmentation, ed. J. Michael Hogan (Colum-
bia: University of South Carolina Press, 1998), 93–110, quotation on 97.
39. Michel Foucault, Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings,
1972–1977, ed. Colin Gordon (New York: Pantheon, 1980), 78–108, quotations on 82.
40. Michel Foucault, “Friendship as a Way of Life,” in The Essential Works of Foucault
1954–1984, Volume One—Ethics: Subjectivity and Truth, ed. Paul Rabinow, trans. Robert
Hurley (New York: The New Press, 1997), 135–40.
41. Krista Ratcliffe explores dis-identification, a concept that she ascribes to Diana Fuss, in
Rhetorical Listening: Identification, Gender, Whiteness (Carbondale: Southern Illinois Univer-
sity Press, 2005), see especially 48, 53, and 60–66.
42. Richard B. Gregg, “The Ego-Function of the Rhetoric of Protest,” Philosophy & Rheto-
ric 4, no. 2 (1971): 71–91.
43. Burke, “Comic Correctives,” 171.
44. Christopher Isherwood as quoted in Parker, Isherwood, 618.
45. Didion, “On Self-Respect.”
46. With regard to spirituality, Victor Marsh claims that “Isherwood theorised [sic] the
writing of religion in his essay ‘The Problem of the Religious Novel’, yet it is in the least
Public Memory of Christopher Isherwood’s Novel, A Single Man 209
overtly religious text, A Single Man, where the influence of his training in the Ramakrishna
Vedanta tradition is seamlessly integrated.” See Victor Marsh, “On ‘The Problem of the Relig-
ious Novel’: Christopher Isherwood and A Single Man,” Literature & Theology 24, no. 4
(2010): 378–96, quotation on 378. In contrast, S. Nagarajan has claimed that “A Single Man is
not a religious novel if we adopt the definition of such a novel provided by Isherwood himself
in his article on ‘The Problem of the Religious Novel.’ It gives us the portrait neither of the
saint nor of the saint-to-be” in “Christopher Isherwood and the Vedantic Novel: A Study of A
Single Man,” Ariel: A Review of International English Literature 3, no. 4 (1972): 63–71,
quotation on 70.
47. This was among Alan Collins’s misgivings, according to Parker, Isherwood, 633.
48. Chris Freeman, “Too Much Information!” Gay & Lesbian Review Worldwide 18, no. 2
(2011): 31.
49. Parker, Isherwood, 635.
50. The play, A Single Man, was adapted by Michael Michaelian and directed by Waris
Hussein for performance at the Greenwich Theatre at Grooms Hill, London, from June 21 to
August 4, 1990.
51. The letter from Isherwood to Vidal deserves to be read and can be found with commen-
tary in the biography by Parker, Isherwood, 500. I have silently corrected the version in Parker,
who wrote “Many men” instead of “Men,” though, in a way, his revision is accurate, too. A
somewhat shorter version can be found in Charles Kaiser, The Gay Metropolis, 1940–1996
(Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1997), 61–62. For Isherwood’s initial impressions of Vidal, whom
he had only recently met, see Christopher Isherwood, Diaries: Volume One, 1939–1960, ed.
Katherine Bucknell (New York: HarperCollins, 1996), 401. Thanks to Sue Hodson of the
Huntington Library for providing me with a photocopy of Isherwood’s letter and looking for a
reply to it from Vidal, November 30, 2012. Though Isherwood’s letter explicitly requested a
reply from Vidal, the collection of his papers at the Huntington does not hold one, nor does the
collection of Vidal’s papers at Harvard University.
52. Isherwood, as quoted in Parker, Isherwood, 500.
53. For Isherwood’s response to the dedication, see Fred Kaplan, Gore Vidal: A Biography
(New York: Doubleday, 1999), 584.
54. Ibid., 256.
55. Ibid., 276–77; also see Lehmann, Christopher Isherwood, 77.
56. Parker, Isherwood, 533; Christopher Isherwood, Christopher and His Kind, 1929–1939
(New York: Farrar, Straus, & Giroux, 1976), 127; Richard Canning, “Tomb with a View,” The
Gay & Lesbian Review Worldwide 16, no. 2 (2009): 10; Joshua Adair, “‘Christopher Wasn’t
Satisfied with Either Ending’: Connecting Christopher Isherwood’s The World in the Evening
to E. M. Forster’s Maurice,” Papers on Language & Literature 48, no. 3 (2012): 302–31,
especially 311–13.
57. Canning, “Tomb with a View,” 10.
58. There is a substantial body of scholarship on adaptation of novels into film. Particularly
useful is Colin MacCabe et al., eds., True to the Spirit, quotation on 3; Robert Stam and
Alessandra Raengo, eds., Literature and Film: A Guide to the Theory and Practice of Film
Adaptation (Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2005); James Naremore, ed., Film Adaptation (New
Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press, 2000). Thanks to Randall Halle and Jane Feuer for
recommending these resources to me.
59. Tom Gunning, “Literary Appropriation and Translation in Early Cinema,” in True to the
Spirit, 41–57, especially 42–43.
60. Dudley Andrew, “The Economies of Adaptation,” in True to the Spirit, 27–40, quotation
on 27.
61. See Peter Knegt, “A Tale of Two Trailers: The De-Gaying of ‘A Single Man,’” Indie-
wire, Nov. 9, 2009, www.indiewire.com/article/a_tale_of_two_trailers_the_de-gaying_of_a_
single_man.
62. Walters, “The Trouble with Perfume,” 15.
63. Ibid., 16; Holleran, “The Sloth of Sadness,” 49.
64. Sir Thomas Willes Chitty under a pseudonym, Thomas Hinde, “George and Jim,” Times
Literary Supplement (London), Sept. 10, 1964, Issue 3263, p. 837.
210 Lester C. Olson
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Adair, Joshua. “‘Christopher Wasn’t Satisfied with Either Ending’: Connecting Christopher
Isherwood’s The World in the Evening to E. M. Forster’s Maurice.” Papers on Language &
Literature 48, no. 3 (2012): 302–31.
Andrew, Dudley. “The Economies of Adaptation.” In True to the Spirit: Film Adaptation and
the Question of Fidelity, edited by Colin MacCabe, Kathleen Murray, and Rick Warner,
27–40. New York: Oxford University Press, 2011.
Berg, James J. “Introduction: The American Isherwood.” In Isherwood on Writing: Christo-
pher Isherwood, edited by James J. Berg, 1–33. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press, 2007.
Berg, James J., and Chris Freeman. Conversations with Christopher Isherwood. Jackson: Uni-
versity Press of Mississippi, 2001.
Berg, James J., with Chris Freeman. “Isherwood the Multiculturalist.” Chronicle of Higher
Education 56, no. 18 (Jan. 10, 2010): B13–15.
Bourdieu, Pierre. Language & Symbolic Power. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,
1991.
Bradbury, Malcolm. The Modern British Novel. London: Secker & Warburg, 1993.
Browne, Stephen Howard. “Reading, Rhetoric, and the Texture of Public Memory.” Quarterly
Journal of Speech 81, no. 2 (1995): 237–50.
Burke, Kenneth. “Comic Correctives,” in Attitudes Toward History, 3rd ed. Berkeley: Univer-
sity of California Press, 1937, reprinted 1959 and 1984.
Canning, Richard. “Tomb with a View.” Gay & Lesbian Review Worldwide 16, no. 2 (2009):
10.
The Celluloid Closet. VHS. Culver City, CA: Columbia TriStar Home Video, 2001.
Chitty, Sir Thomas Willes [Thomas Hinde, pseud.]. “George and Jim.” Times Literary Supple-
ment (London), Sept. 10, 1964, Issue 3263, 837.
Public Memory of Christopher Isherwood’s Novel, A Single Man 211
Christiansen, Adrienne E. and Jeremy J. Hanson. “Comedy as a Cure for Tragedy: Act Up and
the Rhetoric of AIDS.” Quarterly Journal of Speech 82, no. 2 (1996): 157–70.
Cuddon, Mary Vaughan. “Tragi-comic Tale of a Saint and Sinner.” Catholic Herald, Nov. 27,
1964, 6.
Dargis, Manohal. “A Love That Speaks Its Name: A College Professor’s Fateful Day.” New
York Times, Dec. 10, 2009, movies.nytimes.com/2009/12/11/movies/11singleman.html.
Darsey, James. “‘The Voice of Exile’: W. E. B. DuBois and the Quest for Culture.” In Rhetoric
and Community: Studies in Unity and Fragmentation, edited by J. Michael Hogan, 93–110.
Columbia: University of South Carolina Press, 1998.
Demo, Anne Theresa. “The Guerrilla Girls’ Comic Politics of Subversion.” Women’s Studies in
Communication 23, no. 2 (2000): 133–57.
Dickinson, Greg. “Memories for Sale: Nostalgia and the Construction of Identity in Old Pasa-
dena.” Quarterly Journal of Speech 83, no. 1 (1997): 1–27.
Didion, Joan. “On Self-Respect.” In Slouching Towards Bethlehem. New York: Simon &
Schuster, 1968.
Dunn, Thomas R. “Remembering Matthew Shepard: Violence, Identity, and Queer Counter-
public Memories.” Rhetoric & Public Affairs 13, no. 4 (2010): 611–52.
English, Tanya, ed. Cue: Greenwich Theatre. Croons Hill, London: [1990], issue 139.
Foucault, Michel. The Courage of Truth, edited by Frédérick Gros, translated by Graham
Burchell. New York: Palgrave MacMillan, 2011.
———. “Friendship As a Way of Life.” In The Essential Works of Foucault 1954–1984,
Volume One—Ethics: Subjectivity and Truth, edited by Paul Rabinow, translated by Robert
Hurley, 135–40. New York: The New Press, 1997.
———. Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings, 1972–1977, edited by
Colin Gordon, 78–108. New York: Pantheon, 1980.
Freeman, Chris. “Too Much Information!” Gay & Lesbian Review Worldwide 18, no. 2 (2011):
31.
Garnes, David. “A Single Man, Then and Now.” In The Isherwood Century: Essays on the Life
and Work of Christopher Isherwood, edited by James J. Berg and Chris Freeman, foreword
by Armistead Maupin, 196–202. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 2000.
Gregg, Richard B. “The Ego-Function of the Rhetoric of Protest.” Philosophy & Rhetoric 4, no.
2 (1971): 71–91.
Gunning, Tom. “Literary Appropriation and Translation in Early Cinema.” In True to the
Spirit: Film Adaptation and the Question of Fidelity, edited by Colin MacCabe, Kathleen
Murray, and Rick Warner, 41–57. New York: Oxford University Press, 2011.
Haramis, Nick. “Julianne Moore on the De-Gaying of ‘A Single Man.’” BlackBook, Feb. 3,
2010, www.blackbookmag.com/article/julianne-moore-on-the-de-gaying-of-a-single-man/
15773.
Heilbrun, Carolyn G. Christopher Isherwood. New York: Columbia University Press, 1970.
Holleran, Andrew Holleran. “The Sloth of Sadness.” Gay & Lesbian Review Worldwide 17, no.
2 (2010): 48–49.
Hubler, Richard G. “Disjointed Limp Wrist Saga.” Los Angeles Times, Aug. 2, 1964, B15.
Ingebretsen, Edward J. “Monster-Making: A Politics of Persuasion.” Journal of American
Culture 21, no. 2 (1998): 25–34.
Isherwood, Christopher. Christopher and His Kind, 1929–1939. New York: Farrar, Straus, &
Giroux, 1976.
———. Diaries: Volume One, 1939–1960, edited by Katherine Bucknell. New York: Harper-
Collins, 1996.
———. Kathleen and Frank. New York: Simon and Schuster, 1971.
———. A Single Man. New York: Simon & Schuster, 1964.
Jacobs, Richard. Penguin History of Literature. Vol. 7, The Twentieth Century. London: Pen-
guin, 1994.
Kaiser, Charles. The Gay Metropolis, 1940–1996. Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1997.
Kammen, Michael G. The Mystic Chords of Memory: The Transformation of Tradition in
American Culture. New York: Vintage, 1993.
Kaplan, Fred. Gore Vidal: A Biography. New York: Doubleday, 1999.
212 Lester C. Olson
Knegt, Peter. “A Tale of Two Trailers: The De-Gaying of ‘A Single Man.’” Indiewire, Nov. 9,
2009, www.indiewire.com/article/a_tale_of_two_trailers_the_de-gaying_of_a_single_man.
Lehmann, John. Christopher Isherwood: A Personal Memoir. New York: Holt, 1987.
MacCabe, Colin. “Introduction.” In True to the Spirit: Film Adaptation and the Question of
Fidelity, edited by Colin MacCabe, Kathleen Murray, and Rick Warner, 3–25. New York:
Oxford University Press, 2011.
Marsh, Victor. “On ‘The Problem of the Religious Novel’: Christopher Isherwood and A Single
Man.” Literature & Theology 24, no. 4 (2010): 378–96.
Morgan, Daniel. “Rethinking Bazin: Ontology and Realist Aesthetics.” Critical Inquiry 32, no.
3 (2006): 443–81.
Nagarajan, S. “Christopher Isherwood and the Vedantic Novel: A Study of A Single Man.”
Ariel: A Review Of International English Literature 3, no. 4 (1972): 63–71.
Naremore, James, ed. Film Adaptation. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press, 2000.
Olson, Lester C. “Concerning Judgment in Criticism of Rhetoric.” Review of Communication
12, no. 3 (2012): 251–56.
Olson, Lester C., Cara A. Finnegan, and Diane S. Hope. Visual Rhetoric: A Reader in Commu-
nication and American Culture. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage, 2008.
“The 100 Best Lesbian and Gay Novels.” Triangle Publishing. www.publishingtriangle.org/
100best.asp.
Parker, Peter. Isherwood: A Life Revealed. New York: Random House, 2004.
Phillips, Kendall, ed. Framing Public Memory. Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press,
2008.
Ratcliffe, Krista. Rhetorical Listening: Identification, Gender, Whiteness. Carbondale: South-
ern Illinois University Press, 2005.
Russo, Vito. The Celluloid Closet: Homosexuality in the Movies. Revised ed. New York:
Harper & Row, 1987.
Saindon, Brent Allen. “A Doubled Heterotopia: Shifting Spatial and Visual Symbolism in the
Jewish Museum Berlin’s Development.” Quarterly Journal of Speech 98, no. 1 (2012):
24–48.
Shapiro, Gregg. “A Singular Man: Tom Ford Talks to the B.A.R. [Bay Area Reporter].” Bay
Area Reporter, Dec. 24, 2009. www.ebar.com/arts/art_article.php?sec=film&article=704.
“A Single Man.” Wikipedia. en.wikipedia.org/wiki/A_Single_Man.
Stam, Robert and Alessandra Raengo, eds. Literature and Film: A Guide to the Theory and
Practice of Film Adaptation. Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2005.
Thompson, John B. Studies in the Theory of Ideology. Berkeley: University of California Press,
1984.
“21st Annual GLAAD Media Awards (2010)—English Language Nominees.” GLAAD.org.
www.glaad.org/mediaawards/21/nominees.
Vivian, Bradford. “Neoliberal Epideictic: Rhetorical Form and Commemorative Politics on
September 11, 2002.” Quarterly Journal of Speech 92, no. 1 (2006): 1–26.
Walters, Ben. “The Trouble with Perfume.” Film Quarterly 63, no. 4 (2010): 14–17.
White, Edmund. “A Love Tormented but Triumphant.” New York Times Book Review, Dec. 12,
2010, 15.
———. “Tale of Two Kitties” [Review of Peter Parker’s biography]. Times Literary Supple-
ment (London), June 4, 2004, Issue 5279, 3.
III
Organization as Other
Professional Civility as Communicative
Care for Institutions
215
216 Janie M. Harden Fritz
ing and promoting the local home 26 as a place hosting productivity generated
by the persons who participate in the work of the organization. 27 Care for
institutions involves a recognition of the organization as Other and is enacted
by organizational participants through communicative practices protecting
and promoting various goods leading to institutional flourishing. 28 Care for
the organization or institution as Other is the responsibility of organizational
leaders and of other organizational participants—paraphrasing Marie Baker-
Ohler and Annette Holba’s work on dialogue as the labor of care in human
relationships, 29 care for institutions is a shared labor dedicated to the ongoing
durability of structures necessary for human survival. It is within this context
that I offer this reflection on the organization as “Other” and on care for the
institutional/organizational Other through practices of professional civility—
professional civility as communicative care for institutions.
This chapter offers further development of a perspective on care for insti-
tutions initially articulated in the context of women’s leadership in educa-
tional institutions 30 and extended into the professional civility framework
elsewhere. 31 I begin with brief consideration of theoretical perspectives that
point to a conceptualization of organization as Other, offer a perspective on
care for institutions, and then turn attention to practices of professional civil-
ity that provide communicative care for the organization as Other.
ORGANIZATION AS OTHER:
THEORETICAL PERSPECTIVES
This section reviews the professional civility perspective as laid out in recent
work on the topic, 67 highlighting elements of that theorizing that speak spe-
cifically to issues of productivity, place, and persons. Each good of the
professions finds its origin in the history of the professions as practice within
the ongoing narrative of professions in general and within the specific history
of a given profession. 68 Professional civility as communicative virtue at work
protects and promotes these goods, and by so doing, manifests as communi-
cative care for institutions by supporting institutional maintenance, continua-
tion, repair, and connection of members to a guiding organizational narrative.
Productivity
Place
Persons
NOTES
44. Julia T. Wood, Who Cares? Women, Care, and Culture (Carbondale: Southern Illinois
University Press, 1994).
45. Marlene G. Fine, “Women Leaders’ Discursive Constructions of Leadership,” Women’s
Studies in Communication 32, no. 2 (2009): 180–202; Marina Tomàs, et al., “Women in
Academic Administration at the University,” Educational Management Administration and
Leadership 38, no. 4 (2010): 487–98.
46. Tomàs, et al., “Women in Academic Administration.”
47. Fritz, “Women’s Communicative Leadership”; Fritz, Professional Civility.
48. Fritz, “Women’s Communicative Leadership,” 26.
49. Janie M. Harden Fritz, “Christian Approaches to Communication Scholarship and Peda-
gogy,” in Faith and the Media: Reflections by Christian Communicators, ed. Dennis Cali
(Mahwah, NJ: Paulist Press, 2010), 77–95; Fritz, “Women’s Communicative Leadership.”
50. Fritz, Professional Civility.
51. Arendt, The Human Condition.
52. Fritz, Professional Civility, 24.
53. Fritz, “Women’s Communicative Leadership.”
54. Baker-Ohler and Holba, The Communicative Relationship.
55. Fisher, Bernice, and Joan Tronto, “Toward a Feminist Theory of Caring.” In Circles of
Care, edited by Emily K. Abel and Margaret K. Nelson, 35–62 (Albany: State University of
New York Press, 1990).
56. Patricia Benner and Judith Wrubel, The Primacy of Caring (Reading, MA: Addison-
Wesley, 1989).
57. MacIntyre, After Virtue.
58. Baker-Ohler and Holba, The Communicative Relationship.
59. Arendt, The Human Condition.
60. Fritz, Professional Civility.
61. Ibid.
62. Arnett, Dialogic Education.
63. Stephanie A. Groom, Janie M. H. Fritz, and Ronald C. Arnett, “Examining Organiza-
tional Reputation from the Inside Out,” presentation, International Conference on Reputation,
Brand, Identity and Competitiveness, Oslo, Norway, May 31–June 3, 2007.
64. Ronald C. Arnett, Communication and Community: Implications of Martin Buber’s
Dialogue (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1986).
65. Janie M. Harden Fritz, “Protecting and Promoting Workplace Relationships: Profession-
al Civility,” in Problematic Relationships in the Workplace, Vol. 2, ed. Becky L. Omdahl and
Janie M. Harden Fritz (New York: Peter Lang, 2012), 257–66.
66. Fritz, Professional Civility.
67. Ibid.
68. Ibid.
69. Ibid.
70. Ibid., 146–50.
71. Ronald C. Arnett and Pat Arneson, Dialogic Civility in a Cynical Age: Community,
Hope, and Interpersonal Relationships (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1999);
Fritz, Professional Civility.
72. Fritz, Professional Civility, 151.
73. Jennifer Byrd-Craven, et al., “Co-ruminating Increases Stress Hormone Levels in Wom-
en,” Hormones and Behavior 53, no. 3 (2008): 489–92; Jennifer Byrd-Craven, Douglas A.
Granger, and Brandon J. Auer, “Stress Reactivity to Co-rumination in Young Women’s Friend-
ships: Cortisol, Alpha-amylase, and Negative Affect Focus,” Journal of Social and Personal
Relationships 28, no. 4 (2011): 469–87.
74. Becky L. Omdahl and Janie M. Harden Fritz, eds., Problematic Relationships in the
Workplace, Vol. 2 (New York: Peter Lang, 2012).
75. Anne C. Mancl and Barbara Penington, “Tall Poppies in the Workplace: Communica-
tion Strategies Used by Envious Others in Response to Successful Women,” Qualitative Re-
search Reports in Communication 12 (2011): 79–86.
