The Constitutional Corporation - Rethinking Corporate Governance
The Constitutional Corporation - Rethinking Corporate Governance
The Constitutional Corporation - Rethinking Corporate Governance
STEPHEN BOTTOMLEY
ANU College of Law
The Australian National University, Australia
© Stephen Bottomley 2007
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or
transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or
otherwise without the prior permission of the publisher.
Stephen Bottomley has asserted his right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to
be identified as the author of this work.
Published by
Ashgate Publishing Limited Ashgate Publishing Company
Gower House Suite 420
Croft Road 101 Cherry Street
Aldershot Burlington, VT 05401-4405
Hampshire GU11 3HR USA
England
ISBN: 978-0-7546-2418-9
Printed and bound in Great Britain by MPG Books Ltd, Bodmin, Cornwall.
Contents
List of Cases vi
List of Statutes ix
Preface xiv
Acknowledgements xvi
3 Corporate Constitutionalism 53
4 Corporate Accountability 77
Index 181
List of Cases
Australia – Commonwealth
Australian Securities and Investments Commission Act 1989 164
Australian Securities and Investments Commission Act 2001
s 227A 104
Companies Code 1981
s 78 25
Corporate Law Economic Reform Program (Audit Reform and Corporate Disclosure) Act
2004 172
Schedule 1 101
Corporations Act 2001 14, 18, 32, 54, 66, 78, 86, 101, 102, 103, 109, 115, 123, 136, 141,
165
Part 2F.1 74, 149
Part 2F.1A 14, 23, 74, 149
Part 2F.2 74, 149
Part 2G.1 82
Part 2G.2 82
Part 5.8A 7
Part 9.4AAA 107
Part 7.6 138
Chapter 2M 125
Chapter 6 125, 140
Chapter 6C 140
Chapter 6CA 125
Chapter 6D 125
s9 23, 98, 103
s 16 140
s 82A 155
s 113 17
s 135 62
s 136 21, 23, 54, 60, 62, 111
s 140 21, 24, 25, 30, 60
s 162 21
s 180 68, 124
s 182 58
s 183 58
s 189 95
s 190 95
s 195 84
s 198A 20, 82
s 198B 20
s 201G 21
s 203C 21, 62
s 203D 21, 62, 111
s 203E 62
s 204A 98
x The Constitutional Corporation
s 232 58, 62, 66, 165
s 233 62, 65, 165
s 234 62, 165
s 235 62
s 236 62, 154, 155
s 237 62, 154, 155, 157
s 238 62, 154
s 239 62, 154, 157
s 240 62, 154
s 241 62, 154
s 242 62, 154, 161
s 246B 21
s 247A 69
s 247D 69
s 248F 72
s 248G 72
s 249C 20
s 249D 62, 151, 152
s 249E 62, 151
s 249F 62, 151
s 249H 72, 127
s 249I 72, 127
s 249J 72, 127
s 249K 72, 127
s 249L 72, 127
s 249N 131, 149
s 249O 141
s 249Q 151
s 249R 127
s 249T 72, 127
s 249V 103
s 249X 72, 128, 139
s 249Y 72, 116, 139
s 250A 72, 135, 136
s 250B 72
s 250C 72
s 250D 72
s 250E 72, 115
s 250F 72
s 250G 72
s 250H 72, 116
s 250I 72
s 250J 72, 116, 127, 135
s 250K 72
s 250L 72, 116
s 250M 72
s 250N 84, 127
s 250PA 78, 177
s 250R 86, 141
s 250RA 63, 103, 128, 177
s 250S 72, 78, 128
List of Statutes xi
s 250T 78, 103, 128, 177
s 251A 72, 128
s 251B 72, 128
s 254U 20
s 256C 21
s 300 102
s 301 99
s 307 99
s 307A 104
s 308 99
s 311 109
s 324CA 103
s 324CB 103
s 324CC 103
s 324CD 103
s 324CE 104
s 324CF 104
s 324CG 104
s 324CH 104
s 324CI 103
s 324CJ 103
s 324DA 103
s 324DC 103
s 324DD 103
s 327 99
s 329 99
s 609 140
s 674 79, 127
s 1289 109
s 1317AA 108
s 1324 74
Corporations Amendment Bill (No. 2) 2006 135, 136, 153, 172
Superannuation Guarantee (Administration) Act 1992 3
Trade Practices Act 1974 136
Canada
Canada Business Corporations Act, RSC 1985 22
PtXIII 128
s 102 20, 82
s 109 111
s 133 127
xii The Constitutional Corporation
s 135 127
s 137 86
s 139 127
s 141 127
s 148 139
s 150 140
s 152 139
s 173 111
s 237 156
s 239 154, 155
s 241 164
s 242 157
New Zealand
Companies Act 1993
s 109 86
s 165 154, 155, 156
s 166 154
s 167 154
s 168 154
United Kingdom
Bubble Act 1720 23
Companies Act 1844 24
s7 24
s 26 24
Companies Act 1862 116
Companies Act 1985
s8 62
s9 111
s 14 22
s 35A 61
s 235 99
s 303 111
s 366 127
s 368 151, 152
s 369 127
s 370 115, 127
s 370A 127
s 372 127, 139
s 376 141
s 382 128
s 459 164, 165, 166
s 744 98
Companies Act 1989
s 459 58
Companies (Audit, Investigations and Community Enterprise) Act 2004 172
Companies Regulations 1985 62
Company Law Reform Bill 2005 154
cl 239 155
List of Statutes xiii
cl 242 155, 157
cl 279 172
cl 290 172
Joint Stock Companies Act 1856 24
s9 24
s 10 24
United States
Delaware General Corporation Law
s 141 82
Revised Model Business Corporations Act (2002)
s 7.02 151
s 8.01 82
s10.20 18, 111
Sarbanes-Oxley Act of 2002 (Public Company Accounting Reform and Investor Protection
Act) 172
s 201 102
s 203 103
s 303 96
Securities Exchange Act of 1934
s 10A 108
Preface
This book has had a long gestation (far too long, for those who have been closely
involved in its production). What sparked it off was the decision of the Australian
High Court in Gambotto v WCP Ltd in 1995, which upheld the claim of a minority
shareholder not to have his shares compulsorily bought from him by the majority
shareholder in the corporation. My sense was that the High Court had made an
important contribution to corporate jurisprudence, although one that required more
explanation and justification than could be found in the pages of the judgements.
But I was also struck by the speed with which the many critics of that case were
able to muster their counter-attack (and I don’t think that ‘attack’ overstates the
nature of some of the responses). Several articles, books, and conference papers
appeared within a short period after the decision was handed down. Without
wanting to down-play the diversity of those responses, it is accurate to say that
most of the criticisms were anchored, one way or another, in a law and economics
framework. It occurred to me that these critics had something of a strategic
advantage — the well-established law and economics framework supplied them
with a ready-made conceptual model which could be used to respond quickly to the
High Court’s decision. On the other hand, those corporate law scholars who found
something of value in the decision, and who were troubled by some of the
criticisms, were largely (but not entirely) silent, myself included. Perhaps, I
thought, a competing conceptual framework was needed, from which to mount a
response to the issues raised by that case and future developments.
This book is the outcome of my attempt to develop such a framework. As the
work continued, the specific issues raised by the Gambotto decision ceased to be
my central concern (indeed, the case is mentioned only occasionally in what
follows). But my wish to develop a conceptual framework for analysing corporate
law issues, that could work as an alternative to the widely accepted law and
economics model, persisted. Whether the ideas presented in this book are
successful in achieving this goal is, of course, for readers to decide.
The book draws on a number of previously published articles, book chapters
and conference papers. It is not, however, a simple compilation of that work. In
attempting to integrate that work I found that my ideas had changed at many points.
Also, the task of ‘putting it all together’ for the purposes of the book revealed
inconsistencies and conceptual gaps, forcing me to re-think, develop and (I hope)
clarify my arguments.
Over the years many people have helped me in the process of organising my
thoughts for this book. Given the passage of time, it is quite likely that some have
forgotten their contribution, but every argument and idea presented here has been
assisted by the questions, comments and gentle critique of others. Here, at last, is
the chance to acknowledge and thank John Braithwaite, Angus Corbett, Christine
Preface xv
Parker, Philip Pettit, Colin Scott, Peta Spender (who read through many of the
chapters in their near final form), Daniel Stewart, the late Michael Whincop, and
John Williams. Thanks also to Tom Campbell for urging some last minute
revisions. I have listened to their ideas and suggestions, although I confess that I
have not always acted on them. In line with customary practice, I absolve them
from any responsibility for what lies between the covers of this book, although I
don’t see why I should. After all, they encouraged me to continue with the project.
Thanks also to Jenna Bottomley for her work in compiling the tables of
statutes and cases, and to Vera Joveska for formatting and preparing the text for
publication.
The real driving force behind this book, however, has been my wife, Sheri.
She has the good sense not to be engrossed in corporate law, but nevertheless she
has continually challenged, urged and encouraged me to write this book
(occasionally enlisting the aid of our daughters, Kristen, Sarah, Taryn and Jenna).
Moreover — and here is my greatest debt — she has made space for me to do so.
Acknowledging her support and patience in this, the final product, seems to be
both an appropriate and a perverse way of thanking her.
Finally, the long period during which this book was being written witnessed
the untimely and unexpected deaths of two corporate law scholars whose work is
referred to on a number of occasions in the following chapters. Michael Whincop
(Professor of Law at Griffith University) died in June 2003. I knew Michael, and
his death was a great shock. John Parkinson (Professor of Law at Bristol
University) died in February 2004, and although I didn’t know him (we were to
have met at a conference I was organising, but he died shortly before this), the
news of his death was nevertheless saddening. They were scholars of different
theoretical persuasions, but I have great admiration for their contributions to
corporate law scholarship. I hope that this book might be regarded as being in the
same company as theirs.
Stephen Bottomley
Acknowledgements
In parts this book draws upon previously published work. I thank the editors of the
following publications for permission to use material from the following articles:
‘The Birds, The Beasts and The Bat: Developing a Constitutionalist Theory of
Corporate Regulation’ (1999) 27 Federal Law Review 243.
The book also refers to my research into company general meetings. This research
was funded by a grant from the Australian Research Council, which I acknowledge
with thanks.
Chapter 1
1
W Twining, Law in Context: Enlarging a Discipline (1997) 210-213; Globalisation and
Legal Theory (2000) 1-2.
2
For a readable history of the rise of the corporation, see J Micklethwait and A
Wooldridge, The Company - A Short History of a Revolutionary Idea (2003).
3
Well known examples in the United States are the Enron Corporation in late 2001 and
WorldCom Inc in mid-2002. In Australia One.Tel Ltd in May 2001, and HIH Insurance
Ltd in March 2001 have a similar significance.
4
This is not to say that interaction between corporations and states is all one-way.
Corporations frequently have to adjust or structure their own activities to meet the
demands of state agencies or court rulings, as in monopoly or anti-trust actions.
5
For example, in 1998 the Australian Prime Minister John Howard called on the
Australian corporate sector to contribute more to community welfare – Keynote
Address to the Australian Council of Social Service National Congress, Adelaide,
November 1998.
2 The Constitutional Corporation
accept responsibility for the protection of, human rights. 6 Corporations work
behind the scenes (and increasingly on centre-stage) to influence many aspects of
national government policy and legislative action. Corporate donations are a major
source of funding for political parties.7 It is large corporations that determine the
formulation of a wide array of regulatory standards on issues ranging from air
safety to pharmaceutical products and telecommunications.8
This corporate influence is not always the product of deliberate lobbying
or planned political pressure. More often it is simply the product of ordinary
commercial activity. A corporation’s decision to ‘downsize’, relocate, or expand its
operations can have a significant impact on local and national economies and on
social policy. Consequently, the mere threat of a major corporate restructuring can
often produce governmental responses that individual citizens are unable to
achieve.9
The significance of corporations in modern society is not confined to the
private business sector. Corporate forms of organisation are now commonplace in
the non-business and non-profit sectors, including social groups and religious
organisations, sports and recreational clubs, educational institutions, professional
firms, and welfare organisations.10 There are many reasons behind this spread of
the corporate form, including the perceived attractions of limited legal liability,
perceptions (accurate or otherwise) about the efficiency of corporate styles of
management, and the risk-assessments of lenders and grant-giving bodies about
6
See United Nations Sub-Commission on the Promotion and Protection of Human
Rights, Norms On The Responsibilities of Transnational Corporations and Other
Business Enterprises With Regard to Human Rights, August 2003; also M Addo (ed),
Human Rights and the Responsibility of Transnational Corporations (1999); S
Bottomley and D Kinley (eds), Commercial Law and Human Rights (2002).
7
I Ramsay, G Stapledon, and J Vernon, ‘Political Donations by Australian Companies’
(2001) 29 Federal Law Review 117 (also referring to the situation in the United
Kingdom).
8
See generally J Braithwaite and P Drahos, Global Business Regulation (2000); C Scott,
‘Private Regulation of the Public Sector: A Neglected Facet of Contemporary
Governance’ (2002) 29 Journal of Law and Society 56.
9
A recent example in Australia concerned the closure by Mitsubishi Motors Australia of
its car assembly operations in the State of South Australia. With the prospect of losing
an estimated 22,000 jobs and $2 billion gross state product, the South Australian
Treasurer and the Federal Industry Minister flew to Japan to negotiate with the parent
corporation: ‘South Australia must drive its own future’, Australian Financial Review
(Sydney), 29 April 2004, 62; Brendan Pearson ‘Mitsubishi on brink after crisis talks’
Australian Financial Review (Sydney), 18 May 2004, 1. In June 2004, the Australian
Government announced a $10 million subsidy for Mitsubishi workers.
10
In some jurisdictions there are specialised forms or methods of incorporation for these
types of corporations. See, for example, the associations incorporation legislation in
Australian States and Territories (for example the Associations Incorporation Act 1991
(ACT)). In the United Kingdom there is a recommendation that there should be a
separate form of incorporation specifically for charities: Company Law Review
Steering Group, Modern Company Law For a Competitive Economy: Final Report
(2001), para 4.63.
Corporations and Shareholders 3
what constitutes an acceptable organisational structure. Governments have also
been attracted to corporate forms of management, not only modelling their
departmental structures along corporate lines (‘corporatisation’) but, increasingly,
creating government-owned corporations to do the work of government.11 Failing
that, governments around the globe have demonstrated a fascination for
‘outsourcing’ areas of public administration to private sector corporations, or
simply ‘privatising’ whole aspects of governmental operations. The range of
activities that has been given over to private sector corporations includes power
and water supplies, telecommunications, banking, roads, transport and shipping,
and prisons.
In summary, corporations now feature in all aspects of social, political
and economic life — private and public, business and non-business, large and
small enterprise.
Related to this spread of the corporate form is the rise and spread of share
ownership in the general population of many countries as a form of investment,
savings, and retirement planning. This is particularly noticeable in Australia where
since the late 1990s share ownership has become a significant feature of economic
and political life. This trend has been driven by factors such as the compulsory
superannuation requirement which has operated in Australia since 1992,12 the full
or partial privatization of large government-owned businesses such as Telstra and
the Commonwealth Bank, 13 and the demutualisation of some corporations that
have had ‘icon’ status (for example, the Australian Mutual Provident Society and
the National Roads and Motorists Association). According to the Australian Stock
Exchange (the ASX), Australia has one of the highest levels of direct and indirect
share ownership in the world. 14 Data published by the ASX shows that the
proportion of the Australian adult population holding shares either directly or
indirectly (eg through managed investment schemes) rose from 34 per cent in 1997
to 55 per cent in 2004; 44 per cent of adults held shares directly. Similar figures are
found in other countries. In New Zealand, for example, 39 per cent of adult
investors had some form of share ownership in 2005, although only 23 per cent had
11
S Bottomley, ‘Regulating Government-owned Corporations’ (1994) 53 Australian
Journal of Public Administration 521; S Bottomley, ‘Corporatisation and
Accountability: the Case of Commonwealth Government Companies’ (1997) 7
Australian Journal of Corporate Law 156; B Collier and S Pitkin (eds),
Corporatisation and Privatisation in Australia (1999).
12
The Superannuation Guarantee (Administration) Act 1992 (Cth) requires employers to
provide a prescribed minimum level of superannuation support for employees.
Superannuation schemes are operated by private and public sector funds rather than a
central government operated fund. See G Stapledon, ‘Share Ownership and Control in
Listed Australian Companies’ (1999) 2 Corporate Governance International 17, 21.
13
Telstra, the Federal Government-owned telecommunications corporation, was partially
privatised in 1997 with the public float of 33 per cent of its shares. A further 16 per cent
was sold in 1999. The sale of the remaining 51 per cent continues to be a topic of
political debate. The Commonwealth Bank was fully privatised in 1991.
14
Australian Stock Exchange, Australian Share Ownership Study 2004 (2005).
4 The Constitutional Corporation
direct shareholdings. 15 In the United States 49.5 per cent of households owned
equities as at January 2002.16 In 2003 shares had become the second most popular
form of personal investment in Australia, ranking only behind superannuation. The
value of individual share portfolios has also increased, from an average of $29,000
in 2000, to $41,400 in 2004. In that year 38 per cent of investors had less than
$10,000 invested directly in shares, while 35 per cent had more than $50,000
invested.17
Of course, high levels of share ownership do not necessarily mean high
levels of direct investor participation in the corporate economy or in the processes
of corporate governance. Despite the high level of share ownership in Australia,
many investors are relatively passive in their direct share holdings — this is one of
the concerns of this book. The 2004 ASX survey found that about half of all direct
share owners had not traded in the twelve months prior to the survey. Looking at
another aspect of shareholder passivity, a survey of 217 Australian listed
corporations in 2002 found that in 98 per cent of annual general meetings
shareholders attending in person or by proxy represented no more than 20 per cent
of all shareholders in the corporation. In the same group of corporations none of
the 203 extraordinary general meetings held between 2001 and 2003 were called
by shareholders.18
At the same time, the connection between citizens and their national and
global communities is increasingly mediated through the financial and securities
markets and, therefore, through the activities of corporations. A nation’s state of
well-being is judged as much by stock-market indices and corporate profit
announcements as by non-economic factors. Perhaps this is why so much of the
nightly television news bulletin is taken up with information about share price
movements, shifts in various market performance indexes, currency fluctuations,
and corporate reporting. When governments announce new policies or abandon old
ones, when major national and international events take place, we are as likely to
find that expert commentary is sought from an economist or a financial analyst as
from a political or a social commentator.
This book takes this corporate world (for better or for worse) as its
starting point. The book does not yearn for a return to some bygone era — if it ever
15
New Zealand Stock Exchange, Press Release: More New Zealanders are investing in
the share market, (15 July 2005) <http://www.nzx.com/aboutus/news/
press/research_15jul/view> at 3 January 2006.
16
Investment Company Institute/Securities Industry Association, Equity Ownership in
America 2002 (2002)
<http://www.ici.org/shareholders/dec/1rpt_02_equity_owners.pdf> at 13 May 2004.
Not all countries reveal the same trend. A survey in the United Kingdom, for example,
found that in June 2002 only 22 per cent of private investors held stocks or shares:
Proshare, Private Share Ownership in Britain in 2002 (2002)
<http://www.proshare.org/Research/bso2002.pdf> at 13 May 2004.
17
Australian Stock Exchange, Australian Share Ownership Study 2004 (2005).
18
S Bottomley, The Role of Shareholders’ Meetings in Improving Corporate Governance
(Research Report, Centre for Commercial Law, Australian National University, 2003)
vi-vii.
Corporations and Shareholders 5
existed — in which corporations knew their place, and when the word ‘share’ was
as likely to make one think of cooperative or altruistic behaviour as of a device for
individual wealth accumulation. The purpose of this book is, however, to challenge
some of the assumptions and practices that have come to define this corporate
world. In particular, the book challenges the idea that the only, or the best, way in
which shareholders should relate to corporations is as investors. It challenges the
idea that the only, or the best, way in which corporations can relate to shareholders
is through a short or medium term focus on profits and dividend returns. It
challenges the idea that the only, or the best, criteria for assessing the relationship
between shareholders and corporations are efficiency and wealth-maximisation.
And, lastly, it challenges the sometimes explicit, but mostly implicit claim of
economics to be the pre-eminent discipline for making real sense of these
developments, and the capacity of economics to provide an over-arching
metatheory for all things corporate.19
Focusing on Shareholders
As the previous paragraph indicates, the argument in this book is concerned with
the relationship between a corporation’s shareholders and its board of directors.
This follows the standard legal model of the corporation that underpins corporate
law regimes in many Western legal systems, whereby directors’ actions must be
oriented towards the best interests of the corporation’s shareholders.20 This book
adopts this legal model, not because the model presents an organisational ideal to
which corporations should necessarily aspire, and certainly not because the model
is an accurate description of the way in which all corporations actually operate.
Instead, the formal legal model is used because, regardless of the diversity in
corporate structures, it does provide a common and resilient reference point and
language for all corporations that operate in corporate law systems such as those
found in Australia, the United Kingdom, and North America.
In the context of the literature on corporate governance, much of which
urges a shift away from a shareholder primacy model of the corporation, this might
be thought to be a narrow and legalistic focus, and so it requires further
explanation. Many writers urge a much wider view than this. For example:
Corporate governance is more than simply the relationship between the firm and
its capital providers. Corporate governance also implicates how the various
constituencies that define the business enterprise serve, and are served by, the
corporation. Implicit and explicit relationships between the corporation and its
employees, creditors, suppliers, customers, host communities – and relationships
19
An example is M Whincop, An Economic and Jurisprudential Genealogy of Corporate
Law (2001) 3, claiming that economics is the key to understanding corporate law.
20
This model is analysed in more detail in Chapter 2.
6 The Constitutional Corporation
among these constituencies themselves – fall within the ambit of a relevant
definition of corporate governance.21
Some writers argue quite strongly that the shareholder primacy model has no
compelling moral basis, that shareholders warrant no greater attention or protection
than other stakeholders in the corporation, and that the time has come to move
away from ‘shareholder primacy’ towards models that, one way or another,
recognise the interests of all stakeholders in the corporation.22 Others charge that
shareholder primacy allows (or, even worse, requires) corporations to ignore or
downplay important human rights, environmental, and health and safety
concerns.23 Most shareholders, we are told, are passive, absentee owners, and ‘[i]f
it is not the shareholders’ efforts and abilities which direct the economic activities
of the corporation, then why should they have the right to have it run purely in
their interests?24
Why are these broader concerns not addressed in this book? I assume that
one purpose of taking a broader stakeholder approach is to call into question the
way we think about the corporation and its purposes as a legal, economic and
social institution. For directors, managers, lawyers and other professionals who are
involved in the day-to-day business of corporate practice and corporate law, a
broader approach demands some significant shifts in attitude and practice. This has
been attempted before, in repeated calls for corporate social responsibility or for a
communitarian approach to corporate governance. 25 These calls have not been
widely accepted in practice, largely, I suspect, because they are seen to depart too
21
M Bradley, C Schipani, A Sundaram, and J Walsh, ‘The Purposes and Accountability
of the Corporation in Contemporary Society: Corporate Governance at a Crossroads’
(1999) 62 Law and Contemporary Problems 9, 11.
22
See, for example, P Ireland, ‘Company Law and the Myth of Shareholder Ownership’
(1999) 62 Modern Law Review 32; D Wood, ‘Whom Should Business Serve?’ (2002)
14 Australian Journal of Corporate Law 1; L Stout, ‘Bad and Not-So-Bad Arguments
for Shareholder Primacy’ (2002) 75 Southern California Law Review 1189. With Blair,
Stout advocates a ‘team production’ model: M Blair and L Stout, ‘A Team Production
Theory of Corporate Law’ (1999) 86 Virginia Law Review 247; M Blair and L Stout,
‘Director Accountability and the Mediating Role of the Corporate Board’ (2001) 79
Washington University Law Quarterly 403. See below n 38 and accompanying text.
