A Critique of Markedness-Based Theories in Phonology

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 30

Eastern Illinois University

The Keep
Faculty Research and Creative Activity Communication Disorders & Sciences

October 2001

A critique of markedness-based theories in


Phonology
Naomi Gurevich
Eastern Illinois University, [email protected]

Follow this and additional works at: http://thekeep.eiu.edu/commdis_fac


Part of the Phonetics and Phonology Commons

Recommended Citation
Gurevich, Naomi, "A critique of markedness-based theories in Phonology" (2001). Faculty Research and Creative Activity. 8.
http://thekeep.eiu.edu/commdis_fac/8

This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Communication Disorders & Sciences at The Keep. It has been accepted for inclusion in
Faculty Research and Creative Activity by an authorized administrator of The Keep. For more information, please contact [email protected].
Studies in the Linguistic Sciences
Volume 31, Number 2, Fall 2001

A CRITIQUE OF MARKEDNESS-BASED THEORIES IN PHONOLOGY

Naomi Gurevich
University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign
[email protected]

The notion of markedness has been prevalent in phonology since


its use by one of the founders of the Prague school of phonology,
Trubetzkoy (1939). In contemporary writing it is most often used as a
measure of the relative naturalness of linguistic elements. In this paper
I explore the use of markedness in phonology literature and argue that
it is an ill-defined notion that relies on circular reasoning and, quite
often, leads to conflicting or vacuous predictions. Specifically, I
question the generative theory-internal notion that markedness is
encoded in the grammar. I focus on the multi-dimensional aspect of
markedness in phonology and the various criteria used as diagnostics
for the assignment of markedness values. I conclude that the predictive
and descriptive powers of the dimensions of markedness, when taken
individually, are far superior to those of markedness used as a cover
term.

1. Literature Survey

1.1. Introduction

The goal of this paper is to explore the commonly accepted notion in


phonology that markedness is somehow encoded in the grammar. I argue that, at
best, markedness is a notion that exists only for linguists to make our job of
describing languages easier and our generalizations more elegant. This argument
is similar to the one made by Cole and Hualde (1998) against abstract Underlying
Representations (UR’s):

We find that, without any doubt, UR’s are a valuable, and perhaps even
essential tool for linguistic field work, whose adoption often allows for
simple and concise statements of phonological patterns. However, our
concern in this paper is not with the task of the linguist in identifying and
describing sound patterns, but with the psychological status of UR’s as an
encoding [of] the sound representation of a word in the mental lexicon. (p.3)
2
Similarly, I question the psychological status of markedness as an encoding of
some universal ‘naturalness’ in the phonology, although I readily admit that the
notion of markedness may very well be a useful tool for linguists in a number of
ways.

Providing conclusive evidence in favor of my argument will surely prove


impossible. The existence of markedness as some psychological entity, much like
Universal Grammar (UG) and many other linguistic mechanisms posited by
generativist theorists, is an unfalsifiable hypothesis.1 It is a deus ex machina: like
the Greek literary mechanism used as a last resort to resolve overcomplicated
plots, markedness is a supposed faculty that humans possess which can somehow
resolve the tangled plot of phonology by linking the generativist-posited symbolic
system to some physical reality. Despite the lack of evidence for the existence of
some such faculty or even, as is shown in the present paper, agreement on what
markedness means, it is a commonly used notion in the field of phonology as well
as in other domains of linguistics.

Markedness goes by many names and a variety of definitions. It is a notion


that is deeply embedded, although to varying degrees, in linguistic theories. And
yet there is no consensus on what the term means. A similar sentiment is often
articulated in other surveys that target the notion of markedness (recent work on
this front includes Battistella 1990, 1996 and Rice 1999). Battistella (1990) notes
that

Different approaches to markedness (and there are many) define the


markedness relation in different ways, apply the concept to different domains
of inquiry, and integrate it into different theoretical approaches. (p.ix)

And Rice ends her paper with the following conclusion:

Markedness is something about which linguists come to have strong


intuitions. In many areas there is agreement: Something called markedness
exists. It is multidimensional, with several factors involved at various levels
(e.g., featural, combinatorial, positional). Variation exists in what can pattern
as unmarked, although it is not without limit. However, many questions
remain. […] The issues surrounding markedness do not appear to be ones
that will find quick solutions, and the area promises to continue to be one of
lively debate for some time to come. (p.37)

For the reasons detailed above, and others that will be expanded on within this
paper, exploring the notion of markedness is both important and difficult.

In this part of the paper I consider and critique some of the major definitions
of markedness that have been explored in the literature. I examine the entrance of
the term markedness into mainstream linguistics jargon, how this notion gained
ground, and how it became so closely tied to linguistic universals, and hence to
3
some psychological reality. I also attempt to isolate the often controversial theory-
specific (more often than not, generative theory-specific) assumptions that are
presupposed in various uses of markedness theory. The present discussion calls
attention to the complications and misconceptions involved in the use of the notion
of markedness in contemporary theories and helps build a case against the view
that markedness is in some way significant to speakers.

My exploration of the notion of markedness in phonology literature is, at


first, chronological. I start with the origin of the term in the writings of one of the
founders of the Prague school of phonology, Trubetzkoy’s Principles of
Phonology (1939), where the notion of markedness is heavily utilized in the
classification of types of neutralization. Chomsky and Halle note that “the notion
of markedness is hardly mentioned in the phonological literature of the 1940s and
1950s” (1968:402). Hence The Sound Pattern of English (1968) is the next work I
explore on the subject. Guitart’s Markedness and a Cuban Dialect of Spanish
(1976) draws on both Trubetzkoy’s and Chomsky & Halle’s work, as well as on
Jakobson’s (1968, 1971) and Postal’s (1968), and offers a clear idea of the
development of markedness after its entrance into the generativist framework.
Herbert’s Universals and Markedness (1986) and Greenberg’s Language
Universals (1966), as is obvious from the titles, further the view of markedness as
a universal. Kaye’s On the Alleged Correlation of Markedness and Rule Function
(1979) showcases the complications of utilizing markedness notions within
definitions of rule types in phonology. I finish with Rice’s Featural Markedness in
Phonology: Variation (1999), which begins with a review of various studies
related to markedness and, perhaps inadvertently, leads to the conclusion that
existing work complicates, rather than explicates, the situation.

1.2. Principles of Phonology (Trubetzkoy 1939)

It is commonly agreed that the term ‘mark’ originates with Trubetzkoy, one
of the founders of the Prague school of phonology. The notion of markedness in
his work is associated, to varying degrees, with articulatory complexity,
combinatory possibilities of sounds, phonological statistics, functional load, and
neutralization. Most prevalent, and most often cited, is Trubetzkoy’s observation
that the outcome of neutralization is normally the unmarked member of an
opposition. Having borrowed the term from Trubetzkoy, generativists suggest that
in contrast to their own approach he considered markedness assignments to be
language-specific rather than universal; however, it is his work that sparked the
use of markedness in the context of universal tendencies of language.

Trubetzkoy wrote that if two phonemes share the same set of features, except
for one feature found in only one of the phonemes, this feature is the ‘mark’ and
involves an extra articulatory gesture. Guitart (1976) points out that within the
generative framework it is not always the case that the marked member involves
an extra gesture. For example, a [+nasal] element is considered marked, but it is
the unmarked oral sounds that require the extra gesture of closing the velum.
4
While the generativist argument that the marked element does not always require
an extra gesture is well taken, the example shows how complex this situation
really is. The resting position of the velum is neither completely open nor closed.
Furthermore, in running speech the position of the velum depends on the
surrounding sounds.

From a notational point of view, for Trubetzkoy the ‘+’ member of an


opposition usually corresponds to ‘marked’. That is, [+nasal] is marked whereas [–
nasal] is unmarked; similarly, [+glottal] is marked whereas [-glottal] is unmarked,
etc. In adopting the term markedness generativists depart from Trubetzkoy’s work
in this respect as well. Since an element could be formally described as [+nasal] or
[-oral], the ‘marked = +’ aspect of Trubetzkoy’s use of the term was abandoned.