228 Janie M. Harden Fritz
76. Pamela Lutgen-Sandvik, Sarah Riforgiate, and Courtney Fletcher, “Work as a Source of
Positive Emotional Experiences and the Discourses Informing Positive Assessment,” Western
Journal of Communication 75, no. 1 (2011): 2–27.
77. Fritz, Professional Civility.
78. Kathy E. Kram and Lynn Isabella, “Mentoring Alternatives: The Role of Peer Relation-
ships in Career Development,” Academy of Management Journal 28, no. 1 (1985): 110–32.
79. Fritz, Professional Civility.
80. Ronald C. Arnett, Janie M. Harden Fritz, and Leeanne M. Bell, Communication Ethics
Literacy: Dialogue and Difference (Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage, 2009).
81. Ronald C. Arnett and Janie M. H. Fritz, “Sustaining Institutional Integrity: Management
in a Postmodern Moment,” in Institutional Integrity in Health Care, ed. Ana Smith Iltis (Dor-
drecht, Netherlands: Kluwer, 2003), 41–71.
82. Michael Kramer, Organizational Socialization: Joining and Leaving Organizations
(Malden, MA: Polity, 2010).
83. Fritz, Professional Civility, 158.
84. Fritz, Professional Civility.
85. Ibid.
86. Ibid.
87. Arnett, Fritz, and Bell, Communication Ethics Literacy.
88. Steve Duck, Megan K. Foley, and D. Charles Kirkpatrick, “Uncovering the Complex
Roles behind the ‘Difficult’ Coworker,” in Problematic Relationships in the Workplace, ed.
Janie M. H. Fritz and Becky L. Omdahl (New York: Peter Lang, 2006), 3–19; Fritz, Profession-
al Civility.
89. Fritz, Professional Civility, 169.
90. Ibid., ch. 3.
91. Arendt, The Human Condition; Fritz, Professional Civility.
92. Patricia M. Sias, Organizing Relationships: Traditional and Emerging Perspectives on
Workplace Relationships (Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage, 2009).
93. Fritz, “Protecting and Promoting”; Fritz, Professional Civility.
94. Kennan Bridge and Leslie A. Baxter, “Blended Relationships: Friends as Work Asso-
ciates,” Western Journal of Communication 56, no. 3 (1992): 200–225.
95. Arnett, Fritz, and Bell, Communication Ethics Literacy; Fritz, “Protecting and Promot-
ing”; Fritz, Professional Civility, 28.
96. Ronald C. Arnett, “Professional Civility,” in Problematic Relationships in the Work-
place, ed. Janie M. Harden Fritz and Becky L. Omdahl (New York: Peter Lang, 2006), 233–48.
97. Patricia M. Sias, “Ostracism, Cliques, and Outcasts,” in Destructive Organizational
Communication: Processes, Consequences, and Constructive Ways of Organizing, ed. Pamela
Lutgen-Sandvik and Beverly Davenport Sypher (New York: Routledge, 2011), 145–63; Patri-
cia M. Sias, “Exclusive or Exclusory: Workplace Relationships, Ostracism, and Isolation,” in
Problematic Relationships in the Workplace, Vol. 2, ed. Becky L. Omdahl and Janie M. Harden
Fritz (New York: Peter Lang, 2012), 105–21.
98. Fritz, Professional Civility.
99. Sandra Metts, William R. Cupach, and Lance Lippert, “Forgiveness in the Workplace,”
in Problematic Relationships in the Workplace, ed. Janie M. Harden Fritz and Becky L. Om-
dahl (New York: Peter Lang, 2006), 249–78; Vincent R. Waldron and Dayna N. Kloeber,
“Communicating Forgiveness in Work Relationships,” in Problematic Relationships in the
Workplace, Vol. 2, ed. Becky L. Omdahl and Janie M. Harden Fritz (New York: Peter Lang,
2012), 267–88.
100. Jon A. Hess, “Distancing from Problematic Coworkers,” in Problematic Relationships
in the Workplace, ed. Janie M. Harden Fritz and Becky L. Omdahl (New York: Peter Lang,
2006), 205–32.
101. Jon A. Hess and Katelyn A. Sneed, “Communication Strategies to Restore Working
Relations: Comparing Relationships that Improved with Ones that Remained Problematic,” in
Problematic Relationships in the Workplace, Vol. 2, ed. Becky L. Omdahl and Janie M. Harden
Fritz (New York: Peter Lang), 235–56.
Organization as Other 229
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Fisher, Bernice, and Joan Tronto. “Toward a Feminist Theory of Caring.” In Circles of Care,
edited by Emily K. Abel and Margaret K. Nelson, 35–62. Albany: State University of New
York Press, 1990.
Frank, Thomas. One Market under God: Extreme Capitalism, Market Populism and the End of
Economic Democracy. London: Secker & Warburg, 2001.
Fritz, Janie M. Harden. “Christian Approaches to Communication Scholarship and Pedagogy.”
In Faith and the Media: Reflections by Christian Communicators, edited by Dennis Cali,
77–95. Mahwah, NJ: Paulist Press, 2010.
———. “Ethics Matters: Why Ethical Communication Makes a Difference in Today’s Work-
place.” In Workplace Communication for the 21st Century: Tools and Strategies that Impact
the Bottom Line, edited by Jason S. Wrench, 39–60. Westport, CT: Praeger, 2013.
———. Professional Civility: Communicative Virtue at Work. New York: Peter Lang, 2013.
———. “Protecting and Promoting Workplace Relationships: Professional Civility.” In Prob-
lematic Relationships in the Workplace, Vol. 2, edited by Becky L. Omdahl and Janie M.
Harden Fritz, 257–66. New York: Peter Lang, 2012.
———. “Women’s Communicative Leadership in Higher Education.” In Communicative
Understandings of Women's Leadership Development: From Ceilings of Glass to Labyrinth
Paths, edited by Elesha Ruminski and Annette Holba, 3–25. Lanham, MD: Lexington
Books, 2012.Fritz, Janie M. Harden, and Becky L. Omdahl eds. Problematic Relationships
in the Workplace, New York: Peter Lang, 2006.
Gallagher, Richard S. The Soul of an Organization: Understanding the Values that Drive
Successful Corporate Cultures. Chicago, IL: Dearborn Trade Publishing, 2002.
Gerencser, Stephen. “The Corporate Person and Democratic Politics.” Political Research
Quarterly 48, no. 5 (2005): 625–35.
Groom, Stephanie A., Janie M. H. Fritz, and Ronald C. Arnett. “Examining Organizational
Reputation from the Inside Out.” Presentation at the International Conference on Reputa-
tion, Brand, Identity and Competitiveness, Oslo, Norway, May 31–June 3, 2007.
Hess, Jon A. “Distancing from Problematic Coworkers.” In Problematic Relationships in the
Workplace, edited by Janie M. Harden Fritz and Becky L. Omdahl, 205–32. New York:
Peter Lang, 2006.
Hess, Jon A., and Katelyn A. Sneed. “Communication Strategies to Restore Working Relations:
Comparing Relationships that Improved with Ones that Remained Problematic.” In Proble-
matic Relationships in the Workplace, Vol. 2, edited by Becky L. Omdahl and Janie M.
Harden Fritz, 235–56. New York: Peter Lang, 2012.
Hickson, Mark, and Julian B. Roebuck. Deviance and Crime in Colleges and Universities:
What Goes On in the Halls of Ivy. Springfield, IL: Charles C. Thomas, 2009.
Kimball, Bruce A. The “True Professional Ideal” in America: A History. Lanham, MD: Row-
man & Littlefield, 1995.
Kram, Kathy E., and Lynn Isabella. “Mentoring Alternatives: The Role of Peer Relationships in
Career Development.” Academy of Management Journal 28, no. 1 (1985): 110–32.
Kramer, Michael. Organizational Socialization: Joining and Leaving Organizations. Malden,
MA: Polity, 2010.
Lutgen-Sandvik, Pamela, Sarah Riforgiate, and Courtney Fletcher. “Work as a Source of Posi-
tive Emotional Experiences and the Discourses Informing Positive Assessment.” Western
Journal of Communication 75, no. 1 (2011), 2–27.
MacIntyre, Alasdair. After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory, 3rd ed. Notre Dame, IN: Univer-
sity of Notre Dame Press, 2007.
Mancl, Anne C., and Barbara Penington. “Tall Poppies in the Workplace: Communication
Strategies Used by Envious Others in Response to Successful Women.” Qualitative Re-
search Reports in Communication 12 (2011): 79–86.
Manning, Robert John Sheffler. Interpreting Otherwise than Heidegger: Emmanuel Levinas’s
Ethics as First Philosophy. Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press, 1993.
March, James G., and Herbert A. Simon. Organizations. New York: Wiley, 1958.
Marchand, Roland. Creating the Corporate Soul: The Rise of Public Relations and Corporate
Imagery in American Big Business. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1998.
Organization as Other 231
Metts, Sandra, William R. Cupach, and Lance Lippert. “Forgiveness in the Workplace.” In
Problematic Relationships in the Workplace, edited by Janie M. Harden Fritz and Becky L.
Omdahl, 249–78. New York: Peter Lang, 2006.
Miller, Katherine. “Communication as Constructive.” In Communication As . . . Perspectives
on Theory, edited by Gregory J. Shepherd, Jeffrey St. John, and Ted Striphas, 31–37.
Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage, 2006.
Moore, Mark H. “Managing for Value: Organizational Strategy in For Profit, Nonprofit, and
Governmental Organizations.” Nonprofit and Voluntary Sector Quarterly 29, no. 2 (2000):
183–204.
Omdahl, Becky L., and Janie M. Harden Fritz, eds. Problematic Relationships in the Work-
place, Vol. 2. New York: Peter Lang, 2012.
Selznick, Phillip. The Moral Commonwealth: Social Theory and the Promise of Community.
Berkeley: University of California Press, 1994.
Sias, Patricia M. “Exclusive or Exclusory: Workplace Relationships, Ostracism, and Isolation.”
In Problematic Relationships in the Workplace, Vol. 2, edited by Becky L. Omdahl and
Janie M. Harden Fritz, 105–21. New York: Peter Lang, 2012.
———. Organizing Relationships: Traditional and Emerging Perspectives on Workplace Re-
lationships. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage, 2009.
———. “Ostracism, Cliques, and Outcasts.” In Destructive Organizational Communication:
Processes, Consequences, and Constructive Ways of Organizing, edited by Pamela Lutgen-
Sandvik and Beverly Davenport Sypher, 145–63. New York: Routledge, 2009.
Slaughter, Jerel E., Michael J. Zickar, Scott Highhouse, and David C. Mohr. “Personality Trait
Inferences about Organizations: Development of a Measure and Assessment of Construct
Validity.” Journal of Applied Psychology 89, no. 1 (2004): 85–103.
Smith, Ruth C. “Images of Organizational Communication: Root-metaphors of the Organiza-
tion-Communication Relationship.” Presentation at the Annual Convention of the Interna-
tional Communication Association, Washington, DC, May 27–31, 1993.
Sullivan, William M. Work and Integrity: The Crisis and Promise of Professionalism in Ameri-
ca. New York: HarperCollins, 1995.
———. Work and Integrity: The Crisis and Promise of Professionalism in America, 2nd ed.
San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass, 2005.
Taylor, James R., and Elizabeth J. Van Every. The Emergent Organization: Communication as
Site and Surface. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum, 2000.
Tomàs, Marina, Jose Manuel Lavie, Marie del Mar Duran, and Cristina Guillamon. “Women in
Academic Administration at the University.” Educational Management Administration and
Leadership 38, no. 4 (2010): 487–98.
Twale, Darla J., and Barbara M. De Luca. Faculty Incivility: The Rise of the Academic Bully
Culture and What to Do about It. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass, 2008.
Waldron, Vincent R., and Dayna N. Kloeber. “Communicating Forgiveness in Work Relation-
ships.” In Problematic Relationships in the Workplace, Vol. 2, edited by Becky L. Omdahl
and Janie M. Harden Fritz, 267–88. New York: Peter Lang, 2012.
Weick, Karl E. Sensemaking in Organizations. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage, 1995.
Wood, Julia T. Who cares? Women, care, and culture. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University
Press, 1994.
Chapter Eleven
edge required about the field of practices and realities it reports about (people
having to deal, one way or the other, with new techniques of natural gas
extraction in the soil that will affect their circumstances) for us to make our
own judgment not only about the journalist’s treatment but also about the
issue at hand on the field. The same goes for fairness, since a balanced
evaluation of that point requires knowledge of the positions in play. In the
process of ethical analysis, one level is the article’s treatment of the topic:
how each side of the controversy is presented. For instance, people inter-
viewed might feel betrayed or badly represented in the article. This can be
felt as much on one side as on the other, or on both. One specific angle that
we have here regards treatment of the Other. But in our case, we have at least
two Others, each being the other’s Other. The article’s fairness has to do with
this treatment of the Other questioned by the article on both sides—and also
globally for the readers, a third level of Otherness involved here. On top of
that, the Other is portrayed in the discourse of the proponents/opponents; this
portrayal is part of the ideological and symbolic, but sometimes more direct-
ly material, warfare that takes place between the parties. When a party or
person is ridiculed, caricatured, or badly represented by another group or
person, it shows that the controversy exceeded the limits of a polite discus-
sion to become something much more profound. This way of portraying the
adversary might be diversely evaluated in its importance and value, but still
this is one level of analysis that can be taken into account and described.
As a general theoretical statement, I would have to situate myself into a
pragmatism that is mostly influenced by the classics (Peirce, James, Dewey,
and Mead), even though it is a pragmatism revisited with hermeneutics (Gad-
amer and Eco) and critical theory (Habermas and Honneth). 9 I also am under
some influences of Conversation Analysis and everyday discourse ap-
proaches: We have to be cautious and attentive to what is actually said. For
the theory of values, I refer to Dewey’s theory, valuation acts; values are the
elements that are actually valued, and the explicit has to have some priority
in the analysis. 10 We need a focus on discourse; values show themselves in
communication contents. This being said, allusion and indirect assertion, and
even negative or privative statements of values, are also possible, as we will
see in the article.
piece: it shows us people and gives us a chance to better understand them and
the issue at hand. I will not put the focus on the last series of questions and
criteria that refer to more complex and normative requirements, along with
some background limits (see table 11.1).
The text of the article is not sufficient to get the whole picture, but the online
version does feature a hyperlink that leads to background information. 11 For
the purposess of this chapter, let us provide some details about the issue.
Shale gas is natural gas that is stuck inside rock formations. Gas has to be
extracted by a relatively new technology called hydrological fracturing, or
fracking; after a vertical insertion, a pipe or series of pipes intervenes hori-
zontally by pushing into the rock formation, under heavy pressure, water
mixed with chemicals assembled according to secret formulas owned by the
gas or service companies operating the drilling operation. These chemicals
are followed by sand; this process collects the gas, but it is clearly implied
that liquids and solids stay in the ground and surrounding soil.
This technology, then, comes, for many actors, with some risk to the
environment, especially water contamination as a result of the pressurized
liquids that are used to push gas out of its rocky envelope. Minimization and
maximization of these risks might then emerge in argumentative stances. It is
possible that some of the gas and the polluted water used will infiltrate
deeper, touching and contaminating water sources, including aquifers. In
some cases, that possibility might not be probable, but we can understand
that there is a whole gray area between those two situations, providing in
many cases grounds for caution. This polemic is present throughout North
America, in the states of Pennsylvania, Ohio, and New York, and it also
rages in Quebec. The Marcellus Shale formation covers a good part of the
northern United States, including New York and a smaller part of Canada.
On the other side of the debate are the calls for energy independence (espe-
cially in the United States), the fact that natural gas is relatively less polluting
than oil, and the needs of energy consumption. See figure 11.1 to situate the
distribution. 12
The historical context of this particular kind of exploitation is the relative
scarcity nowadays of easily accessible fossil fuels, on which our economies
largely depend. Demand for new fossil fuels on a global scale is growing at
an increasing rate, especially with the emerging giants of Brazil, China,
India, and Russia. These countries seem well advanced in the process of
joining, or even surpassing, the so-called developed nations, as users and
sometimes providers of fossil fuels (e.g., Russia).
238 Alain Létourneau
Figure 11.1. The World Shale Gas Map. Source: US EIA (Energy Information
Administration).
Now that the easily accessible resources in fossil fuel are less and less
sufficient at the global level, companies and countries rely on less easily
accessible ones, among which are offshore resources in deeper water and the
tar sands in many places, such as Canada. Among the unconventional fossil
fuels, shale gas is on the rise, it is seen as giving the United States a better
chance at energy sufficiency. Figure 11.1 shows where the shale gas forma-
tions are in the world; we can see that North America has a great deal. North
Dakota and Pennsylvania are particularly important on the global scale. Spe-
cialists assert that this development will continue, for instance in Pennsylva-
nia, for the next twenty years. When we have these elements in mind, we can
look at the article with different eyes, since a fuller background understand-
ing helps us to put in perspective what is presented.
But since this is an evolving discussion, we also need to stay current on
papers, articles, and videos that are posted and published about this ongoing
issue. The article examined here is only one piece in a long and continuing
series; more recent ones present, for example, the benefits and protections
that can be obtained by people on the basis of collective bargaining. 13 A
more recent EPA (Environmental Protection Agency) report in Wyoming has
also sparked discussions and fed further debate, this time on the other side of
that “fence.” 14 There was also recently an occupation of a mobile home park
that had been bought for the extracting of Susquehanna River water in Piatt
Township, Pennsylvania, for the purpose of future fracturing. 15 A quite strik-
ing video has also been posted that we can call “militant,” clearly positioned
Plurality of Levels of Communication Ethics Analysis 239
THE ARTICLE
Paragraph One
The paper leads with personal and shocking details: Kim Jastremski received
a letter, represented by the article as similar to a threat, requesting that she
cease protesting gas drilling. She and ten others received the unsigned letter,
whose authors were compared in that way to Nazis—the menace is clear:
240 Alain Létourneau
They and their children are declared “watched.” Upon analysis, this innuendo
seems clearly dangerous.
Paragraph Two
Paragraph Three
It is only after these two paragraphs, which are clearly personalizing the issue
(as we find often in newspapers), that some description is given of the con-
text: details about the technology and the situation in the eastern United
States, with many communities “passing or considering bans,” meaning
towns and villages forbidding the use of the technology on their territory. In
small towns, fracking became the “defining, nonnegotiable political issue.” 20
We come back to ill will in a personal manner, and this determination comes
up repeatedly to define the nature of the debate. Upon analysis, emphasis is
not on the fact that many places do allow shale gas exploitation.
Paragraph Four
The newspaper article says a lot about communities divided, suburbs and
villages on one side against backcountry and farmers on the other, economic
aggravation and social media processes amplifying the issue, a point indirect-
ly asserted when it is written that people obtain “instant access to limitless
information” affirming their viewpoints.
Paragraph Five
Gas companies are opposed to people; the first group has money, but the
people have the number and intensity to dominate local discourse. The two
main sides have changed, now it is companies and people as the opposing
Plurality of Levels of Communication Ethics Analysis 241
Paragraph Six
Upon analysis, we understand that New York at this time intends to allow the
process of gas drilling with some regulations, and that some hearings are
planned before an upcoming decision.
Paragraph Seven
Details are given about the Marcellus Shale, the rock formation that covers
Pennsylvania, described as very shallow in Cooperstown, a situation that is
asserted as limiting severely the possibilities of exploitation in the region.
Upon analysis, the article is downplaying the force and the relevance of the
critics’ stance, but not directly.
Paragraph Eight
Reference is given to the town’s website. The actual declaration on the web-
site, consulted November 8, 2011, says that the board of trustees of the town
supports all efforts to stop natural gas drilling. The article, for its part, says
that the town’s website advocates a statewide ban. This is implied by the
city’s statement, but is not as clear-cut or strong as it is made out to be. The
New York Times paragraph mentions the city of Middlefield, very close by,
as one of the first to ban gas drilling by changing its master plan. However,
when we consult Middlefield’s documents, we see that a moratorium was
expressly required by that city, in Resolution 9 of 2010, in reference to
neurotoxins, an element never mentioned by the New York Times; Resolution
10 goes further and calls for a repeal of a New York law that exempts gas
companies from complying with parts of the Clean Water Act, among other
laws. 21
242 Alain Létourneau
Paragraph Nine
We learn that thirty antifracking candidates are running for office in Otsego,
New York, in November 2011. The detail re-emphasizes the strength of this
opposition, mentioned previously in the article. A second part of the article
permits the reader to get closer. We get the opinion of two woman protago-
nists, along with details of their lives, which give a very personal turn to the
article. Upon analysis, the article increasingly moves to disclosure of person-
al perspectives.
Paragraph Ten
Bringing us back to the level of everyday life, the author characterizes the
dispute as circulating like electric current. Jastremski followed her husband
to that town because he found employment at the State University of New
York in Oneonta. She believed that she had found “the perfect place” for her
family, “replete with chicken coops, beehives and a vegetable garden.” A
process of affirmation takes place here by the journalist; first, he clearly
identifies the values held by the person: Not only did she think she had found
the perfect place but she also had moved back onto family-owned land. Upon
analysis, the article indirectly relativizes the value by alluding to the ridicu-
lous characterization of her position: replete with chicken coops. This carica-
ture of a “perfect place” gives the article a humorous twist.