23
A clear example of the adverse impact on health and safety concerns is found in the
attempt by James Hardie Industries Ltd to isolate its liability for asbestos-related illness
from its general operations. See Report of the Special Commission of Inquiry Into the
Medical Research and Compensation Foundation (September 2004)
<http://www.cabinet.nsw.gov.au/hardie/PartA.pdf > at 6 March 2005.
24
M Gilbert, ‘Introduction’ in M Gilbert (ed), The Modern Business Enterprise: Selected
Readings (1972) 20.
25
On corporate social responsibility see, for example, D Engel, ‘An Approach to
Corporate Social Responsibility’ (1979) 32 Stanford Law Review 1; J Tolmie,
‘Corporate Social Responsibility’ (1992) 15 University of New South Wales Law
Journal 268. On communitarian approaches to corporate law, see L Mitchell (ed),
Progressive Corporate Law (1995); and Symposium, ‘New Directions in Corporate
Law’ (1993) 50 Washington and Lee Law Review Issue No 4.
Corporations and Shareholders 7
dramatically from the orthodox and prevailing legal and economic view of the
corporation. In 1989, for example, an Australian Senate inquiry into the law
governing directors’ duties considered the possibility of imposing duties towards
consumers, employees, or the environment, but concluded that:
It is appropriate that matters external to the company be dealt with in separate and
specific legislation … This is because companies legislation should deal only with
corporate structure and organisation and matters arising as and between the
constituents of the body corporate.26
at present our company law lacks the conceptual and remedial tools – and, I think
also, its framers lack the will – to reflect our new perception of the company as no
longer a shareholders’ collective, but an enterprise in which the interests of many
stakeholders have to be balanced.28
Similarly, in the United States, David Millon has concluded that ‘[t]he long-
standing controversy over the rights of corporate shareholders in relation to
nonshareholders involved in or affected by corporate activity is no closer to
resolution today than it ever has been’. 29 The shareholder primacy model has
proven to be resilient, notwithstanding the importance of broader concerns.30 I am
pessimistic about the prospects for a serious consideration by directors, lawyers,
and others of broader perspectives on corporate governance until they can be
convinced that a broader approach is consonant with the ideas that underlie the
orthodox legal model.
Of course there are those who defend the shareholder primacy model in
more positive terms, and on a variety of grounds: for example, that shareholders
are the ‘owners’ of the corporation, that it is the shareholders who appoint the
26
Senate Standing Committee on Legal and Constitutional Affairs, Parliament of
Australia, Company Directors’ Duties – Report on the Social and Fiduciary Duties and
Obligations of Company Directors (1989) para 6.55.
27
Corporations Act 2001, Part 5.8A.
28
L Sealy, ‘Perception and Policy in Company Law Reform’ in D Feldman and F Miesel
(eds), Corporate and Commercial Law: Modern Developments (1996) 28. For another,
but differently framed assessment of the fate of stakeholding in the UK see S Wheeler,
Corporations and the Third Way (2002), 29ff.
29
D Millon, ‘The Ambiguous Significance of Corporate Personhood’ Washington & Lee
Public Law and Legal Theory Research Paper Series, Working Paper No 01-6, January
2001, 28.
30
Theories of ‘path dependence’ provide one explanation for this. See L Bebchuk and M
Roe, ‘A Theory of Path Dependence in Corporate Ownership and Governance’ (1999)
52 Stanford Law Review 127.
8 The Constitutional Corporation
directors to act as their agents, that shareholders are the residual claimants and
main risk bearers in the corporation,31 or that a shareholder primacy rule reduces
the scope for unwanted managerial discretion. 32 Hansmann and Kraakman have
noted that despite some divergence in patterns of share ownership, capital market
structures and business culture, the basic law of the corporate form has achieved a
high degree of uniformity around the globe. 33 They have predicted further
international convergence on the shareholder primacy model of the corporation
(indeed, so confident is their prediction that they have proclaimed ‘the end of
history for corporate law’). In their view, the shareholder primacy model has swept
aside other contenders, including the stakeholder model favoured by proponents of
corporate social responsibility and ethical capitalism.
I am not convinced that we have witnessed the end of history for
corporate law. I am convinced, though, that the way forward means taking the
shareholder primacy model seriously. Whatever its shortcomings, that model
exercises a powerful grip on the mind-set of corporate managers and officers. And,
as we saw earlier in this Chapter, shareholding has become a significant feature of
the economic and political climate. Given all this, the challenge is to work with the
shareholder primacy model. Legally speaking, it is a flexible model and the
arguments presented in this book suggest that it can be fine-tuned and used in ways
that do not necessarily shut out other sets of interests and concerns. What is
required is a way of looking at corporations and shareholders that opens up new
possibilities for shareholder involvement. This need not involve fundamental
changes to corporate structures or operations. Instead, the idea is to bring out
possibilities that already exist in corporate law and corporate organisations. These
adaptations might eventually lead to larger changes, but one premise of this book is
that while a consideration of broader conceptions of the corporation and corporate
governance is a worthwhile exercise, it will occur in small steps. Hence, I take the
existing legal model, with its emphasis on the interests of shareholders, as my
starting point — not because I wish to defend that model, but because, in pragmatic
terms, it is the best place to start. Thus while the purpose of this book is to change
the way in which we think about corporations and their governance processes, it
does not advocate any fundamental transformations or reforms of basic corporate
structures or the corporate legal environment.34
Having said that, another concern of this book is that very often the
shareholder primacy model does not work, even on its own terms. In legal terms it
is an imprecise doctrine, usually expressed as a duty owed by directors to act in the
best interests of the corporation, which may mean the corporation as a commercial
31
See, for example, F Easterbrook and D Fischel, The Economic Structure of Corporate
Law (1991) 35ff.
32
Stout, above n 22, 1199-1201.
33
H Hansmann and R Kraakman, ‘The End of History for Corporate Law’ (2001) 89
Georgetown Law Journal 439.
34
Though some reforms are discussed throughout the book.
Corporations and Shareholders 9
entity or, at other times, the interests of the members as a whole.35 The upshot of
this legal imprecision is that directors have considerable discretionary power. They
can choose to adopt short-term strategies to maximise share price instead of
looking to the longer-term value of the corporation.36 This will satisfy the interests
of some — perhaps many — shareholders. But there are dangers here. One is that
short-term price maximisation comes to be equated with shareholder primacy. 37
Another is that shareholders become marginalised in corporate decision-making
processes. From an economic perspective we are told repeatedly that most
shareholders are merely passive investors, monitoring corporate performance only
to the extent that is necessary for them to decide when to transfer their money from
one corporation to some other corporate investment opportunity. Commentators
urge that corporate law should recognise this ‘reality’ and leave more space for
corporate managers to get on with the job of profit-maximisation without being
overly burdened by the demands of shareholder accountability. One variation of
this argument is Blair and Stout’s ‘team production’ theory, according to which the
role of the board of directors, operating independently of all contributors to the
corporate enterprise, is to allocate the value produced by the team effort amongst
the various contributors. 38 An even more extreme argument (which, like
stakeholder theory, has yet to find general acceptance) is the ‘director primacy’
argument which completely ‘rejects the notion that shareholders are entitled to
either direct or indirect decisionmaking control’. 39 The role of shareholders in
public corporations is thus in danger of being reduced to a level that gives
inadequate opportunity for their concerns (short-term or not) to be heard and
considered. A consequential concern is that this trend makes any consideration of
broader approaches to corporate governance even more difficult to contemplate. If
those who are supposedly at the centre of doctrinal concerns are given short shrift,
what hope is there, eventually, for non-shareholders?
It is one thing to acknowledge that many shareholders are passive
investors with little or no interest in corporate issues beyond the current market
price of their securities.40 It is quite another thing to use this as a premise on which
35
Compare Greenhalgh v Arderne Cinemas Ltd [1951] Ch 286, 291 per Evershed MR
(‘the phrase, “the company as a whole”, does not … mean the company as a
commercial entity distinct from the corporators’) with Darvall v North Sydney Brick &
Tile Co Ltd (1988) 6 ACLC 154 per Hodgson J (‘it is proper to have regard to … the
interests of the company as a commercial entity’).
36
See, eg, L Mitchell, Corporate Irresponsibility: America’s Newest Export (2001).
37
D Millon, ‘Why Is Corporate Management Obsessed with Quarterly Earnings and What
Should Be Done About It?’ (2002) 70 George Washington Law Review 890, 900-902.
38
Blair and Stout, above n 22.
39
S Bainbridge, ‘Director Primacy: The Means and Ends of Corporate Governance’
(2003) 97 Northwestern University Law Review 547, 563. For a law-and-economics
based critique of the assumption of passivity, see B Black, ‘Shareholder Passivity
Reexamined’ (1990) 89 Michigan Law Review 520.
40
In Australia, where compulsory superannuation has brought many people into the share
market, the passivity argument may be overstated. Most superannuation schemes now
operate as ‘accumulation funds’ in which the final retirement benefit depends very
10 The Constitutional Corporation
to build corporate law rules and corporate governance principles. Evidence of
shareholder passivity and lack of shareholder activism should not become the
normative and policy foundation for corporate law reform. To adapt a point made
by Charkham and Simpson, shareholder passivity may be individually rational, but
it is collectively to the detriment of our economic and social structures.41 This book
therefore argues for a new approach to the role of shareholders, one which can
serve as the basis for going on to consider the interests of other stakeholders in the
corporation.
I have noted already that the contemporary debate about corporate regulation is
dominated by references to ‘corporate governance’. This is a slippery term. It is
found both in discussions about the role of corporations in society (where the
reference is to the governance of corporations) and in discussions about the roles of,
and relations between, directors and shareholders (that is, governance in
corporations). In the latter case, ‘corporate governance’ is sometimes used to
describe broadly defined goals (for example, corporations should aim to maintain
good corporate governance in addition to profitability),43 and at other times to refer
to the means by which certain goals (for example, satisfied shareholders or the
efficient use of capital)44 can be achieved. The term has become so malleable that it
is tempting to dismiss it as being devoid of any real content, as a public relations
slogan that is invoked by image-conscious corporations seeking to gain or maintain
a perceived market advantage.
If, however, we judge it less cynically, the idea of corporate governance
does at least remind us that corporations are systems of government. In this sense,
corporate governance can stand as an organising motif for debates about the role,
composition and duties of the board of directors, and the role and rights of
shareholders, either individually, in groups or as a whole, and about the ways in
which directors and shareholders interact within a corporation. Peeling away the
rhetoric, we find that the underlying theme in all of these debates continues to be
what Mary Stokes, in her influential essay, described as ‘the problem of the
much on the success of the share investments made by the fund. This may well be a
factor behind the continued media interest in corporate governance in large listed
corporations.
41
J Charkham and A Simpson, Fair Shares: The Future of Shareholder Power and
Responsibility (1999) 1.
42
This section draws on parts of S Bottomley ‘From Contractualism to Constitutionalism:
A Framework for Corporate Governance’ (1997) 19 Sydney Law Review 277.
43
For example, Toronto Stock Exchange Committee on Corporate Governance in Canada,
‘Where Were the Directors?’ Guidelines for Improved Corporate Governance in
Canada (1994).
44
See, for example, OECD, Principles of Corporate Governance (2004) 2.
Corporations and Shareholders 11
legitimacy of corporate managerial power’. 45 Viewed in this way, these debates
remind us of longer-standing arguments in the political theory literature about
ideas such as representation, participation, the separation of powers, majority rule,
and the nature of democratic structures.
Whether because of indifference or epistemological resistance, corporate
lawyers have not delved into these underlying ideas very deeply, if at all. This
contrasts sharply with the investigation of the economic aspects of corporate
governance. It is easy to understand that corporations are significant economic
actors, and the relevance of economics to the study of corporations and the reform
of corporate law has readily been accepted by politicians, regulators and academics.
The Australian Government’s Corporate Law Economic Reform Program,
established in 1997, is a clear manifestation of the political acceptance of an
economic framework (even though some economists have criticised it for relying
more on economic rhetoric than economic analysis).46 The economic analysis of
corporate law issues has become the staple contribution of the academic research
literature in the United States and, to a lesser degree, Australia and the United
Kingdom. As Michael Whincop has claimed, ‘[t]he dominant view of the creation
and evolution of corporate law is an economic one’.47
By concentrating on economic analyses and paying insufficient attention
to political and constitutional theory, corporate lawyers have produced a rather
one-dimensional picture of, and occasionally awkward responses to, the problems
of corporate governance. Thus the overall purpose of the book is to argue for a
reconceptualisation of the corporate legal structure in political terms. Forty years
ago Richard Eells made a similar plea:
Using a political perspective we can achieve a rich analytical basis for studying
and responding to corporate governance issues.
This book does not, however, set out a new ‘grand theory of corporate
governance’. I do not aim to supply a replacement for economic theories (or any
45
M Stokes, ‘Company Law and Legal Theory’ in W Twining (ed), Legal Theory and
Common Law (1986) 155.
46
For example M Whincop ‘Token economics? One view of the CLERP fundraising
reforms’ (1997) Australian Corporate Law Bulletin 22 [348].
47
Whincop, above n 19, 12.
48
R Eells, The Government of Corporations (1962) 11. The economic theory of the
corporation has developed considerably since Eells wrote this passage. Nevertheless,
his sentiment is still relevant.
12 The Constitutional Corporation
other theories) of the corporation. The corporate world is too complex and too
variable for any single theory or discipline to be able to supply all of the answers to
all of the problems of corporate governance. There are aspects of corporate life for
which economic theories are well-suited but, equally, there are other aspects for
which we need a different framework, another option on the conceptual menu.
Economics can share the analytical stage with other approaches. I describe the
framework that is offered in this book as ‘corporate constitutionalism’.49
The reasons for adopting this label are set out in more detail in Chapters 2
and 3, but can be summarised briefly here. I have chosen the term ‘corporate
constitutionalism’ because of its association with lines of inquiry that draw on
political theory and because it directs our attention to questions of institutional
structure and process. A corporation is a body politic; it embodies a system of
governance. This is not to say that corporations can be equated with parliaments or
other institutions of public government. Instead, it means that in their own way
corporations are political entities. Similarly, constitutions are political; as Stephen
Macedo observes, ‘[c]onstitutional issues are political in the deepest sense of that
term’.50 Amongst other things, constitutions establish structures and processes for
institutions. Within corporations, questions of politics and institutional structure
are important because, as I argue in Chapter 3, a significant part of corporate life
involves processes of decision-making. So, the idea of ‘corporate
constitutionalism’ suggests that there are values and ideas in our public political
life that can provide useful insights when considering the legal regulation of
corporate governance and decision-making. At the same time, the qualifier
‘corporate constitutionalism’ indicates that within the corporate context these
values and ideas will have different formulations, applications, and consequences
than in other political contexts.
The corporate constitutionalist framework that is developed in this book
relies on three principles. The first of these is the idea that accountability can be
enhanced if the role of the board of directors is differentiated from that of the
general meeting of shareholders, and also if corporate decision-making processes
are characterised by a separation of decision-making powers. The second idea is
that corporate decisions should be the product of processes that involve
deliberation. Thirdly there is the idea that corporate decisions that do not track the
interests of members should be readily contestable. Taking these three principles
together, I argue that corporate constitutionalism provides a normative framework
with which we can assess the legitimacy of corporate decision-making.
49
I am not the first to use this label. To my knowledge it has also been used by Eells,
above n 47; M Kahan and E Rock, ‘Precommitment and Managerial Incentives:
Corporate Constitutionalism: Antitakeover Charter Provisions as Pre-Commitment’
(2003) 152 University of Pennsylvania Law Review 473. See also A Fraser, Reinventing
Aristocracy: The Constitutional Reformation of Corporate Governance (1998). Whilst
the label is the same, the content of the argument in each case is different.
50
S Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue and Community in Liberal
Constitutionalism (1990) 162.
Corporations and Shareholders 13
This normative framework invites us to shift the way in which we think of
corporations and corporate relations. There are at least four significant conceptual
shifts which become apparent from this constitutional perspective. The first is a
shift from purely contractual ways of thinking. The idea of a ‘constitution’ is
intended to supply a counterpoint to legal or economic notions of ‘contract’ as the
conceptual foundation of corporate governance. Instead of a contractual separation
of corporate ownership from corporate control 51 that is based upon notions of
implied consent and bilateral (or even multilateral) agreement, we can think of the
corporate constitution as a framework or structure within which decisions are made.
Instead of the corporation being regarded as an aggregation of individual actors,
the idea of a constitution suggests the possibility that a collective purpose is
constituted when a corporation is formed. Contract is a useful way of thinking
about interactions between individuals where the aim is maximising individual
advantage; constitution is concerned more with ‘coordination interactions’. 52
Corporations give rise to both of these interactions, although much more emphasis
has been given to the first type, usually to the exclusion of the latter. Accordingly,
this book looks at corporate relationships through a constitutional lens to highlight
and bring into focus issues and ideas that may otherwise be lost in corporate law
scholarship.
Secondly, and consequently, a constitutional perspective invites us to shift
our perception of shareholders from their role as investors to that of members. I do
not claim that this shift is possible only from a constitutional perspective, just that
it is more likely to occur. How we characterise or think of shareholders has strong
implications for their role in corporations and for the regulation of that role. 53
When we think of shareholders as investors we give priority to their economic role
and to their status as owners of property. From the corporation’s point of view the
shareholder-as-investor is a supplier of capital or, in the secondary share market, a
means of signalling information about the corporation’s financial situation to other
investors. To think, instead, of shareholders as members requires that we pay more
attention to their role as participants in a collective enterprise. The concept of
membership has varying connotations. In a weak sense it refers simply to any
grouping that is based on some shared identifying characteristic (for example,
having brown eyes). 54 In a much stronger sense, membership entails ideas of
51
The separation thesis was popularised by the work of Adolf Berle and Gardiner Means,
The Modern Corporation and Private Property (revised ed, 1968). It has since become
integral to economic analyses of corporate governance, particularly in light of M Jensen
and W Meckling, ‘Theory of the Firm: Managerial Behaviour, Agency Costs, and
Ownership Structure’ (1976) 3 Journal of Financial Economics 305.
52
R Hardin, ‘Why a Constitution?’ in B Grofman and D Wittman (eds), The Federalist
Papers and the New Institutionalism (1989) 101.
53
See J Hill, ‘Visions and Revisions of the Shareholder’ (2000) 48 The American Journal
of Comparative Law 39.
54
This description (and example) is taken from Patricia Smith, Liberalism and Affirmative
Obligation (1998) 81.
14 The Constitutional Corporation
participation,55 identity and identification, responsibility and obligation. As Patricia
Smith describes it, ‘[i]t is the idea of being part of something that is most basic to
the idea of membership’. 56 Although corporate law continues to use the term
‘member’, 57 in practice the implications of ‘membership’ are frequently under-
emphasised or overlooked — in effect, owning shares in a corporation is given the
same significance as having brown eyes.
There is a need for balance here. For one thing, ‘membership is a
deceptively complicated concept’. 58 Further, it is important not to overstate the
case for thinking of shareholders as members. The significance of corporate
membership will vary between different corporations, but it is safe to say that
being a member of a large public corporation is unlikely to have the same
significance for someone as, say, being a member of a local community
association. And, of course, the role of shareholders as investors is important. But
while there are many currents that pull us towards the view that shareholders are
primarily suppliers of capital (these currents include the popularisation of capital
markets, the rise of institutional investors, and the proliferation of financial
investment products), there are also indications that the concept of membership
still has significance. Recent indications in Australia include the introduction of a
statutory form of shareholder derivative action, 59 the 1999-2000 inquiry into
shareholder participation in listed public corporations60 and, more generally, the
regular attention which is given by the finance and business press to reporting the
proceedings at the annual general meetings of public corporations. Similarly, calls
for institutional shareholders to become more active in corporate governance,61 or
for small shareholders to accept their share of responsibility for ensuring good
corporate management,62 rely on the idea that shareholders should act as members,
55
Later in the book I qualify this reference to participation. I argue that corporate
constitutionalism does not mean that each and every member must participate in the
corporation, and nor does each participating member need to do this in the same way –
see Chapter 5 n 36 to n 38 and accompanying text.
56
Smith, above n 54, 82.
57
For example, in Australia the Corporations Act 2001 uses the word ‘member’ as a
generic term to cover corporators in companies with share capital (in which
membership is constituted by share ownership) and corporators in companies limited by
guarantee (which do not have share capital).
58
F Baumgartner and B Leech, Basic Instincts: The Importance of Groups in Politics and
in Political Science (1998) 33.
59
Corporations Act 2001 Part 2F.1A, introduced in 1999.
60
Companies and Securities Advisory Committee, Shareholder Participation in the
Modern Listed Public Company: Final Report (2000); in the United Kingdom see
Company Law Review Steering Group, Modern Company Law For a Competitive
Economy: Final Report (2001) Chapters 3 and 7.
61
See generally G Stapledon, Institutional Shareholders and Corporate Governance
(1996).
62
See, for example, J Hayes, ‘Shootout over which sheriff rides herd on corporate
cowboys’ The Weekend Australian (Sydney) 3-4 August 2002, 35; in the United
Kingdom similar calls have been made: Rt Hon Patricia Hewitt (Secretary of State for
Trade and Industry), Speech to Hermes Stewardship and Performance Seminar (2003)
Corporations and Shareholders 15
not simply as self-interested investors. Put simply, there is no necessary
contradiction between the pursuit of profits and the idea of shareholders as
members.
The third shift emphasised by a corporate constitutional framework is that
corporations are seen to have a public dimension in addition to their role as private
actors. This idea has been noted by a number of writers and is not exclusive to
corporate constitutionalism.63 The idea is developed in this book by arguing for the
possibility that corporations can operate (at least some of the time) as a type of
intermediary organisation, occupying a place between individual citizens and the
state. In this view, corporations have a role as ‘outlets’64 for views about economic
and other issues that extend beyond the self-interest of the individual corporate
participants.
The fourth shift to be emphasised stems from the fact that corporations are
decision-making organisations, ranging from the many informal decisions that are
made on a daily basis by corporate officers and managers, to the fewer formal
decisions made on an annual basis at general meetings. The corporate governance
literature frequently concerns itself with the effects of corporate decisions,
inquiring whether a given decision is efficient or fair. While these are important
questions, the answers do not tell us all we need to know about corporate decision-
making. The premise of this book is that how decisions are made is as important as
the outcomes that they achieve. The ideas of accountability, deliberation and
contestability are therefore concerned with the processes by which decisions are
made. Corporate decisions can be assessed not just by the efficiency or fairness of
their results, but also by assessing the quality of all of the formal and informal
processes that are involved in reaching those decisions. Note that I have stressed
‘all’ of the processes; as I will argue in Chapter 4, a concern for process is not
restricted to the formal counting of votes and adoption of resolutions. Corporate
decision-making processes begin well before that point is reached.
Two final points of clarification are needed regarding the idea of
‘corporate constitutionalism’. First, the word ‘constitutionalism’ is not being used
in any of the formal or technical senses with which constitutional lawyers are
familiar. Nor do I intend this to be a contribution to the literature on theories of
constitutionalism, although — as Chapter 2 makes clear — I have mined that
literature for ideas. Secondly, the idea of corporate constitutionalism is presented
as an evaluative framework rather than an explanatory theory. An explanatory
theory of the corporation and of corporate law and regulation would seek to
explain the origins and development of the corporate form and of corporate law. It
would seek to understand why corporations and corporate law are as they are. It
would attempt to predict future developments (for example, that the Anglo-
American corporate model will achieve global acceptance), and it might insist on
65
This is not, however, an attempt to directly apply republican or deliberative theory to
the corporate context. Adaptation is necessary.