In his classification of neutralization types, at the highest level of the


typology Trubetzkoy distinguishes between contextually (in the environment of
specific phonemes) and structurally (in specific positions in the word) conditioned
neutralization. Within these two basic sets he also distinguishes between
dissimilative and assimilative neutralizations.2 The notion of markedness relates to
the four types of dissimilative contextually conditioned neutralization. That is,
these types of neutralization can serve as diagnostics for markedness values, as
detailed below.

Contextually Conditioned Dissimilative Neutralization: The trigger for this type of


neutralization is the same feature being neutralized (e.g. voicing triggers voicing
neutralization); also, by definition, this involves change in polarity (+– or –+)
when not privative. There are 4 possible types of this neutralization:

a) In the vicinity of both members of the same opposition: In many languages


there is neutralization between voiced and voiceless obstruents in the vicinity
of voiced and voiceless obstruents. (1) are examples from Serbo-Croatian:

(1) Serbo-Croatian obstruent voicing:


a. srb ‘Serb. (masc.)’
srpski ‘Serbian’ srpkinja ‘Serb. (fem.)’
b. naruc&iti ‘to order’ narudz&ba ‘the order’

In (a) the labial obstruent is voiced when it is word final (srb) but voiceless
when it is followed by voiceless obstruents (srpski and srpkinja).
Similarly, in (b) voicing of the palatal obstruent is determined by the voicing
properties of the following obstruents: voiceless in naruc&iti but voiced
when followed by b in narudz&ba. Another example comes from French,
where the opposition between nasalized and nonnasalized vowels is neutralized
before all (+/- nasal) vowels.

b) In the vicinity of the marked member, but retained in the vicinity of unmarked
member: For example, in Slovak the opposition between long and short vowels
5
is neutralized after a syllable with a long nucleus. Another example comes
from Sanskrit, where the opposition between dental and retroflex n is
neutralized after retroflex s` (which occurs even with intervening vowels,
labials, or gutturals), but is retained after nonretroflex consonants.

c) In the vicinity of both members of a related phonological opposition: For


example, in Lezghian the opposition between rounded and unrounded
consonants is neutralized before and after high vowels (u, u_, i) because these
vowels are members of the opposition of timbre rounded/unrounded; but the
low vowels (a, e) are not.

d) In the vicinity of the marked member of a related opposition, but retained in


the vicinity of the corresponding unmarked member: For example, in Japanese,
Lithuanian and Bulgarian the opposition between palatalized and
nonpalatalized consonants is only phonologically valid before back vowels,
and is neutralized before front vowels.

Types (a) and (c) cannot serve as diagnostics for markedness because the features
in question could be either marked or unmarked; types (b) and (d) can, because
there is a difference in results depending on whether the marked or unmarked
feature is in the vicinity.

Trubetzkoy’s work on Phonological Statistics, while not incorporated into


his own notion of markedness, is relevant to later work on the subject. According
to Trubetzkoy, statistics in phonology are significant because they can show how
often a specific phonological element of a given language recurs in speech (token
frequency), and more importantly for our purposes, they show the importance of
the functional load of such an element or of a specific phonological opposition
(type frequency):

By this method of examining the vocabulary it is also possible to determine


for each language in numbers the extent to which the individual phonological
oppositions are utilized distinctively (their functional load), as well as the
average load of the phonemes in general. (pp.267-268)

However, markedness per se is never cited by the author as related to functional


load. His discussion focuses on the relationship between neutralization and
functional load, with markedness playing a role only due to its use in the definition
of certain types of neutralization.

Trubetzkoy turns to Zipf’s (1935) theory that frequency depends on the


degree of articulatory complexity. Trubetzkoy rejects this theory, arguing that it is
difficult to pin-point the degree of complexity of sounds; for example, which is
more complex: tense vocal cords but relaxed organs of mouth, or lax cords and
tense mouth organs? Trubetzkoy categorically rejects the explanation of
phonological facts by means of biological, extra-linguistic, causes. However, he is
6
willing to translate Zipf’s theory into phonological terms; for this he uses
markedness. That is, markedness, rather than degree of complexity, determines
frequency.

Such use of markedness as a substitute for some abstract notion, in this case
the difficult to measure degree of complexity, suggests that markedness values are
concrete, and even absolute. This tendency is echoed in the generative framework,
where markedness values are linked to +/- feature values. And yet, when
phonologists started work on determining markedness values they found
themselves relying on many of the notions deemed abstract and in need of
translation into markedness values, such as articulatory effort, for their decisions
(e.g., Guitart 1976, Postal 1968, and Greenberg 1966 to name a few). This type of
circular thinking can be observed throughout the literature on markedness.

On the subject of frequency, Trubetzkoy adds that one must take into
account the possible presence and the extent of neutralization. That is, the
differences between unmarked and marked opposition members, and the
differences between oppositions that can be neutralized and those that cannot,
affect phoneme frequency. Put simply, the presence and extent of neutralization
affects the frequency of a sound: if neutralization can occur, the unmarked
elements, which are the usual results of neutralization, will be more frequent. It
becomes obvious that, in this diagnostic for frequency, it is not the markedness
values that matter but whether or not the elements in question can be results of
neutralization.

Trubetzkoy adds that this diagnostic does not always work because in some
languages the markedness relationship cannot be objectively established. Since all
other references to markedness in his work can be translated into ‘presence of
neutralization’, this statement can be understood as the following: in some
languages there may be cases of neutralization where no one member of an
opposition is more likely to be the target of the process than the other member. In
such cases, then, the presence and extent of neutralization does not affect the
frequency of the elements in question. As discussed in §1.4, Guitart (1976)
attempts to resolve the problem of neutralization where the outcome, contrary to
expectations, appears to be marked. This becomes an important issue once, based
on Trubetzkoy’s work, the outcome of neutralization is formally declared a
diagnostic for markedness values.

Frequency plays an important role in the “extent of utilization” of an


opposition. By examining the vocabulary it is possible to determine for each
language the extent to which the individual phonological oppositions are utilized
distinctively, as well as the average load of the phonemes in general. Trubetzkoy
distinguishes between “economical” and “wasteful” languages: the “economical”
languages have numerous words that are only distinguished by one phoneme, and
the percentage in which theoretically possible phoneme combinations are realized
is very high. The “wasteful” languages have a tendency to distinguish words by
7
several phonological elements and to realize only a small percentage of the
theoretically possible phoneme combinations.

Here Trubetzkoy discusses one of the key issues in phonology: the relation
between sound substitutions and meaning. Neutralization will have different
functional consequences for economical and wasteful languages. For economical
languages the functional load of an opposition is expected to be higher, and
phonological neutralization is more likely to yield functional neutralization.3 It is
vital to note that markedness has no functional purpose whatsoever. Its only
connection to the subject is its use to distinguish between two of the types of
contextually conditioned dissimilative neutralization. In Trubetzkoy’s discussion
of functional load, no one type of neutralization is singled out; in this particular
discussion, markedness brings nothing to the party: it has no theoretical value.

In summary, Trubetzkoy not only brings the term markedness into the
phonological arena; he also draws associations between this notion and many of
the characteristics that markedness takes on in later literature (e.g., neutralization,
functional load, and frequency), as well as its use as a translation mechanism from
abstract notions such as articulatory complexity. However, as I suggest in the
discussion of his work, in most cases Trubetzkoy intended to draw connections
between the occurrence and result of neutralization processes, rather than
markedness values per se.

1.3. The Sound Pattern of English (Chomsky and Halle 1968)

In the final chapter of The Sound Pattern of English (SPE) Chomsky and
Halle discuss unresolved problems from previous chapters. In particular, they
acknowledge that their previous discussion suffers from the fundamental
theoretical inadequacy of being overly formal and ignoring the fact that features
have intrinsic content.

For example, their theory suggests that the “naturalness” of a class can be
measured in terms of the number of features needed to define it. This diagnostic of
naturalness often fails, as in the case of voiced obstruents: they have the more
complex definition, as they are measured with a larger number of features than all
voiced segments, but are intuitively more natural as a class than the class of all
voiced segments (vowels as well as consonants). The authors point out that the
content of the features, rather than the form of the definition, is responsible for
naturalness. Hence, ignoring the content is precisely the reason for the failure
detailed above.