Paragraph Eleven
Paragraph Twelve
The article gives a long quote from Jastremski. Individuals might not be
greedy, but they are absorbed in what she calls corporate greed. They see
dollar signs everywhere instead of the big picture—that they are harming
their neighbors. Upon analysis, this is a strong example of framing the adver-
sary, setting how they are portrayed. 22
Plurality of Levels of Communication Ethics Analysis 243
Paragraph Thirteen
The article provides a brief presentation of Jastremski, who holds a PhD. She
is uncomfortable with discord, like the conflict with a mother in the gym
“who stood to gain from a gas lease” but felt silenced.
Paragraph Fourteen
The article then moves to the other side, represented in the person of Hunt-
ington, a farmer with 500 cows, who sued the town of Middlefield in Sep-
tember 2011 seeking to overturn its drilling ban, arguing that only the state
has the right to ban fracking. Clearly, the other side of the argument is
introduced here by presenting a personal context to the issue. This will be
pursued from paragraphs fourteen through twenty.
Paragraph Fifteen
Huntington felt she had to remove her daughter from the local school in
which she herself had studied as a child. Partly because of anti-fracking
activism in schools, including a movement to ban fracking on school
grounds, and the demographic changes, a dairy farmer’s daughter seemed to
her to be out of place. This is alluding indirectly to the fact that the daughter
would be known as a daughter of a supporter of fracturing.
Paragraph Sixteen
The article implies that farmers see their opponents as “comfortable urban-
ites,” “retirees,” and “second-home owners” unknowledgeable about “the
economics of farming and . . . the safety of drilling.” Farmers’ economic
difficulties are obviously evoked here. The opponents are represented as
comfortable urbanites.
Paragraph Seventeen
Paragraph Eighteen
“This land and my family are my life,” Huntington said. “We probably use
three to four million gallons of water to feed my cows. I’m not going to spoil
something I need to make my living and for future generations to come.”
Upon analysis, this implies the following: She knows and trusts the validity
of the scientific-technological approach to the issue and sees herself as a
responsible person for her generation and the next, which is coherent with a
sustainable development perspective. There is a clear affirmation of the value
of the land, and she presents herself as knowing what is best and as being
environmentally responsible, which is also an important attribution of value.
Paragraph Nineteen
“Proponents of fracking say that many farmers are on the verge of losing
their property.” Upon analysis, this part continues to explicate the economic
side of the issue for farmers.
Paragraph Twenty
Paragraph Twenty-One
The article then mentions other businesses. They fear that an industrialized
landscape would be detrimental and “antithetical” to Cooperstown’s tourism.
Upon analysis, industrial landscape effects and outlooks would be negative
for tourism; it is a countervalue to be avoided. As we can see, starting with
this paragraph and through the next one, voice is given back to the oppo-
nents.
Paragraph Twenty-Two
reporting against each other seems like an activity with a harassment quality.
Some farmers say fracking could ruin them. Siobhan Griffin, an organic
dairy farmer, cited a letter from the Park Slope Food Co-op in New York
City, which explained that the organization’s members would refuse to pur-
chase goods from areas permitting fracking. Upon analysis, the article shows
that the farming community is not unified on the issue because the organic
farmers are siding with the neo-residents. They are presented as boycotting
businesses and exerting pressure.
Paragraph Twenty-Three
Paragraph Twenty-Four
“People on both sides say the ill will probably goes beyond fracking.” We
can see that this is the introductory paragraph to the conclusion.
Paragraph Twenty-Five
“At one time, people in Cooperstown could disagree, but it was never per-
sonal,” said Catherine Ellsworth, who writes a column in a local weekly
newspaper and supports drilling. “Now it’s more like they want what they
want, . . . There’s no sense we’re in this together. But I guess that’s not just
here. Society has changed, and Cooperstown has changed along with it.”
This comment by a citizen and local journalist ends the article, between past
and present. Upon analysis, the deterioration seems to be clear. By its ab-
sence or negativity, the value of community life is at risk.
As we will see in the two following tables that summarize our results, the
values portrayed and the framings of the others and of oneself by others (or
by oneself) occupy quite a bit of space in the article. This process involves
the values proposed by both proponents and opponents of the fracking tech-
nology. I distinguish reciprocal framings from valuing acts, even though they
are quite related. In fact, to frame in bad terms some adversary is to allow a
246 Alain Létourneau
Values Counter-values
Values affirmed by She found the perfect Industrial landscape that
Jastremski place; she moved back comes with drilling.
onto family-owned land.
Clean water, natural
landscape, economic value
of house (all under attack).
Values affirmed by herself Confidence in technology
and her group by and of herself as an expert.
Huntington Shows herself as
environmentally
responsible.
Sense of belonging to the
land by the families, as
something to hold onto.
Valuation of farmers,
showcased as being at the
service of nature’s outlook,
even in their poverty
The debate itself is seen throughout the article as dispute, discord, ill will,
nonnegotiable issues, no dialogue with opponents, no debate or conversation; conflict
has hijacked everything else and personal clash occurs.
“There’s no sense we’re in this together”: privatively asserted value of community as
required and lacking. In the past, “it was never personal.”
Plurality of Levels of Communication Ethics Analysis 247
presented more as a victim than the other is; in fact, this is done by referring
to her own speech acts (as reported). They both seemed to have a lot to say
against the other group, but the negative predicates are more numerous
against the urbanites, from and against Huntington, than they are from and
against Jastremski and their relative group. In a corresponding way, as we
can see in the first table, there are more values associated with Huntington
than those we find associated with Jastremski. Few countervalues are as-
serted, and only on one side of the fence. The pro-fracturing side is thus
given a little more exposure and more positive values than the other side,
despite the appearance of equity in the treatment, which gives both sides
some exposure. In that sense, the image given is not neutral, even though it
does present both sides sufficiently to give us a good idea of the social split.
Table 11.3. Summary of reciprocal framings involved
Frames Counter-frames
The others framing With other opponents, she was Ridicule of her position:
Jastremski (against “threatened” and compared with she is “replete with chicken
gas fracturing) Nazis; she is “watched.” coops” (secondary sources
alleged by article).
Framing the others The proponents are sucked into
“by” Jastremski greed, see dollar signs
everywhere, do not see the big
picture, and harm their
neighbors.
The others framing Treated as being a sellout, She was publicly abused,
Huntington (proponent prostitute. targeted on web
of fracturing) documents, and had her
business threatened with
boycotts.
Framing the others by The other side was presented
“other proponents” as antigrowth and ideology-
driven people.
Framing others by Urbanites and retirees against a
Huntington music festival, wind turbines,
and Little League
TOPOI OF DISCUSSION
whether there is nevertheless in the field and in practice some dialogue and
some recognition of the Other on those issues is not really treated. We are
inclined by the article to think that if it exists, it is at best marginal.
If we look for such things as dialogues on gas fracturing, we might find
appeals to dialogue, for instance, by the American Petroleum Institute, but
experiences of the kind in the authentic sense are not easily found. 23 Some
“opponents” that also appeal to dialogue do recognize some values on the
other side, while still calling for restraint and protections, for instance, as the
Sierra Club of Michigan does. 24 Let us say that appeals seem really situated
and politically opinionated somewhere from the start.
But is it the place of a newspaper article to propose mediation or delibera-
tive processes to get ahead in the debate? A normative vision of the news-
paper could respond in the affirmative to such a question—for instance, if we
say that the press has a facilitative or even a radical role. Of course, in the
second case, it would be more militant than in the first. 25 At the reading of
the article, such an enterprise would seem doomed to failure anyway. We
could surmise that it is hard to demand of an article that it propose a practical
way of leading people out of such a protracted issue. What it does is to show
us the abyss between the parties.
For an ordinary reader of written media, this piece can introduce us to a
discussion that is grave and important; it has some quality and diversity in it,
representing and documenting both sides, their circumstances and views,
helping us understand some personal situations involved that might be (or
might not be) typical. And again, if we look at it from a normative stand-
point, we could find it lacking on many counts.
If the monitorial role is assumed by the piece, but with imperfections, let
us forget completely in this case about a facilitative role or a radical role that
a newspaper article could play. 26 Moreover, if we consider the classical
opposition in communication ethics between procedure and substance, here
the procedural aspect of dialogue or deliberation is completely missed, while
substance on given issues is also not treated as something other than ideolog-
ical posturing. 27 Values are presented and discredited almost as soon as they
are entered into the “conversation.”
One formula of criteria to express the monitorial role would be to say that
the article should give adequate and sufficient information on the issue and
on the context. It should help us to be able to appreciate the situation, includ-
ing adequate knowledge of the controversy. We cannot say it informs the
reader thoroughly on that point because we ourselves have to supplement it,
in light of the lack of information and technical data, if we want to under-
stand the debate. The human side seems to be given here as a way to avoid
entering into the scientific and technical detail.
Another formulation of that same monitorial role would be that fairness
of exposure should be given to both sides of the issue. At a first reading, we
Plurality of Levels of Communication Ethics Analysis 249
will have this impression with this article because obviously each side is
reflected, or has a kind of representative. Both sides seem to have had their
share of verbal or personal media abuse: direct or indirect threat and carica-
tures of self as urbanites, sellouts, and so on. And both sides seem to be
expressing themselves quite fairly. But one side is more able to express its
own positions, strengths, and values than the other. By presenting the sides as
equals and creating an effect of balance, the journalist seems to aim at fair-
ness, but in the end, the pros obtain more space to develop their point, their
position seems stronger, posed with a person’s confidence and assertion.
Only the pro side gets to express its vision of itself in a positive way. The
second reading shows a priority given to one side, and we have seen that this
has some quantitative basis. But is this the final word on the issue? Some
qualitative reception of the paper as a whole is also important. If we keep
quantity of references and exposure as our main criteria, we will not evaluate
the piece in the same way as we would if we had balanced it with a qualita-
tive outlook. Said otherwise, even if there is a little more space given to one
side, we still can see a little of both sides.
When humans are involved, some human treatment would be adequate:
this might look good as a criterion when we look at the article and other
similar documents. That part seems well done in the article. But that obvious
consideration of the human side might not be so helpful because it also
prevents the paper from taking any side. Otherness of the other, here, does
not help; here it helps to neutralize the discussion instead of getting ahead
with it, and it does this by fixing each other’s Other in a determined and
seemingly unmovable position.
The preceding analysis shows clearly that expressions of value are present in
this article, and it helps us understand the nature of the situation. But the
article does not manage to formulate the dilemma represented by these op-
posing values. I would also suggest that value issues are obscured in carica-
turing each side and in framing detrimentally the other’s Other. Each side
gets to caricature the other side by using countervalues that play a rhetorical
role in an attacking position. It is given only as a space of expression for the
parties, but ends up stonewalling them into dogmatic posturing, which might
or might not be completely adequate. This also adds up with the already
noted fact that the antifracking side is more criticized than the pro-fracking
side. Here, we could say that the otherness of the Other is not fully respected,
while at first glance the opposite seems to be true. This fluctuation in the
250 Alain Létourneau
evaluation says a lot about the complexity of the criteria involved and the
difficulty in deciding among them.
It can be argued that the text helps us know the conflict better, again mostly
by personalizing the issue. A first reading might give us this impression. But,
on the contrary, we could argue that this article, instead of fighting against
societal political biases, just reinforces them. By showing the entrenched
positions and by characterizing the present debate as “dispute,” “ill will,” and
similar characterizations, we only get the image of two dogmatisms facing
each other. At the same time, once analyzed, the article does show some
shared values that are not really exploited in the article, notably the same
desire on both sides to repair a lost sense of community.
NOTES
11. Under “Energy and Environment,” specifically the heading “Natural gas.” See topics.
nytimes.com/top/news/business/energy-environment/natural-gas/index.html?inline=nyt-
classifier.
12. Source of the map: United States Department of Energy, The Wikipedia Commons,
2011.
13. For instance, see “New Value for Land in Rural Ohio,” www.nytimes.com/2012/06/05/
us/mineral-leases-give-boost-to-rural-ohio.html?pagewanted=all.
14. See “In Land of Gas Drilling, Battle for Water That Doesn’t Reek of Fizz,” www.
nytimes.com/2012/06/02/us/in-land-of-hydraulic-fracturing-a-battle-over-water-pollution.html.
15. See ecowatch.org/2012/riverdale-residents-blockade-fracking-water-withdrawal-constru
ction-road-to-save-their-community/.
16. See “Fracking Hell: The Untold Story,” www.youtube.com/watch?feature=player_
embedded&v=dEB_Wwe-uBM.
17. Promised Land, directed by Gus Van Sant, Hollywood, Universal Pictures, Focus Fea-
ture, 2012, 106 minutes.
18. The article was accessible as of April 18, 2013, for reading and testing at www.nytimes.
com/2011/10/30/nyregion/in-cooperstowns-fight-over-gas-drilling-civility-is-fading.html?
pagewanted=all&_r=0.
19. Applebome, “Drilling Debate.”
20. At this point, the article moves from page 1 to the beginning of page 18.
21. Middletown and Cooperstown: the second includes the first, inside Otsego County.
22. The notion of frame to which I refer here is twofold. Inside the content of the analysis, I
use the term only to describe the way parties to the dispute portray each other under striking
images, which are often simplistic in their content. Framing can also be used to describe more
generally the way the dispute itself is constructed, structured, and typified by the article taken
as a whole. I will have to take up the latter issue later. One excellent book about frames is
Martin Rein and Donald Schön, Frame Reflection: Toward the Resolution of Intractable Policy
Controversies (New York: Basic Books, 1995).
23. Reed Porter, “API Supports DOE Dialogue on America’s Vast Natural Gas Resources,”
api.org/news-and-media/news/newsitems/2011/jun-2011/api-supports-doe-dialogue.aspx.
24. “Hydraulic Fracturing: Talking Points,” The Michigan Sierra Club, michigan.sierraclub.
org/democracy/Fracking%20Talking%20Points%20-%20Fall%202011.pdf.
25. Christians, et al.
26. Christians, et al.
27. On procedure versus substance, see Jürgen Habermas, Between Facts and Norms (Cam-
bridge, MA: MIT Press, 1998), especially chapter 7.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Applebome, Peter. “Drilling Debate in Cooperstown, NY, is Personal.” New York Times, Octo-
ber 30, 2011.
Christians, Clifford G., et al., eds. Normative Theories of the Media. Urbana: University of
Illinois Press, 2009.Cresswell, John. Research Design: Qualitative, Quantitative, and Mixed
Approaches. Newbury Park, CA: Sage, 2008.
Dewey, John. Theory of Valuation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1939.
Dilthey, Wilhelm. The Formation of the Historical World in the Human Sciences. Vol. 3 of
Selected Works. Edited by R. Makreel and F. Rodi. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press, 2010.
Gadamer, Hans-Georg. Truth and Method. London: Bloomsberry Academics, 1960/2004.
Habermas, Jürgen. Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and
Democracy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992/1998.
Honneth, Axel. Kampf um Anerkennung [The Struggle for Recognition]. Franfurt, Suhrkamp
Verlag, 1994/2012; Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996.
Létourneau, Alain. “Definition and Prescription as Classifiers of Arguments: A Comparison of
Two Models for Analysing Arguments, Sproule (1980) and Toussaint-Ducasse (1996).” In
252 Alain Létourneau
Proceedings of the 7th Conference of the International Society for the Study of Argumenta-
tion. Edited by F. Van Eemeren, Bart Garssen, David Godden, and Gordon Mitchell,
1076–88. Amsterdam: Sic/Sat-Rosenberg, 2011.
———. “Towards an Inclusive Notion of Dialogue for Ethical and Moral Purposes.” In
(Re)Presentations and Dialogue. Edited by François Cooren and Alain Létourneau, 1-36.
Amsterdam: John Benjamins, 2012.
Lewicki, Ray et al., eds. Making Sense of Intractable Environmental Conflicts: Concepts and
Cases. Washington, DC: Island Press, 2003.
Rein, Martin, and Donald Schön. Frame Reflection: Toward the Resolution of Intractable
Policy Controversies. New York: Basic Books, 1995.
Russell, Nick. Morals and the Media. Vancouver: UBC Press, 2006.
Weber, Max. The Vocation Lectures: Science as a Vocation and Politics as a Vocation. Edited
by D. Owen and T. B. Strong. Cambridge, MA: Hackett, 2004.
Chapter Twelve
Annette M. Holba
A life in which leisure is understood and experienced is a life that honors and
respects the other. A commitment to leisure weds philosophy and ethics into
a practice that creates dynamic and dialogic meeting spaces that have the
potential to transcend difference. Leisure begins in a contemplative starting
place described by Josef Pieper as a “philosophical act.” 1 This philosophical
act cultivates a spirit of selflessness designed to exemplify hermeneutic hu-
mility 2 and a particular recognition of the other. Leisure as a philosophical
act holds one accountable to the other without demand. Similar to Emmanuel
Levinas’s “ethics as first philosophy,” 3 leisure enables one to turn toward the
other in humility, honor, and respect, which is an embodiment of a virtue
ethic of being.
As a philosophical act, leisure transforms one’s interiority and prepares
one to respond to the call of the other constructively. The practice of leisure
in one’s life enables one to productively engage silence, where one experi-
ences the present and the now; happiness, which is found through contempla-
tion and considered the ultimate beatitude; 4 and contemplation, one’s move-
ment in wonder. Leisure connects one to the vita contemplativa and the
philosophical act, enabling a meeting with the other in an ethical communi-
cative space. This chapter explores how leisure is a catalyst that brings to-
gether an interplay of the self and other and philosophy and ethics. After a
short section defining leisure philosophically, this chapter considers ethics
and the other through the lens of Emmanuel Levinas’s ethics as first philoso-
phy. Next, this chapter explores Josef Pieper’s virtue ethics, where leisure is
the spiritual and contemplative key to turning toward the other. Finally, the
chapter ends with a discussion about how leisure provides the space for
253
254 Annette M. Holba
LEISURE
Leisure is a term and a concept that is misunderstood. There has been much
attention to this word and its action throughout history and from multiple
world paradigms and traditions. 5 One thing these positions on leisure have in
common is the acknowledgment of its importance to the human condition;
however, the idea of leisure is wrought with conceptual and multidimension-
al differences. For some philosophers, leisure is the first principle of all
action 6 and the mother of philosophy. 7 For other philosophers, leisure is the
counterpart to a contemplative life that seeks presentness; 8 for others, leisure
is the foundation of culture. 9 These accolades describing leisure are, for the
most part, celebrating the deep philosophical and wise actions embedded
within its moral tradition.
Some philosophers and theorists have alternative perspectives on leisure
that might touch on these kinds of accolades but take a different approach to
it entirely or totally dismiss the attribution of any kind of moral value to it.
For example, Chris Rojek, a contemporary social and economic philosopher,
positions leisure as a catapult for developing emotional intelligence and emo-
tional labor especially related to social and economic environments. 10 Others
simply interpret leisure to be the idle use of one’s time and equate it without
distinction to entertainment and relaxation. 11 So we see that there are diverse
perspectives on leisure that sometimes complement and sometimes contra-
dict other positions.
For the purpose of this chapter, leisure is defined closely to the position of
the ancient philosophers who charged it to be a high intellectual activity and,
similar to Josef Pieper’s understanding of leisure, as a philosophical act
originating from within a contemplative spirit. The difference between Piep-
er’s understanding of leisure and the position presented in this chapter is that
Pieper’s leisure leads one to the divine, to God. In the position of this chap-
ter, leisure is a philosophical act that cultivates one’s interiority in a herme-
neutic humility that permits one to be open to the other and to the possibil-
ities of any given moment. There is no attachment to a religious position—
though leisure in a philosophically secular sense still maintains elements of
festivity and celebration that can be sacred or secular.
Activities of leisure remain separate from the pressures and distractions
of working for a living and physical daily sustenance. Leisure does not need
to be equated with privilege or economic class. Leisure is an embodied
Leisure and the Other 255
activity of the mind that permits one to get lost in wonder and in the excite-
ment of phenomenological learning and seeing. It cannot be totalized be-
cause it is open and responsive; there is freedom and liberation when one
engages leisure.
Leisure is not tied to a particular activity. Leisure is a mindset; it is an
approach to an activity that permits a corporeal mindfulness in which one
feels leisure in the body as well as in one’s interiority (secular) or soul
(sacred). Anyone can do leisure and there is no required equipment. One can
lose oneself in one’s mind listening to music in a way that lets the composi-
tionality be foregrounded while one seeks to see the intervals and the mean-
ings that become the music. One might focus on what one hears, the instru-
mentation, the individual instruments, the harmony and melodies, the inter-
val augmentation, the modulating keys, the dynamics, the tonalities, the fugal
aspects, and the conversation of the composition. And then there is more—
the historical moment, the questions concerning the individual composer,
tensions between competing composers at the time of the writing of the
composition. One need not play an instrument to experience music as a
leisure activity. One needs only to contemplate and permit the body to be-
come involved in the activity; one corporeally experiences the music.