Corporations and Shareholders 17
In Chapter 5 I examine the idea of deliberation as a pre-requisite to formal
decision-making, and how this might be applied in a corporate context. Not all
shareholders will deliberate, and those that do will deliberate in different ways. The
goal is to devise ways in which even minimal forms of deliberation can be
channelled into the formal decision-making processes of the corporation.
Chapter 6 completes the detailed examination of the three main ideas in
the book by explaining the importance of contestability in legitimate corporate
decision-making. Contestability is not limited to court-based litigation, although
that is clearly significant. The Chapter explains the role of contestability
mechanisms that are ‘internal’ to the corporation, such as extraordinary (or special)
general meetings.
Lastly, in Chapter 7 I come back to consider how the ideas of
accountability, deliberation and contestability work together within a framework of
corporate constitutionalism. I look at where this can take us in approaching
questions of corporate governance, pulling together some suggestions and ideas
raised throughout the book. And, acknowledging that the arguments in the book are
premised on the shareholder primacy model, I offer some suggestions as to how
corporate constitutionalism can allow us to move beyond the strict parameters of
that model.
I have noted the breadth and diversity of the corporate world and I have
commented on the pitfalls of attempting to devise a grand theory for all
corporations in all contexts. For these reasons, and in order to keep the argument to
a manageable length, there are certain parameters that must be kept in mind
throughout the book.
First, the arguments refer generally to corporations that have large and
dispersed shareholdings (with, perhaps, one or two major shareholders). These tend
to be public corporations (that is, they have the capacity to raise finance from the
public) but they can also include large proprietary (or private) corporations.66 If
they are public, they may be listed on a stock exchange, but this is not crucial to
the arguments developed in this book. The book does not, however, expressly
address the situation of corporations limited by guarantee, closely-held
corporations, one-person or wholly-owned corporations, or small to medium sized
enterprises (although they are mentioned occasionally). The ideas presented in the
book may nevertheless find some resonance with these other corporate forms.
Secondly, the book concentrates on corporations that operate
predominantly within a national setting, and does not specifically address the issues
raised, and the problems posed, by transnational or multinational corporations.
66
In Australia, a proprietary company can have a maximum of fifty shareholders (this
limitation does not include employee-shareholders): Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) s
113(1).
18 The Constitutional Corporation
Thirdly, as is apparent already, the book uses Australian corporate law
and the Australian corporate environment as its main reference point, although
comparisons are made with, and examples are taken from, other jurisdictions.67
This Australian focus does not imply that the model of corporate constitutionalism
is inappropriate elsewhere. Indeed, many aspects of Australian corporate law have
their equivalents in Canada, New Zealand, the United Kingdom, and (perhaps to a
lesser extent) the United States. 68 However, despite the alleged international
ubiquity of the corporate model that is based upon full legal personality, limited
liability for shareholders, separation of corporate management from share
ownership, and ready transferability of shares, the workability of the arguments
made in this book must be assessed by reference to local factors. Thus, the
arguments presented in this book draw on the corporate climate and the legislation
with which I am most familiar.
67
For this reason, throughout the book the primary reference is to the Australian
legislation, the Corporations Act 2001 (Cth).
68
There are significant differences in US law regarding the allocation of power between
shareholders and directors (eg the power of directors in US corporations to amend the
corporation’s by-laws: Revised Model Business Corporations Act §10.20 (2002). For a
challenge to this situation, see L Bebchuk, ‘The Case for Increasing Shareholder
Power’ (2005) 118 Harvard Law Review 833.
Chapter 2
Introduction
Despite the critical attention that has been given to ‘corporate governance’, and
notwithstanding the variety of perspectives used, there is a noticeable uniformity in
the underlying conceptualisation of this topic. This Chapter describes and assesses
the dominant legal and economic frameworks which continue to structure the way
we think about corporate law and corporate governance. It begins by examining the
formal legal model that has shaped ideas about corporations and corporate
regulation for over a century. This legal model uses the idea of contract to define
the nature of relations inside the corporation. The legal-contractual model is then
compared with economic models that have exerted considerable influence over the
corporate law reform agenda in recent years.
The legal and economic frameworks both rely on a contractual paradigm,
and so they have some common points of reference. Importantly, though, there are
also significant differences between these two frameworks. As will be discussed,
some of these differences involve technical distinctions — for example, lawyers
refer to ‘the corporation’ or ‘the company’ while economists talk about ‘the firm’.
These technical distinctions indicate underlying conceptual differences. Legal
analysis posits the existence of the corporation as a separate legal entity;
economists, on the other hand, generally ignore or downplay the idea of separate
legal status. Furthermore, whilst economists and lawyers rely on contract to
emphasise the voluntary, consensual, and private nature of corporate relationships,
each discipline has its own reasons for doing so. When a lawyer says that the
relation between parties in a corporation has effect as a contract, the focus is on the
nature of the legal obligations thereby created and, more particularly, on the legal
enforceability of those obligations. 1 The lawyer intends to tap into established
principles and understandings of contract law (allowing for the peculiarities of this
corporate contract, noted later in this Chapter). In contrast, the economist tends to
use contract as an analytical method or even as a metaphorical device to describe
corporate relations. The economist is not concerned so much with the
enforceability of the contract as with emphasising the reciprocal nature of the
1
See M Eisenberg, ‘The Conception that the Corporation is a Nexus of Contracts, and
the Dual Nature of the Firm’ (1999) 24 Iowa Journal of Corporate Law 819, 822.
20 The Constitutional Corporation
arrangements that are embodied in the contract.2 So, despite some similarities in
rhetoric, the legal and economic contractual frameworks say different things about
corporations and corporate law.
Because of these differences, difficulties can arise when legal and
economic analyses intersect, as they do in ‘law and economics’ scholarship.3 The
difficulty with much law and economics scholarship is that these different uses of
the term ‘contract’ are not always acknowledged; indeed, law and economics
writers frequently ‘slip back and forth between the two meanings of “contract”,
exploiting the ambiguity of the term’.4
After assessing these two contract-based approaches, the Chapter then
considers how a constitutional approach, drawing on political theory, provides a
rich conceptual alternative. This requires us, first, to understand the relevance of
political theory to the study of corporate governance, and then to consider the
relative advantages of constitutional theory over other types of political theory.
Contractualism
2
Ibid.
3
As I explain below, there is some diversity in this literature, so it is probably more
accurate to talk of ‘schools’ of law and economics.
4
T Joo, ‘Contract, Property and the Role of Metaphor in Corporations Law’ (2002) 35
University of California Davis Law Review 779, 795.
5
I say ‘as a general rule’, because while in some jurisdictions (eg Canada Business
Corporations Act, RSC 1985, s 102) this division of power is prescribed by statute, in
others it is the default position that may be varied by a corporation (eg in Australia the
‘replaceable rule’ in s 198A Corporations Act) although it is rare to find departures
from this default position.
6
In Australia, see Corporations Act 2001ss 198B, 254U, and 249C respectively.
From Contract to Constitution 21
Notwithstanding this grant of power to the directors, corporations
legislation reserves decisions on certain matters exclusively for the members in
general meeting. In Australia this includes the adoption, modification or repeal of a
corporate constitution, the decision to convert from one type of corporation to
another (for example, from public to proprietary), reductions of share capital, and,
in the case of a public corporation, the removal of directors. 7 In addition, a
corporation may specify in its constitution other matters that are to be decided by
the general meeting. This usually includes the appointment of directors, the
variation of rights attached to a class of shares, and the removal of directors (in the
case of a proprietary company).8 If a corporation is listed on the Australian Stock
Exchange, the Listing Rules of the Exchange also require that certain matters must
be approved by the shareholders in general meeting, including any significant
change to the corporation’s activities, the sale of the corporation’s main
undertaking, or (in certain instances) a new issue of shares. 9 Finally, there are
powers given to the members by principles of fiduciary law, including the power to
ratify a breach of duty by the directors.10
Corporate law restricts the capacity of members to intervene in the
directors’ exercise of managerial powers. When a corporation confers general
powers of management exclusively on its directors then the members have no
power to intervene in the day-to-day exercise of that power or to dictate the manner
of its exercise.11 In the High Court of Australia, Barwick CJ described the legal
position this way:
Directors who are minded to do something which in their honest view is for the
benefit of the company are not to be restrained because a majority shareholder or
shareholders holding a majority of shares in the company do not want the directors
so to act.12
In other words, according to the legal model the board of directors is a decision-
making organ that has relative autonomy from the general meeting of members.
7
In Australia, see Corporations Act 2001 ss 136, 162, 256C, 203D, respectively.
8
In Australia, see the replaceable rules in Corporations Act 2001 ss 201G, 246B, and
203C.
9
In Australia, see the Australian Stock Exchange Listing Rules 11.1, 11.2, and 7.1.
10
Regal (Hastings) Ltd v Gulliver [1967] 2 AC 134; Furs Ltd v Tomkies (1936) 54 CLR
583.
11
Automatic Self-Cleansing Filter Syndicate Co Ltd v Cunninghame [1906] 2 Ch 34, 44;
John Shaw & Sons (Salford) Ltd v Shaw [1935] 2 KB 113, 134; NRMA v Parker (1986)
4 ACLC 609, 613-614.
12
Ashburton Oil NL v Alpha Minerals NL (1971) 123 CLR 614, 620.
22 The Constitutional Corporation
A key component of this legal model is that each corporation is regarded as a legal
entity, distinct from its members and directors.13 The legal model posits a set of
legal relationships between this corporate legal entity, its directors, and its
members. These three sets of legal actors are said to be bound together by a
contract that is embodied in the corporation’s constitution. This is one of the
foundational concepts of Anglo-Australian corporate law. In Australia it is
enshrined in s 140(1) of the Corporations Act 2001 which declares that the
provisions in a corporate constitution ‘have effect as a contract’ between the
company and each member, between the company and each director and company
secretary, and between a member and each other member.14 The burden of this
contract is that each party agrees to observe and perform the rules in the
constitution so far as is applicable to them.
For directors the terms of this contract are supplemented by important
fiduciary duties, and each director is required to act in the best interests of ‘the
company’ or (in other formulations) ‘the shareholders as a whole’. These duties are
not imposed by the corporate contract; instead their basis lies in equitable
principles. However, while the statutory corporate contract does not create a
director’s fiduciary duties, they are exercised within the context of that contract
and the relationships it encompasses. According to Bryson J (in the NSW Supreme
Court):
[C]ourts have accepted for the purposes of equitable obligations as for legal
obligations the reality of the legal personality of the company and of the structure
of rights among shareholders, company and directors created by the legislation
and articles of association [now the replaceable rules and corporate constitution]
under which they have chosen to conduct their affairs.15
In the first place, a contract cannot be altered except by the mutual consent of the
parties, whereas a regulation can be altered by the legislative authority of the
company even as against dissenters. In the second place, a contract is personal and
binds only the party who made it and his executors and administrators; whereas a
13
The authority usually cited for this is the House of Lords decision in Salomon v
Salomon & Co Ltd [1897] AC 22, although the separate legal status of the company had
been recognised prior to this.
14
In the United Kingdom see s 14(1) Companies Act 1985. No such section exists in the
Canada Business Corporations Act, RSC 1985.
15
Glavanics v Brunninghausen (1996) 14 ACLC 345, 355.
From Contract to Constitution 23
regulation binds the owners of the shares for the time being, and the obligation
imposed thereby is appurtenant to the shares and passes with them to every person
who for the time being is the owner of them.16
More recently McHugh and Gummow JJ in the High Court of Australia noted five
features of this ‘unusual type’ of contract.17 First, the terms of the contract can be
altered without the agreement of all of the parties to a contract, since a special
resolution requires only a three quarters majority of votes by those members who
actually choose to exercise their voting rights.18 Secondly, ‘there is no jurisdiction
in a court of Equity to rectify [the terms of the constitution] even if they do not
accord with the concurrent intention of all the signatories thereof at the moment of
signature’. Thirdly, individual members face considerable obstacles to enforcing
the contract against the corporation.19 Fourthly, their Honours referred to Salmond
J’s observation (quoted above) that in a corporation with share capital the contract
attaches to the shares rather than to the shareholder. Finally, they noted that under
present authority a shareholder is precluded ‘from suing the company for damages
for breach of contract whilst still a member and without seeking recision of the
contract whereby the shares were obtained’.20
Given that ordinary legal notions of contract are so strained when they are
applied in the corporate context we must wonder about the rationale for applying
this contractual framework in first place. The historical explanation traces the
evolution of modern corporations back to the English unincorporated joint stock
companies based on a deed of settlement which were prominent in the eighteenth
and early nineteenth centuries. These companies were an amalgamation of
partnership and trust concepts, the idea being to escape the restrictions of the
Bubble Act of 1720.21 They consisted of large numbers of investors pooling their
finances on a joint stock basis. The joint stock was vested in trustees to be
managed according to the terms of a deed of settlement which was executed by
each member of the company.22 These deeds of settlement were the forerunners of
the later articles of association, and now the corporate constitution. A useful
summary of their operation can be found in the judgement of Jordan CJ in
Australian Coal & Shale Employees’ Federation v Smith:
16
Shalfoon v Cheddar Valley Co-operative Dairy Co Ltd [1924] NZLR 561, 580.
17
Bailey v NSW Medical Defence Union Ltd (1995) 13 ACLC 1698, 1717.
18
Corporations Act s 136(2) permits alteration of the constitution by special resolution; s
9 defines ‘special resolution’.
19
This observation was made prior to the introduction of the statutory derivative action
into the Corporations Act (Pt 2F.1A), which is discussed later in this book.
20
Their Honours refer to Houldsworth v City of Glascow Bank (1880) 5 App Cas 317 as
authority for this point.
21
The Bubble Act of 1720 (6 Geo 1, c 18) was an attempt by the English Parliament to
regulate the rapid growth in share speculation. The Act prohibited the formation of joint
stock companies unless by an Act of Parliament or Royal Charter.
22
For more detail on the history of the modern corporate form, see R Tomasic, S
Bottomley and R McQueen, Corporations Law in Australia (2nd ed, 2002) Chapter 1.
24 The Constitutional Corporation
[T]he Memorandum and Articles comprise what was formerly contained in the
deed of settlement of the old unincorporated joint stock companies. Such a deed
was executed by all the members of the company, and contained a covenant by the
members with a trustee for the company to observe its provisions. This practice
was recognised by the English Companies Act of 1844 (7 and 8 Vic c 110) which
provided by s 7 that no joint stock company should be entitled to receive a
certificate of complete registration under that Act unless its deed of settlement
contained a covenant on the part of every shareholder to pay up the amount of the
instalments on the shares taken by such shareholder and to perform the several
engagements in the deed contained on the part of the shareholders.23
The 1844 Act that is referred to in this passage was the first English
companies statute to introduce incorporation by registration. Indeed, the Act
represented the beginning of the modern system of corporate regulation. However
the Act still clung to earlier ideas of a joint stock form of association based upon
ideas of partnership. Thus, as a prerequisite to registration, the deed of settlement
had to be executed by all members.24 Nevertheless, the advent of incorporation by
registration, followed eleven years later by limited liability on incorporation, 25
meant that the number of large joint stock company registrations began to grow.
The requirement that each member must execute the deed of settlement became an
inconvenience, and thus in 1856 the Joint Stock Companies Act introduced a
provision that deemed execution to have occurred.26 This is explained in Jordan
CJ’s judgement:
In other words, for most of its history the statutory provision that is now found in
s 140 of the Corporations Act was not primarily concerned with declaring the
contractual status of the corporate constitution. Instead, the earlier provisions were
concerned with resolving what was essentially a practical procedural problem:
obtaining the execution of the corporation’s governing rules by each person in a
diverse group of members. Despite this, the focus of subsequent versions of these
legislative provisions shifted to declaring the contractual status of intra-company
23
Australian Coal & Shale Employees Federation v Smith (1937) 38 SR (NSW) 48, 54.
24
Companies Act 1844 ss 7 and 26.
25
18 & 19 Vict c 133.
26
See W E Patterson and H H Ednie, Australian Company Law (2nd ed, 1971) 1444. See
also R Gregory, ‘The Section 20 Contract’ (1981) 44 Modern Law Review 526, 528.
27
(1937) 38 SR (NSW) 48, 54.
From Contract to Constitution 25
relations, stating that the corporate constitution ‘has the effect of a contract under
seal’ or ‘has effect as a contract’.28 As McHugh and Gummow JJ have noted in the
High Court of Australia, the continued inclusion of such sections in corporations
statutes has ‘evinced the intention, as a matter of form, to preserve the link with the
old deed of settlement by carrying over contractual notions to support what, in any
event, would later come to be seen as incidents of modern corporate law’.29
Modern corporate law thus uses the idea of a contract to define the
boundaries of the corporation, to define which legal actors fall within the
parameters of the corporation, and who falls outside. Contract is also used to define
what types of claims and interests will count for the purposes of intra-corporate
governance. For example, in Andy Kala Pty Ltd v EJ Doherty (Northcote) Pty Ltd30
the court had to decide whether a clause in a corporation’s articles of association
which stipulated a particular method for resolving disputes between members of
the corporation thereby created a contractual obligation on a member to accept a
determination made under that process. The court held that such a provision was
not enforceable as a term of the statutory contract. This conclusion was justified on
the grounds that:
[n]ot every dispute which arises between members of a company, even if it may
touch upon their respective obligations as members, is encompassed by [s 140]. ...
The “statutory contract” contemplated by such sections as [s 140] arises from and
is limited to the nature of the relationships which exist between an entity and its
members, or between members, with respect to the entity itself.31
Similarly, in Bailey v New South Wales Medical Defence Union Ltd, where the
plaintiff sought to enforce an indemnity agreement between a member and the
corporation, the High Court drew a distinction between rights arising from the
statutory contract formed by what is now s 140, and the indemnity agreement
which was found in a ‘special’ contract formed outside the statutory contract.32
The use of contract law principles in the corporate context thus does two
things: it excludes the interests of those who are deemed to be non-contracting
parties,33 and it excludes what are deemed to be the non-corporate interests of the
contracting parties. 34 So, for shareholders, ‘the purpose of the [corporate
constitution] is to define the position of the shareholder as shareholder, not to bind
28
This ‘has effect’ formulation was introduced in 1985 (amending what was then s 78 of
the Companies Code 1981).
29
Bailey v NSW Medical Defence Union Ltd (1995) 13 ACLC 1698, 1717.
30
(1995) 13 ACLC 1630.
31
Ibid 1635.
32
(1995) 13 ACLC 1698.
33
See, for example, Forbes v NSW Trotting Club Ltd [1977] 2 NSWLR 515 (holding that
a professional punter who was excluded from admission to race tracks controlled by the
company could not enforce provisions in the company’s articles of association).
34
See, for example, the often cited case of Eley v Positive Government Security Life
Assurance Co (1875) 1 Ex D 20 (holding that a member could not use the articles of
association to enforce his rights as the company’s solicitor).
26 The Constitutional Corporation
him in his capacity as an individual’. 35 By using the device of contract, the
corporation is reduced to a limited set of strictly defined relationships.
35
Bisgood v Henderson’s Transvaal Estates Ltd [1908] 1 Ch 743, 759 per Buckley LJ.
36
See the list of indicative Australian work set out in M Whincop, ‘Of Fault and Default:
Contractarianism as a Theory of Anglo-Australian Law’ (1997) 21 Melbourne
University Law Review 187, 189. The influence in the United States has been much
more remarkable, as is evident from even a cursory review of the American corporate
law literature.
37
The Australian Government’s Corporate Law Economic Reform Program, initiated in
1997, is a clear indication of the rhetorical appeal of economics to corporate law
reformers. The program has been criticised for its poor use of economics: M Whincop,
‘The Political Economy of Corporate Law Reform in Australia’ (1999) 27 Federal Law
Review 77. For an example of a simple use of cost-benefit analysis, see Registrar-
General v Northside Developments Pty Ltd (1989) 7 ACLC 52, 59 per Kirby P.
38
For example M Whincop, An Economic and Jurisprudential Genealogy of Corporate
Law (2001).
39
For a review of these and other economic theories, see O Hart, ‘An Economist’s
Perspective on the Theory of the Firm’ (1989) 89 Columbia Law Review 1757.
40
Agency theory is associated principally with the work of M Jensen and W Meckling, in
particular their paper ‘Theory of the Firm: Managerial Behaviour, Agency Costs and
Ownership Structure’ (1976) 3 Journal of Financial Economics 305.
41
Transaction cost economics is associated principally with the work of Oliver
Williamson — see especially The Mechanics of Governance (1996) — building on the
seminal article by R Coase, ‘The Nature of the Firm’ (1937) 4 Economica 386.
42
Williamson, above n 41, 171.
From Contract to Constitution 27
Oliver Williamson, ‘both work out of a managerial-discretion setup. They also
adopt an efficient-contracting orientation to economic organisation. And both
argue that the board of directors in the corporation arises endogenously’.43 Relying
on these commonalities, the following synopsis draws on both of these strands,
although I acknowledge along the way that there are some differences in analytical
approach.44
In the economic world the corporation is analysed as a type of firm. The
economic concept of ‘the firm’ is not synonymous with the legal concept of ‘the
corporation’ or ‘the company’, despite a tendency in law and economics
scholarship to conflate the two. Corporate status is not an essential feature of the
firm, which can take the form of an unincorporated association, such as a
partnership. According to one definition, ‘the firm is simply a set of feasible
production plans which buys inputs and sells outputs in well-developed spot
markets’.45 Put another way, a firm is simply a method of organising production,
consisting of a series of transactions, or contracts, between investors, managers,
employees, creditors and customers. It is also important to bear in mind here that
the use of the term ‘contract’ does not necessarily correspond to the legal idea of
contract. Rather, it is intended to draw attention to the adaptive and voluntary
nature of the arrangements which are made between the participants.
Agency theory sums up this arrangement in the well-known description of
the firm as ‘a nexus of contracts’, a description that implies that there is no
difference between a firm and ordinary market exchanges; a firm, just like a market
‘represents a mere series of contracts joining inputs to produce output’. 46
Transaction cost theory does draw a distinction between the market and the firm —
one of its key inquiries is why it is that some production processes take place via
market exchanges but others adopt a hierarchical firm structure to achieve their
output. Thus, transaction cost theory regards the firm as a hierarchical governance
structure, rather than a nexus of contracts.47 Despite this difference, both theories
regard the firm as ‘a construct of contract’, and both ‘explain its structural features
as cost saving devices of transacting parties’.48
The economic framework assumes that, given their wide grant of
managerial discretion, there is a real risk that a firm’s managers 49 will seek to
maximise their own gains in ways that will not necessarily coincide with
maximising the firm’s profits. Investors in a firm will therefore be concerned to
43
Ibid 173.
44
For a discussion of the commonalities and differences see ibid 171-179.
45
R McEwin, ‘Public versus Shareholder Control of Directors’ (1992) 10 Companies &
Securities Law Journal 182, 185.
46
W Bratton, ‘The “Nexus of Contracts” Corporation: A Critical Appraisal’ (1989) 74
Cornell Law Review 407, 420.
47
Williamson, above n 41, 173.
48
Bratton, above n 46, 422.
49
This is another difference between legal and economic analysis: the economist’s
‘manager’ is not necessarily restricted to the legal category ‘director’.
28 The Constitutional Corporation
ensure that the managers — their ‘agents’ 50 — will run the firm in a way that
maximises profits rather than managerial self-interest. The problem for investors
then lies in monitoring managers’ behaviour effectively. Monitoring requires time,
knowledge, money and coordination between the investors. For their part, the
managers will be concerned to retain their positions, and therefore they will seek to
assure investors that their interests are not at risk from managerial misconduct.