Another example where their framework is found lacking is provided by


independent phonological processes which somehow work together. E.g., Cole
(1955) and Fudge (1967) subsume the following processes in Tswana under the
single heading of “strengthening”: voiced stops become ejectives after nasals, non-
obstruent continuants become voiceless aspirated plosives, and obstruent
8
continuants become voiceless aspirated affricates. Chomsky and Halle agree, but
lament the lack of a formal device to bring out the relation between the 3
processes.

A third example of where the framework is lacking centers on the fact that a
vowel system as in (2) is more natural than those in (3) and (4), but the measures
of evaluation previously suggested by the authors cannot make such a distinction.

(2) i u (3) i u (4) u# I


e o e o U
a é ê a

Similarly, no distinction can be made between a more natural situation where all
the vowels in a language are voiced, and an unattested situation where all vowels
in a language are voiceless.

The above examples suggest a need to extend the theory in order to


accommodate the effects of the content of features. This would allow the theory to
distinguish between the natural and expected configurations and the less natural
and less expected ones. In other words, the final chapter of SPE addresses
situations where linguists can tell something is natural (whether it is one element
as compared to another, a class of elements, a system within a language, or the
relationship between some processes in a given language) but have no way to
formalize this intuition within the framework as articulated at that point.

Note that these observations, used to motivate the need for a notion of
markedness, are indeed valuable to the linguist; but the question of what value a
language learner could derive from such knowledge, e.g., that some element in
their language is more natural than another element, or that their vowel inventory
is not as natural as their neighbors’, is not addressed. This is due to the underlying
generative belief (at least at that stage of the theory) that the job of the linguist is
the same as the job of the learner, and that the theory’s formalisms are equivalent
to the manner in which learners code language. That is, that which is common
across languages is presumed to be part of the UG and hence the knowledge
learners are born with, and that which is unique about each language is what
learners must acquire about their individual languages. The linguistic
formalization of a language’s grammar is, therefore, primarily a matter of
identifying the exceptions and additional rules to the UG, which according to this
theory mimics the job of a learner.4 But while it makes sense for speakers of
English to know that nasals assimilate in place of articulation to following stops in
their language, what benefit is there to also being aware that this process is much
more natural than, say, iI after non palatalized consonants (as occurs in
Russian)? While arguing against this particular generative approach is beyond the
scope of the present paper, I do try to emphasize that most knowledge
encompassed by markedness issues is knowledge a learner either does not require
(such as knowing a process in their language is more natural than a process in
9
some other language) or can easily determine with no prior knowledge (e.g., that
intervocalically voiced stops are easier to articulate than voiceless ones).

An especially significant aspect of the framework detailed in SPE requires


that rules that lead to the more natural configurations (e.g., voicing vowels,
determining a vowel system as in (2), etc.) do not add to the complexity of a
grammar because, as noted above, such rules are part of the UG and are therefore
part of a speaker’s knowledge already. Instead, the absence of such rules should
increase complexity because a speaker must “unlearn” such rules if they are absent
in their language. Thus, the Praguian notion of ‘marked’ and ‘unmarked’ values of
features are incorporated into the framework in order to inject the intrinsic content
of features into the theory; furthermore, the values are used in a manner such that
unmarked values do not contribute to complexity.

As a first step, the specifications in a matrix that constitutes a lexical entry


are u (for unmarked) and m (for marked), along with + and –. We then add
universal rules of interpretation which systematically replace the symbols u
and m by the symbols + and –. Being universal, these rules are not part of a
grammar but rather contentions for the interpretation of a grammar; they do
not affect the complexity of a grammar, as determined by the evaluation
measure, any more than the rules for interpreting  or {}. (pp.402-403)

Echoing Trubetzkoy’s strategy of substituting markedness values for more


abstract values, as if markedness values were any less abstract, u and m are offered
as the content-wise replacements for the overly formal and content-lacking + and –
. If intrinsic content of features could be evaluated in some absolute (non-abstract)
manner, u and m might be considered less abstract than + and –. However, as
noted above and repeated throughout my work, the diagnostics for assigning
markedness values have remained abstract as well as controversial. In short, it is
difficult to see how adding the abstract translation between phonetic reality and
feature values can possibly resolve the problems of neglecting intrinsic content.

Finally, the authors suggest that with the use of markedness they now have
the machinery for making distinctions between more and less plausible rules in
purely formal terms.

If it should prove possible to define a reasonably short list of such


“plausible” phonological processes and show that all—or the majority of—
the phonological processes encountered in different languages belong to this
set, this would constitute a very strong empirical hypothesis about the nature
of language. (p.427)

That is, what appears natural in human languages, once translated into markedness
terminology, can be used to argue what is natural in languages. This type of
circular reasoning is a recurring theme in markedness based theories.
10
1.4. Markedness and a Cuban Dialect of Spanish (Guitart 1976)

Guitart’s work explores the benefits of the markedness version of generative


phonology over the pre-markedness version. It is for this reason that his work is so
useful in detailing the development of the notion of markedness after its
incorporation into the generative framework. For Guitart, markedness can be
divided into two theories: one is a more general theory of the phonological
structure of human language; the second is a more specific theory of the
phonological structure of the lexicon. I focus on the more general aspect in his
work because the details of markedness and lexical representation, i.e., the
intricacies of encoding information without complicating the grammar, are theory-
specific and marginal to the present discussion.

In §1.3 I discuss the SPE notion that markedness helps formalize intuitions
that linguists have based on the content of features. On a similar note, Guitart
reiterates the idea that certain phenomena are somehow more natural in the
languages of the world. For example,

1. Vowels can be voiceless, but are usually voiced; languages exist that have only
voiced vowels, but there are no known languages that have only voiceless
vowels.
2. When stops are neutralized in word-final position—a fairly common
phenomenon—the result is usually the voiceless stop.
3. Commonly, languages have only two nasal consonants as systematic
phonemes. When this is indeed the case, these two phonemes are most often m
and n.
4. Children learning languages that have liquids usually master these sounds quite
late, and before they do they tend to use glides instead.

These phenomena suggest that certain feature values are more common, more
likely to appear in a given context, are acquired earlier than others, and are hence
more natural. The already familiar strategy detailed in SPE is to characterize this
naturalness, that is based on the intrinsic content of features, with markedness
values. And, Guitart clarifies, since the set of features is universal, the intrinsic
content of features is also universal. Hence if it is decided that it is more natural
for back vowels to be rounded, that decision has been made for all languages.

Guitart is concerned with the heavy burden of making the universal marking
decisions. He relies quite heavily on Postal (1968) for a discussion of marking
criteria:

Relative occurrence of sounds: Certain sounds are very common in the languages
of the world while others are rare. This leads to generalizations such as that
nasality is marked for vowels because vowels are normally oral and there are no
languages with only nasal vowels. Similarly, voicelessness is marked for vowels
because no languages exist with only voiceless vowels.
11

Appearance in position of neutralization: This criterion is already familiar from


Trubetzkoy’s work where it originated as an observation rather than a diagnostic
for markedness values. Postal does not rule out the possibility that for some
features the marked value appears in a neutralized environment, so for him, this
criterion is not absolute. Later in this section I discuss a strategy that Guitart
suggests, which he terms “relative markedness”, to deal with Postal’s mistrust of
this criterion.

Language acquisition and language loss: Guitart refers to Jakobson’s (1968, 1971)
hypothesis that sounds are acquired by the child—and lost by the aphasic—in a
certain fixed, universal order. Those phonological elements that are acquired later
and lost earlier are marked.

Phonological change and dialect variation: It should be expected that sound


change would affect marked elements more often than the unmarked ones. This
should lead to situations where marked features are lost; a hypothetical example is
two dialects that differ in that one has both glottalized and plain consonants while
the other has only non-glottalized consonants (which are cognate with both series
in the former). Opposite situations, however, where there is a merger of unmarked
to marked elements, would be extremely rare or even nonexistent.