There are other kinds of leisure activities that permit and require the use
of instruments. Whether sports, reading, painting, walking, or swimming,
one can engage these activities as leisure or as recreation. In leisure, the
focus of attention is key, which is a contemplative attention and attunement
to ideas of what one is doing. One is driven by the experience. In recreation,
one is driven by other things, such as chronos (kronos), competition, or
getting to some thing, getting to the next thing. In leisure, that kind of telos is
not present; in leisure, telos is open and time becomes outside of time, driven
by kairos and collapsing any sense of kronos. 12 In leisure, time is an ontolog-
ical experience as the experience of time falls away in the doing or playing.
Playing an instrument can be recreation or leisure, and the key to understand-
ing the activity as one or the other is the approach one takes to the act.
This is most assuredly a short description of leisure, and it points to a
different kind of conceptualization from the contemporary framing of leisure
through the leisure and tourism industry. In an effort to commoditize leisure
(for business owners to make money off of it and for everyday people to
purchase it), American culture has obscured leisure from the understanding
of it as a philosophical act. Today, leisure is more often considered like a
coffee break or a vacation, activities that hold short-term reprieve from the
commotion of everyday living. As the rest of this chapter suggests, leisure
holds far more import to the human condition—because leisure as a philo-
sophical act can provide the cultivation needed and be the catalyst in some
cases for an ethically imbued and philosophically infinite existence. Consid-
256 Annette M. Holba
ering leisure through the lens of the ethical reminds us of its most valuable
contribution to the cultivation of humanity.
The idea that our responsibility to the other is never removed from us
changes how we see the world around us; we are then called to engage the
other in an ethical manner that places priority of the other above all other
commitments and desires. Our connection to and responsibility for the other
is a social relationship that Levinas describes as “infinite responsibility for
the other.” 14 The approach toward the Other is made possible only by the
Other, where the I is in the presence of the face of the other with a “total
uncoveredness and nakedness of defenseless eyes . . . a disquietude of con-
sciousness, seeing itself, in all its adventures, a captive of itself . . . [and]
forbids me my conquest.” 15 Through this relationship, we realize that the
infinite is not the object of contemplation; rather, contemplation resides with-
in in the infinite. This infinite space is an ethical space that is cultivated by
leisure; leisure has the potential to transform this space into an ethically
responsible communicative space. Situating recreation as an object (which is
totality) and leisure as a subject (which is infinite), it becomes clear that
leisure is a philosophical act that can transform individuals and the commu-
nicative landscapes in which one ethically meets the other.
A moral conscience reveals freedom in judgments toward the other.
When a moral conscience resides in pure desire, we experience totality,
which means we are separated from the possibility of infinity and, conse-
quently, of leisure. When desire permeates toward the other, it is unquench-
able, and this unquenchability opens us to the other, and simultaneously we
become disinterested and turn away from ourselves. 16 This desire is not agent
driven and worldly; it is the exercise of moral exigency. We can only exer-
cise our moral exigency through disinterestedness, which is the outcome
when we turn away from agency. Morality transcends in an authentic dis-
interestedness toward the other, which is a responsibility that transcends
separateness, enabling us to reach toward and beyond the exteriority and
interiority of the other.
Leisure and the Other 257
Responsibility
serious play involving ideas that begin with inner discourse. Inter-discourse
is life-giving because it is through this inter-discourse that the I is derived
from the other.
Contemporary media environments that have been described as fast-
paced and the cult of fast 22 pose dangers to this kind of inter-discourse as
well as its counterpart, inner discourse. Inner discourse is necessary, yet it is
often an afterthought or fully ignored, especially in American culture, where
speed and the idea of more is privileged and taking care of one’s interiority
has been obscured or eliminated completely. 23 Leisure teaches us to engage
in serious play and cultivates that inner discourse; it is perhaps one of the
only spaces left in American culture where inner discourse can be experi-
enced. Without inner discourse, inter-discourse is likely not achievable, and
if it is, it will more likely be destructive than constructive.
As thinking agents in a consumption-driven environment, we find it diffi-
cult to focus on our priorities, assuming we are able to prioritize. 24 When we
are engaged intellectually and actively with inner discourse and inter-dis-
course, we become alive in the world. In this living engagement, we lose
ourselves and our interestedness; we become disinterested, and in this dis-
interestedness, we are able to turn toward the other in humility. Turning
toward the other in this fashion fully engages us in the world with others—
the turning presupposes an ethicality that undergirds our communicative en-
actments. Disinterestedness in this way permits the kind of engagement that
there is in the play in leisure. It is only when we are fully at play that we are
more fully alive with and to the other. Leisure provides the intellectual and
embodied space from which we can engage the other in humility, and in this
engagement the self and the other are celebrated.
Leisure privileges alterity in that as one engages contemplative action, the
freedom to turn away from agency and turn toward the other is nurtured
through a disinterestedness that permits reflection and openness. If we em-
brace responsible disinterestnedness toward the other, ethics begins to inform
our communicative behaviors.
Inner discourse and inter-discourse permit one to be in a synchronic pres-
ence with the other that does not need to conform or become a consensus.
The I enters into thinking or thought of the other. Entering into this relation-
ship shapes intellectual play through a poiesis already committed to an ethi-
cal relation with the other.
There is an exchange of ideas within inter-discourse, and this involves an
intellectual activity that creates a presence so that the cultivation of one’s
field of knowledge is ongoing. Engaging otherness in this way is not a
common practice in a world driven by impressions, façades, and chronologi-
cal temporality. The increase of phatic communication due to technological
advancements has left human beings with little to say; however, we must
Leisure and the Other 259
continue to seek and explore realms for nurturing conversation, dialogue, and
dialectic.
It seems as though there is no limit to the development and advancement
of all kinds of technologies that influence and obstruct everyday communica-
tive lives. New media technologies that are invented to bring human beings
closer together are in reality more likely to become barriers that keep human
beings from communicating with each other, human to human. Martin Hei-
degger felt that communicating through talk was fundamentally human and
an activity in which people experience that notion of being with another. 25
When we begin to communicate through virtual environments and cyber-
spaces, something fundamentally changes with the notion of being with, and
this experience might well be the beginning of the end of being with in
general.
Diverse philosophical perspectives help us to understand the nature and
need for leisure in our lives as these relate to the consequences of leisure—
how leisure affects our relations with the other. Different philosophical tradi-
tions pursue questions that consider how human communicative beings come
to understand the agility and flexibility that is needed to negotiate contingen-
cies in our environment. In order to transcend these contingencies, a pheno-
menological seeing becomes necessary, potentially enabling us to see beyond
these matters and become healthier communicators. This kind of seeing bey-
ondness can recuperate our communicative condition, which nurtures our
Being.
SEEING BEYOND
times in known and other times in unknown places. Through the togetherness
of our mindfulness approach and our physical bodies, we connect, blend, and
cross over ideas and traditions. Our corporeal experiences and our natural
attitudes transcend and propel our movement and discoveries. Experiencing
leisure moves us to transcend the mundane and opens us up to new ideas and
potentiality.
We construct social realities so that we can live with others—by choice.
Even if we want to be hermits or if we intentionally want to live outside of a
traditional social order, we still need to communicate with others; we are still
social beings. It is that need to be social, to live with others, that becomes
primordial to our existence. So, seeking leisure through our understanding of
our responsibility for the other enables us to start outside ourselves so that we
can seek inside ourselves. Human freedom makes the idea of otherness chal-
lenging to us, especially in a world confronted by difference and indiffer-
ence, distractions, and violence. Though we never can be released from the
violence of otherness, we start there; this condition is inescapable. In recog-
nizing this inescapabilty, starting with the other becomes a priority—leisure
is one kind of activity that enables us to constructively participate in and
from that ethical starting place.
Accepting leisure as a virtue ethic also provides balance to this turning
toward the other by turning toward the self in relation to the other through a
reflexive virtue ethic. Introducing the ethical philosophy of Josef Pieper into
this discussion foregrounds his commitment to leisure as having philosophi-
cal ground and his moral stance on the importance of virtues in our lives.
Leisure cultivates virtues. While Pieper’s theological perspective is ever-
present in his writings, theological positioning is not of central application in
this chapter. Related to leisure, Pieper’s virtue ethics can be considered com-
plementary to Levinas’s ethics as first philosophy in that they both point to
understanding leisure as being transformative to the self and the other—not
only to be life-giving but also to be life sustaining.
Leisure
kind of work, one that is responsible for cultivating one’s interiority, the
human spirit. Pieper sees leisure as a philosophical act and argues that in the
doing of leisure, one makes a commitment—it becomes a habit or a practice
in one’s life. 30 It is the practice of leisure that enables cultivation and trans-
formation of the human spirit, or interiority. It is the practice of leisure that
enables one to philosophize and to wonder.
Wonder permits playful engagement with ideas, permitting one to see
beyond what is there, beyond the obvious and the emotional. 31 Wonder de-
scribes the kinds of action that envelop play in the engagement of leisure.
While the idea of leisure being transformative is either under-acknowledged
or linked to the divine, it does provide a starting place from which we can
reexamine and understand leisure. Leisure cultivates one’s ability to philoso-
phize and nurture one’s being—it is a commitment to a contemplative world-
view that enables development of human virtue.
Human Virtue
Pieper’s ethics and philosophy revolves around four key virtues that he refers
to as the cardinal virtues—prudence, justice, fortitude, and temperance. 32
Prudence for Pieper is the mother of all virtues; he referred to it as the
“genitrix virtutum.” 33 Pieper understood prudence differently from the con-
temporary popular understanding that often depicts it as being timorous,
small-minded, and characterized by self-preservation. In popular culture to-
day, prudence is also considered to be selfishness or rigidity in perspective
and experience. For Pieper, prudence is the understanding that the good
presupposes one’s knowledge of one’s reality; this means that the actions one
takes fit the reality of the situation and that they are appropriate to the real
situation in which one is embedded either intentionally or unintentionally. 34
This means that one takes action that is right and good because one knows
the reality of a given situation. To know and understand one’s reality, one
must be able to see beyond the obvious and through an openness; one must
be able to philosophize—to wonder.
Our contemporary understanding of prudence is much weaker than Piep-
er’s. His perspective requires humility and attention. For him, prudence is a
noble characteristic that seeks what is good. Prudence in this light becomes
elevated to a higher characteristic, and it is not tied to worldly things, events,
or conditions.
The second cardinal virtue for Pieper is justice. Justice, as a habit (habit-
us), suggests that one renders to the other what is due in deliberate fashion. 35
Pieper’s understanding of justice is consistent with Plato’s understanding,
which reflects the sentiment that each person should receive what is due
based upon his or her actions; one gets what one deserves. Pieper suggested
that justice cannot develop outside of or separate from moral convictions; it
Leisure and the Other 263
Contemplation
Humility
tion tied to the good life, wisdom, and virtue that make it stand out from
other kinds of action. Leisure cultivates human virtue because it begins from
and is tied to the inner landscape of a human being. Consequently, leisure
can be considered a virtue ethic because it encompasses an ethic of being
(interior) and an ethic of doing (exterior). An ethic of being relies upon
tending to one’s interiority or inner landscape through contemplation, and an
ethic of doing involves humility in all of one’s actions. These aspects of
leisure as a virtue ethic enable an ethical turn toward the other.
indicated that it is never too late; we can never be too old to learn about the
health of our soul and to replace any emptiness with leisure. 48 Some popular
misunderstandings of Epicurean philosophy consider it to be driven by he-
donism only. But Epicurus emphasized the seeking of wisdom through pleas-
ure; his pleasure is not a worldly or bodily pleasure. The pleasure that he
advocated was a pleasure for the sake of itself, and it involved acts of con-
templation, modesty, and moderation. 49 This Epicurean insight paints a pic-
ture of an experience informed by contemplation, modesty, and moderation
that diverges from and passes beyond sensual pleasures toward a life with a
peaceful soul. In the Epicurean spirit, leisure provides enriching potential for
our human condition.
Through leisure, the embodied consciousness is “the occasion whence we
enact communicative praxis . . . [that] demands philosophical considera-
tion.” 50 This is where there emerges an a-whereness that negotiates between
our finite bodies and the infinite possibilities when we open to hermeneutic
humility. 51 A-whereness “accounts for both the passive and active moments
of possibility. It allows for descriptions of world disclosure” 52 In this sense,
to be truly free in turning toward the other, leisure provides a way to cultivate
an ethically laden corporeal openness of our thoughts and deeds, thus bring-
ing together philosophy and ethics as a natural bridge to the other.
NOTES
1. Josef Pieper, Leisure, the Basis of Culture (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2009/1952),
77.
2. Ramsey Eric Ramsey, The Long Path to Nearness: A Contribution to a Corporeal
Philosophy of Communication and the Groundwork for an Ethics of Relief (Amherst, NY:
Humanity Books, 1998), 74–78.
3. Emmanuel Levinas, “Ethics as First Philosophy,” in The Levinas Reader, trans. Seán
Hand (Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishers, 1989), 75–87.
4. Josef Pieper, Happiness and Contemplation (South Bend, IN: St. Augustine Press,
1998), 13.
5. Chris Rojek, The Labour of Leisure: The Culture of Free Time (Los Angeles: Sage,
2010); Annette Holba, Philosophical Leisure: Recuperative Praxis for Human Communication
(Milwaukee, WI: Marquette University Press, 2007); Pieper, Leisure, the Basis of Culture.
6. Aristotle, Politics, in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon, 1127–1324
(New York: The Modern Library, 2001).
7. Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996).
8. Thich Nhat Hanh, You Are Here: Discovering the Magic of the Present Moment (Bos-
ton: Shambhala Books, 2012).
9. Pieper, Leisure, the Basis of Culture.
10. Rojek, The Labour of Leisure, 3.
11. Thorstein Veblen, The Theory of the Leisure Class (New York: Mentor Books, 1899/
1952).
12. Charles Guignon and Kevin Aho, “Phenomenological Reflections on Work and Leisure
in America,” in The Value of Time and Leisure in a World of Work, ed. Mitchell R. Haney and
A. David Kline, 25–38 (Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2010).
13. Emmanuel Levinas, Alterity and Transcendence, trans. M. B. Smith (New York: Colum-
bia University Press, 1999), 127.
268 Annette M. Holba
14. Ibid.
15. Emmanuel Levinas, “Philosophy and the Idea of the Infinite,” in To the Other: An
Introduction to the Philosophy of Emmanuel Levinas, trans. A. Peperzak (West Lafayette, IN:
Purdue University Press, 1993), 110.
16. Ibid.
17. Emanuel Levinas, Totality and Infinity, trans. A. Lingis (Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne
University Press, 1969), 181.
18. Ronald C. Arnett, “The Responsive ‘I’: Levinas’s Derivative Argument,” Argumenta-
tion and Advocacy 40, no. 1 (2003): 39–50
19. Ibid.
20. Ibid., 40.
21. Emmanuel Levinas, Entre Nous: Thinking of the Other (New York, Columbia Univer-
sity Press, 1998), 202.
22. Carl Honoré, In Praise of Slowness: Challenging the Cult of Speed (New York: Harpe-
rOne, 2004).
23. Ibid.
24. Veblen, Theory of the Leisure Class; Honoré, In Praise of Slowness.
25. Martin Heidegger, Discourse on Thinking (New York: Harper and Row, 1966).
26. Thomas Beauchamp, Philosophical Ethics: An Introduction to Moral Philosophy (New
York: McGraw-Hill, 1982); Stephen Toulmin, Reason in Ethics (Cambridge, MA: Cambridge
University Press, 1968).
27. Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics (New York: Oxford University Press, 1998).
28. Beauchamp, Philosophical Ethics, 150.
29. Pieper, Leisure, the Basis of Culture.
30. Ibid.
31. Linda Weiner and Ramsey Eric Ramsey, Leaving Us to Wonder: An Essay on the
Questions Science Can’t Ask (Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 2005).
32. Pieper, The Four Cardinal Virtues (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press,
1954/2007). Citations are to the 2007 version.
33. Ibid, 3.
34. Ibid.
35. Ibid.
36. Pieper, The Four Cardinal Virtues.
37. Ibid., 63.
38. Ibid, 117.
39. Ibid.
40. Pieper, Happiness and Contemplation, 109.
41. Ibid., 101.
42. Ibid., 100.
43. Ibid., 14.
44. Aristotle, Metaphysics, in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon, 689–934
(New York: Modern Library, 2001).
45. Relationship Re Ramsey, The Long Path to Nearness, 9.
46. Ramsey, The Long Path to Nearness.
47. E. Brown, “Contemplative Withdrawal in the Hellenistic Age,” Philosophical Studies
137, (2008): 79–89.
48. Ibid.
49. Ibid.
50. Ramsey, The Long Path to Nearness, 62.
51. Ibid., 76.
52. Ibid., 77.
Leisure and the Other 269
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Aristotle. Metaphysics. In The Basic Works of Aristotle. Edited by Richard McKeon, 689–934.
New York: The Modern Library, 2001.
———. The Nicomachean Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press, 1998.
———. Politics. In The Basic Works of Aristotle. Edited by Richard McKeon, 1127–34. New
York: The Modern Library, 2001.
Arnett, Ronald, C. “The Responsive ‘I’: Levinas’s Derivative Argument.” Argumentation and
Advocacy 40, no.1 (2003): 39–50.
Beauchamp, Thomas. Philosophical Ethics: An Introduction to Moral Philosophy. New York:
McGraw-Hill, 1982.
Brown, Eric. “Contemplative Withdrawal in the Hellenistic Age.” Philosophical Studies, 137
(2008): 79–89.
Guignon, Charles and Kevin Aho. “Phenomenological Reflections on Work and Leisure in
America.” In The Value of Time and Leisure in a World of Work. Edited by Mitchell R.
Haney and A. David Kline, 25–38. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2010.
Hanh, Thich Nhat. You Are Here: Discovering the Magic of the Present Moment. Boston:
Shambhala Books, 2012.
Heidegger, Martin. Discourse on Thinking. New York: Harper and Row, 1966.
Hobbes, Thomas. Leviathan. New York: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Holba, Annette M. Philosophical Leisure: Recuperative Praxis for Human Communication.
Milwaukee, WI: Marquette University Press, 2007.
Honoré, Carl. In Praise of Slowness: Challenging the Cult of Speed. New York: HarperOne,
2004.
Levinas, Emmanuel. Alterity and Transcendence. Translated by M. B. Smith. New York:
Columbia University Press, 1999.
———. Entre Nous: Thinking of the Other. New York: Columbia University Press, 1998.
———. “Ethics as First Philosophy.” In The Levinas Reader. Translated by Seán Hand, 75–87.
Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishers, 1989.
———. “Philosophy and the Idea of the Infinite.” In To the Other: An Introduction to the
Philosophy of Emmanuel Levinas. Translated by Andrew Peperzak, 88–120. West Lafayette,
IN: Purdue University Press, 1993.
———. Totality and Infinity. Translated by Alphonso Lingis. Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne Uni-
versity Press, 1969.
Pieper, Josef . The Four Cardinal Virtues. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press,
1954/2007.
———. Happiness and Contemplation. South Bend, IN: St. Augustine Press, 1998.
———. Leisure, the Basis of Culture. San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1952/2009.
Ramsey, Ramsey Eric. The Long Path to Nearness: A Contribution to a Corporeal Philosophy
of Communication and the Groundwork for an Ethics of Relief. Amherst, NY: Humanity
Books, 1998.
Rojek, Chris. The Labour of Leisure: The Culture of Free Time. Los Angeles: Sage, 2010.
Toulmin, Stephen. Reason in Ethics. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press, 1968.
Veblen, Thorstein. The Theory of the Leisure Class. New York: Mentor Books, 1899/1952.
Weiner, Linda and Ramsey Eric Ramsey. Leaving Us to Wonder: An Essay on the Questions
Science Can’t Ask. Albany, NY: SUNY, 2005.
Chapter Thirteen
The classical category of ethos has had an enduring relevance for rhetorical
theory and for analytic applications. At the same time, this concept is notori-
ously complex and even confusing, especially since a competing vocabulary
that includes terms like identity, role, self, or position has also steadily
emerged over the past few decades. In this chapter, I focus on a particular
aspect of the classical notion of ethos, one that is usually ignored by scholars:
its implicit ethnocentrism. The Greek ethos was, fundamentally, the ethos of
a citizen already authorized to deliberate in public. To speak of the ethos of a
woman or of a noncitizen would have made no sense in the context of the
classical Greek polis, where women, slaves, and foreigners had no public
voice. Contemporary analyses, however, ignore this peculiarity. Elsewhere, I
have discussed it fully, 1 probing its origin and cultural background, but in
this chapter I look at its consequences for understanding a contemporary
political problem: the reparation of a damaged national ethos in the aftermath
of historic conflagrations.