Therefore, contracts between managers and investors will try, amongst other things,
to minimise these ‘agency costs’ 51 (or, in the language of transaction-cost
economics, they will try to reduce managerial opportunism).
The process of negotiating these contracts is imperfect. Investors will be
limited in the amount of time and knowledge they can devote to negotiations (in
transaction-cost terms, investors have ‘bounded rationality’).52 Moreover, in firms
with widespread ownership the opportunities for collective or coordinated
negotiation amongst investors will be very small. In summary, the prospects of
effective monitoring are low, and the transaction costs of negotiating contracts to
deal with the problem are high.
In the case of corporations, economic analysis argues that there are two
mechanisms that can reduce these transaction costs and act as an efficient
substitute for investor monitoring of management behaviour. The first mechanism
is the free operation of efficient, competitive market forces. The three markets that
are most commonly referred to are: the market for corporate securities (whereby
information about a corporation, including the terms which bind the managers, is
said to be built into the price of the corporation’s securities); the market for
corporate control (whereby under-performing and inefficient corporations will be
taken over by those who place a higher value on the corporation’s assets); and the
market for corporate managers (which controls the risk of negligence or the abuse
of managerial power). The operation of these competitive markets supplies
information about corporations to investors, and constrains the misuse of private
economic power.53
The second mechanism is provided by a system of corporate law.
According to Easterbrook and Fischel:
50
Yet another difference between corporate lawyers and economists is that in the context
of intra-corporate relations, the law does not classify directors strictly as agents of
shareholders. The fiduciary position of directors is sui generis: ‘In some respects they
resemble agents, in others they do not’ Regal (Hastings) Ltd v Gulliver [1942] 1 All ER
378, 387.
51
Jensen and Meckling, above n 40.
52
O Williamson, ‘Transaction Cost Economics’, reprinted in R Romano (ed),
Foundations of Corporate Law (1993) 13.
53
See M Stokes, ‘Company Law and Legal Theory’ in W Twining (ed), Legal Theory and
Common Law (1986) 157.
From Contract to Constitution 29
enabling the venturers to concentrate on matters that are specific to their
undertaking. ... Corporate law - and in particular the fiduciary principle enforced
by the courts - fills in the blanks and oversights with the terms that people would
have bargained for had they anticipated the problems and been able to contract
costlessly in advance. On this view corporate law supplements but never displaces
actual bargains...54
This passage emphasises the private and voluntary nature of corporate relationships
within the economic model. Corporations are not regarded as though they are
‘creatures of the state in any important or fundamental sense’.55 A consequence of
this private, consensual view is that corporate law rules ought to be regarded only
as default options, allowing tailor-made contracts to be adopted within individual
corporations.56 Corporate actors should have the freedom to opt out of statutory or
judicially created rules and to construct their own contractual arrangements. Some
law and economics writers take a less dogmatic view, allowing that corporate law
should prescribe some mandatory rules and impose some duties and
responsibilities in order to correct potential problems that arise from the principal-
agent relationship.57
A Critique of Contractualism
The legal and economic models just described offer the promise of ‘illuminating
the internal operation of the firm’, 58 but they fail to deliver completely on that
promise. The shortcomings in each approach can be traced, in different ways, to
their contractual origins. Below, I list four limitations or problems for corporate
law and corporate theory that result from this preoccupation with the contractual
paradigm. I emphasise the word ‘limitations’; I am not arguing that we should
abandon contractual approaches. When we look at corporations and corporate law
through a contractual lens we are able to see some things quite clearly (for example,
the different roles played by various participants in the corporate enterprise, and
54
F Easterbrook and D Fischel, The Economic Structure of Corporate Law (1991) 34. For
an argument that fiduciary obligations should not be regarded as hypothetical contract
terms see D DeMott, ‘Beyond Metaphor: An Analysis of Fiduciary Obligation’ [1988]
Duke Law Journal 879.
55
R Clark, ‘Contracts, Elites, and Traditions in the Making of Corporate Law’ (1989) 89
Columbia Law Review 1703, 1706.
56
There are different versions of this argument. Coffee, for example, argues that default
terms can be excluded but only after careful judicial scrutiny of the new replacement
terms: J Coffee, ‘The Mandatory/Enabling Balance in Corporate Law: An Essay on the
Judicial Role’ (1989) 89 Columbia Law Review 1618.
57
For example, C Riley, ‘Contracting Out of Company Law: Section 459 of the
Companies Act 1985 and the Role of the Courts’ (1992) Modern Law Review 782.
58
V Brudney ‘Corporate Governance, Agency Costs, and the Rhetoric of Contract’
(1985) 85 Columbia Law Review 1403.
30 The Constitutional Corporation
the need to assess the variable impact of market forces and legal rules on them).59
Through the same lens, however, some issues become distorted (for example, the
argument that market forces are a presumptively preferable form of regulation to
mandatory rules), 60 and we risk losing sight completely of other concerns (for
example, the identification of a corporate or collective interest, or the possibility of
other-regarding behaviour by shareholders).
The first limitation is that the contract paradigm has a tendency to reduce
complex relationships between many people to agreements between pairs of
individual legal or economic actors. The resulting image of the corporation is that
of an arena in which members and managers meet each other one to one as private
and individual actors in the pursuit of private and individual goals. This is quite
obvious with the economic contractual models, which rely on the philosophy of
methodological individualism, emphasising that only the actions of individuals are
relevant in explaining social and economic phenomena: ‘[m]ethodological
individualism holds that only individuals are responsible, and that corporate action
or corporate responsibility is no more than the sum of its individual parts’.61 Indeed,
the very idea of the corporation is dismissed as an abstraction or, at best, treated as
‘a matter of convenience rather than reality’. 62 In this view, corporations only
involve the actions of individual actors and the only relevant function of that
activity is to maximise the returns to individual investors. The corporation is
reduced to a multiplicity of dyadic agreements; it is a ‘nexus of contracts’. 63
Corporations are thus analysed on the same dimension as sole traders; they are
regarded simply as different ways of organising production.
The legal model promises some relief from this one-dimensional image by
bringing the corporation into the picture as a separate contracting party.
Nevertheless, the result is a set of individualised contracts, summarised in s 140 of
the Corporations Act, between the corporation as an entity and ‘each’ director and
‘each’ member. Brennan and Buchanan’s reminder that ‘2 remains the magic
number for the economic analyst’ also holds for the legal framework. 64
Furthermore, the role and nature of the corporation as one of these contracting
parties remains unclear. We are presented with a disjointed collection of rules in
which the concept of the corporation is sometimes reduced to a mere legal device
(the corporation categorised as a legal person for liability purposes), but at other
times is described by reference to the decisions of majority voters at a general
59
Brudney concedes this: ibid 1404.
60
M Eisenberg, ‘Bad Arguments in Corporate Law’ (1990) Georgetown Law Journal
1551.
61
B Fisse and J Braithwaite, Corporations, Crime and Accountability (1993) 18. See also
S Lukes, Essays in Social Theory (1977) chapter 9.
62
Easterbrook and Fischel, above n 54, 12. Whincop described the idea as ‘a pragmatic
compromise’: above n 37, 45-47.
63
Later in this Chapter I discuss another strand of contract theory that seeks to escape this
limitation by referring to ‘relational contracts’. See below n 74 and accompanying text.
64
G Brennan and J Buchanan, The Reason of Rules: Constitutional Political Economy
(1985) 28.
From Contract to Constitution 31
meeting, or ‘the interests of the members as a whole’, or as an entity with interests
that transcend the immediate concerns of its present members and directors.
It is, of course, true that the majority of corporations are designed to
further private rights and interests, 65 but these need not be considered solely in
individualistic terms. None of these models provides an image of the corporation
as an organisation. Yet, as William Bratton has reminded us, ‘the “organisation”
remains central to our experience of corporation’. 66 The organisational life of a
corporation is not just the sum of the actions of individual corporate insiders. 67
What individuals do as members or directors of a corporation involves a complex
interplay of power relations, hierarchies, loyalties, and systems of control which
may vary over time and from one decision-making context to another. As Ewick
emphasises:
Although organisations are not synonymous with individuals (or their interests and
goals), neither are they entirely distinct from the individuals who comprise
them. .... The relationship is dialectic. Individuals can no more be separated or
detached from their organisational affiliations than the organisation can be
abstracted from its membership.68
Some may object that the idea of ‘organisational affiliations’ is hardly an apt
description of the relationship between the typical investor and the modern public
corporation. Surely, it will be said, shareholders are more concerned with market
price than corporate identity. In other words, if shareholders choose to behave like
short-term maximisers of personal wealth, isn’t it appropriate to analyse them in
contractual terms? The answer that is developed throughout this book is that while
this is certainly true of some shareholders it is not true of all, and it should not be
accepted as the basis of an all-encompassing model for corporate governance.
Contract-based frameworks on their own cannot cope adequately with the
complexity, variety and shifting nature of relations between individuals and
corporate organisation, nor with the great variety of organisational structures that
are produced as a result.
The second limitation of contract-based models is that they display a
general orientation towards economic analyses of corporate governance issues to
the exclusion of other perspectives. This is not surprising: contracts are concerned
chiefly with bringing about an effective exchange between parties. They are the
65
There is an argument that this is not the sole legitimate purpose of corporations, and
that they should also have regard to public or social interests. For an elaboration, see J
Parkinson, Corporate Power and Responsibility (1993).
66
W Bratton, ‘The Economic Structure of the Post-Contractual Corporation’ (1992) 87
Northwestern University Law Review 180, 209.
67
P Selznick, The Moral Commonwealth: Social Theory and the Promise of Community
(1992) 242. For a revealing sociological study that makes this point, see R Jackall,
Moral Mazes: The World of Corporate Managers (1988).
68
P Ewick, ‘“In the Belly of the Beast”: Rethinking Rights, Persons and Organisations’
(1988) 13 Law and Social Inquiry 175, 179 and 181.
32 The Constitutional Corporation
paradigmatic arrangement for economic analysis. Viewed from this perspective,
the corporation is assessed simply on economic means to achieve economic ends.
As I indicated in Chapter 1, one important perspective that is ignored by this
preoccupation with economic analysis is political theory.
The label ‘political theory’ is used here in its broadest sense. The
difference between ‘economic’ and ‘political’ perspectives is explained succinctly
by Kukathas and Pettit:
When two or more people seek to make an agreement which affects their interests
differently, so that each would most prefer a different arrangement from the other,
the agreement may be pursued in either of two ways: one we describe as economic,
the other as political. The economic way is for each to calculate what best suits his
own interests and then to try to get this: say, to bargain with the other or others,
seeking to win the largest benefit possible at the least concession from themselves.
The political way is for the parties to put aside their own particular interests and to
debate about the arrangement that best answers to such considerations – usually
considerations in some sense to do with the common good – as all can equally
countenance as relevant. The economic approach is institutionalized in the process
of market negotiation, the political – at least ideally – in the forum of discussion
where the parties are blocked, if only by the sanction of social disapproval, from
arguing by reference to special as distinct from common concerns.69
69
C Kukathas and P Pettit, Rawls — A Theory of Justice and Its Critics (1990) 32-33.
70
S Wolin, ‘Collective Identity and Constitutional Power’ in G Bryner and D Thompson
(eds), The Constitution and the Regulation of Society (1988) 97.
From Contract to Constitution 33
The fourth and final limitation is that under a contractual paradigm we
tend to treat corporations and the things they do as essentially private phenomena.
The origins of contract law lie in facilitation of private economic exchanges, and
even though contract analysis has been applied to the exercise of public power,
contract-based analyses of corporations and corporate law have an overwhelmingly
private orientation. Corporate law is generally regarded as a body of rules that
facilitates private, voluntary, individual agreements. Consequently, legislators,
judges and corporate regulators bear the burden of justifying why there should be
any external regulation of corporate activity, and why market forces should not be
given free reign. In the same vein, any apparent intrusion of public law-like
concepts into the world of corporate law, such as natural justice, procedural
fairness, or equality of opportunity, is also judged with suspicion.71 Of course to
say that corporate law is completely private is an overstatement. Despite the claims
of some economists, the market has not been entirely successful in controlling the
conduct of corporate managers. 72 For all of its alleged (and sometimes
demonstrable) deficiencies, the state’s involvement in corporate life has not
withered away, and it cannot be dismissed simply as an historical anachronism.73
To sum up: the application of contract-based approaches to the study of
corporate governance is limited because their approach is essentially individualistic,
economic, teleological, and private. Again, in listing these limitations, I am not
suggesting that contract has no role in analysing corporate governance and
corporate regulation. My criticism is directed at the tendency for these ideas to be
used to the exclusion of other approaches, or to be regarded as the ‘default setting’
for corporate law analysis. Furthermore, I suggest that the contractual paradigm
offers little scope for moving beyond these limitations. What is needed is a
complementary framework that draws upon a different paradigm. Before moving
to explore the detail of that paradigm, it is worthwhile considering one attempt by
contract scholars to broaden their analysis.
71
See L Griggs and R Snell, ‘Natural Justice - An Alternative Ground for Intervention in
Corporate Decision-making?’ (1994) 10 Queensland University of Technology Law
Journal 22.
72
W Bratton, ‘Public Values and Corporate Fiduciary Law’ (1992) 44 Rutgers Law
Review 675, 682.
73
A similar point is made in K Greenfield, ‘From Rights to Regulation in Corporate Law’
in F Macmillan Patfield (ed), Perspectives on Company Law: 2 (1997) 1, 21.
74
Relational contract theory is most commonly associated with the work of Ian Macneil.
For example, ‘Contracts: Adjustment of Long-Term Economic Relations Under
34 The Constitutional Corporation
Although discrete transactions (such as a simple sale/purchase contract)
and relational contracts all involve economic exchanges, relational contracts are
also said to involve ‘significant elements of non-economic personal satisfaction’.75
The complexity and the relational nature of these exchanges makes it difficult for
the parties to specify all the terms of their agreement in advance. In addition, these
relationships are characterised by uncertainty about the future conditions under
which the agreement will be performed, coupled with the difficulty of defining in
advance the sorts of adjustments that the parties should make to meet those future
contingencies. 76 Relational contract theory thus recognises the importance of
flexible and generalised obligations in contracts, such as the requirement that one
party must use their ‘best endeavours’ to meet the expectations of the other party.
Similarly, the parties might agree to certain processes and structures that will allow
for future adjustments and negotiations between the parties. Relational theory
acknowledges that obligations, like the relationship itself, can evolve. Relational
theory also recognises the existence of multiparty contracts which can create a
collective identity amongst the participants, moving away from the two-party
model favoured by classical contract theory.77
Relational contract theory has been suggested as a more appropriate
framework for understanding relations between corporations, directors and
shareholders than the classical contract ideas which underpin agency theory. 78
Certainly there is much about the association between a shareholder and a public
corporation that fits the relational theorist’s description of complexity, uncertainty
and difficulty in specifying detailed terms. The imposition of fiduciary obligations
of good faith on directors can be read as a flexible response to these problems,
offering the possibility of future adjustments to contractual obligations. In the same
way, ‘[m]echanisms such as the general meeting and other governance processes to
which the shareholders have access enable members to contribute to the final form
of alterations’. 79 Relational theory also offers the conceptual advantage over
classical contract approaches by emphasising the importance of the relationship
between the corporate parties, rather than focusing on the intended product of that
relationship.80
A different vision of the company might draw upon the democratic ideal which
inspires the relation of the citizen to the state. The democratic ideal asserts that
those who are substantially affected by the decisions made by political and social
institutions in our society should be involved in the making of those decisions.84
In this Part I begin to develop ‘a different vision of the company’ under the banner
of corporate constitutionalism. I begin by explaining the relevance of political
theory to corporations. Then I consider briefly two other political approaches
before going on to explain my preference for a framework based on the idea of
constitutionalism.
81
Ibid.
82
For example, Macneil, above n 75, 720ff and 795-796.
83
See Russell Hardin, ‘Why a Constitution?’ in B Grofman and D Wittman (eds), The
Federalist Papers and the New Institutionalism (1989) 101.
84
Stokes, above n 53, 180.
36 The Constitutional Corporation
Corporations and Political Theory
85
For an earlier argument about corporations and constitutionalism, see R Eells, The
Government of Corporations (1962).
86
Philip Pettit, The Common Mind: An Essay on Psychology, Society and Politics (1993)
284 (references omitted).
87
See, for example, J Rawls, A Theory of Justice (1971).
88
Pettit, above n 86, 222 and 284.
89
See Kukathas and Pettit, above n 69, 1.
From Contract to Constitution 37
Corporations frequently act, in effect, as regulatory agencies, implementing
government policies and enforcing regulatory mandates.90 As political institutions
corporations therefore have significance as public as well as private actors.
This is hardly a new or startling observation, even though it does seem to
go largely unacknowledged in legal analysis. For many years a variety of
commentators, writing from a variety of perspectives, have made the same point.91
Maitland described the corporation and the state as two species within a single
genus of more or less permanently organised groups of individual actors; they are
group units to which we attribute actions, intentions, praise and blame. 92 More
recently, the critical legal scholar Roberto Unger has made the similar observation
that modern society looks more like ‘a constellation of governments, rather than an
association of individuals held together by a single government’.93
Unger’s observation takes us to the second sense in which corporations
can be said to be political entities, and this point is the primary focus of this book.
Corporations are political not simply because they are players in societal power
relations, but also because they themselves are arenas in which power and
authority, rights and obligations, duties and expectations, benefits and
disadvantages, are allocated and exercised, either actively or passively, collectively
or individually, in relationships that can be characterised by conflict, control,
competition, or co-operation. In short, each corporation is a body politic, a
governance system. This is as true, albeit in different ways, for the closely-held
corporation as it is for the largest public corporation. Again, this is not a novel
observation. Writers as diverse as Thomas Hobbes, C Wright Mills, and Adolf
Berle Jnr have made the same point.94 Nor is this an incidental or trivial feature of
corporations. While we might describe some corporations as being more political
than others — perhaps because they are ‘racked by disputation over their structure
90
J Freeman, ‘The Private Role in Public Governance’ (2000) 75 New York University
Law Review 543, 547.
91
For example, P Blumberg, ‘The Politicalization of the Corporation’ [1971] The
Business Lawyer 1551; R Stevenson Jr ‘The Corporation as a Political Institution’
(1979) 8 Hofstra Law Review 39.
92
F W Maitland, ‘Introduction’ to Otto von Gierke, Political Theories of the Middle Age
(1938) ix.
93
R M Unger, Law in Modern Society - Toward a Criticism of Social Theory (1976) 193.
94
This is noted by E Latham, ‘The Body Politic of the Corporation’ in E Mason (ed), The
Corporation in Modern Society (1960) 218, 219. See also Eells, above n 85, 10; A
Fraser, Reinventing Aristocracy: The Constitutional Reformation of Corporate
Governance (1998); J Pound, ‘The Rise of the Political Model of Corporate
Governance and Corporate Control’ (1993) 68 New York University Law Review 1003.
Sometimes the point is expressed by describing corporations as private governments -
eg A S Miller, ‘Private Governments and the Constitution’ in A Hacker (ed), The
Corporation Takeover (1965) 117.
38 The Constitutional Corporation
and governance’ — all corporations are political as much as they are economic
entities.95
Thinking of corporations as political entities does not mean treating them
as analogues of parliamentary systems of public government. Despite superficial
similarities — the election of a group of policy-makers by a diverse group of voters,
with day-to-day implementation of policies being delegated to an unelected
bureaucracy — corporations differ from the institutions of public government in
many significant ways. For example, unlike a parliament, a board of directors is
not a representative body, at least not in the sense that each director represents a
specific constituency. Directors must act for the entire corporation. 96 Moreover,
directors need not be drawn from the ranks of the shareholders who elect them.
There are other obvious differences: there is no institutionalised ‘opposition party’
to challenge the views of the elected directors; voting rights in a corporation attach
to shares not to the shareowner, so there is no fundamental concept of ‘one person,
one vote’; and shareholders have very limited rights of access to corporate
information. 97 None of this, however, undermines the value of regarding
corporations as ‘bodies politic’ that can be analysed in ways that have echoes in
our approach to institutions of public government. As Pound observes: ‘[t]he
political approach to corporate governance accords with ... values about how major
institutions in our society should be governed, emphasising due process,
substantive debate, and the use of formal voting referenda’.98
A political theory of corporate governance does not necessarily entail the
proposition that directors and managers owe duties to non-shareholder stakeholders
or other constituencies (although it is open to that proposition). Nor does it compel
the application of notions of representative or participatory democracy to
corporations. It means simply that existing corporate governance structures and
patterns can be evaluated according to political, as much as economic, criteria.
Rather than focusing exclusively on corporate outcomes we can look at corporate
processes and ask what values ought to be protected and enhanced.99
The choice between an overtly political theory of corporate governance
and the more widely used economic analysis of corporate law has been explored by
several scholars. Lynne Dallas, for example, advocates a ‘power model’ of the firm,
95
Stevenson, above n 91, 40. The quoted words were used to describe NRMA Ltd in
NRMA Ltd v Snodgrass (2001) 19 ACLC 1675 by Mason P.
96
The appointment of nominee directors may be an exception to this. While English
authority insists that such directors must only consider the interests of the company as a
whole, Australian decisions have permitted greater scope to consider the interests of the
director’s appointers. Compare Scottish Co-operative Wholesale Society Ltd v Meyer
[1959] AC 324 with Levin v Clark [1962] NSWR 686 and Re Broadcasting Station
2GB Pty Ltd [1964-5] NSWR 1648.
97
There is no equivalent of ‘freedom of information’ legislation for company members.
98
Pound, above n 94, 1009. This echoes Frug’s point that public law and corporate law
are two versions of the same story: G Frug, ‘The Ideology of Bureaucracy in American
Law’ (1984) 97 Harvard Law Review 1276.
99
See Selznick, above n 67, 351.
From Contract to Constitution 39
which stands in opposition to the ‘efficiency model’ (the latter being located in the
economic-contractualist framework described earlier in this chapter).100 The power
model draws upon organisational and management theory. It ‘focuses upon the
political nature of decision-making in the large corporation’, and sees the firm as
‘an organic institution with its own internal structure and processes that impact on
the control of the firm’.101 Importantly, Dallas argues that managers are not simply
agents of shareholders; management is a strategic player in the power coalitions
within the firm. Mel Eisenberg, on the other hand, favours what he calls the
Economic Model over the Political Model of the large publicly held corporation.102
As he depicts it, the latter model posits the corporation as ‘essentially a political
institution’ whose legitimacy ‘depends upon the extent to which it is governed by
principles appropriate to a democratic state’. 103 Those principles, according to
Eisenberg, require a system of representative government which allows
participation in decision-making by the various constituencies in the corporation.
Eisenberg questions the relevance of this model to large corporations. In his
assessment, the Economic Model better reflects both ‘accepted conceptions of
institutional competence and legitimacy’ and the functional characteristics of the
large public corporation.104
The argument which I present in this book differs from these positions in
two ways. First, unlike Dallas and Eisenberg, I do not think that it is useful to
advocate one model or framework to the exclusion of all others. Whilst I argue for
a broadly political framework, I do so with the intention that it should be
considered as an additional option to, rather than a substitute for, economic
analysis. Because corporations can be categorised as political as much as economic
institutions, they can be subject to political as much as economic analysis.
Corporations can be ‘many things at one and the same time’ and, as Gareth
Morgan reminds us, there can be no privileged or ultimate analytical framework
for studying the complexity of corporate organisations. 105 Different theoretical
frameworks will reveal different things about corporations and their internal
organisation. When analysing a corporate governance situation or issue (be it a
share restructuring, a takeover defence, or the validity of a resolution) the first step
is to discern the character of the situation by referring to different frameworks and
noting what aspects of the situation are highlighted by each framework. The next
step is to make a critical and deliberate evaluation of these different interpretations
of the situation, asking whether all interpretations are equally useful, whether they
100
L Dallas, ‘Two Models of Corporate Governance: Beyond Berle and Means’ (1988) 22
University of Michigan Journal of Law Reform 19.