Physiological and perceptual investigations: This, according to Postal, is the


strongest evidence in favor of marking decisions. Physiologically speaking,
features requiring special instructions to the organs of speech are expected to be
marked. For example, apicality is marked for labials, palatals, and velars, but
unmarked for dentals because this region is closest to the resting position of the tip
of the tongue. On perceptual grounds, sounds that tend to enhance communication
are regarded as unmarked, while marked sounds tend to obscure the signal. Note
that according to this criterion clicks must be considered perceptually unmarked.

Implicational Hierarchy: The hypothesized order of acquisition underlies a


fundamental assumption made by the theory of markedness, that the organization
of features is hierarchical. That is, there are implicational relations among the
sounds of a language. For example, the presence of fricatives in a language
implies the existence of stops in the same language, because according to the
theory, the feature ‘continuant’ is acquired after the feature ‘obstruent’.

Syntagmatic assignments: With the exception of neutralization, the above


markedness assignment criteria are based on paradigmatic properties. Syntagmatic
markedness assignments can also be made on the basis of naturalness; that is, on
the basis of what sequence of sounds are considered more natural. E.g., CVCV is a
sequence that is most natural on both articulatory and perceptual levels.

At this point Guitart echoes my own criticism of markedness theory,


discussed in §2, that the possibility the criteria may be in conflict is often ignored.
12
However, Guitart focuses his criticism on a much narrower scope than my own.
He refers specifically to the situation where the physiological and perceptual
criteria for markedness assignments conflict. He suggests as an example the case
of voiced and voiceless obstruents: the voiceless ones are unmarked, but the
voiced counterparts are chosen intervocalically because, according to him, while
the voiced obstruents may be marked articulatorily, they are unmarked
perceptually. Guitart does not discuss why intervocalic voicing is natural on
perceptual grounds. While I do not doubt that a conflict between the physiological
and perceptual criteria could arise, the case of obstruent voicing is not an example
of such conflict, but instead, an example of the blurred line Guitart makes between
syntagmatic and paradigmatic markedness assignments. That is, the markedness
assignment of voicing in obstruents should be viewed as contextually determined.
Intervocalic voicing of obstruents is generally agreed upon as unmarked
articulatorily.

In any case, Guitart concludes that in situations where the physiological or


perceptual criteria fail on their own, the use of both criteria at the same time may
supply a fairly natural explanation. He points out the ‘tug of war’ aspect of the
interaction between the two criteria, where certain feature values could be
regarded as unmarked physiologically but marked perceptually, or vice versa. The
author proposes the term “relative markedness” to describe the theoretical
framework that would incorporate the following characterizations of phonological
systems:

1. Not all sounds and sequences of sounds are either perceived or produced with
equal ease.
2. The constraints imposed on the organization of phonological systems and on
the utilization of phonological elements are due to the limitations of the human
structures having to do with the production and perception of speech, and are,
as such, universal.
3. Even though there are phonological elements that are both easy to produce and
easy to perceive, there are elements that are physiologically simple but
perceptually complex and elements that are physiologically complex but
perceptually simple.
4. Neither maximal contrast nor least effort is the main guiding principle in
human communication, i.e., neither the speaker nor the hearer is
overwhelmingly preferred. Phonological elements which are neither too simple
nor too complex—if judged by either the perceptual or the physiological
criterion—will be used more frequently than elements which are least complex
according to one criterion but most complex according to the other.
5. Human communication does not utilize sounds that are both harder to produce
and harder to perceive.

The incorporation of these characterizations5 into a theory leads Guitart to make


the following formalization of three possibilities of markedness categories:
13
1. Elements that are unmarked both physiologically and perceptually
2. Elements that are unmarked physiologically but marked perceptually
3. Elements that are unmarked perceptually but marked physiologically
 But no phonological elements that are marked both physiologically and
perceptually.

We now see that “relative markedness” refers to a type of continuum on


which every element is unmarked on some level, either physiologically,
perceptually, or both. For Guitart, this means that the requirement that the output
of neutralization be unmarked is always satisfied, and the reputation of the
Trubetzkoy-inspired criterion is saved. He seems to have little concern that
“relative markedness” allows any and all sounds to be unmarked on some level,
rendering markedness values completely vacuous.

In summary, Guitart claims that markedness assignments are universal.


When these assignments cannot be made based on physiological or perceptual
grounds, they can rely on the relative occurrence and distribution of sounds in the
languages of the world, including appearance in positions of neutralization;
language acquisition and language disorders; and dialectal variation and sound
change. For cases where the criteria fail to select the appropriate markedness value
for some element, usually due to conflict between physiological and perceptual
considerations, Guitart suggests that markedness can be relative, and proposes a
formalization that renders any sound as unmarked on some level.

1.5. Universals and Markedness (Herbert 1986)

As part of his discussion of the underlying nature of prenasalized consonants


and categorization of the types of half-nasal consonants among the world’s
languages, Herbert studies the relationship between diachronic and synchronic
universals in phonology. Markedness surfaces in his discussion of universals.

Herbert describes a theory of markedness as articulated by Chomsky and


Halle, and reiterated, for the most part, by Guitart. He cites a criticism by Lass
(1972), that within markedness theory considerations of simplicity are not
reconciled with language-internal economy of individual phonological systems.
This criticism is based on the fact that, on a statistical level, the theory’s claims
about the frequency of some highly marked elements (e.g., front rounded vowels
or clicks) might be justified; but as universals they do not hold for languages with
the sound inventories of Swedish or Zulu. The author points out that Lass’s
interpretation of the theory, that the unmarked elements will always gain ground,
is equivalent to claiming that all phonological evolution is directed towards the
development of an optimal sound inventory. Markedness theory does not make
such claims, and according to Herbert, it is able to offer some insight even for
languages with highly marked inventories. That is, on a universal level, systems
such as Swedish or Zulu can still obey some language-internal markedness
considerations.
14

The author points out that the assignment of marked and unmarked values
represents only a class of observations, but that statistical frequencies, diachronic
mergers, synchronic neutralizations, etc. point to the fundamental correctness of
this concept. However, “the theory remains one of observation, one of
probabilities” (p.24). Herbert also concedes that the significance of the theory is
weakened due to a total lack of explanation. He offers to provide some of this
explanation in his classification of prenasalized consonants by pin-pointing and
adding more phonetic information to some level of the symbolic system that links
phonetic reality to feature values.

Herbert’s response to criticism that markedness theory lacks explanation,


adding more phonetic information to some level of this symbolic system, does not
render the system any less symbolic or abstract. Herbert recognizes the fact that
markedness theory is one of observations and implicational statistics. But the
“fundamental correctness”, as he puts it, of these observations nevertheless leads
him, as it does most generativists, to suppose a universality that must be encoded
in the UG.

1.6. Language Universals (Greenberg 1966)

Greenberg attempts to generalize the notion of markedness to mean some


psychological reality, or even human nature, based on the fact that its
characteristics can apply to phonology, grammar and the lexicon. He claims that
the concept of markedness provides the possibility of finding more specific
universals than can be arrived at by purely empirical methods. This rather
grandiose statement is supported with circular arguments: Greenberg looks for the
connection between markedness and universals by isolating the common features
of markedness in the various fields of linguistics; he then uses the fact that he can
identify such common features as evidence for the connection between
markedness and universals.

Greenberg emphasizes the origin of the concept of markedness as arising


from the Prague school of phonology in the context of problems of neutralization
and the archiphoneme: although neutralization is a language-specific phenomenon,
it is generally the same category of sounds which appears in the position of
neutralization in the different languages, that is, the unmarked. He offers this as
the first characteristic of markedness to be shared by other fields of linguistics.

The second characteristic of markedness that Greenberg cites, frequency,


also originates in Trubetzkoy’s work: the unmarked category has higher frequency
(he does not specify type or token frequency, nor does he specify if within a
language or universally). This is related to another characteristic of markedness,
taken from Zipf’s (1935) principle of least effort as well as Trubetzkoy’s
discussion of it, that the more complex is less frequent, and therefore, marked. A
third characteristic of markedness is that the unmarked element will show greater
15
variety of subphonemic variation than its marked counterpart. That is, the more
specified, the more marked, and the more variability (less resistance, more features
can be filled) the less marked. A fourth is that the basic allophone is unmarked.
E.g., in English [t] and [th] are allophones of /t/; [t] is the basic allophone, and is
therefore the unmarked.