At the end of World War II, the morally and politically compromised
German identity desperately needed legitimation. The presence of Allied
troops and the de-Nazification programs were not enough to create quickly a
genuine political transformation. 2 Rather, when it took place, the political
transformation of the new German states, from the former Third Reich to
democracies, was an internal development that depended crucially on the
Germans’ ability to create their own postwar moral order and a new postwar
political ethos. 3 The former political exiles were a critical resource in this
271
272 Andreea Deciu Ritivoi
endeavor. During the war, they had fashioned themselves and were perceived
abroad as the “other Germany.” They were those who resisted Hitler and
were therefore not contaminated by the “stench of blood and disgrace,” in
Thomas Mann’s words, 4 which clung to those who remained at home. Legiti-
mation through exiles is not without its problems or contestations. In Germa-
ny, the exiles’ claims to moral and political superiority were often dismissed
by those who had chosen the so-called path of inner migration and opposed
Nazism at home. Nevertheless, in Martin Jay’s terms, in Germany, “once the
dust settled in the 1950s, . . . it was apparent that the relative victors were . . .
[those] who had ‘run away,’ rather than the moral pygmies who defensively
claimed that they had stayed ‘at their posts.’” 5
My argument in this chapter is that the exiles’ victory, to use Jay’s term,
was the product of their ability to position themselves discursively as moral
rescuers of their nation. This also implied that their nation was redeemable.
The political refugees offered it a new credibility on the international scene.
What strategies did they use to achieve such an important and difficult task?
More importantly, how was their achievement philosophically possible, giv-
en the paradoxical situation in which they were? I argue that what the former
political refugee offered was a redemptive ethos. To understand the rhetori-
cal making of this ethos, we must also move beyond the classical legacy and
supplement it with a different heuristic that allows us to avoid any proble-
matic cultural baggage.
The analysis I offer focuses on the provocative case of postwar Germany,
and specifically on Lisa Fittko’s political activity when she was a refugee in
Germany, as recounted in her memoir Escape Through the Pyrenees. 6 Fittko,
née Ekstein, was born in 1909 in Uzghorod, then part of the Austrian-Habs-
burg Empire. She was the daughter of a Jewish avant-garde writer and died in
2005 in Chicago. After spending most of her childhood in Budapest and
Vienna, she moved to Berlin with her family, where her father’s connections
enabled her to enter the entourage of the Weimar intelligentsia. Fittko, how-
ever, preferred a different milieu and eventually joined the underground
communist movement. At the age of twenty-four, she was reprimanded and
then nearly shot for failing to raise her arm in the Hitler salute at a rally and
for admonishing a policeman who was beating another man. She was already
being pursued by the Gestapo when a couple of fellow communists with
whom she had been distributing manifestos betrayed her. To save her life she
fled the country, first to Czechoslovakia, then to Switzerland and Holland,
and in 1938 to France. In France she met and married Hans Fittko, a fellow
communist who was also pursued by the Nazis because of his antifascist
articles. The couple became key players in the operations organized by Var-
ian Fry and the Emergency Rescue Committee to assist the escape of several
European artists and intellectuals fleeing Nazi persecution. Fittko published
two autobiographical books and numerous interviews, while also being fea-
Saving the Nation 273
tured in two documentaries. Her memoir Escape Through the Pyrenees was
named in Germany as the Political Book of the Year, while the author was
awarded the Distinguished Medal of Merit, First Class.
Most studies of the wartime German exiles offer an unflattering perspec-
tive when it comes to assessing their political mission. Commonly described
as ineffective politically, unable to influence the foreign policy of the Allied
states, torn by internal strife, dominated by strong but idiosyncratic personal-
ities as political actors, the German exiles have received mostly unfavorable
reviews. 7 Fittko’s successful memoir prompts me to rethink this view and
perhaps to ask a different question: How do we measure the political impact
of exiles? I ask this question in the context of a philosophical rather than
historical concern.
Fittko positioned herself in a complex network of relations involving
nations (Germany and France), the community of German exiles, and com-
munist organizations with which she was affiliated during the war. It was not
specifically a German ethos, but her uniquely individual one, that constitutes
the persuasive appeal of her memoir. Even when presenting herself as a
German, Fittko chose strategies of positioning designed to allow her to avoid
the charge of guilt leveled collectively against the German nation. This was
especially important, given the perception of the Germans during and after
the war. 8 When presenting herself as an exile, she chose strategies of posi-
tioning designed to identify her as a powerful political actor, rather than a
helpless refugee needing assistance from a foreign state or organization. This
was important, given the representation of the refugee, emerging in the after-
math of World War II as a pathetic, lost, creature, reduced to her bare human-
ity and entirely at the mercy of her saviors, the countries where she had found
refuge.
actor, a univocal ‘true’ self that contrasts with the voice and character taken
on for rhetorical speech and acting.” 11 In the Aristotelian tradition, the main
source of ethos was the moral character of the speaker, usually established as
a series of characteristics: practical wisdom, virtue, and goodwill. The com-
plete list is longer, and includes courage, temperance, magnanimity, liberal-
ity, gentleness, prudence, and justice. 12 While these features might seem
general enough, and therefore one could expect to see them valued in other
cultures and historical periods as well, how they would be established and
recognized was dependent on the specific moral and ethical climate of the
Greek society. What kind of knowledge did the rhetor need to display in
order to appear wise? What kind of moral choices would he need to promote
in order to appear virtuous? How would he establish goodwill? To these
questions, the Greeks had specific answers provided by cultural norms and
societal practices in conjunction with theoretical rhetorical systems. For in-
stance, the use of carefully chosen general observations and, especially, val-
ue judgments—such as “to die for your country is better than to live under
foreign occupation”—could suggest to an audience that the speaker was
capable of making the right moral choices, in pleading that a defendant be
acquitted, for instance. Likewise, knowing what not to say—such as not
mentioning previous defeats in trying to mobilize an audience to support a
new war—indicated the speaker’s awareness of the social decorum, and thus
recommended him as discerning and well-intentioned. Virtue was defined by
Aristotle as “a capacity that provides and preserves goods.” 13 The nature of
such goods has been the subject of much debate, while the rest of the defini-
tion offers frustratingly vague information: Virtue is praiseworthy and can
convince an audience to accept the speaker’s arguments because “it is a
capacity that benefits in many ways, and great ways, and in all sorts of ways
on all sorts of matters.” 14 The Greeks recognized virtue in the context of
common beliefs about what would constitute a particularly beneficial good:
for instance, actions done for the sake of another rather than the agent’s own
sake. 15
There clearly was a hierarchy of virtues in Aristotle’s Rhetoric, with
practical wisdom ranked high. Aristotle described practical wisdom (phrone-
sis) as “a calculative and rational capacity” to identify what is beneficial for a
community in a given situation. 16 But how would an audience recognize that
the rhetor had identified what is beneficial for it in that particular situation,
other than by relying on already established cultural norms that would pair
exigencies with adequate responses? In its reliance on virtues, defined not in
the abstract terms of a moral theory, but as ethical conventions shared by a
community, ethos was a key dimension of a discourse aimed at persuasion: It
grounded such discourse in the “judgment of ethical particulars” and was
thus “virtually co-extensive with the activity of judgment that partly defines
citizenship.” 17
Saving the Nation 275
ers’ beyond their borders and in strange lands where they were outside the
law and denied full legal recognition.” 22
Giorgio Agamben has argued that political mechanisms are impotent
when it comes to helping refugees because such mechanisms are attached to
a national order and reflect state policies, while refugees fall outside such
categories:
The reasons for this impotence lie not only in the selfishness and blindness of
bureaucratic machines, but in the basic notions themselves that regulate the
inscription of the native (that is, of life) in the legal order of the nation-
state. . . . That there is no autonomous space within the political order of the
nation-state for something like the pure man in himself is evident at least in the
fact that, even in the best of cases, the status of the refugee is always consid-
ered a temporary condition that should lead either to naturalization or to repa-
triation. 23
exile and her nation—in relation to particular events depicted in the story,
especially the situation prior to the departure, the arrival in the new country,
and the defection.
Mostly known for its account of Walter Benjamin’s final days and the fate of
his last manuscript, Fittko’s memoir is a story about the life of German
refugees conceived as a category that brings together the famed and the less
famed, the politicos and the Jews, anyone who had left Nazi Germany and
had to cope with the adversity of exile. She uses the term German sparingly
as a generic umbrella term. In the scenes describing life at home prior to her
emigration, she uses naming devices that differentiate carefully among vari-
ous positions individuals occupied within the German nation. Against the
approaches that invoke the German character or the German soul, she stress-
es difference within the German nation. Germans are differentiated accord-
ing to their economic status, profession, views and beliefs, and membership
in political organizations or institutions.
To be German, by this account, is a complicated cluster of positions,
which includes different social and political categories and, most important-
ly, moral values. Fittko places herself in this complex network of relations,
among members of the same generation, active political dissidents, artists
and intellectuals, the Nazi establishment, family members, and friends. Her
position evolves from that of an outsider in wartime Germany to a witness to
social and political problems who feels morally compelled to intervene and
becomes as an actor determined to remedy the country’s ills. This position
crystallizes as a result of how she relates to other Germans and of the moral
and political identity she develops through these relationships. For example,
she presents herself as not sharing her family’s political orientation—that of
the Weimar intelligentsia. She also does not identify as a Jew, any references
to her Jewish origin being patently absent. She also does not identify with an
ideological platform, despite later becoming a communist.
The meaningful performance that positions Fittko in this moral order is
her participation in a Nazi rally—out of sheer curiosity, as she later recounts.
On this occasion, she witnessed a man being brutally attacked. This event
awakens her social and political consciousness and compels her to become a
political actor. Her political awakening is thus defined as a moral obligation
and a gesture of solidarity with a fellow German (it does not even come up
whether the man could have been Jewish), rather than an ideological re-
sponse to Nazism. By defining herself as a political actor in moral terms,
Fittko can claim particular positions, and the rights and responsibilities in-
volved. She deems herself responsible for the fate of a good Germany, de-
278 Andreea Deciu Ritivoi
fined through the symbolic topos of the “happy Berlin” 29—a Germany that
needs to be defended against the “Nazi menace.” 30 But assuming such duty
also implies that there are other Germans who also oppose Nazism. Thus, the
storyline of complacency and submission, associated with the Germans dur-
ing the war, is replaced with one of victimhood and active struggle, thus
allowing Fittko to situate herself in a national community that can also elicit
compassion and even respect, not just outrage and condemnation.
German is first featured in her memoir as a generic national category
when she refers to those who left Germany. This shift has a double purpose:
(1) to level temporarily the diversity and thus to emphasize the common fate
of those who had to leave Nazi Germany; and (2) to suggest that generic
national categories often reflect an external point of view, in this case that of
the foreign nations receiving the emigrants. Thus used, the term marks the
transition to the next section, the exiles’ lives in France, where they are
routinely identified mainly through their national origin, with no concern for
other kind of identifications. While willingly situating herself in the collec-
tive generically identified as “German emigrants,” Fittko also presents her-
self as passive recipient, as a victim: “We were caught in the same trap as
tens of thousands of German emigrants.” 31
By 1938, many German intellectuals and political emigrants had been
stripped by the Nazis of their German citizenship, and they now found them-
selves stranded in the country they had thought would offer them safe refuge,
in desperate need to escape one more time. The naming devices used in this
section to identify the German émigrés as members of a category (rather than
particular individuals) reflect the viewpoint of the French (both officials and
society in general). This external perspective, the one of the host country, is
marked through the use of the French expressions for the reference in ques-
tion. As seen by the French, the German émigrés are ressortisants alle-
mands,” 32 les boches, 33 sales boches. 34 National origin positions them in
relation to the host country, France, more than their refugee status does.
Fittko creates a progression in the positioning of the emigrants by the French,
from the “enemy aliens” 35 to “simply Germans,” 36 to “spies,” 37 and in the
end to “probably Nazi parachutists.” 38 This is a progression which undoes
the earlier careful differentiation of the German nation according to social
class, political stance, or generational affiliation, and which recategorizes all
the émigrés into an amorphous collective, Germans, in order to equate them
with Nazis.
This positioning of the refugees into one indiscriminate grouping appears
all the more illegitimate when contrasted to the internal diversity of the
group, as Fittko describes it. Against the approaches that invoke the German
character or the German soul, she stresses difference within the German
nation. German people are differentiated according to economic status, pro-
Saving the Nation 279
fession, views and beliefs, and their belonging to particular political organ-
izations or institutions:
Most of the women were apolitical Jewish emigrants who had sought asylum
in France from persecution at the hands of the Nazis. They were confined
along with us, the political refugees of the Nazi opposition, many of whom had
fled to escape death and torture. And then there were the Reichsdeutschen,
German citizens with valid passports who had for themselves on French
soil . . . when war broke out. Naturally, there were Nazis among them. 46
in recounting her stay in the French internment camps, Fittko emphasizes the
fact that Germans, too, were victims of the concentration system devised by
the Nazis. In May 1940, the French government ordered the arrest and intern-
ment of all émigrés. Many émigrés used the term “mousetrap” to describe the
camps in which they were interned as the German army advanced. 47 Thus,
the flight to France functions as a significant performance—the escape be-
comes entrapment, and what was initially a safe refuge turns into a reason to
flee again. Fittko plays on the well-established motif of the helplessness of
the refugee, but in doing so she manages to remind the reader that the help-
lessness was also that of some Germans, not just of Germany’s victims.
In the escape scene, the very fact that the crossing includes Walter Benja-
min is significant because it features German exiles helping other German
exiles, thus challenging the depiction of the refugee being rescued by a
foreign benefactor. After delivering Benjamin and a woman named Gurland
with her son, Fittko returned to France and continued for several more
months to guide other refugees across the mountains. In the scene describing
the crossing of the Spanish border, she captures the exceptional nature of the
émigré as a political actor by positioning herself in relation to other refugees,
whose powerlessness becomes a way of stressing her power. Fittko uses the
technique of contrast in the positioning of Benjamin—she calls him “old”
while also acknowledging that he was only forty-eight; describes him as the
typical scholar, “with the intellectual scholar’s head and the searching gaze
behind thick lenses,” 48 just before recounting his ridiculous attempt at imper-
sonating a French sailor. References to Benjamin depict him as inept socially
even though impressive intellectually, as helpless physically even though
resolute morally. One paragraph captures this mix especially well: “What a
remarkable man! I thought. Crystal-clear thinking, an unfaltering inner
strength, and at the same time a hopelessly awkward, clumsy fellow.” 49
The technique of contrast allows her to position Benjamin as helpless
while also positioning herself as his helper. At the same time, capitalizing on
the presence of a major intellectual as a character in the escape scene, Fittko
draws attention to the significance of her mission—to assist the rescue of
European luminaries whose lives were endangered by Nazism. She focuses
on a symbolic detail: a big briefcase holding the writer’s last manuscript.
Benjamin is described as willing to give his own life to save the manuscript
in the briefcase. But from her perspective, the briefcase is “a monstrosity,” so
heavy that carrying it makes the trip harder, whether or not it might constitute
a precious vestige of German Kultur trying to survive. For Fittko, the rescue
has a different stake: it is individual lives rather than documents or ideas—
and Benjamin’s is not more important than those of other exiles. In Fittko’s
words: “I had my hands full guiding our little group upward. Philosophy had
to wait until we were over the mountain. I was busy rescuing some human
beings from the Nazis.” 50
Saving the Nation 281
Fittko’s euphoria, when the crossing is complete, goes beyond the actual
practical achievement: “I stood for a moment and watched as they started
down the bumpy road. . . . It’s high time for me to get going, I thought, and
started back. . . . I wasn’t tired. It had all been so easy—I was lighthearted,
and the whole world with me.” 51
Caught between the universality of the political refugee and the German
guilt, 52 Fittko dealt with the challenge of positioning herself and the German
ethos by taking advantage of the two horns of this dilemma. She used the
position of refugee, depicted as helpless victim, to re-infuse German identity
with humanity, and then also used the position of political refugee, depicted
as courageous actor, to restore an image of the democratic, anti-Nazi Ger-
man.
Reflecting on the political activity of German political exiles during
World War II, scholars have often wondered: Could the exiles have done
more, or acted differently, to fight Nazism? Perhaps if the exiles had been
more united, they could have had a deeper impact. Perhaps if their political
thinking had been more consistent or more attuned to the views of other
national groups abroad, they could have built more powerful, and thus more
effective, alliances. Other accounts draw attention to the remarkable heroism
of the exiles and indeed consider surprising even their limited success, given
the conditions of the fight. But the success of political exiles can also be
measured by the impact they had on their home countries in the aftermath of
the political transformation, after the war in Germany. As narrative scholar
Paul John Eakin has argued, when we read an autobiography, “we repeat in
our imaginations the rhythms of identity experience the autobiographical
narratives describe.” 53 Germans reading Fittko’s memoir were invited to
experience the Nazi past from the perspective of fellow nationals who had
opposed it, not joined it. While the de-Nazification programs forced Germans
to atone for the evil committed by their nation collectively, Fittko offered an
alternative, politically more convenient, basis of identification. She revealed
another side of German identity, brave and democratic, compassionate and
humane. Lisa Fittko did not save Walter Benjamin and she did not rescue his
final manuscript, but she wanted readers of her memoirs to understand that
she did a lot more. When she accepted the Distinguished Merit Award from
President Richard von Weizsäcker in the name of the German resistance (not
herself or the German exiles), she contributed to the moral redemption of her
nation.
The concept of a redemptive ethos allows us to understand difficult rhe-
torical predicaments such as the one faced by post–World War II Germany,
as well as to move beyond some of the conceptual entanglements of the
classical concept of ethos. I rely on positioning theory to develop an analyti-
cally more flexible template, but also for avoiding the strong link between
ethos and moral virtues, a link that becomes especially problematic when we
282 Andreea Deciu Ritivoi
are dealing with a society in a moral crisis. By replacing moral virtues with a
moral order—the category favored by positioning theory—I hope to obtain a
more generous space of reflection and critique. Individuals like Lisa Fittko
were not merely strategic in the postwar rehabilitation of Germany, but genu-
ine supporters of a German rebirth. Her message of optimism and faith is the
most important dimension of a redemptive ethos.
NOTES
1. Andreea Deciu Ritivoi, Intimate Strangers: Foreign Intellectuals and American Politi-
cal Discourse (New York: Columbia University Press, forthcoming).
2. Mary Fulbrook, The Divided Nation: A History of Germany, 1918–1990 (Oxford: Ox-
ford University Press, 1991).
3. Ibid., 312.
4. Quoted in Martin Jay, Cultural Semantics. Keywords of Our Time (Boston: University
of Massachusetts Press, 1998), 87.
5. Martin Jay, Permanent Exiles: Essays on the Intellectual Migration from Germany to
America (New York: Columbia University Press, 1986), 326.
6. Lisa Fittko, Escape through the Pyrenees. (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University
Press, 1991).
7. See Yossi Shain, The Frontiers of Loyalty: Political Exiles in the Age of the Nation-State
(Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press, 2005); Jean Michel Palmier, Weimar in Exile:
The Antifascist Emigration in Europe and America (London: Verso, 2006).
8. Karl Jaspers, The Question of German Guilt, trans. E. B. Ashton (Fordham University
Press, 2001).
9. Dana Anderson, Identity’s Strategies: Rhetorical Selves in Conversion (Columbia, SC:
University of South Carolina Press, 2007), 91.
10. Jan Swearingen, “Ethos: Imitation, Impersonality, and Voice,” in Ethos: New Essays in
Rhetorical and Critical Theory, ed. James S. Baumlin and Tita Baumlin (Dallas: Southern
Methodist University Press, 1994), 116.
11. Ibid.
12. Aristotle, Rhetoric, I, 9, in The Complete Work of Aristotle, The Revised Oxford Trans-
lation, ed. Jonathan Barnes, vol. 2, Bolingen Series LXXI (Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 1984).
13. Aristotle, The Nichomachean Ethics, in The Complete Work of Aristotle, The Revised
Oxford Translation, ed. Jonathan Barnes, vol. 2, Bolingen Series LXXI (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1984), 1366a37.
14. Ibid., 1366a36–1366b1.
15. Ibid., 1366b36–13667a4.
16. Ibid., 3.16.9.1417a23–27.
17. Stephen Halliwell, “The Challenge of Rhetoric to Political and Ethical Theory in Aristo-
tle,” in Essays on Aristotle’s Rhetoric, ed. Amelie Rorty Oksenberg (Berkeley: University of
California Press, 1996), 178.
18. Erich Gruen, Rethinking the Other in Antiquity (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
2011), 312.
19. Ibid.
20. Ibid., 316.
21. Hannah Arendt, “The Perplexities of the Rights of Man,” in The Portable Hannah
Arendt, ed. Peter Baehr (New York: Penguin Classics, 2003).
22. Jeffrey Isaac, “Situating Hannah Arendt on Action and Politics,” Political Theory 21,
no. 3 (1993): 509–10.
23. Giorgio Agamben, “We, Refugees,” Symposium 49, no. 2 (1995): 116.
Saving the Nation 283
24. Rom Harré and Brownyn Davis, “Positioning: The Discursive Production of Selves,”
Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior 20 (1990): 3.