101
Ibid 25-26.
102
M Eisenberg, ‘Corporate Legitimacy, Conduct, and Governance - Two Models of the
Corporation’ (1983) 17 Creighton Law Review 1.
103
Ibid 2.
104
Ibid 17.
105
G Morgan, Images of Organisation (1986) 321.
40 The Constitutional Corporation
are reconcilable, and where each leads us.106 In particular, this two-step process
requires us to make a comparative evaluation of economic criteria such as
efficiency against constitutionalist criteria such as participation.
Secondly, in studying corporations and their regulation, political theory
must be adapted, not simply adopted. Eisenberg apparently sees all political theory
in terms of public (ie state) politics, leading him to dismiss it as inappropriate for
the study of corporations. 107 In his view, the proposition that ‘all political
institutions should be governed by political principles, and that any institution that
makes decisions of major importance to society is a political institution’, 108
trivialises the critical differences that exist between the state and the corporation.
As I have noted already, these differences are important, but acknowledging them
does not then require us to abandon the job of tackling more complex questions
about the ways in which, and extent to which, political theory should influence
corporations. What is needed is a corporate species of political theory. This is what
I mean by referring to corporate constitutionalism.
It is relatively easy to demonstrate the relevance of a political approach to
the study of corporations and corporate law. The more difficult step is to decide
upon a particular approach within the broad domain of political theory. In what
follows I consider three possible approaches which apply politics to corporations,
although in different ways: concession theory, social contract theory, and
constitutional theory. These approaches do not, of course, exhaust the field. I have
selected the first two because they are already recognised in the corporate
governance literature; the case for the third option is made throughout this book.
Concession Theory109
106
This two step analysis is taken from Morgan, above n 105, 322. It must also be stressed
that there cannot be (nor should there be) any meta-rule for determining when to use
any particular framework.
107
This is a common argument – see, for example, R Austin, ‘Commentary on Hill’ in R
Grantham and C Rickett (eds), Corporate Personality in the 20th Century (1998) 211.
108
Eisenberg, above n 102, 4.
109
The following discussion is taken from S Bottomley, ‘The Birds, the Beasts, and the
Bat: Developing a Constitutionalist Theory of Corporate Regulation’ (1999) 27 Federal
Law Review 243.
110
William Bratton also distinguishes weak and strong versions, although he draws the
categories in a slightly different way – see ‘The New Economic Theory of the Firm:
Critical Perspectives from History’ (1989) 41 Stanford Law Review 1471, 1475.
From Contract to Constitution 41
state’s claim to control the process of incorporation and its subsequent use. An
illustration of this view and its consequences is found in the New Zealand Court of
Appeal’s judgement in Nicholson v Permakraft Ltd where Cooke J stated that:
The status claim has two variants. The weak version limits itself to the
proposition that a corporation owes its legal existence and powers to the grant of
corporate status from the state. The weak version therefore seeks to avoid the
metaphysical question ‘what is a corporation?’ by confining itself to the legal
aspects of corporate status. The strong version is that the corporation is an artificial
entity which owes its very existence to the state, thereby inviting a much wider
debate about the legitimacy of state-based corporate regulation.
The second claim (‘the regulatory claim’) can be read as a quid pro quo
for the grant of corporate status. As a consequence of being created by the state,
concession theory argues that there is a presumption in favour of state regulation of
a corporation’s post-incorporation activity.112 This presumption purports to give the
state control over both the extent of the corporation’s legal capacity and the
exercise of that capacity.113 This is the weak version of the regulatory claim. The
claim is occasionally put in stronger terms, requiring not just compliance with
public regulations but also creating a positive duty to act in the public interest or in
a socially responsible manner. 114 The idea that a corporation should act in the
public interest was first developed at a time when charters of incorporation were
granted primarily to those enterprises which could demonstrate the pursuit of some
sort of public purpose or utility (eg development of trade by overseas trading
corporations such as the Hudson’s Bay Company, or the construction of
111
(1985) 3 ACLC 453, 459. Other examples can be found in the High Court of
Australia’s decision in Northside Developments Pty Ltd v Registrar-General (1990) 8
ACLC 611, 626 (per Brennan J) and in Salomon v Salomon & Co Ltd [1897] AC 22, 29
and 51. Concession theory was also influential in early United States corporate
jurisprudence – see Trustees of Dartmouth College v Woodward (1819) 17 US 518, 636
per Chief Justice Marshall.
112
Roberta Romano argues that there is no necessary link between these two claims.
Having created a new legal actor, the state ‘could conceivable imbue it with inviolable
rights’. See R Romano, ‘Metapolitics and Corporate Law Reform’ (1984) 36 Stanford
Law Review 923, 933.
113
A S Dewing, The Financial Policy of Corporations (5th ed 1953) vol 1, 12.
114
Noted in Parkinson, above n 65, 26. Parkinson disputes this claim, arguing that the
social responsibilities of corporations stem from a political theory about the legitimacy
of private power, and not from any theory about the state’s role in the creation of
corporations. See Chapter 3 n 15 and accompanying text.
42 The Constitutional Corporation
railways).115 It seems to be generally accepted in modern corporate law scholarship
that the strong regulatory claim was an early casualty of the introduction of general
incorporation statutes. However, remnants of the idea have survived in the form of
arguments about the need for corporate social responsibility, and in the theory that
corporations should be regarded essentially as social enterprises.116
While the origins of concession theory can be dated back to Roman times,
it became prominent in discussions about corporate regulation in the early
nineteenth century in both England and the United States.117 There is, for example,
Blackstone’s statement in 1765 that ‘[w]ith us, in England, the king’s consent is
absolutely necessary to the erection of any corporation, either impliedly or
expressly given’. 118 Over time the theory appears to have served two different
purposes: with the rise of the nation state the theory served to reinforce the power
of the state against the potential claims of other groupings of power, including
business organisations.119 Then, with the growing reliance on the corporate form in
economic activity in the early nineteenth century, came the realisation that these
incorporated concentrations of private power might use the legal incidents and
consequences of corporate status to cause harm to individuals who deal with the
corporation (including its own members). Thus the theory served to justify the
regulation of corporate activity in the interests of individual actors in their dealings
with corporations.120
Most of the criticisms of concession theory have come from adherents of
contract-based theories of the corporation (especially neoclassical economic
theory). 121 The debate is cast in stark terms: concession theory is aligned with
arguments in favour of public regulation, even with organic/holistic visions of the
community, 122 while neoclassical economic theory advocates the private and
individual ordering of private affairs.
Contract-based criticisms of concession theory combine a number of
claims, all of which seek to minimise the role of the state in the creation and
115
Ibid, 28-29. See also C A Cooke, Corporation, Trust and Company (1950) 102. The
alternative to incorporation was to organise an unincorporated association along joint-
stock lines. For discussion of a similar situation in the United States, see J Hurst, The
Legitimacy of the Business Corporation in the Law of the United States 1780-1970
(1970) 33-47.
116
See, eg, Parkinson, above n 65, 22-23, and Greenfield, above n 73.
117
As noted in the text above, it has continued to be cited in judicial opinions throughout
the twentieth century.
118
Cited in Dewing, above n 113, 11. See also Cooke, above n 115, 78.
119
J Dewey, ‘The Historic Background of Corporate Legal Personality’ (1926) 35 Yale
Law Journal 655, 666-667.
120
See Bratton, above n 110, 1486-1489 for a description of how corporate law doctrine
continued to respond to individualist concerns in the absence of concession theory.
121
This is a generalisation — not all critics would identify themselves as contract-based
theorists. See for example, Parkinson, above n 64. It has been suggested that advocates
of the neoclassical economics have resurrected concession theory simply as ‘a foil for
the new economic theory’: Bratton, above n 46, 433-434.
122
Romano, above n 112, 933-934.
From Contract to Constitution 43
regulation of corporations. One claim is empirical: concession theory does not fit
the facts of modern corporate life. Concession theory may have made sense at a
time when corporate status could only be obtained by the grant of a special charter
or by a special Act of Parliament, but the advent of general incorporation laws in
the late nineteenth century, widespread usage of which was sanctioned by the
House of Lords in Salomon’s Case,123 and the availability of standardised corporate
structures, means that concession theory has long since lost its relevance. As
Bratton puts it, ‘[o]nce equal and substantially free access to the corporate form
became the norm, the notion of ‘concession’ no longer described the practice of
incorporation’.124 Most commentators, whether contractualist or not, agree that on
this ground the concession theory of corporate regulation no longer has any
theoretical use. 125 A second set of claims takes a stance in favour of private
ordering. A good example is Butler and Ribstein’s argument that:
because corporations are not wards of the state, and because the capital markets
that discipline corporate contracts do not require more legal intervention than
other markets, it follows that there is no justification for subjecting corporate
arrangements to a higher level of regulation than other contracts.126
Hessen takes a similar approach, arguing that the three features most commonly
associated with the corporate form — separate entity status, perpetual succession,
and limited liability — can each be achieved through ordinary contract or trust
arrangements and therefore that the state has no special role to play in the creation
or continued regulation of corporations.127 In other words, the state grant of these
attributes is simply a cost-saving exercise for the incorporators, sparing them the
effort of having to secure these advantages by private negotiation. Hessen’s
argument is not convincing; as John Parkinson points out, in all practical terms
these state granted attributes are ‘beyond the reach of private agreement’.128
These criticisms set up a false dichotomy: the corporation is to be
categorised either as a ‘ward of the state’ or (the favoured position) as the product
of a freely-constructed private contractual agreements. In this way, neo-classical
contractarian critics tie the fate of concession theory to the fate of state regulation
of corporations.129 The theory of corporate constitutionalism developed in this book
123
Salomon v Salomon & Co Ltd [1897] AC 22.
124
Bratton, above n 46, 435 (footnote omitted). See also M Horwitz, ‘Santa Clara
Revisited: The Development of Corporate History’ (1985) 88 West Virginia Law
Review 173, 181-183.
125
In addition to Bratton, above n 46, and Horwitz, ibid, see Parkinson, above n 65, 25-32.
126
H N Butler and L E Ribstein, The Corporation and the Constitution (1995) 2.
127
R Hessen, In Defense of the Corporation (1979) Chapter 2. See also G M Anderson and
R D Tollison, ‘The Myth of the Corporation as a Creation of the State’ (1983) 3
International Review of Law and Economics 107.
128
Parkinson, above n 65, 32.
129
A point also noted by M Whincop and M Keyes, ‘Corporation, Contract, Community:
An Analysis of Governance in the Privatisation of Public Enterprise and the
Publicisation of Private Corporate Law’ (1997) 25 Federal Law Review 51, 67.
44 The Constitutional Corporation
tries to separate these two ideas. It accepts that the state does have a valid role to
play in regulating corporations. It also acknowledges that concession theory places
too much emphasis on the state’s responsibility for control of corporations, leading
to inappropriate command-control styles of corporate regulation and giving
insufficient weight to the importance of private interests and concerns in forming
and running corporations.
Given the attraction of contract-based frameworks for legal and economic analyses
of corporate law, it seems obvious to ask whether we should use a similar
framework when analysing corporations as political institutions. Contract-based
approaches to political theory have a long heritage, often being based on the idea
of a social contract between the citizen and the state. Courts have occasionally
described the corporate constitution as a social contract, although the meaning of
the term in this context has not been explained.130
Tom Campbell’s general description of the idea of a social contract is
helpful:
A social contract that is voluntarily agreed to by all citizens is said to form the
basis of the social and political obligations which those citizens owe to each other
and to the state. At the same time, it legitimates intrusions into individual freedom
and restrictions on personal liberty. 132 As Campbell explains, political theorists
such as Hobbes, Locke, Rousseau, and Rawls have formulated the details of the
130
For example, the judgements of Isaacs J in Ardlethan Options Ltd v Easdown (1915) 20
CLR 285, 294; Dutton v Gordon (1917) 23 CLR 362, 395; Wood v W & G Wood Pty
Ltd (1929) 43 CLR 77, 87.
131
T Campbell, Justice (2nd ed, 2001) 92-93.
132
K Scheppele and J Waldron, ‘Contractarian Methods in Political and Legal Evaluation’
(1991) 3 Yale Journal of Law and the Humanities 195, 200-201.
From Contract to Constitution 45
social contract in different ways.133 This is not the place for a detailed description
of these various arguments, but it is useful to highlight three elements of social
contract theory.
First, the purpose of the agreement which is embodied in the social
contract is to define, protect and advance the interests and needs of individual
citizens. This, like other forms of contract-based argument, seeks to legitimate
political structures and processes on the grounds of individual consent. Social
contract is a theory about how individuals live in society; it is not a theory about
society itself.
The second element concerns the nature of the agreement. How do
citizens express their consent to be ruled? Social contract theorists have provided
three answers to this question. The weakest answer is that the social contract must
be the result of actual agreement between citizens who have actually addressed
their minds to the issues. There is an obvious empirical problem with this argument
— there is little, if any, evidence that people in modern society have gone through
this process. A slightly stronger answer suggests that consent is given implicitly by
individual citizens, for example, by voting in an election or simply by continuing
to live within the political group. The problems with this argument lie in
identifying the actions which will constitute consent, and in determining the extent
of obligation which can be supported by implied consent.134 The third answer is
that these agreements are hypothetical. This argument suggests that:
133
See also D Held, Models of Democracy (1987).
134
See J Hampton, ‘Contract and Consent’ in R Goodin and P Pettit (eds), A Companion to
Contemporary Political Philosophy (1993) 379, 381. An alternative argument is that
consent can be implied from the fact that each individual is free to exit the contract if
they choose – see R Hills Jr, ‘The Constitutional Rights of Private Governments’
(2003) 78 New York University Law Review 144.
135
Scheppele and Waldron, above n 132, 196. John Rawls’ theory of justice is perhaps the
best known modern example of the hypothetical social contract approach: J Rawls, A
Theory of Justice (1971).
46 The Constitutional Corporation
ruler on the condition that it can later be withdrawn if the people so wish. In this
‘agency’ form of social contract theory, the people retain ultimate sovereignty.136
Social contract theory has limitations and disadvantages for developing a
political approach to modern corporate governance. To the extent that social
contract theory is built upon the ideal of implied individual agreements and
agency-based grants of power then the criticisms about the limitations of the
economic contractual models which I made earlier in this Chapter are relevant.137
This emphasis on individual rights and their protection seems to offer little scope
for parties to the contract to ‘put aside their own particular interests’ and to enter
into debates about ‘the common good’.138 A more particular problem arises because
the social contract is based on the premise that each and every person must give
their consent before there can be a legitimate exercise of power over them. This is
at odds with the idea of decisions made by a majority vote, in which the non-
consent of persons in the minority is disregarded.139 Corporate law presumes that
majority rule is the means by which decisions are made within a company.140 A
political theory which cannot accommodate this method of decision-making is
therefore of limited use in the corporate context.
Constitutional Theory141
The type of political inquiry that I argue has most to offer corporate law derives
from constitutional theory. The term ‘constitutional theory’ is slightly misleading
— there are many specific theories that can be grouped under this heading. Here I
will introduce some of the key ideas in constitutional theory in broad terms. In the
next Chapter I will ‘corporatise’ the concept by setting out a theory of corporate
constitutionalism.
There is considerable diversity in the way in which terms such as
‘constitution’ and ‘constitutionalism’ are defined and used. For present purposes,
two broad approaches can be contrasted: the first approach categorises
136
Hampton, above n 134, 380. The preceding summation of the Hobbesian and Lockean
approaches is taken from Hampton’s review.
137
See also Hardin, above n 83, criticising social contract theory and the idea of agreement
as the basis for constitutional order.
138
See Kukathas and Pettit, above n 69.
139
Scheppele and Waldron, above n 132, 198 and 221, also pointing out that although the
contract may leave certain issues to be resolved by majority vote, the theory still
requires unanimous agreement in advance on what issues can be settled in this manner.
140
It is worth remembering that majority rule in the corporate context can mean either a
majority of voting shareholders or a majority of voting shares. That is, a minority of
members who own a majority of the voting shares can control decisions at company
meetings.
141
The following discussion develops some of the ideas in S Bottomley, ‘From
Contractualism to Constitutionalism: A Framework for Corporate Governance’ (1997)
19 Sydney Law Review 277, 293ff.
From Contract to Constitution 47
constitutions as agreements, the second regards them as frameworks for reaching
agreement.142
In the first approach a constitution is regarded as an agreement according
to which certain substantive goals and interests are to be achieved and served.
These goals and interests pre-date the formulation of the constitution. In the
corporate context one such goal might be the efficient use of the corporation’s
capital. Thus the purpose of a constitution is simply to permit the fulfilment of
those pre-determined goals and interests. It is easy to see how classical contract-
based perspectives fit within this approach.143
One particular example of this approach is found in the economic theory
of constitutions. 144 This strand of economics is concerned principally with the
situation of the rational individual who is faced with a choice about participating in
a collective decision. Constitutional economics argues that the individual’s course
of action will depend upon the rules which govern collective decisions in that
setting – for example, does the decision require a bare majority, a special majority,
or unanimity? The role of a constitution is to specify these rules, and the purpose of
studying constitutions is to decide what the optimal rules will be. Two concerns of
this theory are the need to agree upon rules which will reduce decision-making
costs within a collective, and the necessity of imposing constraints on collective
action in order to protect individual interests. Thus, while this theory takes
collective decision-making seriously, its perspective is that of the individual. The
constitution is regarded as a framework within which each individual consents to
specific rules governing collective decision-making. To put it another way,
constitutional economics is concerned with how decisions are constituted, not with
how the group that makes those decisions is constituted. It also eschews any
conception of concepts such as ‘the common good’ or ‘the public interest’.
In the second approach a constitution is regarded as a framework within
which the members of the constituted organisation can identify or formulate
preferences and make decisions. This approach is also based on pre-determined
ideas, but in this case they are not primarily substantive goals and interests. Instead,
they are questions of structure and procedure, or what some commentators have
142
This analysis is prompted by, but not necessarily consistent with, S L Elkin,
‘Constitutionalism: Old and New’ in S L Elkin and K E Soltan (eds), A New
Constitutionalism: Designing Political Institutions for a Good Society (1993) 20, and R
Bellamy and D Castiglione, ‘Constitutionalism and Democracy - Political Theory and
the American Constitution’ (1997) 27 British Journal of Political Science 595.
143
W J Stankiewicz, Aspects of Political Theory: Classical Concepts in an Age of
Relativism (1976) 12-14.
144
See, for example, J Buchanan and G Tullock, The Calculus of Consent: Logical
Foundations of Constitutional Democracy (1965), and G Brennan and J Buchanan, The
Reason of Rules: Constitutional Political Economy (1985). For an application to
corporate decision-making, see M Whincop, ‘The Role of the Shareholder in Corporate
Governance: A Theoretical Approach’ (2001) 25 Melbourne University Law Review
418.
48 The Constitutional Corporation
referred to as ‘matters of institutional design’.145 These questions have been central
to the liberal democratic approach that has influenced much of modern
constitutional thought in countries such as Australia.
Liberal democratic approaches to constitutionalism have been concerned
primarily with three issues.146 These approaches begin from the proposition that the
systems of direct or self-government are not feasible in modern large-scale
societies. At the same time, there is a concern to preserve, as much as is possible,
the idea that individuals can participate in the processes of societal decision-
making. Hence, what is required is a system of representative government by
which a smaller number of elected individuals can exercise state functions and
make decisions that are binding on the entire community. 147 Representative
government, however, is no guarantee against arbitrary rule; there is always the
possibility that those who are elected to govern may use their power to ignore the
mandate of representation and serve only the interests of the majority faction in
society (‘the tyranny of the majority’) or of a smaller elite. Thus, like constitutional
economics, the liberal democratic version of constitutional theory is concerned to
restrain the public exercise of power and on the creation of structures to maintain
those restraints in the interests of individual citizens. In liberal theory,
constitutionalism defines and tries to maintain a formal separation between ‘the
private’ and ‘the public’. One way to reduce the possibility of this abuse of power
is to break up concentrations of government power and to impose a system of
checks and balances on the exercise of that power. These goals are usually
summarised in the idea of the separation of powers.148 In particular, the power to
make rules (legislative power) should be separated from the power to enforce those
rules (executive power), and both should be independent of the power of the
judiciary in deciding disputes about the validity and application of the rules. This
separation of powers is reinforced by the recognition of constitutionally reinforced
rights and liberties. Where these safeguards fail there may then be calls for avenues
of political participation that go beyond mere electoral processes.
The liberal democratic concept of constitutionalism has a strong
association with legal thought. Within legal discourse the idea of constitutionalism
is allied with, and often treated as a synonym for, the rule of law. Whatever the
degree of linkage between these two ideas, the point is the same: constitutionalism
145
Bellamy and Castiglione, above n 142, 602. The importance of structure and process in
corporate law is emphasised by D Branson, ‘The Death of Contractarianism and the
Vindication of Structure and Authority in Corporate Governance and Corporate Law’ in
L E Mitchell (ed), Progressive Corporate Law (1995) 92.
146
Here I am rolling together the diverse theories of Hobbes, Locke, Madison, Bentham,
and J S Mill. Not all had something to say about the three points made in the text.
147
Of course, different theorists have different explanations for why and how this system
of representation should operate, and about the nature of the relationship between the
representatives and those whom they represent. These arguments include competing
attitudes about issues such as majority rule and the allocation of voting rights.
148
The origins of this idea are commonly attributed to Montesquieu’s The Spirit of Laws,
published in 1748.
From Contract to Constitution 49
is usually defined in terms of procedures and structures. As an example,
constitutionalism is said to refer to:
149
C Ten, ‘Constitutionalism and the Rule of Law’ in Goodin and Pettit, above n 134, 394.
150
G Schochet, ‘Introduction: Constitutionalism, Liberalism, and the Study of Politics’ in J
R Pennock and J W Chapman (eds), Nomos XX: Constitutionalism (1979) 8.
151
There is generally no accepted demarcation between liberal, deliberative, and
republican theories, and I am not concerned to locate this book within any particular
category. However, I do want to distinguish a constitutional approach from a
contractual approach and for that reason I lean more heavily on republican and
deliberative approaches.
152
See M Perry, ‘What is “the Constitution”? (and Other Fundamental Questions)’ in L
Alexander (ed), Constitutionalism: Philosophical Foundations (1998).
153
Schochet, above n 150, 11.
50 The Constitutional Corporation
applies not only to comparisons between corporations and states, but also between
different types of corporations. Because of this, different applications of political
theory, different conceptions of democratic organisation and process, and different
political standards (eg levels of voter participation) will be required for different
types of institution.
Constitutional theory thus has the capacity to direct our attention to what
it is that pulls individuals together in a group, rather than just what separates them.
It allows us to contemplate the relations between the group and the individuals who
comprise the group. In other words, a constitution has an integrating role. Sheldon
Wolin puts it this way:
154
Wolin, above n 70, 94.
155
Ibid 98.
156
See text accompanying n 68.
From Contract to Constitution 51
Conclusion
In this Chapter I have charted a route that takes us away from the idea of contract
as the sole organising framework for analysing corporations and takes us towards
the idea of a constitution. The argument is that there are qualitative differences
between contracts and constitutions. Of course, in the corporate context the
difference between contract and constitution is not always stark. It is true that
corporate constitutions have more ‘contract-like’ features than do the constitutions
of nation states. Nevertheless, important differences persist, even in the corporate
context. As I have argued in this Chapter, contracts are concerned with bringing
about an exchange between individual parties; constitutions, on the other hand, are
concerned with the co-ordination of relations between constituents.