Having identified what he considers the main characteristics of markedness,


Greenberg attempts to generalize them to Phonology, Grammar and the Lexicon.
However, while the same major criteria of markedness seem to apply for grammar
and lexicon, in phonology this concept is used differently. Greenberg’s solution is
to construct a grammar and a lexicon in terms of features. And so, going one-by-
one through the above characteristics of markedness for phonology he “translates”
them into the domains of grammar and lexicon. This translation of phonological
characteristics of markedness into other domains then becomes Greenberg’s
evidence for the universality of markedness, and its existence as psychological
reality, and even human nature. Certainly this is the best example of how
markedness is part of the universals of linguistic theory, rather than of languages.

1.7. On the Alleged Correlation of Markedness and Rule Function (Kaye


1979)

Kaye’s work was published in response to Houlihan and Iverson’s


Functionally-Constrained Phonology, appearing in the same volume. Specifically,
Kaye presents data that calls into question the diagnostics proposed by these
authors for whether a rule is neutralizing (contrast-obliterating) or allophonic
(contrast-maintaining). Kaye’s argument is based on the very formal definitions of
neutralization and allophonic rules, which are, in part, dependent on markedness
relations. The uncontroversial assumption that a rule cannot be both neutralizing
and allophonic is complicated by the expectation that a rule that starts out
diachronically as either allophonic or neutralizing must remain as such over time
in the grammar.6 Most importantly for the present paper, Kaye’s work emphasizes
the circular nature of markedness definitions, as well as definitions of other
phenomena that formally depend on markedness (e.g., neutralization).

Houlihan and Iverson state that rules which convert marked segments into
unmarked ones must be neutralization rules, and all rules which are not
neutralizing are allophonic. Given this definition, Kaye points out that it is hardly
surprising that neutralization results in less-marked segments. Furthermore, since
the presence of marked segments in a language typically implies the presence of
their unmarked counterparts (we know this as implicational hierarchy), it is to be
expected that rules that result in unmarked segments will do so in the context of a
phonological inventory that already contains these segments. In the same line of
reasoning, the claim that rules resulting in relatively marked segments are
allophonic rules follows from the fact that marked segments are found less
frequently and are thus less likely to be found among the underlying phonemes of
16
a language or as the output of a phonological rule applying before the rule in
question.

Kaye concludes, therefore, that the fact that these definitions are generally
true is in no way an argument in their favor, but merely a consequence of their
formalizations. Put simply, defining these two types of rules using markedness
relations, when markedness relations are basically defined using the rules they
participate in, is circular and provides no insight into either situation.

To illustrate his point Kaye discusses an example from Algonquin where a


rule converts marked segments to unmarked ones, but is obviously an
allophonic—and not neutralization—rule. This, and other examples in Kaye’s
work, clarify how Houlihan and Iverson’s principles fail because their definitions
lead to contradictions. In many dialects of Algonquin there is a rule that devoices
initial obstruents. This initial devoicing rule turns relatively marked segments
(voiced) into relatively unmarked ones (voiceless) and ought to be a neutralization
rule following Houlihan and Iverson’s definitions. But in fact it is an allophonic
rule because although both voiced and voiceless obstruents exist in Algonquin,
according to Kaye only voiced obstruents occur in word-initial position—the
context in which initial devoicing applies. Thus it is clearly a meaning-
maintaining, and not a meaning-obliterating, rule. This example shows that basing
definitions of rule types on markedness rather than meaning considerations is
ineffective.

In summary, the author illustrates violations of Houlihan and Iverson’s


definitions, and emphasizes that the fact their principles generally hold is beside
the point. This fact follows from general notions of markedness as well as the
circular definitions of neutralization and allophonic rules, and therefore plays no
role in constraining the class of possible phonologies.

1.8. Featural Markedness in Phonology: Variation (Rice 1999)

Rice’s work comprises an extensive survey of literature on markedness in


phonology. Rice puts together a nearly exhaustive list of the various definitions,
used in sources such as Jakobson, Trubetzkoy, Kenstowicz, and other works on
phonological theory and writings on the theory of markedness, to describe the
difference between marked and unmarked categories. This list of definitions is
reproduced in (5).

(5) Marked Unmarked


Less natural More natural
More complex Simpler
More specific More general
Less common More common
Unexpected Expected
Not basic Basic
17
Less stable Stable
Appear in few grammars Appear in more grammars
Later in language acquisition Earlier in language acquisition
Subject to neutralization Neutralization targets
Early loss in language deficit Late loss in language deficit
Implies unmarked feature Implied by marked feature
Harder to articulate Easier to articulate
Perceptually more salient Perceptually less salient

This list, surely, represents the intuitions most linguists have about elements that
are characterized using markedness terminology. These are the general
observations that can be made about such elements; the general tendencies that are
often repeated in elements belonging to the same category (of marked or
unmarked), and hence considered universal.

Rice’s own approach to markedness, which stems from the study of language
acquisition, is to treat it as related to structure: markedness is mostly a
consequence of the amount of structure, where the less structure, the less marked
and vice-versa. Her goal is no different from similar works that stem from other
disciplines within linguistics. It is to provide “an account of what universal
grammar allows to be unmarked and what the universal and language particular
aspects to markedness are” (p.34).

Rice and Avery (1995, cited in Rice) argue that two aspects of language must
be accounted for: that there is cross-linguistic uniformity in the features that
pattern phonologically as unmarked (“global uniformity”), but these features are
not always the same (“local variability”).7 The variability aspect is, of course,
what makes the pattern only a tendency rather than a law. For Rice, it seems, the
key to explaining markedness resides in the criteria that separate elements that
succumb to the general tendency to pattern with others of the same markedness
category, from those that do not.

Rice devotes the bulk of her study to reviewing existing work on


markedness, adding her own approach at the end. However, she does not appear to
be able to make any generalizations that encompass the works she reviews, save
for recognizing the fact that markedness is a controversial area that will continue
to be debated for some time to come.

1.9. Discussion

The one constant that is retained, and reiterated, in the sections above relates
to the origin of the notion of markedness as a universal. This is the observation
that unmarked elements tend to pattern similarly cross linguistically, as well as to
some extent within languages. Encoding markedness categories in the grammar is
deeply rooted in the recognition that such universal tendencies exist. This is
18
emphasized in generative theories, where universal tendencies are especially
significant because these are the aspects of languages that are attributed to the UG.

The trend of universalizing markedness statements starts with the


observation, credited to Trubetzkoy, that there is a similarity between the elements
that can appear in positions of neutralization across languages. Regardless of
Trubetzkoy’s original intention for using the notion of ‘mark’, which was to help
classify types of neutralization, this generalized the language-specific processes of
neutralization. For linguists, who are interested in generalizations, this finding is
not one that can be ignored. Thus, the notion of markedness from its very
beginning embodies some universal aspect of a theory of language.

The trend of using markedness as a translation system for more abstract or


symbolic notions, a trend which mistakenly regards markedness values as less
abstract or symbolic than the notions it translates, can also be traced back to
Trubetzkoy. Trubetzkoy used markedness to translate the extra-linguistic
biological causes of articulatory complexity into a linguistic system. Chomsky and
Halle use markedness as a link between phonetic reality (that is, content of
features) and the purely symbolic system of +/- feature values, creating linking
rules that are somehow encoded in the grammar without complicating it. And
Greenberg finds a novel use for markedness as a translation system: he uses it to
translate phonological characteristics into other domains of linguistics.

Steriade (1995) outlines exactly how markedness statements, in the form of


redundancy rules that may be left unspecified lexically, might ease the burden of
the learner by moving this burden into the UG. A typical problem with the
generativist approach arises: in an attempt to simplify the task of the learner, as
much of the burden as possible is moved into the UG; the tradeoff aspect of this
theory—the fact that this supposed entity acquires more and more complexity—is
conveniently ignored because the UG can be anything that is required of it; it is
not a physical entity that can ever be examined.