25. Ibid., 4.
26. Ibid., 5–6.
27. Ibid., 6.
28. Ibid.
29. Fittko, Escape, 2.
30. Ibid., 3.
31. Ibid., 30.
32. Ibid., 7.
33. Ibid., 11.
34. Ibid.
35. Ibid., 7.
36. Ibid., 11.
37. Ibid.
38. Ibid.
39. Ibid., 2.
40. Ibid.
41. Ibid., 3.
42. Ibid., 2, my emphasis.
43. Ibid., 3.
44. Ibid.
45. Ibid., 7.
46. Ibid., 12.
47. Palmier, Weimar in Exile, 442.
48. Fittko, Escape, 32.
49. Ibid., 45.
50. Ibid., 47.
51. Ibid., 89.
52. Karl Jaspers, The Question of German Guilt, trans. E. B. Ashton (New York: Fordham
University Press, 2000).
53. John Paul Eakin, How Our Lives Become Stories (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press,
2005), 130.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Isaac, Jeffrey. “Situating Hannah Arendt on Action and Politics.” Political Theory 21, no. 3
(1993).
Jaspers, Karl. The Question of German Guilt. Translated by E. B. Ashton. New York: Fordham
University Press, 2000.
Martin, Jay. Permanent Exiles: Essays on the Intellectual Migration from Germany to America.
New York: Columbia University Press, 1986.
Palmier, Jean Michel. Weimar in Exile: The Antifascist Emigration in Europe and America
London: Verso, 2006.
Ritivoi, Andreea Deciu. Intimate Strangers: Foreign Intellectuals and American Political Dis-
course. New York: Columbia University Press, 2014.
Shain, Yossi. The Frontiers of Loyalty: Political Exiles in the Age of the Nation-State. Ann
Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press, 2005.
Swearingen, Jan. “Ethos: Imitation, Impersonality, and Voice.” In Ethos: New Essays in Rhe-
torical and Critical Theory, edited by James S. Baumlin and Tita Baumlin. Dallas: Southern
Methodist University Press, 1994.
Chapter Fourteen
Perhaps there are others who can relate to my mother’s didactic rhetoric,
which frequently took the form of cultural clichés, such as “Misery loves
company.” It was a warning that I should stay clear of other people who
would unnecessarily embroil me in their problems. “Mind your own busi-
ness,” she would say, and “Let others tend to their business.” Out of respect
and admiration, I listened, heeded her admonitions and grew up thinking that
every person has a mind, each mind a separate and unrelated entity not
responsible to the others. This sort of cognitive behavioral therapy for her
children seemed practical, even if Norman Vincent Peale tacitly informed it.
The colloquialisms of our egocentric culture subtly reify the tendency to
understand mental issues, among others, as purely individual in origin and
warranting individual treatment. Moreover, we have never been able to shed
the illusion that mind and brain are identical. Here, and against my mother's
advice, I ask my readers to worry with me. I hope the undertaking is not too
steep a hill to climb, another thing she warned me about.
When I present conference papers and public lectures on the present
topic, I am always asked personal questions in subsequent interpersonal en-
counters and in hushed confidential tones, so let me be explicit from the
beginning: I am not depressed, and neither is anyone in my family. Unfortu-
nately, most of us know someone who suffers from depression. Maybe it is
someone for whom we have deep concern. Perhaps the worries of this world
are already sufficient, even overwhelming, so that my suggestion of taking
on yet another one may seem an unnecessary and unacceptable burden. How-
285
286 Isaac E. Catt
ever, it is this very anxiety of existence at the roots of our social experiences
that motivates this project.
I do not believe that a problem as widespread as depression is merely an
individual issue. Nor do I believe that it is a biological malady. With the
exceptions of organ donations upon death and organ transplants, we do not
normally share our bodily organs. We do share our minds, because the mind
is social and a result of communication. Depression is a problem of mind.
However, my focus is not as much on depression itself as it is on the issue of
therapy, and specifically the medicalization of the illness that renders it a
disease. I am not the first to say that we live in an era of depression. 1 Yet, if
the problem of depression is ubiquitous, then so is its treatment. The genesis
of my worry is in personal observations of people who suffer from this
human pathology and who have sought a medical cure, specifically through
antidepressant medicines. Here is a succinct description of the medicine:
“Antidepressants are drugs that treat depression and improve the symptoms.
The main types of antidepressants are tricyclic antidepressants, selective se-
rotonin reuptake inhibitors, monoamine oxidase inhibitors and other atypical
antidepressants.” 2
Where antidepressants are involved, the medical community has readily
dismissed the significance of patient claims to being numbed or drugged, but,
on the face of it, this is indeed strange. After all, the patients are drugged.
Drugs often numb or stupefy the body. Treatments of symptoms of this mood
condition are founded on the experience of being drugged. I worry because I
have perceived changes in personality and altered interpersonal communica-
tion among those whom I know to be on antidepressants. Some of them are
self-described as mellowed out, dazed, or numbed. These symptoms of the
supposed cure of their illness seem quite similar to symptoms of people I
have known who self-administered illegal drugs or alcohol. I began to ques-
tion whether my associates and friends were better off on drugs than they
might have been with a more traditional communication-centered psycho-
therapy. Certainly, I do not wish to make choices for someone else; their
ethics must remain their own. Nonetheless, their choices may be more con-
strained by the morality of the dominant paradigm of wellness codified in the
cultural milieu than they may recognize. Bringing attention to this is my
purpose. Perhaps, my work may contribute to informed choices of alternative
treatments.
Few of us enjoy watching people suffer, especially if those sufferers
count among those invested with our affections. Yet, it seems that we have
given up on a cure for this illness, as evidenced by the fact that depression is
no longer theorized. The symptoms are now assumed to be identical with the
disease, and therapy is as close as the prescription pad. An easy fix is encour-
aged. Still, I wonder whether the course of least resistance is the right one.
Whatever else it might be, surely the right path remedies the illness both
Communicology and the Ethics of Selfhood 287
because the drug is also prescribed for other maladies, some of which are
assumed to be related to depression, such as anxiety, panic disorder, and
post-traumatic stress disorder (PTSD). Doctors are allowed to prescribe vir-
tually any legal drug, regardless of the use for which it is initially intended.
The psychopharmacological industry has a long and sordid history of per-
suading medical professionals to prescribe these drugs for an increasing va-
riety of maladies unrelated to research or to approval by the Food and Drug
Administration (FDA).
The rate of antidepressant use by Americans increased 400 percent be-
tween 1988 and 2008. While we wait for recent data, we may safely assume
that increases in use have continued to occur in the last few years. Research
shows that the rate of depression climbs during economic downturns such as
the most recent recession. As depression elevates as a national statistic, so
does intake of antidepressants. Personal identity suffers. The longer a person
is unemployed, the less likely are the chances of regaining employment. The
depression only deepens. It is known that depression is socially contagious in
marriages and other living arrangements with significant others. Living in
close proximity with a despondent loved one is depressing. Being diagnosed
with a mental illness further lessens the likelihood of employment. Depletion
of income during unemployment decreases the prospects of pursuing psycho-
therapy. And, of course, it may have been depression on the job that contrib-
uted to being unemployed in the first instance.
Almost 25 percent of American women aged forty to fifty-nine are on
antidepressants. Women are twice as susceptible to depression as men and
are more likely to seek treatment.
Less than 30 percent of persons taking the drugs saw a mental health
professional in the last year. Consumers of antidepressants are, for the most
part, not under continuing care and monitoring by a mental health profession-
al. Once on the drugs and once compliance is regularized, the therapeutic
intervention is usually finished. At this point, the best that can be said is that
psychiatrists monitor prescriptions, their job reduced to medical mainte-
nance. Other studies confirm and extend the CDC research.
It is estimated that 25 to 50 percent of undergraduate college students in
America are on antidepressants. 16 A significant number of this group would
appear to fall under age twenty-four, the cutoff below which the drugs are not
normally recommended for fear of suicidal ideation. Many of these students
take the drugs to allay stress, some of them on the advice of their parents who
see the drugs as a strategy of prevention.
Especially startling are these data: Four out of five of all prescriptions
filled by pharmacists contain antidepressants. Seventy-three percent of the
prescriptions for antidepressants are given to patients who have not been
diagnosed with depression. 17 Nonspecialists, not psychiatrists, write 80 per-
cent of prescriptions for these drugs. 18
Communicology and the Ethics of Selfhood 291
In this step of the chapter, I examine the construction of the medical reality of
depressive disease. The accepted view is simply not supported by scientific
evidence.
The story of science justifying antidepressants and related drugs is an
eye-opener that I briefly render here. A principal and recurring theme is the
availability of chemicals and very creative imaginations put to work on how
they might be used for profit. This point bears repeating: The chemicals
existed, then massive research was conducted to discover how they might be
used. Initial research reported failed attempts to positively alter brain chemis-
try as a cure for depression and other illnesses. The link was then reported as
successful, even while citing the published reports that said the opposite.
Further research referred to the aforementioned secondary articles and the
false rendering of the facts simply snowballed over time. The myth of a
biological basis for sad social relations was promoted. Contrary research
findings and known dangers of the drugs were not reported. Research was
twisted to fit desired outcomes. Economic interests figured heavily. The
pharmacology industry entered the professional medical scene and influ-
enced doctors, medical journals, schools of psychiatry, the American Psychi-
atric Association (APA), the DSM, and medical school textbooks. Doctors
were paid large fees and treated to exclusive vacations if they agreed to
promote the drugs. They were also paid to sign their names to legitimate the
supposed science of proprietary research produced by the industry. Medical
292 Isaac E. Catt
excruciatingly rigorous research, there has never been evidence proving that
people who are depressed have different amounts of serotonin or norepineph-
rine in their brains from those who are not depressed. 25 Keep in mind that the
diagnosis of depression does not involve a test for chemical imbalance. To
the contrary, it is based on verbal responses to a general protocol designed on
the basis of the DSM category of depressive mood disorder.
The psychopharmacological industry’s public relations campaign in favor
of these drugs is a monumental success. 26 In the United States, the manufac-
turers are allowed to market their medicine directly to consumers. Potential
consumers are advised in numerous television commercials to, in so many
words, instruct their doctors in the drugs they need. It is one of the most
successful rhetorical efforts ever conducted. The chemical imbalance story is
now a cultural truism. It will take a major paradigm shift to upset this deeply
ingrained belief. Once accepted, the appeal to the authority of science, even
if the science is false, is a difficult barrier to transcend.
Interestingly, all websites of the drug companies state explicitly that the
causes of depression are not precisely known. Additionally, they agree that it
is not known why or how the antidepressants work. Nevertheless, they com-
monly allege that “each antidepressant class affects the levels of chemicals in
the brain called neurotransmitters, which are thought to be involved in regu-
lating mood” (my italics). 27 In other words, the diagnosis of depression is
ultimately a result of administering the drugs; a tautology of post hoc ergo
propter hoc prevails. Subsequent trips to the doctor, should there be any, are
to check on the drug regime for compliance. If the patient is better as evi-
denced by satisfactory responses to questions asked, it is assumed that the
disease was there but is now subdued. The medicine creates the disease.
Small wonder, then, that the growth of the malady has increased dramatically
since the advent of the drugs. To reiterate, before that time, depression was
an exceedingly rare diagnosis.
brain and the world, obedient to the former with incidental incorporation of
the latter.
Now, this bifurcated philosophy of self and world is very convenient in
the short run because it serves the interests of every player on the “field,” to
employ a technical term from Bourdieu. 32 If consciousness originates in the
brain, the study of human beings may be strictly localized, rendered a materi-
al object, and then owned by neuroscientists. That is, in fact, the case as the
discourse on these matters is now nearly the exclusive province of medical
psychiatry. Research in this area is heavily financed by grants, and the mon-
ey goes to that which is generally understood to be natural science proper,
not to human science. Psychotherapy, the traditional human science ap-
proach, employed talk as a qualitative treatment for an affective problem on
the presupposition that emotions inhere in communicative relations. Psycho-
analysis, for example, focuses on conflicts internalized from social circum-
stances. By contrast, neuroscience suggests that there is a quantifiable deficit
in the brain, the supposed center of consciousness. If consciousness is univer-
sal, it can be treated as such with little or no regard for self, significant other,
social group, or cultural mores. It is important to be quite clear about this. In
his phenomenology of depressive experience, Karp puts the issue concisely:
“Research about a feeling disorder that does not get at people’s feelings
seems, to put it kindly, incomplete.” 33
The American definition of depression and its subsequent diagnosis and
treatment is now conquering the planet. Antidepressants are prescribed
worldwide and increasingly in third world countries. Mind is assumed to be
identical with the brain, which is of course universal. The pill is the answer
for depression everywhere for all peoples. 34 Indeed, antidepressants are as-
sumed by the World Health Organization (WHO) to be an instrument of
democracy. The WHO has already said a third of the world’s population is
depressed, a body, name, and person being nonessential to the diagnosis and
presumably the subsequent prescription of drugs. The brain is assumed to be
the arbiter of social being, so the antidepressants are believed to move pa-
tients into activity, bodies of passivity finally employable and made useful.
Consider the ethical agents involved in the enterprise as a whole and
including the APA, WHO, FDA, CDC, medical schools, pharmaceutical in-
dustries, psychiatrists, medical doctors and other prescribers of medicine,
health insurance companies, the media, and organizations such as the Mental
Health Alliance. Then, in this vast, global, and powerful institutional matrix,
there is the patient, a self in the world, whose relational being or selfhood is
eclipsed in a ubiquitous and bewildering maze of money, medical authority,
pseudo-science and popular myth. No doubt many are ill, but the choice of
context for diagnosis and treatment is pre-inscribed by the dominant medical
conception. From a semiotic point of view, ethical being is already deter-
mined in the depression discourse; authentic choosing is a feeble option in
Communicology and the Ethics of Selfhood 297
relation to the pre-coded paradigm of choice. The sign disease that is at-
tached to the illness condenses and absorbs it, ruling out all alternative per-
spectives.
I should like to conclude this enterprise by considering something nearly
absent in discussions of depression and treatment: the conscious experience
of being drugged by antidepressants. First, the experience of depression was
excluded. Second, the experience of being on the prescribed medicine was
not studied. Or, more precisely, the medical concern was with possible ad-
verse side effects of the prescriptions but not the experience, per se. It is
important to realize that earlier drugs caused severe side effects. Though later
drugs did much better with unintended effects in the short-run, they remain
unstudied for their long-term effects. Keep in mind that despite the myths
perpetuated around them, antidepressants have no disease-specific effects of
any kind.
If the APA and the DSM had not essentialized the symptoms of a disease
from a medical point of view, perhaps doctors could read them as phenomen-
ological signs worthy of alternative and contextual coding. Witnessing
changes of appetite, insomnia, loss of energy, restlessness and irritability,
feelings of worthlessness and guilt, difficulty in making decisions, and suici-
dal thoughts, 35 it seems odd not to consider in a valid diagnosis the everyday
communicative matrix in which the patient exists. Clearly, the medical cod-
ification of disease disciplines and enforces an unnatural diagnosis based in a
manufactured link of these symptoms to a presupposed, but imaginary,
chemical problem in the brain. Only by not being attentive to the patient can
such a diagnosis proceed. In every symptom mentioned, we have an issue of
discordant worldly experience where consciousness begs to be compre-
hended as consciousness of; whereas, in every case and as a whole, the
diagnosis and treatment defy context. In fact, the medical diagnosis de-con-
textualizes everyday experience. 36
There are few studies of the experience of being on SSRIs. Empirical
phenomenological investigations 37 of depression have been conducted, but
there are fewer than a handful that have considered what it is like to be on the
prescription regimen. Drawing upon these avant-garde ventures, an interest-
ing comparison can be made between experiencing depression and experi-
encing the antidepressants. 38 The APA, DSM, and other sources already
mentioned attempt to get at the essence of depression, but in politically
invested descriptive language. The phenomenology of depressive experience
depicts it as a problem of selfhood intrinsic to communicative relations with
the world. In particular, Karp specifically concludes that “depression, at its
root, is a disease of disconnection.” 39 Carefully and insightfully probing the
essential structure and lived-body meaning of the illness, Karp accepts the
disease label but puts it in context by reference to “a cultural chemistry that
catalyzes depression.” 40 It is a problem that manifests as social isolation,
298 Isaac E. Catt
NOTES
1. Alain Ehrenberg, The Weariness of the Self: Diagnosing the History of Depression in the
Contemporary Age (Montreal and Kingston: McGill-Queens University Press, 2010/1998).
2. “Antidepressants,” accessed March 10, 2013, www.drugs.com/drug-class/anti
depressants.html.
3. Isaac E. Catt, ed., “Pierre Bourdieu: A Sign,” special issue, American Journal of Semiot-
ics 22, no. 1–4 (2006).
4. Deborah Eicher-Catt and Isaac E. Catt, Communicology: The New Science of Embodied
Discourse (Madison Teaneck, NJ: Fairleigh Dickinson University Press, 2010). See also the
website of the International Communicology Institute (ICI): www.communicology.org.
5. Isaac E. Catt, “Communicology and Narcissism: Disciplines of the Heart,” Journal of
Applied Psychoanalytic Studies 4, no. 4 (2002): 389–411.
6. Loren Mosher, “Are Doctors Betraying Their Patients?,” Psychology Today (September
1, 1999): 5, www.psychologytoday.com/articles199909/are-psychiatrists-betraying-their-
patients?page=5.
7. American Psychiatric Association, “Depression,” accessed June 8, 2012, www.
psychiatry.org/mental-health/key-topics/depression.
8. Isaac E. Catt, “Communicology and the Worldview of Antidepressant Medicine,” in
“Semiotics and Worldview,” ed. Isaac E. Catt, special issue, American Journal of Semiotics 28,
no. 1–2 (2012): 81–103.
9. Ibid.
10. Richard L. Lanigan, Phenomenology of Communication: Merleau-Ponty’s Thematics in
Communicology and Semiology (Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1988), 3–17.
11. Isaac E. Catt, “The Signifying World Between Ineffability and Intelligibility,” Review of
Communication 11, no. 2 (2011): 122–44. See also Isaac E. Catt, “Korzybski and Charles
Sanders Peirce,” in Korzybski and . . . , eds. Corey Anton and Lance Strate (Austin, TX:
Institute for General Semantics, 2012).
12. Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM-5). (Washington, DC:
American Psychiatric Association, 2013.
13. For an exemplary study, see David Karp's Speaking of Sadness: Depression, Disconnec-
tion, and the Meanings of Illness (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996). Karp writes from
the perspective of symbolic interaction, which is part of the pragmatism tradition, the essence
of which is semiotic phenomenology (James, Peirce, Dewey, Mead, Morris).
14. World Health Organization (WHO), “Mental Health: Depression,” accessed May 15,
2012, www.who.int/topics/depression/en/.
15. L. D. Pratt, J. Brody, and Quiping Gu, “Antidepressant Use in Persons Aged 12 and
Over: United States, 2005–2008,” NCHS Data Brief, number 76, Hyattsville, MD: National
Center for Health Statistics. 2011, accessed June 1, 2012, cdc.gov/nchs/data/databriefs/db76.
html.
16. R. Kadison, “Getting an Edge: Use of Stimulants and Antidepressants in College,” New
England Journal of Medicine 353, no. 11 (2005): 1089–91.
17. See also Bornfeld, Steve, “Antidepressants Most Popular Prescription Medication in
U.S.,” Las Vegas Review Journal, August 22, 2011, accessed May 15, 2012, www.
reviewjournal.com/life/health/antidepressants-most-popular-prescription-medication-us.
Communicology and the Ethics of Selfhood 301
18. Johns Hopkins Bloomberg School of Public Health, “Prescriptions for Antidepressants
Increasing among Individuals with no Psychiatric Diagnosis,” August 4, 2011, accessed June 5,
2012, www.jhsph.edu/publichealthnews/press_releases/2011/mojtabai_antidepressant_prescrip
tions.html.
19. Robert Whitaker, Anatomy of an Epidemic (New York: Crown Publishers, 2010).
20. I summarize a considerable body of literature in this section of the chapter. See Isaac E.
Catt, “Communicology and Worldview” cited above. A number of recognized experts within
psychiatry and psychology trace these matters: See Alain Ehrenberg, cited above, as well as the
following: Gary Greenberg, Manufacturing Depression: The Secret History of a Modern Dis-
ease (New York: Simon & Schuster, 2010); Irving Kirsch, The Emperor's New Clothes: Ex-
ploding the Antidepressant Myth (New York: Basic Books, 2010); Ethan Watters, Crazy Like
Us: The Globalization of the American Psyche (New York: Free Press, 2010); Joanna Mon-
crieff, The Myth of the Chemical Cure: A Critique of Psychiatric Drug Treatment (New York:
Palgrave MacMillan, 2008); Elliot Valenstein, Blaming the Brain: The Truth about Drugs and
Mental Health (New York: Free Press, 1998). These sources supplement growing research
available in academic journals that is opening the path to a reconsideration of the dominant
drug paradigm in psychiatry, if not an outright revolt against it.
21. Karp, Speaking of Sadness, 81.
22. Kirsch, The Emperor’s New Clothes, 28.
23. Ibid., 30.
24. Ibid.
25. Valenstein, Blaming the Brain, 132–36.
26. See Greenberg, Manufacturing Depression, for an enlightening history of the industry’s
public relations campaign to sell the chemical imbalance in the brain story.