To conclude, the idea of ‘constitutionalism’ which is employed here has
rhetorical, methodological, and normative uses. It is rhetorical in that I use it to
import political theory into the discussion of corporate governance. It is
methodological in that it presumes that ‘in order to discuss individuals one must
look first at their communities and their communal relationships’.157 It is normative
in that it provides a benchmark against which to evaluate the structures and
processes of particular governance systems. The next step is to apply these
constitutional ideas to the corporation, to develop the idea of corporate
constitutionalism. That is the task of the next Chapter.
157
S Avineri and A De-Shalit (eds), Communitarianism and Individualism (1992) 2. This
contrasts with methodological individualism, discussed earlier – above n 61.
This page intentionally left blank
Chapter 3
Corporate Constitutionalism
Introduction
1
See Chapter 2 at text accompanying n 94.
2
The ideas of voice and exit are taken from Albert O Hirschman, Exit, Voice, and
Loyalty: Responses to Decline in Firms, Organisations and States (1970).
54 The Constitutional Corporation
the option of voicing dissent should be ignored; the principle of ‘contestability’
that I outline later addresses this question.
Acknowledging these differences, the adaptation of constitutionalist
thought to the corporate context is nevertheless not as novel as it may first seem.
History and everyday usage suggest that corporate law has already accommodated
some constitutional language and ideas. Historically, as Harold Berman has shown,
it was early corporate law which played an important role in the development of
the constitutional structures of the church in Europe during the late eleventh and
twelfth centuries. Berman points out that:
it was the church as a corporate legal entity that conferred jurisdiction upon
individual ecclesiastical officers (pope, bishops, abbot), and it was the law of
corporations that determined the nature and limits of the jurisdiction thus
conferred.3
Corporate law is constitutional law; that is, its dominant function is to regulate the
manner in which the corporate institution is constituted, to define the relative
rights and duties of those participating in the institution, and to delimit the powers
of the institution vis-à-vis the external world.5
3
H Berman, Law and Revolution: The Formation of the Western Legal Tradition (1983)
215.
4
Corporations Act 2001 s 136 (providing, inter alia, that a company may adopt a
constitution in substitution for, or in addition to, the replaceable rules found in the Act).
5
M Eisenberg, ‘The Legal Roles of Shareholders and Management in Modern Corporate
Decisionmaking’ (1969) 57 California Law Review 1, 4.
6
See D Millon, ‘Theories of the Corporation’ (1990) Duke Law Journal 201, 201-202
for a discussion of external and internal perspectives. See also W Bratton, ‘Public
Values and Corporate Fiduciary Law’ (1992) 44 Rutgers Law Review 675, 690-691.
Corporate Constitutionalism 55
which the state has responsibilities and powers in relation to individual citizens,
groups, and organisations. This external aspect of corporate constitutionalism deals
with the relationship between the corporation, on the one hand, and the state and
society on the other.
This Chapter examines these two aspects in more detail. First, it looks at
the external aspect of corporate constitutionalism, explaining how the corporate
constitution contains private and public elements. This also involves an
examination of the form and content of the corporate constitution. The Chapter
then examines the internal aspect, looking at the role played by the corporate
constitution in constituting relations between members and directors in a
corporation. This leads to a summary discussion of the key constitutional ideas that
underpin these relations; these ideas are then elaborated in subsequent Chapters.
By the end of the present Chapter it will be obvious that the idea of
corporate constitutionalism draws on many strands. In particular, it has elements of
liberal constitutionalism (a regard for individual rights and interests),
communitarianism (the idea that, in addition to individual members, the group has
significance), and republicanism (stressing, in particular, the idea of governance
according to the common good).
A corporate constitutionalist framework entails a claim about the political and legal
status of the corporation and where the rules that govern corporate behaviour
should come from.7 This also has implications for how we understand the form of a
corporate constitution. Under this sub-heading I examine the claim about political
and legal status; under the next sub-heading I look at the form of the corporate
constitution.
As we saw in Chapter 2, arguments about corporate regulation tend to be
grouped on either side of a public/private dichotomy. Concession theory, for
example, points to the fact that corporations depend on a state grant of corporate
status, and argues that this justifies a system of public regulation of corporate
activity. In contrast, many versions of economic theory argue that corporations are
essentially private arrangements that should therefore be subject to minimal public
regulation. The limitations of these either/or approaches have already been noted.
What is needed in their place is recognition that corporations and corporate
regulation embody a complex interplay between the public regulation and the
private ordering of corporate affairs. As Bratton puts it, ‘[c]orporate law is not an
entirely ‘private’ proposition, even though it tends to lie on the private side of the
broader continuum of public and private law’.8 Corporations are organisations in
7
From a different angle, economic contractualists recognise the same point. Their
arguments about the contractual nature of intra-corporate relations are tied to wider
arguments about the legal status of companies as private economic actors.
8
Bratton, above n 6, 696.
56 The Constitutional Corporation
which private actors exercise powers that are both privately generated and state-
sanctioned. Richard Eells describes it this way:
Each individual has some subjective notion of the common good — a notion that
embodies public values shared with others in the community. Civic republicanism
requires that the government base its actions on these public values rather than on
the private desires that citizens bring into political discourse.10
Determining what the common good is on a given issue requires that government
and legislators make impartial judgements and not give undue weight to particular
private or factional interests. 11 Moreover, the state has a role in deterring or
constraining behaviour that is inimical to these public norms or values. Provided
that these state actions are not arbitrary, they need not be automatically regarded as
an affront to individual freedom. 12 This is not to say that state regulation is an
unqualified good — governments, laws, and the agencies that administer those
laws can be oppressive and unfair, and so we require legal processes and structures
that will constrain arbitrary and unwarranted state action. But the republican
message is that state regulation should, and can, be beneficial for society as a
whole.
9
R Eells, The Government of Corporations (1962) 67 (emphasis in original). Eells
highlights the permissive nature of this action because of the capacity which
corporations have to amend the constitution after incorporation.
10
M Seidenfeld, ‘A Civic Republican Justification for the Bureaucratic State’ (1992) 105
Harvard Law Review 1512, 1536-1537. See also C Sunstein, ‘Beyond the Republican
Revival’ (1988) 97 Yale Law Journal 1539, 1574.
11
M Sellers, Republican Legal Theory: The History, Constitution and Purposes of Law in
a Free State (2003) 32. Of course the process of determining the public good will
frequently be a complex and difficult process.
12
P Pettit, Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government (1997) 148-150.
Corporate Constitutionalism 57
A particular concern of the state should be the potential threats to liberty
that can arise when private organisations accumulate and exercise power. As was
noted in Chapter 1, the actions of corporations frequently have significant public
and private consequences. Corporations become powerful intermediate
organisations between citizens and the state. It is the role of government and the
courts to ‘play a role in limiting the power of such organisations without denying
the importance of their continued existence’.13 The republican message is that we
can think favourably about a system of government that gives the law and the state
a considerable range of responsibilities regarding corporate regulation, and that
operates to challenge unaccountable accumulations of power and authority.14
Implicit in this argument is the idea that corporations are not entirely
private associations. As John Parkinson describes it, they are also social
enterprises:
[C]ompanies are able to make choices which have important social consequences:
they make private decisions which have public results. It is possession of this kind
of power that gives rise to a distinct need for justification, and which forms the
basis for the claim that companies must be required to act in the public interest.15
Parkinson goes on to argue that the ‘practical significance [of this claim] is to hold
that the state is entitled to prescribe the terms on which corporate power may be
possessed and exercised’.16 To be clear: the state’s role as a corporate regulator
arises not from the state grant of corporate powers and attributes (as concession
theory argues), but from the potential for the accumulation of private power
created by those powers and attributes. As Parkinson explains, ‘it is not the legal
qualities of limited liability or separate personality in themselves that justify
intervention [by the state], but the concentration of power in private hands that has
come about partly as a result of their existence’.17
Joining this idea with the republican perspective on state regulation, we
can say that along with facilitating the realisation of private interests, a system of
corporate law should be concerned to enhance public values such as the avoidance
of oppressive or unfair behaviour, the use of objective, rather than purely
subjective, standards in the evaluation of corporate behaviour, and the importance
of accountability in the exercise of power within and by corporations. Values such
as these are already prominent in contemporary corporate law jurisprudence. For
example, a concern about oppressive or unfair conduct is enshrined in legislation
13
Sunstein, above n 10, 1574.
14
Pettit, above n 12, 150.
15
J Parkinson, Corporate Power and Responsibility: Issues in the Theory of Company
Law (1993) 10.
16
Ibid 23.
17
Ibid 30. This argument is therefore distinct from the concession theory, outlined in
Chapter 2, which argues that the state’s right to regulate companies is a necessary quid
pro quo for the grant of corporate status.
58 The Constitutional Corporation
such as s 232 of the Australian Corporations Act,18 as well as in judicial opinion (a
prominent example being the High Court of Australia’s decision in Gambotto v
WCP Ltd).19 There is a discernible trend towards the use of objective standards in
recent judicial pronouncements on the law of directors’ fiduciary duties, both in
general law and in statute. 20 The requirement of accountability in financial and
managerial decision-making is a mainstay of the regulatory system of modern
corporate law.21
Turning now from state regulation to private governance, we begin with
the claim made in Chapter 2 that corporations are polities in their own right. While
corporate constitutionalism entails a claim that the status of corporations as legal
actors is dependent on state action, this does not mean that the state is the sole
source of corporate governance rules. That is, the second aspect of this governance
and regulatory framework is supplied by the private ordering of the members and
directors.22 A corporation is not simply a microcosm of society at large; corporate
relationships are also structured by their own sets of values.23 Presumably this is
what Eells has in mind when, as noted before, he emphasises ‘the permissive action
of states’. 24 Eells highlights the permissive nature of this action because of the
capacity which members have to engage in private constitutional ordering by
amending terms of their constitution after incorporation. If corporations are
thought of as polities, then it becomes easy to see why the corporators should have
some space to determine and pursue their conception of the corporation’s best
interests.
It is important to be clear about the relationship between state regulation
and private ordering in this framework. Unlike the command-control model of
regulation, the state does not occupy centre-stage in this regulatory scheme; instead,
to use Clifford Shearing’s description, the state’s role is ‘decentred’.25 Nor should
18
The UK equivalent is s 459 Companies Act 1989 which refers to unfairly prejudicial
conduct. Of course, sections such as these have generated considerable debate about
their appropriate scope, meaning, and application.
19
(1995) 13 ACLC 342.
20
See eg Permanent Building Society (in liq) v Wheeler (1994) 12 ACLC 674 (proper
purpose to be objectively determined) and R v Byrnes; R v Hopwood (1995) 13 ACLC
1488 (the test of impropriety in what are now ss 182 and 183 of the Corporations Act is
objective).
21
Taken together these ideals have parallels with Philip Pettit’s idea of freedom as non-
domination ie freedom as the absence of arbitrary and unchecked interference with the
choices of another person — see above n 12. John Coffee also emphasises the role of
the courts in recognising mandatory minimum standards such as a duty of good faith
and protection against unconscionable provisions: J Coffee, ‘The Mandatory/Enabling
Balance in Corporate Law: An Essay on the Judicial Role’ (1989) Columbia Law
Review 1617, 1623.
22
C Shearing, ‘A Constitutive Concept of Regulation’ in P Grabosky and J Braithwaite
(eds), Business Regulation and Australia’s Future (1993) 73.
23
Bratton, above n 6, 695.
24
Above n 9.
25
Above n 22, 73.
Corporate Constitutionalism 59
state regulation be regarded as superior to, or having automatic precedence over,
private ordering. To quote Shearing again: ‘the state’s claim to the apex of a
regulatory hierarchy with private regulators performing no more than delegated
roles is unfounded’.26 Similar comments apply to private ordering: this framework
differs from contractarian theories in that private ordering is seen neither as a
substitute for state regulation, nor as an inherently preferable alternative. State
regulation and private ordering are both necessary but neither of them alone is
sufficient.
26
Ibid.
27
W F Murphy, ‘Constitutions, Constitutionalism, and Democracy’ in D Greenberg et al
(eds), Constitutionalism and Democracy: Transitions in the Contemporary World
(1993) 3.
28
See D Branson, ‘The Death of Contractarianism and the Vindication of Structure and
Authority in Corporate Governance and Corporate Law’ in L Mitchell (ed), Progressive
Corporate Law (1995) 99, arguing that modern corporate law has abandoned a concern
with detailed rules in favour of relying on structure and process.
60 The Constitutional Corporation
association).29 This usage is reflected in s 136 of the Australian Corporations Act,
which allows a company to adopt a constitution to govern the corporation’s
internal management in addition to, or as a substitute for, the ‘replaceable rules’
that are set out in the statute. This usage usually reflects a narrow view, in which
the term ‘constitution’ stands as a synonym for ‘agreement’ or ‘contract’.30 The
idea of a corporate constitution that I develop here is broader than this.
The limitations of this contractual usage of the term ‘constitution’ are
illustrated by the case of Wilcox v Kogarah Golf Club Ltd. 31 The articles of
association of an incorporated club gave the board of directors the power to make
rules and by-laws dealing with the rights and obligations of members, including
matters such as membership fees and the suspension or expulsion of members. A
dispute arose in which the plaintiff complained that his rights under the by-laws
had been breached. The question before Young J was whether the by-laws could be
enforced by a member, relying on the ‘statutory contract’ created by what is now s
140 of the Corporations Act.32 His Honour held that this was not possible; the by-
laws were merely a ‘a consensual compact’ between the members and it was a
feature of this compact that members should not be able to legally enforce its terms
except in limited situations. The by-laws were not enforceable as part of the
statutory contract created by the statute.33 Young J stated that:
29
In the UK, for example, see P Davies, Gower and Davies’ Principles of Modern
Company Law (7th ed, 2003) 55. In Australia the requirement for a memorandum and
articles of association was replaced by a single constitution in 1998.
30
See R Hardin, ‘Why a Constitution?’ in B Grofman and D Wittman (eds), The
Federalist Papers and the New Institutionalism (1989), arguing that constitutions are
categorically distinct from the ideas of agreement and contract.
31
(1996) 14 ACLC 421.
32
The idea of the statutory contract is explained in Chapter 2 n 13 and accompanying text.
33
Above n 31. The judgement does not explain what a ‘consensual compact’ is.
34
Ibid, 425.
35
Not least because in this case the Articles of Association made express reference to the
by-laws.
Corporate Constitutionalism 61
difficult to see why in cases such as this where the by-laws deal with fundamental
aspects of membership, those by-laws should not be treated as part of a constitution
which binds the members.
To be useful, a conception of the corporate constitution should be capable
of extending beyond the formal statutory document. As I noted earlier, a
constitution defines the place of members in an organisation — it constitutes them
as members. More specifically, one function of a corporate constitution is to define
who the members are and which interests of members are to count. We find similar
concerns in the long-established body of case law that puts the interests of non-
members, and the non-membership interests of members, outside the bounds of the
corporate constitution.36 This case law has drawn sharp lines between the statutory
constitutional documents and so-called special contracts. It has also shown that
defining what counts as a membership interest and what does not can sometimes be
difficult and will vary from one corporation to another.37 The argument here is that
the courts should not be too quick to remove from consideration documents that
play a key part in defining the members, their interests, or corporate decision-
making processes. As the Kogarah Golf Club Ltd case indicates, there can be other
sources that create or significantly affect the structure of authority relationships in
a corporation that are not dealt with explicitly by its formal constitution, or which
are dealt with only by implication. The formal internal rules alone, whilst
important, will not reveal everything about ‘the real ground rules for the scope and
nature of corporate powers’.38 Hence, a corporate constitution must be understood
to include, or must be read in the context of, sources outside these internal rules.
This wider construction could, in certain cases, include shareholder
agreements. Shareholder agreements are contractual arrangements between
individual shareholders that bind the parties on matters such as the exercise of
voting rights, buy-out of shares in the event of a dispute, and restrictions on the
transfer of shares. Such agreements are typically found in small proprietary
companies,39 and in joint-venture companies. They often (though not necessarily)
bind all shareholders in the company. Subject to a later comment, shareholder
agreements could be regarded as part of the corporate constitution where they
purport to affect or define the processes of decision-making in a corporation.40 A
36
Eley v Positive Government Security Life Assurance Company (1876) 1 Ex D 88;
Hickman v Kent or Romney Marsh Sheep-Breeders’ Association [1915] 1 Ch 881.
37
See the High Court of Australia’s decision in Bailey v NSW Medical Defence Union Ltd
(1995) 13 ACLC 1689 holding that a clause in the constitution of a mutual insurance
company that provided for the indemnification of members for liability arising from
their medical practices did not confer an entitlement on them as members; criticised in
M Whincop, ‘A Relational and Doctrinal Critique of Shareholders’ Special Contracts’
(1997) 19 Sydney Law Review 314.
38
Eells, above n 9, 59.
39
Thus falling outside the parameters of this book.
40
Davies suggests that for this reason the UK Companies Act 1985 s 35A(3)(b) includes
shareholder agreements in the meaning of the constitution of a company for the
purposes of sections dealing with outsiders and corporate contracts: above n 29, 66.
62 The Constitutional Corporation
good example of why can be seen in Hopkins v Foyster41 where a shareholders
agreement was made between the corporation, its major shareholder, and ‘each
other person who becomes a shareholder of the Company’. The agreement dealt
with the composition of the board of directors. Without deciding whether the
agreement was binding, the court nevertheless granted an interim injunction to
restrain the majority shareholders from exercising their voting rights at a general
meeting on the grounds that the contractual rights of minority shareholders under
the agreement might be infringed. Thus, in the court’s view, the agreement was of
sufficient weight to override the exercise of rights in the formal corporate
constitution.
A further source of constitutional rules is found in the general
corporations legislation. This includes, but extends beyond, those provisions that
apply to a corporation as default constitutional terms. 42 To the extent that
provisions in the legislation require, facilitate or constrain certain decision-making
structures and processes within corporations, then those sections can be read as a
part of a corporate constitution. This includes, for example, sections dealing with
the rights of members to requisition or convene a special general meeting; sections
that prescribe processes for the removal of directors; sections that prescribe
methods for modifying the formal constitution; and sections that provide statutory
rights of action for members (eg actions for oppressive conduct or derivative
actions). 43 Necessarily it also includes binding judicial interpretations of those
sections, as well as supplementary or complementary common law doctrines.44 In
this way a corporate constitution permits public values in corporate law (such as
accountability and fairness) to be brought to bear on the power and authority
structures of each corporation. In the same way, the ‘text’ of the corporate
constitution also includes the fiduciary duties and the duty of care and diligence
owed by directors to members.45 The corporate constitution need not be restricted
to the text of formal documents. As I noted in the conclusion to Chapter 2,
41
(2002) 20 ACLC 396.
42
In Australia, these are the ‘replaceable rules’ (found throughout the legislation) that
apply to a corporation by virtue of Corporations Act 2001 s 135 unless modified or
replaced. In the United Kingdom a similar result is achieved through the model articles
of association set out in Table A of the Companies (Tables A to F) Regulations 1985,
applied by virtue of Companies Act 1985 s 8(2).
43
In Australia these sections are: Corporations Act 2001 ss 249D-249F (members’ right
to call meetings); ss 203C-203E (removal of directors); s 136 (modification of
constitution); ss 232-235 (action for oppression); ss 236-242 (derivative action).
44
Stock exchange listing rules that impose similar requirements about company decisions
should also be added to this picture.
45
The same argument applies to the proper purpose and absence of oppression
requirements specified by the High Court in relation to alterations to the corporate
constitution that involves an expropriation of shares: Gambotto v WCP Ltd (1995) 13
ACLC 342.
Corporate Constitutionalism 63
corporate constitutions have contract-like features, one of which is that, in
appropriate circumstances, terms can be implied into the constitution.46
It is important to add that in order to properly understand the operation of
a corporate constitution (in the expanded sense just described), account must also
be taken of unwritten conventions, understandings and practices that lie outside the
constitution but which commonly affect and guide the conduct of corporate
directors, officers and members.47 Constitutional lawyers have long recognised this
point in relation to state constitutions. 48 Well-recognised and established
conventions and practices can assist in the interpretation and affect the application
of more formally expressed rules without being justiciable in themselves. The same
is true for corporate constitutions.
One example of an accepted corporate ‘convention’ or practice is found in
the appointment of directors to the boards of public corporations. Typically, a
corporate constitution provides that the power to appoint directors lies with the
members in general meeting. Even where the board has power to appoint a director
in order to fill a casual vacancy, the usual requirement is that this appointment
must be subsequently confirmed at a general meeting. All this suggests a level of
shareholder control over board appointments that, in practice, is not often found. It
is widely accepted that the power to make casual appointments, combined with the
operation of the proxy system of voting, frequently gives the incumbent directors
de facto control over the composition of the board;49 it is not common for a general
meeting to refuse to confirm a board appointment. This is reinforced by various
corporate codes of conduct which urge the creation of board nomination
committees and the need for careful succession planning by directors.50
There is a limit to the extent to which things such as shareholder
agreements or implied terms can be given constitutional significance. It should
46
H Ford, R Austin, I Ramsay, Ford’s Principles of Corporations Law (12th ed, 2005)
189, citing Stanham v National Trust of Australia (NSW) (1989) 15 ACLR 87; 7 ACLC
628.
47
Practices that are widely accepted in the corporate community are sometimes converted
into formal requirements. For example, it is common practice in Australian listed
corporations for the auditor to attend the AGM: S Bottomley, The Role of
Shareholders’ Meetings in Improving Corporate Governance (Research Report, Centre
for Commercial Law, Australian National University, 2003) 32. In 2004 this was made
a statutory obligation: s 250RA of the Corporations Act requires that auditors attend the
annual general meetings of listed public companies.
48
See, for example, S A de Smith and R Brazier, Constitutional and Administrative Law
(7th ed, 1994) 27-41.
49
See, for example, Re Marra Developments Ltd (1976) 1 ACLR 470.
50
See, for example, the UK’s Combined Code on Corporate Governance (2003) Principle
A.4.1 <http://www.fsa.gov.uk/pubs/ukla/lr_comcode2003.pdf> at 5 Jan 2006;
Australian Stock Exchange Corporate Governance Council, Principles of Good
Corporate Governance and Best Practice Recommendations (2003), Recommendation
2.4.
64 The Constitutional Corporation
always be kept in mind that ‘a careful prospective shareholder’51 may wish to know,
before acquiring shares in a corporation, what rights and potential liabilities she
may be exposed to, and how those rights and liabilities may be affected by the
corporation’s governance structures. Existing members ‘should not become bound
to do something unrelated by their membership of a company as a consequence of
a provision one would not expect to find in the constitution of the company in
question’.52
With this caution in mind, we arrive at a concept of a corporate
constitution that can have many dimensions. It can be partly written, with elements
that include the corporation’s own formal internal rules and relevant sections of the
legislation, and partly unwritten, including common law doctrines. This reflects the
idea of a multi-dimensional constitution that is well recognised in the wider
constitutionalist literature. With this in mind, Eells’ definition of the corporate
constitution is apt:
It will be apparent from this description that there are aspects of the corporate
constitution which cannot be determined or changed directly by the members of the
corporation. To the extent that corporations legislation requires certain procedures
or structures then its provisions prevail over those in the internal rules of a
corporation. Moreover, those parts of the corporate constitution that are found in
statute or in judicially created standards can be altered without the consent or
involvement of the members. This is a necessary feature of a corporate
constitutionalist model. The corporate constitution is more than an agreement or
contract between constituents of the corporation. It embodies an allocation of
powers and responsibilities between the state and the corporation and, within the
corporation, between the corporators. Constitutional debate in the corporate
context therefore takes place at two levels. One is societal. Since aspects of the
corporations legislation form part of the corporate constitution then it is important
that there be informed public debate about reforms to that legislation. The second
level is intra-corporate, involving, for example, debates about amendments to the
formal internal rules.