Whether one believes in the UG or not, it is still interesting to ask the


following questions: What is the advantage of including markedness statements in
the grammar? Why should properties of language that are easily observable (such
as ease of articulation8), and those that are not at all important to learners of a
language (such as cross-linguistic frequency of some element) be built into the
linguistic mechanism we are supposedly born with? Never mind the questionable
advantage of removing the burden from being the responsibility of a learner, what
is the advantage of possessing such knowledge at all? Why should a learner have
access to the knowledge that sonorants are voiced before any exposure to the data,
when the minimum of such exposure would make this fact clear? It seems obvious
that any and all advantages of encoding markedness statements are theory-internal:
the only motivation for including markedness statements in the grammar is that
such statements represent some universal tendencies. The goal of generative
19
phonologies is closely tied to isolating such tendencies for the express purpose of
building a UG.

Beyond questioning generativist wisdom, in this section I emphasize the


circularity of so many of the markedness definitions and uses. First and foremost
is the circularity of using markedness values to characterize aspects of language
that are difficult to measure (e.g., articulatory effort, frequency), which are in turn
used as criteria for awarding markedness values. Second, there is Greenberg’s
search for the connection between markedness and universals by isolating the
common features of markedness in various fields of linguistics, which are in turn
used as evidence for the existence of this connection. Third comes Kaye’s
illustration of how defining rule types as either neutralizing or allophonic using
markedness values is not insightful because markedness values themselves depend
on the types of rules an element can undergo: markedness values are awarded to
elements based on the behavior of these elements within a system, and
participation in neutralization or allophonic rules is what makes up this behavior.

Finally, this section shows that, while few agree on exactly what markedness
means, nobody questions its encoding in the grammar. The generativist-internal
motivation for the existence of such a component in the grammar is clear: the UG
contains (but is not limited to) that which is common across languages;
markedness captures these commonalities, and must therefore be part of the UG.
External motivation for allowing markedness to represent some psychological
reality is nonexistent, and yet such an essential part of scientific reasoning does
not seem lamented in the literature.

2. The Multi-Diagnostic Approach

In this section I draw on the various characterizations of markedness


reviewed in the previous section in order to show motivation for, but also
problems with, the multi-diagnostic approach to markedness in phonology.

2.1. Motivation for the multi-diagnostic approach

The discussion in §1 of the history of the term markedness and the


development of this notion in linguistics suggests that this notion was never uni-
dimensional. Trubetzkoy’s (1939) use of the term is associated most commonly
with neutralization processes, that is with the fact that the output of such processes
is usually the unmarked member of an opposition. But his work also links
markedness to articulatory effort, where the marked member of an opposition is
defined as requiring an extra articulatory gesture as a means of explaining the
biological causes of such effort in linguistic terms.

In bringing the term into the generative framework, and thereby into
contemporary phonology theories, Chomsky and Halle (1968) attempt to formalize
some degree of naturalness based on the intrinsic content of features. While
20
naturalness could be considered the one leading dimension of markedness, it is
clear that it is a dimension that is inherently abstract and cannot be determined
based on any one diagnostic. The most notable reasons for this are that naturalness
is based on articulatory as well as perceptual grounds, which don’t always agree,
and that it is context dependent rather than absolute. Furthermore, not only is
naturalness in itself a multidimensional measure but its use in the generative
framework is applied to a variety of phenomena which are common among the
languages of the world (listed in §1.4).

Within the generative framework, markedness values can be awarded to


elements as compared with each other within an inventory system, a class of
elements, an inventory of elements from one language as compared to another
language, the relationship between some processes in a given language, and
processes among those possible in all languages. Since the naturalness of so many
different aspects of language is measured using markedness, it is obvious that no
one diagnostic could accommodate the full load (e.g., what diagnostic could
possibly measure both frequency and voicing distinction?). In short, the fact that
markedness values accommodate a variety of phenomena is uncontroversial in
phonology literature, and the multi-diagnostic determination of markedness values
is necessary in order to oblige the variety, and could therefore also be considered
uncontroversial.

For a list of diagnostics for assigning markedness values, I turn to Postal


(1968). He discusses SPE’s framework of allowing marked-unmarked to represent
+ and – feature values, and notes:

Accepting such a theory involves the responsibility for discovering the right
class of universal rules interpreting M and U representations as + and –. This
is a vast undertaking. At the moment, from the point of view of a completed
system, our knowledge along these lines is limited. But there is already a
great deal of knowledge, and many M-U decisions can be made with some
confidence. (p.168)

The diagnostics he suggests may be used with confidence are the following (these
are cited in §1.4, where they are discussed in detail):

A. Relative occurrence of sounds


B. Appearance in position of neutralization
C. Language acquisition and language loss
D. Phonological change and dialect variation
E. Physiological and perceptual investigations
F. Implicational hierarchy
G. Syntagmatic assignments
21
An additional, and relevant, checklist for assessing markedness can be found in
McMahon’s (1994) discussion of natural morphology, where naturalness is
defined in terms of markedness:

Unmarked or natural features occur frequently cross-linguistically; appear


often in numerous contexts in languages where they occur; are relatively
resistant to change but often result from changes; occur in pidgins and are
introduced early in Creoles; and are acquired early by children, but
unaffected or lost late in aphasia. Furthermore, borrowings and neologisms
in a language will typically follow the unmarked pattern; and it is rarely
affected by speech errors, although marked forms are commonly assimilated
to the unmarked pattern in error. (p.98)

The motivation behind the multi-diagnostic approach to markedness is


summarized as follows: Markedness is meant to encode some degree of what
linguists agree is ‘intuitively natural’. What is considered natural by linguists is
normally based on phenomena that recur or are common in many of the world’s
languages. For generativists this implies a connection to the UG (i.e., what is
common between languages is usually part of the UG, and should not add
complexity to the learning of any individual language). For non-generativists some
degree of naturalness is also a useful measure as a general observation that can be
made about human languages (that is, there is an intellectual benefit to making
generalizations regardless of whether one is building a UG or not). The
characteristics that are shared by many languages are in themselves multi-
dimensional, and range from articulatory complexity, to behavior in certain
processes, to order of acquisition. For these reasons markedness value assignments
necessarily involve a variety of diagnostics.

2.2. Problems with the multi-diagnostic approach

There is an inherent problem with assigning only one of two values (marked
or unmarked) based on what, as explained above, must necessarily be a variety of,
sometimes unrelated, criteria. A choice of one of only two values is far too
limiting and cannot be expected to resolve cases where the various dimensions
involved in assigning markedness values are in conflict. Thus, when the
diagnostics for markedness contradict each other the predictive and explanatory
value of markedness is weakened.

In addition to the problem of conflicting markedness value assignments,


there is a misconception that markedness drives linguistic processes (e.g., that it is
the markedness status of some element that renders it more, or less, stable
diachronically). Since markedness is used to evaluate a variety of phenomena that
are common among the world’s languages, it emerges as a cover term for the
multitude of characteristics of language it can represent. A close examination of
the individual facets of language subsumed under markedness illustrates the
conflicting, and even vacuous, predictions they make. This leads to one important
22
conclusion: it is not markedness per se that drives linguistic behavior but the
processes that are subsumed under the concept of markedness.