27. “Depression Treatments,” Pristiq.com, www.pristiq.com/depression-treatments.aspx?
source=google&HBX_PK=s_antidepressants&o=47362258|223601699|0&skwid=
43700003070516905&13942.949999999999.
28. Isaac E. Catt, “Communicology for an Era of Precarity: A Research Paradigm for Inter-
rogating the Confluence of Social Structures and Human Experience,” in Prekarisierung und
Flexibiliierung [Precarity and Flexibility], ed. Rolf Dieter Hepp (Munster: Westfalisches
Dampfboot, 2012).
29. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, trans. Donald A. Landes (Lon-
don: Routledge, 2012/1945). Merleau-Ponty announces his argument for the communicative
ground of consciousness from the very beginning of this text: “The phenomenological world is
inseparable from subjectivity and intersubjectivity, which establish their unity through the
taking up [la reprise] of my past experiences into my present experiences, or the other person's
experience into my own” (lxxxiv). In the concluding passage of his Preface he states: “All
forms of knowledge are supported by a ‘ground’ of postulations, and ultimately upon our
communication with the world as the first establishing of rationality” (lxxxv).
30. Catt, “Communicology and Worldview.”
31. See for example Arthur Kleinman, Leon Eisenberg, and Byron Good, “Culture, Illness,
and Care: Clinical Lessons for Anthropologic and Cross-Cultural Research,” Focus 4 (2006):
140–49.
32. Isaac E. Catt, “Pierre Bourdieu’s Semiotic Legacy: A Theory of Communicative Agen-
cy,”American Journal of Semiotics 22, nos. 1–4 (2006): 31–54.
33. Karp, Speaking of Sadness, 12.
34. Watters, Crazy Like Us.
35. These are the symptoms specified by the American Psychiatric Association, www.
psychiatry.org/mental-health/key-topics/depression.
36. This de-contextualization of living context by means of antidepressants is particularly
devastating when it is imperialistically imposed on unsuspecting cultural others. See Vieda
Skultans for a specific phenomenology of this in an intercultural situation: “From Damaged
Nerves to Masked Depression: Inevitability and Hope in Latvian Psychiatric Narratives,” So-
cial Science and Medicine 56 (2003): 2421–31. I have pursued this aspect of the issue in
several public lectures and conference papers.
302 Isaac E. Catt
37. The word empirical is frequently and too casually used as a reference to quantitative
research. The Greek term empirikos actually refers to experience, that which is closest to lived-
body consciousness. Thus, quantification is distinctly nonempirical activity, and in that quality
rests its utility—its abstraction from experience. Empirical phenomenology examines embodi-
ment of signs, which is the production of meaning.
38. My proceeding analysis surmises a good deal of reading in this area. See exemplary
studies by Ehrenberg, Skultans, and Karp referenced above, as well as the following: Pamela
Joan Aselton, “The Lived Experience of College Students Who Have Been Medicated with
Antidepressants,” (Dissertation: University of Massachusetts, Amherst, Open Access Disserta-
tion Paper, 2010), 235, scholarworks.umass.edu/open_access_dissertation/235; Jay Teal,
“Nothing Personal: An Empirical Phenomenological Study of the Experience of Being-on-an-
SSRI,” Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 40 (2009): 19–50; Virginia Moreira, “Critical
Phenomenology of Depression in Brazil, Chile and the United States,” Latin-American Journal
of Fundamental Psychopathology 4, no. 2 (2007): 193–218; R. Kadison, “Getting an Edge: Use
of Stimulants and Antidepressants in College,” New England Journal of Medicine 353, no. 11
(2005): 1089–91.
39. Karp, Speaking of Sadness, 178.
40. Ibid., 177–78.
41. Ibid., 26–27.
42. Ibid., 27.
43. Isaac E. Catt, “Communicology and Human Conduct,” Presidential Address to the
Semiotic Society of America, 37th Annual Meeting, Toronto, Ontario, Canada, November 3,
2012, forthcoming in Semiotica.
44. Kleinman, Eisenberg, and Good, “Culture, Illness and Care.”
45. Moncrieff, The Myth of the Chemical Cure.
46. Karp, Speaking of Sadness, 79.
47. Ehrenberg, Skultans, Karp, Aselton, Teal, Moreira, and Kadison.
48. Isaac E. Catt and Deborah Eicher-Catt, “Communicology: A Reflexive Human Sci-
ence,” in Communicology: The Science of Embodied Discourse (Madison Teaneck, NJ: Fair-
leigh Dickinson University Press, 2010 [also distributed by Rowman & Littlefield]), 15–29.
See also Isaac E. Catt and Deborah Eicher-Catt, “Semiotics in Mainstream Communication
Studies: A Review of Principal USA Journals in the Context of Communicology,” Review of
Communication 12, no. 3 (2012): 176–200.
49. Robert Frost, “Nothing Gold Can Stay,” Poets.org, www.poets.org/viewmedia.php/
prmMID/19977#sthash.vEde3dT2.dpuf, originally published in The Poetry of Robert Frost, ed.
Edward Connery Lathem, 2nd rev. ed. (New York: Henry Holt and Company, 1979).
BIBLIOGRAPHY
———. “Communicology for an Era of Precarity: A Research Paradigm for Interrogating the
Confluence of Social Structures and Human Experience.” In Prekarisierung und Flexibiliie-
rung [Precarity and Flexibility], edited by Rolf Dieter Hepp, 260–74. Munster: Westfalis-
ches Dampfboot, 2012.
———. “Korzybski and Charles Sanders Peirce.” In Korzybski and . . . , edited by Corey
Anton and Lance Strate, 69–99. Austin, TX: Institute for General Semantics, 2012.
———, ed., “Pierre Bourdieu: A Sign,” Special issue, American Journal of Semiotics 22, no.
1–4 (2006).
———. “Pierre Bourdieu’s Semiotic Legacy: A Theory of Communicative Agency.”
American Journal of Semiotics 22, nos. 1–4 (2006): 31–54.
———. “The Signifying World Between Ineffability and Intelligibility.” Review of Communi-
cation 11, no. 2 (2011): 122–44.
Catt, Isaac E.and Deborah Eicher-Catt. “Communicology: A Reflexive Human Science.” In
Communicology: The Science of Embodied Discourse, edited by Deborah Eicher-Catt and
Isaac E. Catt, 15–29. Madison Teaneck, NJ: Fairleigh Dickinson University Press, 2010
(also distributed by Rowman & Littlefield).
———. “Semiotics in Mainstream Communication Studies: A Review of Principal USA Jour-
nals in the Context of Communicology.” Review of Communication 12, no. 3 (2012):
176–200.
“Depression Treatments.” Pristiq.com. www.pristiq.com/depression-treatments.aspx?source=
google&HBX_PK=s_antidepressants&o=47362258|223601699|0&skwid=
43700003070516905&13942.949999999999.
Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM-5). (Washington, DC: American
Psychiatric Association, 2013.
Ehrenberg, Alain. The Weariness of the Self: Diagnosing the History of Depression in the
Contemporary Age. Montreal and Kingston: McGill-Queens University Press, 2010/1998.
Eicher-Catt, Deborah and Isaac E. Catt, eds. Communicology: The New Science of Embodied
Discourse. Madison Teaneck, NJ: Fairleigh Dickinson University Press, 2010.
Frost, Robert. “Nothing Gold Can Stay.” Poets.org., www.poets.org/viewmedia.php/prmMID/
19977#sthash.vEde3dT2.dpuf. Originally published in The Poetry of Robert Frost, ed. Ed-
ward Connery Lathem, 2nd rev. ed. New York: Henry Holt and Company, 1979.
Greenberg, Gary. Manufacturing Depression: The Secret History of a Modern Disease. New
York: Simon & Schuster, 2010.
Johns Hopkins Bloomberg School of Public Health, “Prescriptions for Antidepressants Increas-
ing among Individuals with no Psychiatric Diagnosis,” August 4, 2011, accessed June 5,
2012, www.jhsph.edu/publichealthnews/press_releases/2011/mojtabai_antidepressant_
prescriptions.html.
Kadison, R. “Getting an Edge: Use of Stimulants and Antidepressants in College.” New Eng-
land Journal of Medicine 353, no. 11 (2005): 1089–91.
Karp, David. Speaking of Sadness: Depression, Disconnection, and the Meanings of Illness.
New York: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Kirsch, Irving. The Emperor’s New Clothes: Exploding the Antidepressant Myth. New York:
Basic Books, 2010.
Kleinman, Arthur, Leon Eisenberg, and Byron Good. “Culture, Illness, and Care: Clinical
Lessons for Anthropologic and Cross-Cultural Research.” Focus 4 (2006): 140–49.
Lanigan, Richard L. Phenomenology of Communication: Merleau-Ponty’s Thematics in Com-
municology and Semiology. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1988.
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. Phenomenology of Perception. Translated by Donald A. Landes Col-
in Smith. London: Routledge, 2012/1945.
Moncrieff, Joanna. The Myth of the Chemical Cure: A Critique of Psychiatric Drug Treatment.
New York: Palgrave MacMillan, 2008.
Moreira, Virginia. “Critical Phenomenology of Depression in Brazil, Chile and the United
States.” Latin-American Journal of Fundamental Psychopathology 4, no. 2 (2007):
193–218.
304 Isaac E. Catt
Mosher, Loren. “Are Doctors Betraying Their Patients?” Psychology Today, September 1,
1999. www.psychologytoday.com/articles199909/are-psychiatrists-betraying-their-patients?
page=5.
Pratt, L. D., J. Brody, and Quiping Gu. “Antidepressant Use in Persons Aged 12 and Over:
United States, 2005–2008.” NCHS Data Brief, number 76, October 2011. Hyattsville, MD:
National Center for Health Statistics. 2011. Accessed June 1, 2012. cdc.gov/nchs/data/
databriefs/db76.html.
Skultans, Vieda. “From Damaged Nerves to Masked Depression: Inevitability and Hope in
Latvian Psychiatric Narratives.” Social Science and Medicine 56 (2003): 2421–31.
Teal, Jay. “Nothing Personal: An Empirical Phenomenological Study of the Experience of
Being-on-an-SSRI.” Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 40 (2009): 19–50.
Valenstein, Elliot. Blaming the Brain: The Truth about Drugs and Mental Health. New York:
Free Press, 1998.
Watters, Ethan. Crazy Like Us: The Globalization of the American Psyche. New York: Free
Press, 2010.
Whitaker, Robert. Anatomy of an Epidemic. New York: Crown Publishers, 2010.
World Health Organization (WHO). “Mental Health: Depression.” Accessed May 15, 2012.
www.who.int/topics/depression/en/.
Afterword
Machiavelli’s Question Mark and the
Problem of Ethical Communication
Gerard A. Hauser
305
306 Gerard A. Hauser
For those who look on such collisions as rare, exceptional, and disastrous, the
choice to be made is necessarily an agonizing experience for which, as a
rational being, one cannot prepare (since no rules apply). But for Machiavelli,
at least in The Prince, The Discourses, Mandragola, there is no agony. One
Machiavelli’s Question Mark and the Problem of Ethical Communication 307
chooses as one chooses because one knows what one wants, and is ready to
pay the price. 2
Since neither the church nor the laboratory nor speculative reason can
offer a final solution, Machiavelli’s advice to his prince, whether intended or
not, undermines the quest for an ultimate answer to the question of how
humans should live. If more than one valid answer is possible, then “the idea
of the sole, true, objective, universal human ideal crumbles.” 3 The infection
of doubt thenceforth threatens all monistic constructions. The only antibody
would seem to be retreat to the security of one ideal as the true goal, with its
accompanying consequence that no cost is too high to insure it is reached.
The second and third sections of this volume provide stunning evidence that
the spirit of monism is alive and kicking, and they advance multiple perspec-
tives for an ethical (possibly equally monistic) standpoint in its face. On the
other hand, if how we live is solely a matter of choice, then the path leading
to empiricism, pluralism, tolerance, and compromise is equally possible, as
some of these same studies show.
The ramifications of Machiavelli’s question mark surround us in whatev-
er frame we choose to border our image of human life. Monism is a choice,
but it is not a decisive one. Today’s questions are, in that regard, reminiscent
of those Adam Smith wrestled with in The Theory of Moral Sentiments. 4
Smith shared the Enlightenment’s concern with a virtuous society. Con-
fronted with the reality of a civil society in which conflicting moral, political,
and economic interests were cast in relationships of mutual dependency,
Smith recognized a subtle but important shift in social organization from the
Western tradition of civic virtue.
The ideal of civic virtue that permeated Greek and Roman political
thought emphasized the role of the individual as a public person. A virtuoso
public performance that commanded respect, including an oratorical tour de
force, was a personal accomplishment and a sign of arête for the Greeks and
virtú for the Romans. Sociologist Adam Seligman observes that since civic
virtue projects itself as conformity of particular wills to the general will, its
moral vision is of personal will and action regulated by the sovereign author-
ity of the political community, not the sovereign or despot. 5 He goes on to
explain that the community’s political authority does not refer to the obvious
sociological fact that it is the source of morality but that the community
exists as morality. At its heart, the civic virtue tradition locates social good
by subjugating the private self to the public realm. 6 This line of thought
continues into the present era, as the work of Hannah Arendt illustrates. 7 By
contrast, the eighteenth-century Scottish moralists saw the moral basis of
society as a private ideal. A civil society was one in which individual respon-
sibility for actions toward others could be counted on to exceed pure ex-
308 Gerard A. Hauser
change value because, as Adam Smith argued, humans are naturally inclined
to benevolent sentiments toward one another.
Smith’s The Theory of Moral Sentiments 8 developed a psychology based
on a person’s ability to project him or herself into the situation of the other.
Smith argued that sentiments, which condition our approval or disapproval of
actions and, therefore, guide actions, arise from our ability to imagine, based
on personal sensations, the pain or sorrow or joy we would experience were
we in the other’s situation. 9 The capacity to project ourselves into the other
person’s situation bears equally on explaining approval or disapproval of
another’s opinions. It is not just that we accept or reject the opinions they
hold, but our approbation or disapprobation comes from their capacity to
arouse our sympathy. Moreover, since the aroused sympathy is internal to the
judging individual, it actually is approval of what he or she personally holds
true. Even in those cases where a person’s opinions imitate views of the
powerful, the wealthy, or current fashion, Smith regarded the locus of ap-
proval as internal to the individual, by “the man within the breast, the ab-
stract and ideal spectator of our sentiments and conduct.” 10
Smith’s doctrine on sympathy carried over into the public arena of civil
society, for which benevolent sentiments ultimately were responsible for
guiding conduct. Enlightenment thinkers recognized that in civil society you
did not have to like those with whom you interacted; so long as interactions
in the complex web of human dialogue were marked by tolerance and kind-
ness, differences could be overcome. 11 Unlike the tradition of civic virtue, in
which a person’s merit was established by public conduct, in the civil society
tradition, the quality of relations with strangers found its basis in the individ-
ual self rather than a person’s public being. Individual actions were seen and
judged by others, not in terms of virtuosity, as they are in the civic virtue
tradition, but in terms of propriety. Smith contended that when we judge
matters of conduct, we are like a spectator who “must endeavor, as much as
he can, to put himself in the situation of the other.” 12 This observation was
generalized in the impartial spectator as arbiter of social passions, leading to
generosity, humanity, kindness, compassion, mutual friendship, and esteem
“even towards those who are not particularly connected with ourselves.” 13
The impartial spectator provides a referent outside the individual subject
whose judgment insured the virtue, first, of personal conduct by freeing the
individual from purely subjective and self-interested understandings of con-
duct. As such, this imagined judge gathers our approbation, even in our
personal judgment of our own conduct:
We endeavour to examine our own conduct as we imagine any other fair and
impartial spectator would examine it. If upon placing ourselves in his situa-
tion, we thoroughly enter into all the passions and motives which influenced it,
Machiavelli’s Question Mark and the Problem of Ethical Communication 309
Smith’s model founded morality within the individual and then carried its
belief in benevolence to provide guidance for the self-regulation of society. It
presented the impartial spectator as a guarantor of virtuous public actions
that accommodated differences without being blinded to personal interests or
blinded by them. The pursuit of interests was thought to counterbalance the
stronger passions that, if left unchecked, would produce the tyranny of feudal
lords who kept their vassals in economic servitude and would produce the
injustices of avarice and ambition that interfered with free association and
commerce. 15 The natural inclination to advance one’s interests within the
“marketplace” of civil society inevitably brings one’s interests into competi-
tion with those of others, and here the communal other of the impartial
spectator, internalized as the “invisible hand,” 16 offers the rational basis for
comparing and reaching a just resolution. Smith’s words on this point de-
serve repeating because they reflect confidence in a public exchange guided
by a morality that accepts difference as inherent to public life:
sion. They were concerned with the construction of a human world, one that
might be otherwise and that could be shaped by molding public sentiment to
act in a particular way through the force of the better argument. In this world
of contingencies, certain traits of mind and performance mattered. Since a
world of contingencies lacks hard and fast rules for conduct, they understood
that intelligent and virtuous choice was subject to situational considerations.
They valued insight that provided guidance for conduct in the given case 19
and accorded ethos (attribution of moral character) to those who demonstrat-
ed habits (hexis) of phronesis (prudence), arête (virtue), and eunoia (good
will toward the other). They recognized the conditional nature of choices
based on doxa—common beliefs and opinions, not the opinions of experts or
knowledge of absolute truth—since decision making in a democracy was by
ordinary citizens who were not necessarily experts on the subject at hand and
since contingencies did not permit the certainty of absolute truths.
Although Western thinking about communication has been grounded on
contingency, Machiavelli’s question mark was not part of its founding equa-
tion. Rhetoric’s ancient origins offered accounts—both in theory and prac-
tice—of public discourse tempered by the relative ethnic homogeneity
among those who were engaged in public deliberation and the common val-
ues they might use as touchstones to resolve differences. In The Liberal
Temper of Greek Politics, Eric Havelock offers translation of portions of an
oration written by Thrasymachus. 20 It provides a glimpse into the thought of
ancient Athenians and an opportunity to hear what this figure, once freed
from Plato’s ventriloquism that renders him an unscrupulous pleader, actual-
ly thought about governance. Since the oration was to be delivered by an-
other, the speaker in this excerpt might be taken as a representative figure for
how Greeks thought about resolving differences. The speaker addresses his
audience as divided by conflict that war has intensified through personal
disasters. Their leaders have told them grand things about their city, while
their lived experiences have been dire. The oligarchs have encouraged them
to blame their misfortunes on the gods or fortune rather than the policies of
those in charge. And thus factions have formed around false issues that keep
them divided. He continues:
They [contesting factions] think their discourses are mutually antithetical but
are not aware that the policies pursued are identical, nor that the discourse of
their opponents is inherent in their own. Ask yourselves, going back to the
beginning: what is it that both sides are looking for? In the first place there is
the issue of the constitution of the fathers; this, which throws them into confu-
sion, can be grasped mentally with the greatest of ease and is supremely
something in which citizens have community. Thus (a) as to matters beyond
our own cognition we must of necessity depend on the discourse of olden
times to tell us about them; and (b) as to anything that came within the purview
Machiavelli’s Question Mark and the Problem of Ethical Communication 311
of the older generation we must ascertain from the men with the informa-
tion. 21
The speaker points to a common heritage that offers guidance to both sides:
A shared constitution established by the city’s fathers gives them commu-
nity; the discourses of the past give guidance when matters seem to defy
reason; history and other sources of information also offer instruction on
issues the elders confronted. In short, there are shared cultural resources that
resolve differences into unity and offer guidance both sides can accept when
dealing with contingency because, at their core, the antagonists are one.
Machiavelli’s question mark signifies the demise of such unifying re-
sources as the defining conditions of communication. Catapulted from con-
tingency into radical contingency, we now experience life as increasingly
complex networks of actors defined by those attributes that accentuate their
diversity rather than their unity. Radical contingency makes associations
fragile and shared commitment to agreements tenuous, often because rela-
tions and issue resolution are defined in terms of efficacy. It is comparatively
easier to attend to the Other when the Other is of our own tribe than when she
or he is definitively different. It costs very little to extend ourselves to those
with whom we share bonds of affiliation that define us monistically. We do
not have to challenge our core beliefs, alter our core behavioral principles, or
risk our sense of self by considering the possibility that what we believe may
actually be false.
In the absence of consensus on core assumptions, the idea that things
could be otherwise means that all things are possible, and if all things are
possible, who is to say that one mode of conduct is ethically superior to
another? Doesn’t ethical probity depend on the standpoint of the actor? Cer-
tainly interpreted in a means-ends calculus, the telos of action that prizes
achieving one’s goal would seem to ratify the validity of a self-interested
standpoint. That orientation, however, would lead to the Hobbesian night-
mare of each against all that was the bête noire to which Locke, Montes-
quieu, and Rousseau responded by reintroducing the idea that humankind
forms a community of sorts constituted under natural law and in existence
prior to society, which is itself prior to the government. Their refutation of
the Hobbesian identification of society with its political organization posited
the idea of civil society as a third arena, independent of the family and the
state, engaged in conscious acts of self-management that were integrated
with the state.