51
Bratton Seymour Service Co Ltd v Oxborough [1992] BCLC 693, 699 per Sir
Christopher Slade.
52
Bailey v NSW Medical Defence Union Ltd (1995) 13 ACLC 1698, 1718 (McHugh and
Gummow JJ).
53
Eells, above n 9, 85.
Corporate Constitutionalism 65
Balancing State and Corporate Inputs
Having established the idea that the corporate constitution is based on both state
and corporate inputs, the next task is to consider the ways in which each might
contribute to the overall constitutional framework. A range of possible approaches
might be considered. For example: should the state supply broad standards, leaving
it to the corporations to formulate more specific or detailed rules? Should the state
deal only with extra-corporate affairs or only with non-member concerns, leaving
internal member-related matters to be decided by each corporation? Should the
state mandate certain structures and processes and, if so, to what extent?
The model outlined in this Chapter suggests that at a minimum there
should be certain mandatory standards set by the state. I have suggested that these
would include the avoidance of oppressive or unfair conduct and the need for
financial and decision-making accountability. Enforcement of such standards
would, in extreme cases, justify judicial intervention in a corporation’s
constitutional affairs. In Australia an example of this power is found in s 233(1)(c)
of the Corporations Act which permits a court to make an order regulating the
conduct of a corporation’s affairs. 54 The corporate constitutionalist model also
suggests that there will be a mix of empowering rules, facilitative rules, and
guidelines. Corporators should be able to add their own constitutional rules and to
vary optional rules supplied by the state, provided that this is done by expressly
including provisions in the corporate constitution. The requirement of express
alterations is not just for efficiency reasons, as Coffee argues,55 but also for reasons
of transparency. Such a requirement allows all corporators to see and assess the
extent to which they might be compromising or advancing corporate values.
Beyond these broad observations, it is not feasible to prescribe a single,
neat constitutional blueprint for all corporations in advance. The nature of the
state’s role will depend on factors such as the size and type of corporation
(compare, for example, widely-held public companies, closely-held proprietary
companies, and government-owned companies), the extent to which particular
aspects of corporate law are statute-based or formed by common law, and whether
those laws are expressed as rules or standards. For some types of corporate law
issues, and for some types of companies, we may find that a standards-oriented
approach is more appropriate. With closely-held companies, for example, where
face-to-face negotiation is more likely, it might be thought preferable to rely on
54
In Hannes v MJH Pty Ltd (1992) 10 ACLC 400 the NSW Court of Appeal held that the
Court’s power to alter the articles of association is limited — a Court’s order should not
alter the balance of power in the company radically (at 418).
55
Coffee, above n 21, 1680-1681, argues that a requirement for express alteration of
default rules is efficient because it creates an incentive for careful and precise
formulation of the terms of corporate rules.
66 The Constitutional Corporation
standards rather than detailed prescription.56 It is clear the question of the state’s
regulatory role is complex, requiring attention (at minimum) to issues of
organisational theory, law, and political theory.
So much for what I have called the ‘external aspect’ of the corporate
constitution — the aspect that locates each corporation in its wider political,
economic and social context. This discussion forms the backdrop for the other part
of the picture which occupies the remainder of this book — the role of the
corporate constitution in internal corporate relations.
56
Coffee, ibid 1677, disagrees, suggesting that the close relations between corporators in
this type of company may impede effective negotiation, thereby justifying the need for
mandatory rules.
57
Above n 6, 690.
58
As a reminder, and as foreshadowed in Chapter 1, I am using the standard legal model
of the limited liability public company with share capital as the basis for my argument.
59
Greenhalgh v Arderne Cinemas Ltd [1951] Ch 286.
60
Corporations Act 2001 s 232(d).
Corporate Constitutionalism 67
corporate law recognises that an individual member may take action to protect their
personal rights against intrusions by the majority of members.61 A key function of a
corporate constitution is to establish structures and processes for mediating these
two dimensions of corporate life. In other words, corporate constitutionalism can
do for shareholders in corporations what a wider theory of constitutionalism does
for citizens in society at large.
The rest of this book is concerned principally with a more detailed
examination of how these two internal dimensions — the individual and the
collective — interact.62 This examination is conducted under three headings, each
of which refers to a key constitutional value or principle that ought to be reflected
in every corporate constitution.
61
See, for example, Residues Treatment & Trading Co Ltd v Southern Resources Ltd
(1988) 6 ACLC 1160, and Gambotto v WCP Ltd (1995) 13 ACLC 342.
62
The term ‘collective’ in this context does not imply that there will necessarily be
consensus on all issues. In many instances it will simply mean that there has been a
joint decision.
63
A Pettigrew, The Politics of Organisational Decision-Making (1973) 5, citing Chester
Barnard, The Functions of the Executive (1938) and Herbert Simon, Administrative
Behaviour (1957).
64
G Parry, ‘The Idea of Political Participation’ in G Parry (ed), Participation in Politics
(1972) 1, 6.
65
G Lowe, ‘Corporations as Objects of Regulation’ (1987) 5 Law in Context 35.
66
Pettigrew, above n 63, chapter 2.
68 The Constitutional Corporation
exercise of power and authority, they will involve strategies and tactics, they will
have implications for resource allocation and control, and they will be affected by
problems of hierarchy and specialization.
I have noted already that the law on corporate governance is concerned
primarily with the decisions that are made by directors in corporate board rooms
and, to a lesser extent, by shareholders in general meetings. 67 A large part of
modern corporate law is devoted to rules, doctrines and standards dealing with
different aspects of these decision-making forums. There are, for example, rules
governing the production of information that is relevant to prospective decisions
(eg annual financial reporting requirements); rules relating to the convening and
conduct of meetings; and rules prescribing standards for decision-making (eg the
duty of directors to exercise care and diligence and the business judgement rule).68
Implicit in these rules, doctrines and standards is the idea that
shareholders do have a role to play in corporate decision-making. It may be a role
that is exercised only intermittently, and it is a role that is heavily circumscribed by
legal principles, but nevertheless it has remained as one of the cornerstones of
corporate law in jurisdictions such as Australia and the United Kingdom. A
corporation is not presumed to be a directors’ autocracy. While it is true that some
corporations may in practice become autocracies — perhaps through the
appointment of a governing director, or as a result of being wholly-owned by one
shareholder — the point remains that this is not the model that is assumed by
corporate law or by the corporate governance literature. So this analysis proceeds
on the basis that corporations are decision-making institutions, and that
shareholders play an important, if underrated, role in those processes.
Why choose these three particular principles? Acknowledging that
different versions of constitutional theory will likely generate different principles,69
I suggest that a model of inclusive or responsive decision-making should seek to
emphasise three things: (1) the importance of access to information so that
decisions are properly informed; (2) the need to provide opportunities for
involvement in decision-making so that the information can be properly assessed
and debated by those who will be affected by the decision; and (3) the availability
of mechanisms to challenge and review decisions after they have been made.70 The
principles of accountability, deliberation and contestability represent the corporate
versions of this list. In a corporate setting the law limits shareholder access to
corporate information. This is because of the need to protect sensitive information:
67
Of course, in the case of a company that is insolvent (or is nearly insolvent) the focus
shifts to decisions made by creditors and by administrators or liquidators.
68
Eg Corporations Act 2001 s 180.
69
See R West, ‘Progressive and Conservative Constitutionalism’ (1990) 88 Michigan
Law Review 641.
70
In one of those serendipitous moments that characterises much research, the
formulation of this list was crystallised for me by a chance reading of Principle 10 of
the United Nations Conference on Environment and Development, Rio Declaration on
Environment and Development (1992) <http://www.un.org/documents/ga/conf151/
aconf15126-1annex1.htm> at 27 May 2004.
Corporate Constitutionalism 69
shareholders do not owe duties of loyalty to the corporation. Under Australian
corporate law, a member must obtain the consent of the directors or the general
meeting, or a court order, to inspect the books of their corporation.71 In the absence
of a general right to receive information, shareholders must be assured that those
who do have the information are using it responsibly and effectively. So, in the
corporate context, the principle of accountability substitutes for the idea of access
to information. Similarly, as I have already noted, legal and practical
considerations mean that there are few opportunities for participation in corporate
decision-making. As I hope to show, deliberation provides a useful standard by
which to assess involvement in corporate decisions. The third principle —
contestability — meets the requirement of having review mechanisms.
The ideas of accountability, deliberation and contestability draw our
attention to the structures and processes of corporate decision-making. These
principles should not necessarily be read as descriptions of what actually occurs
within every corporation. Nor will they necessarily be found stated expressly in
corporate constitutional texts. This is an evaluative exercise; these principles
provide benchmarks against which actual corporate practice and its legal regulation
can be assessed. At the same time, these principles are not new or foreign to
corporate law and corporate governance. Examples of each can be found in current
corporate law doctrine, although their importance is often under-emphasized and
under-estimated by corporate lawyers and corporate personnel.
Accountability
71
Corporations Act 2001 ss 247A and 247D. The capacity of the directors or the general
meeting to grant this authority requires that the corporation’s constitution contain a
clause to that effect (s 247D).
72
For example, J Coffee, ‘Market Failure and the Economic Case for a Mandatory
Disclosure System’ (1984) 70 Virginia Law Review 717; I Ramsay, ‘Models of
Corporate Regulation: The Mandatory/Enabling Debate’ in C Rickett and R Grantham
(eds), Corporate Personality in The 20th Century (1998).
73
For example, I Ramsay, Independence of Australian Company Auditors: Review of
Current Australian Requirements and Proposals for Reform, Department of Treasury,
Canberra (2001); Joint Standing Committee on Public Accounts and Audit, Parliament
of Australia, Review of Independent Auditing by Registered Company Auditors, Report
391 (2002).
70 The Constitutional Corporation
These familiar manifestations of the accountability question can disguise
the variety of dimensions and meanings that may be attached to the term
‘accountability’. To ‘be accountable’ can mean simply providing accurate
information about financial and operational performance at regular intervals or,
going one step further, it can mean providing an explanation of, or a justification
for, actions that have been taken. An even stronger sense of accountability requires
that persons be held responsible for their actions. Along with these different modes
of accountability, consideration must also be given to the timeframe for
accountability (for example, should it be ex ante or ex post, or both?), the different
arenas within which accountability is exercised (for example, board meetings, audit
committees, general meetings, and the marketplace), and the different instruments
of accountability (for example, deliberation at a general meeting, or independent
audits).74
A system of corporate accountability must include requirements that force
office-holders and decision-makers to give an account of their use of office and
power and to comply with relevant rules and standards. But it must also provide a
framework that can protect against the improper exercise of power in the first place,
with the aim of diffusing corporate decision-making power while at the same time
rendering it accountable through a plurality of checks and balances. I argue that
this can be achieved through a division and a separation of decision-making power
in corporations.
First, there is a formal division of decision-making authority between the
board of directors and the general meeting of members. Corporate decision-making
has a dual structure. Economic theory tells us that the purpose of this division
between decision and risk-bearing functions is to reduce the transaction and
opportunity costs for shareholders.75 Managerial theory tells us that the division
allows the appointment of directors with skill and expertise to run the corporation
for the benefit of the shareholders.76 This is all true, but there is a further reason for
this division of power. As I suggested earlier, the key function of a corporation is
to work for the common good of all of its members. Republican theory argues that
defining what the common good is on a given issue at a given time requires that
decision-makers should stand aside from their private interests and make impartial
judgements. It is possible that shareholders could do this — possible, but not
certain. So, we require a separate body of decision-makers, selected by the
shareholders and responsible to them, to make these judgements. Thus, it is the
fundamental duty of directors to make non-sectional decisions, to act for the
benefit of the shareholders as a whole. The directors must do this accountably, and
so an important function of the corporate constitution is to constitute these two
separate decision-making sites, to confer specific decision-making powers on each
74
The idea that there are different arenas and instruments of accountability is suggested
by John Uhr, Deliberative Democracy in Australia (1998) 158.
75
See, for example, E Fama and M Jensen, ‘Separation of Ownership and Control’ (1983)
26 Journal of Law and Economics 301.
76
See the discussion in W Bratton, ‘The “Nexus of Contracts” Corporation: A Critical
Appraisal’ (1989) 74 Cornell Law Review 407, 413-414.
Corporate Constitutionalism 71
of them, to regulate the exercise of those powers, and to guard against
encroachment by one upon the other. As will be seen in Chapter 4, the significance
of this dual structure is not diminished by the fact that decisions by members in
general meetings are much less frequent and concern a narrower range of topics
than those made by the board of directors. If for no other reason, this dual structure
is crucial to achieving accountability because of the power of the general meeting
over the election and dismissal of directors.
Secondly, there should be a separation of powers within the corporation.
Constitutional and public lawyers talk about the classical separation of legislative,
executive and judicial powers. In the corporate constitutional context I use the idea
of separation of powers in a broader and looser sense.77 Corporate decision-making
is not restricted to the formal division between the board and the general meeting,
so a separation argument is not limited to the formal aspects of decision-making
power, and it has a broad definition of the types of power with which we should be
concerned. Thus, as will be seen in Chapter 4, in a corporate context the separation
of powers (or, to be precise, the separations of powers) means paying attention to
the role of independent non-executive directors, independent chairpersons, external
and internal auditors, institutional shareholders and other related elements of
corporate organisations. There is nothing new in highlighting the role of these
corporate players — indeed this is the bread and butter of the corporate governance
literature. However there is something new, for corporate lawyers at least, about
conceptualising these issues in terms of a separation of powers.
Accountability by itself does not supply a sufficient rationale for the
division and separation of decision-making power in the corporation. It is only one
part of the corporate constitutionalist picture. For one thing, if accountability was
all that was required, the need to hold actual meetings might be called into question.
Furthermore, flaws in one aspect of the accountability framework (such as poor
audit practices) must be capable of being dealt with or remedied by other means,
such as processes of deliberation at company meetings, or through contestation by
members.
Deliberation
The principle of deliberation seeks to ensure that, as far as possible, the processes
of corporate decision-making are open and genuine, that they are based on
consideration of all relevant arguments (as opposed to a mere aggregation of votes),
and that they are capable of producing decisions that represent a collective
judgement about the issue at hand. Corporate decision-making will be legitimate
insofar as it is a consequence of deliberative processes that meet these criteria.
I will postpone a detailed explanation of this definition of deliberation
until Chapter 5, but some brief points can be made here (all of which are elaborated
in the later Chapter). First, in assessing the quality of corporate decision-making,
77
This approach follows the argument in J Braithwaite, ‘On Speaking Softly and Carrying
Big Sticks: Neglected Dimensions of a Republican Separation of Powers’ (1997) 47
University of Toronto Law Journal 305.
72 The Constitutional Corporation
the principle of deliberation directs our attention to how a decision is made, not
simply to the content of the decision itself or whether it is supported by the
requisite number of votes. Deliberation reminds us that the process of reaching a
decision is as important as the decision itself. In particular, it tells us to take
meetings seriously. Secondly, the idea of deliberation does not mean that every
decision must be unanimous. Deliberation is consistent with majority voting but —
importantly — it is inconsistent with majority domination of decision-making
processes. Thirdly, in a corporate context, deliberative processes do not necessarily
require full and direct participation by all persons who are affected by the decision,
nor do they presume any particular mode of participation. Board meetings and
general meetings are the main deliberative forums of a corporation, but they are not
the only forums. In Chapter 5 we will see that the nature of share ownership in the
modern public listed corporation requires a wider application of the deliberative
principle to ensure the quality of decision-making processes. As I will argue, this
might include the use of internet chat-sites, the business media, and mechanisms to
represent particular interests at general meetings.
Corporate law already embodies the principle of deliberative decision-
making in a number of ways, even though this is often overlooked or not realised.
As I have noted already, corporations legislation typically contains detailed
procedural requirements for the calling and conduct of meetings, including notice
requirements 78 as well as voting, quorum, proxy and minutes requirements. 79 A
clear instance of the deliberative principle is found in s 250S of the Corporations
Act 2001, which requires the chair of a public company annual general meeting to
allow a reasonable opportunity for the members as a whole to ask questions about
or make comments on the management of the company. All of these requirements
are premised on the idea that the general meeting is a forum in which issues will be
raised and arguments will be heard, following which decisions will be made.
Further evidence of the deliberative principle can be found in case law concerning
the duties of care and diligence owed by company directors. Since the 1990s a
succession of decisions in the Australian courts 80 has stressed the obligation of
each director in a company to participate actively in the board’s decision-making
processes.
Despite these legal resonances, there is still room for debate about the
importance of deliberation in the corporate decision-making context. In Chapter 5 I
chart a course between two possible extremes in this debate. At one extreme,
critics of deliberation might argue that the size and diversity of most public
company share registers means that for practical purposes general meetings can be
little more than ritualised affairs, and that deliberative decision-making in such a
context is an impossible ideal. Moreover, it might be argued that an emphasis on
78
In Australia see Corporations Act 2001 ss 249H – L.
79
For general meetings, see s 249T [quorum]; ss 250E – M [voting]; ss 249X – 250D
[proxies]; s 251A – B [minutes]. For directors’ meetings, see s 248F [quorum]; s. 248G
[voting].
80
For example, Statewide Tobacco Services Ltd v Morley (1990) 8 ACLC 827; Daniels v
Anderson (1995) 13 ACLC 614.
Corporate Constitutionalism 73
deliberation at meetings has the potential to impede timely, efficient and effective
decision-making. At the other extreme, some advocates of deliberation might argue
that we cannot choose to be only a little deliberative. The argument might be made
that proper deliberation requires the full and equal participation of all shareholders
(at least) on all significant corporate decisions. The task in a corporate setting, as I
argue in Chapter 5, is to avoid each of these extremes. We should not promote
efficient decision-making at the expense of deliberation, but neither should we
promote deliberation at the expense of effective decision-making.
The final point to emphasise about deliberation — for the moment — is
that deliberative processes by themselves are not enough. For example, a board that
meets its deliberative obligations must also meet the requirement to be accountable
(as discussed above) and there must be possibilities for contestability.
Contestability
81
I have adapted this idea from Philip Pettit’s work, principally his book on
Republicanism, above n 12, together with more recent work, cited in Chapter 6 of this
book.
82
Although my focus is on contestation by members, in some instances a director may
want to contest a decision made by directors and members. In Talbot v NRMA Ltd
(2000) 18 ACLC 600 the Supreme Court of New South Wales stated that before taking
such a step, a director must believe that the litigation will be in the company’s best
interests and that he or she would be in breach of his or her own duties by not taking the
action.
74 The Constitutional Corporation
problem with the ex post argument is that it slides easily into the belief that the
ends will always justify the means and that a beneficial outcome is good,
regardless of how it has been achieved. If, instead, a corporate law system has clear
mechanisms for contestability then there is scope for ex ante confidence. Members
can assume that directors make their decisions against the threat of challenge
where, for example, those decisions are contaminated by improper self-interest. A
contestatory system directs attention to the procedures by which decisions are
made as much as to the substance of those decisions.
Another response to the hypothetical posed above might be to say that the
decisions would be legitimated by the ideas of consent and majority-rule.
Members, it might be argued, are presumed to have consented to the distribution of
decision-making power in their company. This consent is implied from the act of
voluntarily purchasing shares and thereby accepting the terms of the corporate
contract. A key term of that contract is the idea of majority decision-making. The
problem with this argument is that when these two ideas — implied consent and
majority rule — are brought together, they can create and disguise problems such
as lack of accountability, oppressive or self-serving behaviour by directors or
majority shareholders, and a slide from majority decision-making to majority
domination of decision-making processes. Contestability works differently as a
legitimating mechanism, because every decision is made against the factual
possibility that it might be contested by the members and thereby be subject to
review.
Corporate law is already familiar with mechanisms of contestability.
These include the action for oppressive or unfair conduct (in Australia found in
Corporations Act 2001 Part 2F.1), the statutory derivative action (found in Part
2F.1A of the Act), actions to protect class rights (Part 2F.2), and the injunction
remedy (s 1324). In Chapter 6 I will examine in more detail the value of some of
these actions as contestability mechanisms.
Three further, interrelated, points can be noted briefly about the principle
of contestability. First, it does not require that there actually be contestation of each
and every corporate decision or action. What is important is that the possibility of
contestation should be realised, and be realistic.83 The second point is related to
this: contestability does not mean condoning any and all claims by dissenting or
disgruntled members. Contestability is not the same thing as giving each member a
potential power of veto over each decision. Being in the minority on an issue does
not of itself activate the principle of contestability. Similarly, contestability
mechanisms must be able to weed out frivolous or vexatious challenges. The
criterion for determining what interests should be counted as relevant or non-
frivolous will necessarily be couched in general terms, such as ‘the interests of the
members as a whole’, but at their base they are — to adapt Pettit’s description —
the interests that those who are part of a system of government within a corporation
may reasonably expect that system to track.84 Thirdly, contestability relies on the
83
Pettit, above n 12, 185.
84
P Pettit, ‘Republican Freedom and Contestatory Democratization’ in I Shapiro and C
Hacker-Cordón (eds) Democracy’s Value (1999) 163, 176.
Corporate Constitutionalism 75
capacity and willingness of members to challenge decisions that do not meet this
criterion, rather than selling their shares and leaving the corporation. That is,
contestability promotes the exercise of ‘voice’ over the option of ‘exit’.85 Again,
the point is not to rule out exit as an appropriate response in a given situation;
instead, the aim is to resuscitate the use of voice as a response.
Contestability will work effectively if there are adequate mechanisms for
accountability, ensuring the provision of information and explanations, and
ensuring, by a separation of powers, that the powers of members are not eroded.
Contestability can also be enhanced, and its possible overuse curbed, by proper
deliberative procedures.
Conclusion
85
Hirschman, above n 2.
86
Pettit suggests, however, that contestability underlies other ‘democratic desiderata’,
including deliberation, and the division and separation of powers – see above n 84, 185.
76 The Constitutional Corporation
corporate entities operate everyday. As I noted in Chapter 1, the purpose of a
corporate constitutional framework is to reconceptualise existing rules and
practices, rather than to argue for a radical reformation of the corporate form.
Finally, as this Chapter has made clear, corporate constitutionalism is
concerned primarily with issues of structure and process, rather than with
substantive legal doctrines. In the next three Chapters I examine in closer detail the
implications of each of the three principles of corporate constitutionalism for the
structures and processes of corporate governance. Chapter 4 deals with
accountability, emphasising structural questions, particularly the importance of
divisions between the board and the general meeting, and separations of power
within the corporate structure (eg the need for independent directors and external
auditors). In Chapter 5 the analysis of deliberation focuses on the processes and
conduct of company general meetings and board meetings. Chapter 6 argues for
the importance of ensuring mechanisms of contestability by analysing the role of
the statutory derivative action and the action for oppression or unfairness.
Chapter 4
Corporate Accountability
Introduction
Shareholders and directors are familiar with the idea of accountability. A large part
of our system of corporate law rules and doctrines is concerned with mechanisms
for achieving financial and fiduciary accountability. When those rules fail, each
new wave of corporate collapses seems to herald a re-examination of these
corporate accountability systems. Of course, the corporate world does not have a
monopoly on the concept of accountability. Accountability seems to be regarded as
an unqualified good by anyone who has an interest in processes of governance,
whether private or public. But the ubiquity of the concept, and the often casual way
in which it is invoked, suggests that it might also be problematical, too vague to be
useful in assessing or controlling corporate behaviour. As one commentator has
warned:
[accountability] has been viewed as both an end and a means; it has been defined
in terms of procedures, results, disclosure of information, recourse, and
compliance with regulations; and it is often indistinguishable from such concepts
as evaluation, efficiency, effectiveness, control and responsibility.1
1
R Kramer, Voluntary Agencies in the Welfare State (1981) at 290. For a more recent
critique see R Mulgan, ‘“Accountability”: An Ever-Expanding Concept?’ (2000) 78
Public Administration 555.