Guitart’s ‘relative markedness’, discussed in §1.4, constitutes the clearest


example of a case where the multi-diagnostic determination of markedness
assignments leads to vacuous predictions. Postal voices reservations about the use
of neutralization as an almost absolute criterion in assigning markedness values, a
practice that can be traced back to Trubetzkoy’s work. Postal points out that the
output of this process is not necessarily the expected unmarked member of an
opposition. In response, Guitart suggests his ‘relative markedness’ theory, that—
although this does not seem to bother the author—basically allows any element to
be unmarked on some level of the scale between physiological and perceptual
markedness (see Figure 1).

physiologically unmarked physiologically marked

perceptually marked perceptually unmarked


unmarked on both levels
Figure 1
Guitart suggests there is a ‘tug of war’ between the physiological and
perceptual criteria: an element can be unmarked on both dimensions (i.e., fall in
the middle of the scale in Figure 1), or it can be unmarked on one dimension or the
other, but never both. The illustration helps clarify that an element cannot be
marked on both physiological and perceptual grounds (because it cannot be on
both edges of this continuum simultaneously), and that an element could fall
anywhere on the continuum and be considered unmarked (‘relatively unmarked’)
on some level. In this manner the result of neutralization can always be unmarked,
and hence, can always serve as a criterion for markedness assignment, despite
Postal’s reservations. However, this scale renders every element unmarked on
some level, and hence renders the physiological and perceptual diagnostics of
markedness assignments, the diagnostics deemed most important by Postal and
others, vacuous.

Markedness value assignments based on both syntagmatic and paradigmatic


criteria constitute examples of the contradictory predictions that can result from
the multi-diagnostic aspect of such assignments. Consider the simple case of
voicing: on a syntagmatic level, voicing intervocalically is aerodynamically
natural, while on a paradigmatic level voicing inventory-wise is marked (on the
basis of articulation effort; also on the basis of implicational hierarchy: if a
language has voiced stops it has voiceless ones; along other criteria as well, e.g.,
frequency) (Westbury and Keating 1986). While most phonologists readily
acknowledge that naturalness is contextually dependent, few consider the
contradictory predictions of syntagmatic vs. paradigmatic criteria for the
determination of markedness values a defect of the theory.
23
In Rice’s (1999) discussion of the patterning of the unmarked she focuses on
three phenomena that are common: emergence of the unmarked, submergence of
the unmarked, and transparency of the unmarked. Emergence of the unmarked
refers to the fact that unmarked elements, often the ‘default’ elements in their
class, are usually the choice for epenthetic matter. An example is the epenthetic i
in Cairene and Iraqi dialects of Arabic:

(6) Epenthetic i breaks up triconsonantal clusters (Ito 1989:241-242)


a. CCC  CCiC e.g., /?ul-t-l-u/  ?ultilu ‘I said to him’ (Cairene)
b. CCC  CiCC e.g., /gil-t-l-a/  gilitla ‘I said to him’ (Iraqi)

Submergence of the unmarked refers to a very different behavior of


unmarked elements. Those elements which are most susceptible to assimilation,
deletion, and other forms of weakening are diagnosed as unmarked. E.g., the
coronals in Korean, where the coronal feature is a target, assimilating to other
places of articulation (a & b) but not a trigger (c & d), and is therefore considered
unmarked:

(7) Korean place of articulation assimilation (Cho 1988, Iverson & Kim
1987, cited in Rice 1999:8)
a. coronal-labial ko/tp/alo ko[pp]alo ‘straight’
b. coronal-dorsal pa/tk/o pa[kk]o ‘to receive and’
c. labial-coronal pa/pt/o pa[pt]o ‘rice also’
d. dorsal-coronal ka/Nt/o ka[Nd]o ‘rubber’

Unmarked features also display a common behavior that Rice calls


transparency of the unmarked, where they are transparent to assimilation while the
marked features block it:

Steriade (1987) shows that vowel harmony may be restricted to cross


laryngeals but not other places of articulation, suggesting that laryngeals are
unmarked in place while other consonantal places of articulation are marked;
Paradis and Prunet (1989) argue that vowel harmony crosses the coronal
place of articulation in Guere, but not others, implying that coronal is
unmarked amongst the other places of articulation. (Rice 1999:9)

These three ways in which unmarked elements tend to pattern similarly cover a
wide range of phenomena, some exact opposites of each other. What theoretical
significance is there to a diagnostic of markedness that is based on participation in
processes such as loss as well as epenthesis, and assimilation as well as
transparency to it? As with ‘relative markedness’, although to a lesser extent,
almost any element can be characterized as unmarked based on its participation in
one of so many processes.

A final example where the multi-diagnostic determination of markedness


values fails comes from diachronic change. In particular, I explore the
24
contradiction between the predictions markedness values make about the rate of
change: marked elements are usually considered less stable diachronically, but
often they are regarded as the more stable elements.

Marked elements are harder to learn and are less natural and hence are often
subject to weakening or loss. This view of the marked element as being less stable
diachronically has already been presented in §1.4 where the example of glottalized
consonants disappearing from an inventory is offered. Another example of
diachronic change of marked elements towards their unmarked counterparts is the
intervocalic weakening of stops:

(8) Lenition/weakening (Hock 1991:81):


Lat. pacatum > (*)pagado > Sp. [paVaDo]
> dial. [paVašo] ‘pacified, pleased’

In this weakening of intervocalic stops from Latin to a dialect of Spanish, first the
intervocalic stops are voiced in the intermediate, reconstructed, stage. Then they
are spirantized in Spanish, and the dental element is finally lost in the dialect of
Spanish. Since each stage of the change in (8) involves a more “relaxed”
pronunciation than the previous stage and hence a less marked element, the
weakening process is a change of marked elements to unmarked ones.

However, marked elements are often more stable diachronically. Consider an


example from morphology: irregular verbs in English. The more common
irregular verbs resist regularization into –ed forms (e.g., drink/drank/drunk,
eat/ate/eaten, is/was/were, etc.). There are even cases where the irregular form
(considered marked) takes over an unmarked form, as in the case of dove replacing
dived as past for dive. The example is taken from Hock (1991:175):

(9) Old English New English


dy#van dive
dy#v(e)de dived  dove (cf. drive : drove)9

Thus certain irregular verbs in English are more stable, less susceptible to change,
diachronically. Of course, one could claim that their frequency—the most
common explanation for their stability—renders them unmarked, and hence their
stability is expected. The question becomes one of determining the markedness
values of these elements in a situation where more than one value is predicted by
the diagnostics, and hence one of conflicting predictions.

An example of diachronically stable marked elements in phonology comes


from click-languages. Most would agree that clicks are marked inventory-wise in
almost every aspect, but few would predict the loss of these sounds from the
inventory of Zulu, for example. Also, glottalization, offered above as an example
of a marked feature that can be expected to be lost, is actually quite common in
syllable-final stops (Silverman, pc).
25

Since marked elements can be both more and less stable diachronically, it is
doubtful that the markedness status of such elements is behind their behavior. In
fact, it becomes obvious that a variety of phenomena, and the interaction between
them, must be responsible for the variation in diachronic stability between these
elements (e.g., functional load, frequency, contrast maintenance, and social
factors, among others). These are the same phenomena used as diagnostics for the
determination of markedness value assignments. Subsuming them under one cover
term, and representing them with only one of two values, ignores not only the
specifics of these phenomena and their influence on diachronic stability, but also
the interaction between them, and hence reduces the explanatory power of the
theory.

3. Conclusion

In §1 the exploration of markedness in phonology literature concludes that


the term is an abstract notion whose definitions are mostly circular and whose
motivation is limited to theory-internal reasoning. In §2 the circularity of the
previous section’s definitions is echoed in the conclusion that the multi-
dimensional aspect of markedness is, in part, a paradox. On the one hand, the fact
that markedness is used to evaluate a multitude of often unrelated phenomena in a
variety of domains (within a class, an inventory of one language, or all the world’s
languages) makes the determination of markedness values necessarily multi-
diagnostic. On the other hand, the various criteria used as diagnostics often lead to
conflicting assignments of markedness values.

But there is a way out: I suggest that the phenomena subsumed under the
cover term markedness are individually far more valuable than the cover term
itself. It is these phenomena that often drive phonological behavior. The fact that
these phenomena often conflict with each other, and therefore lead to conflicting
or vacuous predictions, is only a problem if they are thought of as dimensions of
one aspect of language, that is markedness. Individually, the fact that these
phenomena don’t always act in unison, as if towards some predetermined goal, is
part of the nature of language. Furthermore, funneling the generalizations that can
be made based on the individual phenomena into one of only two values (marked
or unmarked) emerges as a generalization that is too wide in scope to be truly
insightful. The predictive and descriptive powers of the dimensions of
markedness, when taken individually, are therefore far superior to those of
markedness used as a cover term.
26
NOTES

1 Again I turn to Cole and Hualde’s (1998) questioning the existence of abstract
underlying representations. They believe that “the burden of the proof should be
on the defenders of non-observable entities” (p.8). I agree, but do not believe that
the defenders of markedness as some psychological entity can be persuaded to
take on this burden.