The idea of civil society raises an alternative by conceptualizing a buffer
between, on the one hand, the ideology of the state that defines the person’s
meaning in terms of a political identity, or the ideology of the church that
defines the person’s meaning in terms of a paradisiacal afterlife, and on the
other hand, the family that finds the meaning of life in satisfying private
312 Gerard A. Hauser
needs and desires. It is that area in which a society is defined by the diversity
of its members engaged in all manner of practices of self-regulation—in the
marketplace, in the polis, and in moral relations. Machiavelli’s question mark
brings us to awareness of the agonizing choices among incompatible alterna-
tives in social practices, or worse still, in one’s personal public and private
life (which now, in a postmodern era, becomes increasingly difficult, if not
impossible, to keep apart). On this reading, there is no escaping the ethical
problem of attending to the Other, and of its centrality to community.
At the risk of putting too fine a point on it, the problem of communication
ethics today is akin to Dietrich Bonhoeffer’s challenge of Christian disciple-
ship rendered in his contrast between “cheap grace” and “costly grace.” In
Discipleship, he writes about the Christian Church as having succumbed to
“cheap grace,” grace without the cross. 22
Cheap grace costs nothing. It comes from hearing the gospel as giving you
forgiveness once you acknowledge your sins, giving you the consolation of
forgiveness without imposing a demand for taking up Christ’s cross. In the
face of evil, it opens the door for rationalizing retreat instead of running the
risk of consequences from taking a stand, rationalizing standing on the side-
lines, confident that by faith alone one’s failed efforts are excused when the
combat with evil is placed in the hands of God. By contrast, “costly grace”:
Christians can only defeat evil with “costly grace,” attained through the
discipleship dictated by the Sermon on the Mount. The price of following
Christ’s homily, whose political trajectory leads to activism and passive re-
sistance, is high: “Whenever Christ calls us, his call leads us to death.” 25
Similarly, as Austin S. Babrow and Lindsey M. Rose argue in chapter 7,
there is no credit in easy virtue. It requires little moral will to be friendly to
those with whom it is easy to form bonds of affiliation, those who share a
monistic construction of the good and the just. The more difficult path is in
tending to the needs of those who cost us something, who are the Other who
threatens our position, who may not reciprocate by acknowledging our at-
Machiavelli’s Question Mark and the Problem of Ethical Communication 313
NOTES
1. Isaiah Berlin, “A Special Supplement: The Question of Machiavelli,” New York Review
of Books, November 4, 1971, www.nybooks.com/50/Machiavelli.
2. Ibid.
3. Ibid.
4. Adam Smith, The Theory of Moral Sentiments, 6th ed., ed. D. D. Raphael and A. L.
Macfie (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1790/1976).
5. Adam Seligman, “Animadversions upon Civil Society and Civic Virtue in the Last
Decade of the Twentieth Century,” in Civil Society: Theory, History, Comparison, ed. John A.
Hall (London: Polity Press, 1995), 200–204.
6. Charles Taylor, Philosophical Arguments (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1995),
204–24.
7. Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958).
8. Smith, Theory of Moral Sentiments.
9. Ibid., 10–13.
10. Ibid., 153.
11. Seligman, “Animadversions upon Civil Society,” 204.
12. Smith, Theory of Moral Sentiments, 21.
13. Ibid., 38.
14. Ibid., 110.
314 Gerard A. Hauser
15. Albert O. Hirschman, The Passions and the Interests (Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 1977/1997).
16. Smith, Theory of Moral Sentiments, 184.
17. Ibid., 135.
18. Ibid., 16–34.
19. See Martha Nussbaum, The Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy
and Philosophy (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1986), 290–317.
20. Erik Havelock, The Liberal Temper in Greek Politics (New Haven: Yale University
Press, 1957).
21. Ibid., 232–33.
22. Dietrich Bonhoeffer, Discipleship, ed. Geffrey B. Kelly and John D. Godsey, trans.
Martin Green and Reinhard Krauss, vol. 4, Dietrich Bonhoeffer Works (Minneapolis: Augsburg
Fortress Press, 1937/2001).
23. Ibid., 44.
24. Ibid., 45.
25. Ibid., 87.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Arendt, Hannah. The Human Condition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958.
Berlin, Isaiah. “A Special Supplement: The Question of Machiavelli.” New York Review of
Books, November 4, 1971. www.nybooks.com/50/Machiavelli.
Bonhoeffer, Dietrich. Discipleship. Vol. 4 of Dietrich Bonheoffer Works. Edited by Geffrey B.
Kelly and John D. Godsey. Translated by Martin Green and Reinhard Krauss. Minneapolis:
Fortress Press, 1937/2001.
Havelock, Erik. The Liberal Temper in Greek Politics. New Haven: Yale University Press,
1957.
Hirschman, Albert O. The Passions and the Interests. Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1977/1997.
Nussbaum, Martha. The Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philoso-
phy. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1986.
Seligman, Adam. “Animadversions upon Civil Society and Civic Virtue in the Last Decade of
the Twentieth Century.” In Civil Society: Theory, History, Comparison. Ed. John A. Hall,
200–223. London: Polity Press, 1995.
Smith, Adam. The Theory of Moral Sentiments. 6th ed. Ed. D. D. Raphael and A. L. Macfie.
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1790/1976.
Taylor, Charles. Philosophical Arguments. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1995.
Index
315
316 Index
Being, 56, 57, 60, 61, 62, 63, 259 choice, 65, 65–66, 67, 68, 69, 110, 111,
being-in-the-world, 56, 57, 60, 61 113, 176n37, 260, 306–307, 310, 312
being-singular, 62, 66, 67, 68 Cicero, 6, 29
being together, xiii, 56, 59, 60, 61–63, citizenship, 274, 275
64–65, 66, 67, 68–69 civil society, 33, 306, 307, 308, 309, 311
belles lettres, 10, 11, 41, 50n67, 51n92 collective self, 154, 155, 161, 162, 163
belonging, 82, 83, 89, 244, 279 commemoration, xiv, 163, 164, 168, 172,
benevolence, 39, 108, 108–109, 110, 118, 173
119, 120, 123n25, 309; benevolent common sense, 15, 20n5, 28–29, 29–30,
impulse, 112, 116, 117; benevolent 39, 48n32, 49n51, 287
sentiment, xiv, 104, 105, 108, 108–109, common space, xv
110, 111, 112, 113, 114, 115, 119, 121, communication ethics, ix, ix–xi, xii, xiv,
122, 308 xv, xvi, 56, 57, 59, 66, 76, 103, 104,
Benhabib, Seyla, x 105, 108, 109, 113, 114, 116, 122, 186,
Benoit, William, 155, 165, 175n10 206, 215, 233, 248, 288, 312, 313
Bergson, Henri, 78–79, 85–86; durée, 78, communicative matrix, 287–288, 293, 296,
86 297, 298
bias, ix, xi, 57, 105, 164, 169, 185 communicology, 287, 288, 294
Bitzer, Lloyd, 80–81, 88; exigence, 80–81, community, xiii, xvi, 25, 38, 55, 56, 57, 58,
88, 153, 155, 157, 158; fitting response, 59–60, 61, 61–64, 65, 66, 67, 68, 118,
xiii, 80–81, 88; rhetorical situation, 80, 174, 189, 245, 307, 309, 310–311, 311,
156, 159 312, 313; anarchic, 62, 63, 64, 67, 69
Bonhoeffer, Dietrich, 312; cheap grace, conjectural history, 32–33
312; costly grace, 312 consciousness, 9, 38, 77–78, 85–86, 105,
Broadie, Alexander, 26, 28, 28–29, 30, 31, 110–111, 115, 131, 193, 196, 197, 256,
32, 36, 47n6, 47n20, 49n39 257, 266, 267, 277, 287, 288, 294–295,
Buber, Martin, 57, 84, 132 295–296, 297, 298; double
Buchan, James, 26, 36, 39, 41, 42, 44, 45; consciousness, 192
Crowded with Genius, book, 26, 36; contemplation, 15, 108, 117, 253, 256,
crowded with genius, concept, 25, 36, 259, 261, 263–264, 265, 266–267
37, 44, 46 content, xi, xi–xii, xii, xiii, xiv–xv, xv, xvi,
Buchanan, George, 29, 32, 49n45 60, 61, 62, 63, 76, 108
Burke, Edmund, 42 continuation, 219–220, 221, 222
Burke, Kenneth, 155, 158, 162, 175n24, cosmopolitan, xiii, 32, 33, 42, 46, 133
175n26, 177n72, 186, 193, 200; comic creativity, xiii, xiv, xv, xvi, 25, 25–26, 30,
frame, 158, 159, 167, 169, 170, 171, 31, 32, 35, 36, 41, 46, 100, 101, 104,
173, 177n72, 186, 187, 193, 200, 206; 105, 105–106, 106, 107, 108, 110–111,
mortification, 155, 162, 165; romantic 115, 116, 119, 121, 121–122, 158
frame, 159, 162, 167, 168, 169, 170, crisis, xvi, 55, 153, 162, 275, 282; crisis
175n26; tragic frame, 158, 162, 167, management, 153, 157; image crisis,
171, 177n46, 186, 200 157
Burns, Robert, 45–46 crowdedness, xiii
democracy, 56, 68, 119, 160, 162, 163, 20; Jewish Enlightenment (Haskala),
164, 165, 296, 310 9–10; radical enlightenment, 3, 9;
depression, 285–286, 286–287, 287, 288, Scottish Enlightenment, xiii, 25, 25–26,
288–289, 289–290, 290–291, 291–293, 28, 28–29, 30, 31, 32, 33, 34, 35,
293–294, 294–295, 296–297, 297, 298, 35–36, 36, 41, 42–43, 45–46, 48n38,
299 306
Descartes, René, 8, 11, 29, 77, 288, 295; epistemology, 15, 65, 80, 306
57th principle, 77 ethico-political, 68, 69
description, 233, 240 ethics, xi, 31, 39, 42, 55, 56, 57, 58, 60,
Dewey, John, 68, 235, 300n13 62–63, 64, 65–66, 66, 67, 75–76, 79,
dialogue, 57, 75–76, 76, 79, 81, 84, 85, 86, 79–80, 81, 84, 85, 87, 87–88, 88, 97,
87, 100, 133, 156, 160, 173, 217, 219, 98, 100, 103, 110, 129, 130, 131–132,
241, 246, 247, 248, 253, 254, 259, 299, 145, 154, 157, 158, 253–254, 256, 257,
308; dialogic ethics, 57, 75, 85; internal 258, 260, 260–261, 262, 264, 264–265,
self-dialogue, 26, 257 266, 267, 305, 306, 307, 309, 311, 312,
difference, ix, x, x–xi, xii, xiii, xiv, xv, 57, 313; diversity ethics, 99–100, 101, 286,
98, 99, 133, 140, 142, 186, 188, 206, 287, 288, 291, 296, 299; ethical end,
224, 233, 253, 254, 260, 265, 277, 278, 154; ethical response, 62, 79; ethical
309; radical, x–xi, xii third, xv; ethics of friendship, 129, 130,
Dionysios, 82 132–133, 136, 137, 141, 142, 145, 147
disease, 286, 288, 291, 294, 295, 297, 298, ethnocentric, 271, 275
299 ethos, xvi, 7, 67, 157, 162, 164, 246,
disparate multiplicity, 59, 67 271–272, 273, 273–275, 281, 306, 310;
distance, 33, 35, 132, 138, 220, 233 redemptive ethos, xvi, 272, 281–282
divergence, xii evaluation, 130, 131, 235, 250
diversity, xiii, xiv, xvi, 97, 98, 99–100, existential authenticity, xvi
100–101, 169, 172, 311. See also
ethics, diversity ethics fairness, 234–235, 248–249
doxa, 20, 310 Ferguson, Adam, 30, 32, 33, 36, 38, 43–44,
Drummond, George, 37–38, 38, 43, 45, 45–46, 48n21, 49n39, 50n61
51n91, 52n134 Fiumara, Gemma Corradi, 82, 83–84, 87
dwelling, xi, xv, 35, 46 forgiveness, 134, 139, 140, 158, 159, 167,
dyad, 58, 59, 61 173, 174, 224, 312
Foucault, Michel, 70n6, 192–193
Edinburgh, 26, 31, 36, 37, 38, 40, 41, 43, fracking, xv, 237, 240, 241, 242, 243, 244,
43–44, 45, 51n92, 51n100, 52n135, 245, 249
52n140; University of, 31, 45, 46, framing, 106, 154, 159, 161, 164, 167, 168,
47n18, 49n47, 49n51, 50n67, 51n92 171, 198, 234, 243, 245, 245–246, 249,
efficiency, xiv, 89 251n22, 255; reframing, 159, 161
Einstein, Albert, 76 freedom, x, 8, 18, 27, 43, 106, 107, 145,
emotion, 10, 29, 39, 107, 108, 119, 254, 146, 158, 163, 255, 256, 258, 260, 266
262, 293, 296, 299 French Enlightenment. See Enlightenment
Enlightenment, xiii, 3–4, 5, 6, 7, 9, 12, 13, French Revolution, 3, 27, 36, 44
15, 18, 19, 20n5, 25, 26, 27–28, 30, 31, friendship, xiv, 35, 129, 132, 133, 135,
34, 34–35, 39, 50n67, 77, 306, 307, 136, 137, 138, 139, 140, 141–142, 143,
308, 309; age of reason, xiii; Counter- 144, 145, 146, 192, 193, 196, 224, 308
enlightenment, 13, 14, 20n5; French
Enlightenment, 30; German Germany, xvi, 5, 7, 9, 15, 21n15, 261,
Enlightenment, 4–5, 5–6, 7, 9, 10, 13, 271–273, 277–278, 279, 279–280,
318 Index
281–282; language, 5–6, 11, 18, 20; identity, xvi, 59, 271, 273, 275, 277, 281;
nationality, 277, 278, 281; Nazi, xvi, identity [of person], 111, 118, 217, 257,
277, 278, 279, 280; professorship, 5. 290, 293; identity formation, xvi;
See also Enlightenment organizational identity, 218, 220, 222,
Glasgow, 26, 29, 31; University of, 28, 29, 223
31, 35, 39, 40, 41, 47n6, 47n18, 48n31, illness, 286, 288, 291, 292–293, 295, 297,
50n71 298
God, 8, 14, 15, 29, 34, 39, 48n21, 50n71, image, 153, 155, 156, 157, 158, 160–161,
52n140, 59, 254, 312 163, 165, 169, 173, 218, 273; image
good, 108, 109, 113, 121, 129, 130, 131, repair, 155, 156, 175n10; image
135, 139, 216, 217, 220, 221, 224, 225, restoration, xiv, 154, 155, 160, 162,
261, 262, 264, 274 163, 165–166, 172, 172–173, 174,
good life, xi, 26, 265 175n10, 281
imagination, 33, 39, 42, 86, 106, 133
Hall, Tony, 153, 170, 176n38 institution, 44, 98, 99, 100, 111, 215–216,
Hargrove, Frank (delegate), 170, 171, 217, 218, 219–220, 222, 223, 224,
178n86 224–225
Hauser, Gerard, xvi intellective sense, 105, 105–106, 107, 108,
Heidegger, Martin, 70n1, 82–83, 83, 111, 115, 116, 121
84–85, 89, 105, 217, 259 inter-discourse, 257–258, 258
Heraclitus, 77, 82 interpersonal, 219, 220, 223, 224, 299;
hermeneutics, 103, 112, 235, 250n3, 253, ethics, 132; relations, 129, 141, 145
254, 264, 265, 266, 267 interruption, ix, xiv
higher education, 97, 98, 99, 100, 218–219 intuitive attunement, 104
Highlander, 40, 42, 43, 51n83 Isherwood, Christopher, xv, 183, 184–185,
historical moment, ix, xi, xiii, xiv, xvi, 224, 186, 188, 189–192, 193–195, 196–197,
255 197, 199–200, 200–201, 202, 203, 206
Hobbes, Thomas, 28, 33, 39, 311 Isocrates, 79–80, 82
Home, Henry, 38, 42, 51n92, 51n98 Israel, Jonathan, 3, 9
Home, John, 40, 42, 46; Douglas, 40, 44,
221 Jacobi, Friedrich Heinrich, 4, 7, 9, 12, 13,
hope, xvi, 26, 219 14, 15, 16–19, 20n5
horizon, xiii, 68, 76, 121, 215, 220, 223, Jacobite, 37–38, 41, 43, 44, 50n82, 51n83
305 Jacobite Rebellion, 33, 38, 43, 50n60
human condition, xi, 105, 109, 217, 223, Jefferson, Thomas, 30, 163
225, 254, 255, 267 Johannesen, Richard, x
humanities, xii, 108 Johnson, Samuel, 40, 44, 45, 52n107,
Hume, David, 28, 30, 32, 33, 34–35, 36, 52n135
37, 38, 39–40, 41, 42, 44, 45, 47n18, justice, xiv, 58–59, 64, 80, 104, 107, 110,
47n20, 49n39, 49n47, 52n107, 52n130; 112, 120, 121, 134, 136, 137, 142,
A Treatise of Human Nature, 39, 41 142–143, 146, 157–158, 159, 160, 167,
humility, 253, 254, 258, 261, 262, 264, 174, 262, 262–263, 263, 265, 266, 274
265, 266, 267
Hutchinson, Francis, 28, 30, 33, 34, 35, 39, kairos, xiii, 76, 79–81, 81, 83, 84, 85, 87,
41–42, 44, 45, 48n31–48n32, 50n71 87–88, 88, 89, 153, 255
Hutton, James, 30, 35, 45, 46, 49n39 Kant, Immanuel, 4, 5, 6–7, 12, 13, 18–19,
hypertextuality, xvi 21n15, 26, 27–28, 28, 33, 59, 59–60,
60–61, 62, 63–64, 77–78, 130; “An
Answer to the Question: What Is
Index 319
Spinoza, Baruch, 3–4, 7–9, 9, 10, 11, 13, Tymieniecka, Anna-Theresa, xiv,
14, 15, 16, 17, 19; Ethics, 8–9; 103–104, 104–105, 105–106, 106–108,
Tractatus-Theologico-Politicus, 8, 8–9 108, 109, 109–110, 110–111, 112–113,
Spinozism, 4, 7, 7–9, 9, 11, 12, 13, 14, 15, 114, 115, 116, 121; Imaginatio
16, 19, 21n15 Creatrix, 105, 106, 110, 116
standpoint, xi, xii, xv, 32
Stewart, Dugald, 32, 33–34, 49n51 valuation, 104, 106–107, 110, 111, 119.
subjectivity, 3, 104, 156, 301n29 See alsomoral valuation
subjugated knowledge, 192 value, xii, xiii, xiv–xv, xv, xvi, 9, 99, 100,
sublime, 42, 45 106, 154, 157–159, 162, 164, 167, 168,
suicide, 186, 196, 200–201, 289 172, 173, 233, 234–235, 239, 242, 244,
surrender, 112, 113, 118 245, 245–246, 247–248, 248, 249, 250,
Swearingen, C. Jan, 26, 28, 28–29, 30, 82, 254, 274, 277
273 Virginia, xiv, 153, 154, 160–161, 161,
symbolic violence, xv, 185, 200 161–165, 165–166, 167–168, 169,
sympathy, 30, 33, 34, 41, 42, 306, 308, 309 170–171, 171–174, 177n53;
symptoms, 286, 293, 297 Jamestown, Virginia, 162, 163–164,
165, 172, 173
telos, 3, 56, 68, 69, 70, 216, 223, 255, 263, virtue, xi, 33, 39, 103, 113, 261, 262,
311 262–263, 265, 266, 281–282, 306, 307,
temporality, xiii, 25, 76, 78, 79, 85, 86, 88, 308, 310, 313; communicative virtue,
89, 106, 217, 219, 258; linear, 85; 215; virtue ethics, 253, 260, 260–261,
nonlinear, 78, 83, 85, 88 264, 265, 274
tetrad, 157, 158, 161, 167; agency, 157, Voltaire, 28, 36
162–163, 163–164, 165, 166, 167, 168,
168–169, 172, 174, 177n72; justice, Watt, James, 35
157–158, 159, 160, 167, 174; peace, Whereasclause, 162, 163–164, 165, 168,
157–158, 159, 167, 174; truth, 169, 170
157–158, 159, 163, 166, 167–168, 169, Whig, 37–38, 38, 46
170, 174 Whitefield, George, 39, 51n100
third, the, x, xv, 58, 224, 309 wonder, 253, 255, 262
time, 60–61, 62, 63, 64–65, 66, 67, 69, 76, work, 215, 216, 217, 220, 221, 223, 261,
76–79, 80–81, 83, 85, 86–87, 88, 89, 266
153, 157; diachronic, 88, 89 World War II, xvi, 115, 155, 170, 201, 271,
tolerance, 22n30, 30, 32, 194, 199, 307, 273, 275, 281
308, 313
topos, 81, 278 Žižek, Slavoj, 7, 90n29
Toulmin, Stephen, 25, 130, 146
About the Contributors
323
324 About the Contributors
munication and rhetoric in America, and theories of public rhetoric. His most
recent book is The Ethics and Politics of Speech: Communication and Rheto-
ric in the Twentieth Century (2009).