2 In both cases he means to/from the “contextual phoneme” in a slightly different


use of the terms than is common in contemporary writings. Trubetzkoy classifies
as dissimilative neutralization processes where the trigger of neutralization is the
same feature being neutralized (e.g., voicing triggers voicing neutralization).
Assimilative neutralization refers to processes where an independent feature
triggers loss of contrast (e.g., nasals trigger voicing neutralization in obstruents).

3 Functional neutralization refers to the consequence for meaning that a


phonological neutralization of a distinctive opposition may have. That is, if a
distinction between two sounds is obliterated, it may lead to the obliteration of the
meaning distinction between lexical elements that contain these sounds (and may
previously have been distinguished by them).

4 This is an oversimplification of the theory, especially since the UG is not limited


to commonalities across languages. My intention is only to show the theory-
internal relationship between the job of a linguist and that of a learner.

5 Guitart uses perception somewhat inaccurately, neglecting the fact that


perception is significantly shaped by language specific contrasts. For example, for
speakers of English, where no such contrast exists, it is difficult to perceive the
difference between glottalized and plain stops; but for Korean speakers it is easy.

6 As far as I know, there is no reason for this to be true.

7 It is not clear to me what aspect of this notion is local. Possibly, she means
within a language as opposed to the global cross-linguistic tendencies. Or, more
likely, she means locally within the group of elements that pattern as unmarked
cross-linguistically. I can only guess, but it does not really matter for our purposes.

8 This property is difficult to measure objectively; but it is not objective measuring


that I refer to here.

9 This type of change is a 4-part analogy, a systematic type of proportional


analogy that generalizes a pattern of morphological relationship between given
forms to other forms.
27

REFERENCES

BATTISTELLA, Edwin L. 1990. Markedness: The Evaluative Superstructure of


Language. State University of New York Press: Albany, NY.
——. 1996. The Logic of Markedness. Oxford University Press: New York, NY.
CHOMSKY Noam and Morris HALLE. 1968. The Sound Pattern of English. Harper
& Row Publishers: New York, Evanston, and London.
COLE, Desmond Thorne. 1955. An Introduction to Tswana Grammar. London.
COLE, Jennifer S. and José I. HUALDE. 1998. The Object of Lexical Acquisition: A
UR-free Model. Proceedings of CLS 34.
DINNSEN, Daniel A. (Ed.). 1979. Current Approaches to Phonological Theory.
Indiana University Press: Bloomington & London.
GLEASON, Jean Berko (Ed.). 1993. The Development of Language. Macmillan
Publishing Company: New York, NY.
GOLDSMITH, John A. (Ed.). 1995. The Handbook of Phonological Theory.
Blackwell Publishers: Cambridge, MA.
GREENBERG, Joseph H. 1963. Some Universals of Grammar with Particular
Reference to the Order of Meaningful Elements. In Greenberg, Joseph H.
(Ed.). “Universals of Language”. Second Edition. MIT Press: Cambridge
MA.
——. (Ed.). 1963. Universals of Language. Second Edition. MIT Press:
Cambridge MA.
——. 1966. Language Universals, With Special reference to Feature Hierarchies.
Mouton & Company: The Hague, The Netherlands.
GUITART, Jorge M. 1976. Markedness and a Cuban Dialect of Spanish.
Georgetown University Press: Washington DC.
HERBERT, Robert K. 1986. “Language Universals, Markedness Theory, and
Natural Phonetic Process”. Trends in Linguistics, Studies and Monographs
25. Winter Werner (Ed.). Mouton de Gruyter.
HOCK, Hans Henrich. 1991. Principles of Historical Linguistics. 2nd Ed., Revised
and Updated. Mouton de Gruyter: Berlin and New York.
HOCK, Hans Henrich and Brian D. JOSEPH. 1996. Language History, Language
Change and Language Relationship: an Introduction to Historical and
Comparative Linguistics. Mouton de Gruyter: Berlin and New York.
HOULIHAN, Kathleen and Gregory K. IVERSON. 1979. Functionally-Constrained
Phonology. In Dinnsen, D. A. (Ed.). “Current Approaches to Phonological
Theory”. Indiana University Press: Bloomington & London.
INGEMANN, Frances (Ed.). 1976. 1975 Mid-America Linguistics Conference
Papers. The Linguistics Department, University of Kansas: Lawrence,
Kansas.
ITO, Junko. 1989. “A Prosodic Theory of Epenthesis”. Natural Language and
Linguistic Theory 7: 217-259.
28
JAKOBSON, Roman. 1963. Implications of Language Universals for Linguistics. In
Greenberg, Joseph H. (Ed.). “Universals of Language”. Second Edition. MIT
Press: Cambridge MA.
JESPERSEN, Otto. 1964. Language: Its Nature, Development and Origin. W.W.
Norton & Company: New York.
KAYE, Jonathan Derek. 1979. On the Alleged Correlation of Markedness and Rule
Function. In Dinnsen, D. A. (Ed.). “Current Approaches to Phonological
Theory”. Indiana University Press: Bloomington & London.
KENSTOWICZ, Michael and Charles KISSEBERTH. 1979. Generative Phonology.
Academic Press, Inc.: San Diego, CA.
LABOV, William. 1994. Principles of Linguistic Change. Blackwell: Oxford, UK
and Cambridge, MA.
MCMAHON, April M. S. 1994. Understanding Language Change. Cambridge
University Press: Great Britain.
PARADIS, Carole and Jean-François PRUNET (Eds.). 1991. The Special Status of
Coronals: Internal and External Evidence. Phonetics and Phonology,
Volume 2. Academic Press, Inc.: San Diego, CA.
POSTAL, Paul M. 1968. Aspects of Phonological Theory. Harper and Row: New
York, Evanston, and London.
RICE, Keren. 1999. Featural Markedness in Phonology: Variation. Part 1. GLOT
4.7:3-6. Part 2. GLOT 4.8:3-7.
RICE, K. and P. Avery. 1995. “Variability in a deterministic model of language
acquisition: a Theory of Segmental Elaboration”. Phonological Acquisition
and Phonological Theory. Archibald, J. (Ed.). 23-42. Lawrence Erlbaum:
Hillsdale, NJ.
SMITH, Neilson V. 1981. “Consistency, Markedness and Language Change: On
the Notion ‘Consistent Language’”. Journal of Linguistics 17: 39-55.
Cambridge University Press: London.
STERIADE, Donca. 1995. Underspecification and Markedness. In Goldsmith, John
A. (Ed.). “The Handbook of Phonological Theory”. Blackwell Publishers:
Cambridge, MA.
TRUBETZKOY, N.S. 1939. Principles of Phonology. Translated by Christiane A. M.
Baltaxe. 1971. LA: University of California Press.
VENNEMANN, Theo. 1969. Sound Change and Markedness Theory: On the History
of the German Consonant System. In Stockwell, Robert P. and Ronald K. S.
Macaulay (Eds.). “Linguistic Change and Generative Theory. Essays from
the UCLA Conference on Historical Linguistics in the Perspective of
Transformational Theory”. Indiana University Press: Bloomington and
London.
——. 1988. Preference Laws for Syllable Structure and the Explanation of Sound
Change With Special Reference to German, Germanic, Italian, and Latin.
Mouton de Gruyter: Berlin.
WAUGH, Linda R. 1979. Remarks on Markedness. In Dinnsen, D. A. (Ed.).
“Current Approaches to Phonological Theory”. Indiana University Press:
Bloomington & London.
29
WESTBURY, J. R. and P. A. KEATING. 1986. “On the Naturalness of Stop
Consonant Voicing”. Journal of Linguistics 22: 145-166.
ZIPF, G. K. 1935. The Psycho-Biology of Language. Houghton Mifflin: Boston.

You might also like