78 The Constitutional Corporation
There are several questions that must be answered when we insist that corporate
behaviour should be accountable. What conduct will satisfy the requirement for
accountable behaviour in (or by) a corporation? Who should be accountable? To
whom should they be accountable? When should accountability be provided?
Addressing each of these questions reveals even more dimensions of the concept.
There are different criteria for deciding whether a particular corporation,
or group of decision-makers within a corporation, is being accountable. A
corporation may be said to be accountable if it provides accurate information about
its activities when it is required to do so. This type of accountability has been
described as ‘accounting for’ or ‘accountability as verification’,2 and it is the focus
of the financial reporting and disclosure provisions that are a familiar feature in
modern corporate law statutes. To paraphrase John Uhr, accountability through
disclosure has the aim of allowing members and others to compare what
corporations and their managers say they are doing with investigations of what
corporations and their managers are actually doing. 3 This is summed up in
Brandeis’ well-known aphorism that ‘[s]unlight is … the best of disinfectants;
electric light the most efficient policeman’.4
A stronger form of accountability requires that in addition to providing
information, the corporation or corporate decision-maker should be able to explain
or justify its actions. This is accountability in the sense of ‘accounting to’, or
‘explanatory accountability’.5 An opportunity for this form of accountability can be
found in those provisions of the Australian Corporations Act that require company
members to be given a reasonable opportunity to question the directors and the
auditor about company management or the audit process.6 We can make a further
distinction between weak and strong forms of explanatory accountability,
depending on whether the explanation is primarily reactive and defensive
(providing explanations only when asked and only about what has been asked) or
proactive and responsive (offering information and anticipating the concerns of the
accountability audience). 7 Corporate laws may influence the options here. For
example, under the rules governing the continuous disclosure of information, a
2
J Uhr, ‘Redesigning accountability: From muddles to maps’ (1993) 65 Australian
Quarterly 1.
3
J Uhr, ‘Accountability, Scrutiny and Oversight’ (Background paper prepared for The
Commonwealth Secretariat Canberra Workshop, May 2001) 4.
4
L Brandeis, Other People’s Money and How the Bankers Use It (first published 1914,
1995 ed) 89.
5
Uhr, above n 3.
6
See ss 250PA, 250S and 250T.
7
Uhr, above n 3, 8.
Corporate Accountability 79
8
Corporations Act 2001 s 674, ASX Listing Rule 3.1
9
Mulgan argues that being called to account is the ‘core sense’ of accountability and that
we should limit our use of the term to this – see above, n 1.
10
An extreme example is the ‘vice-president responsible for going to jail’ described in J
Braithwaite, Corporate Crime in the Pharmaceutical Industry (1984) 308.
11
M Bovens, The Quest for Responsibility – Accountability and Citizenship in Complex
Organisations (1998)
12
For example, stock-exchanges.
13
An Australian example is the Australian Banking Industry Ombudsman.
80 The Constitutional Corporation
Clearly, the idea of accountability is capable of being used and applied in different
ways. I do not intend to enter the debate about the ‘proper’ meaning or usage of the
concept. 16 Instead, this brief survey is a reminder that in thinking about
accountability we ought to be concerned with accountability processes and
structures as much as we are with the content or subject matter of the
accountability obligations. Much of the debate about corporate accountability has
been concerned with the latter — for example, whether the focus of the law should
be confined to financial and fiduciary reporting, or whether the obligations should
be widened to the ‘triple bottom line’ of financial, environmental and social
concerns. It is only relatively recently that the corporate governance literature has
begun to concentrate on process and structure issues (for example, questions of
auditor independence, the composition of corporate boards, or the need for board
14
J Goldring and I Thynne, Accountability and Control – Government Officials and the
Exercise of Power (1987) 226.
15
Uhr, above n 3, 14-15.
16
See, eg, Mulgan, above n 1.
Corporate Accountability 81
Dual Decision-making
As I noted in an earlier Chapter, the corporate law systems of Australia, the United
Kingdom and similar jurisdictions recognise only two formal decision-making sites
in a corporation while it is solvent — the board of directors and meetings of
17
See, for example, M J C Vile, Constitutionalism and the Separation of Powers (1967)
7.
18
Mulgan, above n 1, 563.
82 The Constitutional Corporation
[I]f powers of management are vested in the directors, they and they alone can
exercise those powers. The only way in which the general body of shareholders
can control the exercise of the powers vested ... in the directors is by altering their
[constitution], or ... by refusing to re-elect the directors of whose actions they
disapprove. They cannot themselves usurp the powers which by the [corporation’s
19
In Australia, for example, see Corporations Act 2001 Pt 2G.1 directors’ meetings, and
Pt 2G.2 meetings of members of companies. See the discussion in Chapter 2 above, n 5
to 12 and accompanying text.
20
In some jurisdictions (eg Canada: Canada Business Corporations Act, RSC 1985, s
102; United States: the Revised Model Business Corporations Act s 8.01 (2002);
Delaware General Corporation Law s 141) this division of power is prescribed by
statute. In Australia it is the default position that may be varied by a corporation (see
the ‘replaceable rule’ in s 198A Corporations Act 2001).
21
Hogg v Cramphorn Ltd [1967] Ch 254; Bamford v Bamford [1968] 2 All ER 655;
Winthrop Investments Ltd v Winns Ltd [1975] 2 NSWLR 666.
22
[1906] 2 Ch 34.
23
There is authority that the general meeting has a reserve power to act when the board is
unable or unwilling to exercise its powers. However the scope of this reserve power is
unclear and has been interpreted narrowly in Australian courts — see Massey v Wales
(2003) 21 ACLC 1978. Courts are similarly cautious about the unanimous consent rule
whereby a unanimous decision of all of the members is treated as a decision of the
corporation regardless of any division of powers in the corporate constitution — HAJ
Ford, RP Austin, IM Ramsay, Ford’s Principles of Corporations Law (12th ed, 2005)
301-305.
Corporate Accountability 83
constitution is] vested in the directors any more than the directors can usurp the
powers vested ... in the general body of shareholders.24
In Residues Treatment & Trading Co Ltd v Southern Resources Ltd this freedom
from interference in voting rights through the improper actions of directors was
expressed as a personal right of each shareholder. King CJ in the Supreme Court of
South Australia argued that:
A member’s voting rights and the rights of participation which they provide in the
decision-making of the company are a fundamental attribute of membership and
are rights which the member should be able to protect by legal action against
improper diminution.26
24
[1935] 2 KB 113, 134 (references to the articles of association have been replaced with
references to the corporate constitution).
25
[1967] Ch 254 at 268; see also Howard Smith Ltd v Ampol Petroleum Ltd [1974] AC
821.
26
(1988) 6 ACLC 1160 at 1165.
27
What follows is prompted by Bruce Ackerman’s theory of ‘dualist democracy’ - B
Ackerman, ‘Constitutional Politics/Constitutional Law’ (1989) 99 Yale Law Journal
453 [hereafter, ‘Constitutional Politics’], and ‘The Storrs Lectures: Discovering the
Constitution’ (1984) 93 Yale Law Journal 1013 [hereafter, ‘Storrs Lectures’]. This is a
selective adaptation, not an application, of Ackerman’s ideas. As far as I can tell,
Ackerman did not intend his argument to be used in the corporate context.
84 The Constitutional Corporation
significance for the daily operation of the corporation, but they cannot alter its
fundamental structures.
In this dual system, decisions made by the members in a general meeting
are not everyday events. In fact, in most corporations they are quite rare, occurring,
at best, on an annual basis28 and only under special conditions. For example, there
are notice requirements governing the provision of information, and rules requiring
time to consider this information. There are voting rules and requirements that
stipulate — in some cases — the need for special majorities. Nevertheless, despite
their infrequency, these decisions are fundamental to the affairs of the corporation.
And despite the routine way in which these decisions are often made, general
meetings have a formal significance that is not possessed by directors’ meetings. A
general meeting is a gathering of members and directors; it is a meeting of the
corporation. In accountability terms, this division of power gives the members of
the corporation the right and the authority to call the directors to account and to
demand answers. As Mulgan emphasises, ‘those calling for an account are
asserting rights of superior authority over those who are accountable, including the
rights to demand answers and to impose sanctions’.29
Decision-making by directors occurs much more frequently. As noted
above, the directors exercise general managerial power. The directors can then
delegate aspects of this power to senior managers in the corporation. Indeed, if we
group decisions of the board together with those made by managers exercising
power delegated by the directors, we see that these decisions are part of the daily
life of the company. Borrowing Bruce Ackerman’s phrase, this can be regarded as
the ‘normal politics’ for corporate decision-making. 30 That is, normal corporate
decision-making is, with the authority of the members, largely the business of
directors and managers. 31 However, despite their closer connection to daily
corporate operations, board meetings are not usually described as meetings of the
company. Directors’ meetings are not constrained by as many procedural
requirements as meetings of shareholders. The corporate constitution may specify
rules about notice, procedures at board meetings and voting, but ‘[o]rdinarily, less
formality is required for a directors’ meeting than a meeting of members of a
corporation’.32
Two points should be emphasised before proceeding further. The first
concerns the status of the corporate constitution in this model. On one view, the
28
In Australia only public companies are required to hold an annual general meeting
(Corporations Act s 250N). No similar requirement is imposed on proprietary (ie
private) companies.
29
Above n 1, 555.
30
Ackerman, ‘Constitutional Politics’, above n 27, 461.
31
This sentence paraphrases F Schauer, ‘Deliberating about Deliberation’ (1992) 90
Michigan Law Review 1187, 1188.
32
Wilson v Manna Hill Mining Company Pty Ltd [2004] FCA 912 [15]. One restraint is
found in s 195 Corporations Act 2001 which restricts a director of a public company
who has a material personal interest in a matter being considered by the board from
participating in the board’s consideration of and voting on the matter.
Corporate Accountability 85
[T]he shareholders have by their express contract mutually stipulated that their
common affairs should be managed by certain directors to be appointed by the
shareholders in the manner described by other articles, such directors being liable
to be removed only by special resolution. If you once get a stipulation of that kind
in a contract made between the parties, what right is there to interfere with the
contract, apart, of course, from any misconduct on the part of the directors?33
Just as it is established that directors, within their management powers, may take
decisions against the wishes of the majority of shareholders, and indeed that the
majority of shareholders cannot control them in the exercise of these powers while
they remain in office … , so it must be unconstitutional for directors to use their
fiduciary powers over the shares in the company purely for the purpose of
destroying an existing majority, or creating a new majority which did not
previously exist. To do so is to interfere with that element of the company’s
constitution which is separate from and set against their powers.35
In this approach, the constitution sits apart from the day-to-day concerns and
interests of the corporate personnel. It constrains conduct by imposing structures
and processes that are not susceptible to easy variation.
The second point to emphasise is that this characterisation of the different
corporate decision-making sites and processes does not depend on the substantive
content of the particular decisions that are made. The dual decision-making model
acknowledges that in many corporations there are matters that most members will
not understand, will not want to become involved in, or will not have the resources
to pursue, even though their interests are ultimately affected. Decisions to enter
into complex funding agreements, or to hire or fire senior managerial staff are
examples. These are matters that are usually left to the directors and/or managers to
decide. Describing the general meeting as the site for fundamental decision-making
does not deny the obvious fact that directors make many significant decisions
33
[1906] 2 Ch 34, 44.
34
See Chapter 3 n 27 to n 53 and accompanying text.
35
[1974] AC 821 at 837. Ross Grantham makes a similar point, but attributes the Court’s
approach to an organic model of the company — see ‘The Unanimous Consent Rule in
Company Law’ (1993) 52 Cambridge Law Journal 245, 268-269.
86 The Constitutional Corporation
which affect the ordinary operations of the corporation, or that general meetings
often make seemingly mundane decisions. The importance of the dual model is
demonstrated in debates about the matters that should be decided by the members.
For example, should members be able to pass advisory (or non-binding) resolutions
on matters of corporate management that are outside the power of the general
meeting? This is possible in some countries. 36 However, a suggestion that such
resolutions be permitted in Australian corporate law was dismissed in 2000, on the
grounds that ‘the boundaries … between the role of directors and that of the
shareholders in general meeting should not become confused’.37 The key difference
between board decisions and general meeting decisions is that the board is
answerable to the shareholders for its exercise of decision-making power.
Although, as we have seen, shareholders cannot dictate to the board or seek to be
part of the board’s decision-making processes, this does not diminish the
constitutional significance of the board’s accountability to the shareholders.
Notwithstanding the rule of member non-intervention, directors cannot assume that
by being elected to office they have a mandate to do as they wish.38 Shareholders in
general meeting, by contrast, are not prima facie required to explain their decisions
(subject to what I say in Chapter 6 about contestability). In this sense their
decisions are constitutionally superior to those of the directors.
There are two important implications of this dual decision-making system.
First, the system operates as a signalling device to corporate insiders and outsiders
about which issues, and therefore which interests and values, are regarded as
fundamental to the corporation. 39 Those issues that are allocated to the general
meeting may be presumed to be those which are regarded as having fundamental
importance for the corporation. To the extent that a corporation is able to tailor-
make its own constitutional provisions, then different corporations can send
different signals. The second implication takes us to the issue of structural
accountability: the dual process, with the attendant constitutional constraints,
provides a structure that is intended to secure designated rights or interests from
easy or expedient interference by controlling interests in a corporation. Thus
decisions are made by directors on the basis of ultimate accountability to the
general meeting (particularly via the power of shareholders to remove directors, or
to ratify breaches of duty), while those made at the general meeting are open to
scrutiny and deliberation by all members.
36
For example, the Canada Business Corporations Act, RSC 1985, s 137, and the New
Zealand Companies Act 1993 s 109.
37
Companies and Securities Advisory Committee, Shareholder Participation in the
Modern Listed Public Company, Final Report (2000) [3.55]. The Corporations Act
2001 has since been amended to require that the adoption of the remuneration report at
a listed company’s AGM be decided by an advisory resolution (s 250R(2) and (3)).
38
Richard Buxbaum describes the shareholders as the ‘the upstream neighbour’ of the
board: ‘Corporate Governance and Corporate Monitoring: The Whys and Hows’ (1996)
6 Australian Journal of Corporate Law 309, 313.
39
Ackerman, ‘Storrs Lectures’, above n 27, 1039.
Corporate Accountability 87
There are three broad objections that might be raised about relying on this dual
model. One is that it emphasises the role of directors and members at the expense
of other important constituencies. Secondly, it might be said that the model gives
too much significance to the role of the board at the expense of the members. The
third objection reverses the second, arguing that the dual model gives undue
prominence to the role of the members. I consider each of these arguments in turn.
The first objection was discussed in Chapter 1 of this book. Stakeholder
and communitarian theorists (amongst others) have objected that the dual model
defines the set of relevant corporate interests too narrowly. As was noted in
Chapter 1, there is an argument that, given their general passivity, members have
the least right to insist that their interests be recognised against the interests of
other stakeholders. 40 Stakeholder theorists argue that existing corporate legal
structures should be reformed so as to cater for a wider range of non-shareholder
constituencies, principally employees, but also creditors, customers, suppliers, and
local communities. As I pointed out in Chapter 1, it is not the purpose of a
corporate constitutional framework to rule out these concerns. Instead, the aim is to
develop a model which permits those concerns to be heard and expressed within
the still-dominant assumptions of shareholder centrism. As I hope will become
apparent, particularly in Chapter 5, once the constitutional parameters of the
shareholder-centred model have been evaluated, corporate constitutionalism could
well be used as the basis for considering the claims of non-shareholder interests in
the corporate governance process.
The second objection reminds us of the contract-based agency argument
that was discussed in Chapter 2. It argues that the dual model fractures the agency
relationship between managers and owners of the corporation. Agency theory
regards all decision-making processes within a company as having the same weight
and significance. According to this theory, while the shareholders could potentially
make all decisions, it is more rational and efficient for them to appoint others to
make the decisions for them. For an agency theorist, the only issue of interest that
follows from this is how to monitor and control the managers in exercising that
power. Thus, rather than a division of power, the agency model looks more to a
rational division of labour:
The corporate form of firm organization has obvious advantages for shareholders
(suppliers of capital) and managers. Shareholders can participate in the gains from
entrepreneurial ventures even though they lack management skills; managers can
pursue profitable business opportunities even though they lack large personal
wealth. Both parties benefit from this division of labour.41
40
See Chapter 1 n 20 to n 23 and accompanying text.
41
D Fischel, ‘The Corporate Governance Movement’ (1982) 35 Vanderbilt Law Review
1259, 1262 (emphasis added).
88 The Constitutional Corporation
In the final analysis, the principal/agent analysis treats any decisions made by the
agent as if they were decisions of the principal. In contrast, the dual model
highlights the point that director and member decisions are the product of
categorically different processes.
The third objection to the dual decision-making model takes essentially
the opposite stance to the agency theorists, arguing that the model gives undue
recognition to the members when what really counts is decision-making by
directors and managers. This objection is based on the idea that if the directors are
properly elected and are given full managerial power, then they have plenary
decision-making authority in the corporation. Of course members retain formal
decision-making power over certain matters specified in the corporate constitution,
including the power to elect and remove directors. But this power, if it has to be
exercised at all, should be exercised with circumspection. The result is a
governance system based on the idea of ‘director primacy’ rather than ‘shareholder
primacy’.42 I will deal with this argument in a little more detail here, because it has
not been canvassed previously in this book.
This objection finds expression in both economic and political theory. In
the economic literature it is found in the managerialist conception of the
corporation. Prompted by the classic study of Berle and Means in 1932,43 which
highlighted the separation between ownership and control functions in large
corporations, ‘[t]he managerialist picture puts corporate management at the
strategic center of the large firm’.44 Managers obtain their power because the wide
dispersal of shareholdings effectively cedes control to them.45
There is a similar argument in political theory, described as democratic or
competitive elitism. 46 With its origins in the works of writers such as Joseph
Schumpeter and Max Weber, it offers a procedural, rather than a substantive theory
of democracy. As Schumpeter defines it, ‘the democratic method is that
institutional arrangement for arriving at political decisions in which individuals
acquire the power to decide by means of a competitive struggle for the people’s
vote’. 47 Schumpeter’s reference to an ‘institutional arrangement’ indicates that
democracy is defined by reference to the procedure by which voters choose their
political leaders. That procedure involves an electoral system in which there is a
42
L Stout, ‘The Shareholder as Ulysses: Some Empirical Evidence On Why Investors in
Public Corporations Tolerate Board Governance’ (2003) 152 University of
Pennsylvania Law Review 667, 669, referring to S Bainbridge, ‘Director Primacy: The
Means and Ends of Corporate Governance’ (2003) 97 Northwestern University Law
Review 547.
43
Adolph A Berle and Gardiner C Means, The Modern Corporation and Private Property
(1932).
44
William Bratton, ‘The “Nexus of Contracts” Corporation: A Critical Appraisal’ (1989)
74 Cornell Law Review 407, 413.
45
See J Parkinson, Corporate Power and Responsibility (1993) 56-72.
46
The label ‘democratic elitism’ is taken from Philip Green (ed), Democracy (1993),
while David Held, Models of Democracy (1987) uses the term ‘competitive elitism’.
47
J Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy (1987 ed) 269.
Corporate Accountability 89
‘competitive struggle’ for leadership.48 The only function of the electorate in this
process is to exercise its free vote to ‘produce a government’,49 (this function also
includes the power to evict that government). This is the limit of the electorate’s
control over the leadership. Using Schumpeter’s description again:
Voters do not decide issues. ... In all normal cases the initiative lies with the
candidate who makes a bid for the office of member of parliament and such local
leadership as that may imply. Voters confine themselves to accepting this bid in
preference to others or refusing to accept it.50
It follows from this that, having elected their leaders, voters must refrain from
acting as ‘back seat drivers’, 51 interfering in the processes of government.
Schumpeter urges that voters ‘must respect the division of labour between
themselves and the politicians they elect’.52 Weber makes the same point in more
blunt terms:
In a democracy the people choose a leader in whom they trust. Then the chosen
leader says, “Now shut up and obey me.” People and party are no longer free to
interfere in his business.53
This functional division between the elected and the electors is reinforced
by two interrelated developments. One is the professionalisation of leadership roles
in modern society; the other is the separation of leadership from administration,
and the increased specialisation in the latter set of tasks. On the latter development,
both Weber and Schumpeter argue for the necessity of a well-trained bureaucracy.
According to Weber it is ‘the capitalist market economy which demands that
official business of the administration be discharged precisely, unambiguously,
continuously, and with as much speed as possible’. 54 Moreover, ‘[b]ureaucracy
inevitably accompanies modern mass democracy in contrast to the democratic self-
government of small homogeneous units. This results from the characteristic
principle of bureaucracy: the abstract regularity of the execution of authority...’.55
So, to summarise, modern political systems are said to be characterised by a three-
48
Ibid 271.
49
Ibid 272.
50
Ibid 282.
51
Held, above n 46, 175.
52
Above n 47, 295. Schumpeter goes so far as to say that even ‘less formal attempts at
restricting the freedom of action of members of parliament — the practice of
bombarding them with letters and telegrams for instance — ought to come under the
same ban’.
53
Cited in H Gerth and C Wright Mills (eds and trans), From Max Weber: Essays in
Sociology (1947) 42. In his essay ‘Politics as a Vocation’, Weber defined politics as
‘any kind of independent leadership in action’, ibid, 77 (emphasis in original).
54
M Weber, ‘Bureaucracy’ in ibid 215.
55
Ibid 224.
90 The Constitutional Corporation
Separations of Powers
56
This is not surprising. Weber observed that ‘things in a private economic enterprise are
quite similar [to public politics]: the real “sovereign”, the assembled shareholders, is
just as little influential in the business management as is a “people” ruled by expert
officials.’ He went on to note similarities in the dependent relationships of directors
towards company managers and that between elected leaders and administrators in
modern state bureaucracies: ‘Politics as a Vocation’ in Gerth and Mills, above n 53, 91.
57
For examples of more detailed critiques see Green, above n 46, Part V.
58
R Michels, ‘Political Parties’ in Green, above n 46, 69. Weber was critical of Michels’
‘iron law of oligarchy’ — see Held, above n 46, 156.
Corporate Accountability 91
They are also not the most frequently activated decision-making forums: general
meetings usually occur only once a year, and board meetings are usually only
monthly events. Thus we need to be able to control the decision-making processes
that occur outside these formal meetings. We need to recognise the possibility of
many separations of decision-making power in the corporation. This is the second
feature of structural accountability.
The idea of a separation of power amongst different decision-makers
within a governance structure has long been recognised as a key element of
effective accountability. Liberal legal and political theory has demonstrated a deep-
seated mistrust of concentrations of decision-making power within political
communities. Liberal theory requires that these powers should be exercised non-
arbitrarily, and that this should be done in ways that are open and accountable. The
idea of a separation of powers therefore seeks to achieve the dual aim of the
diffusion and the accountability of decision-making power. The exercise of this
power is to be broken up into different branches so that no single person or agency
has full control over those powers, and so that there are checks and balances on
each power-exercising agency or person.
Historically, the separation of powers ideal has developed with reference
to the exercise of public power. The concerns of the key writers in this history,
Locke, Montesquieu, and Madison, were directed at controlling the potential for
state power to impinge unduly on the lives of individual citizens.59 Lawyers — and
constitutional lawyers in particular — have elevated this idea into a formal doctrine
that involves a ‘holy trinity’ of formally distinct public powers: legislative,
executive, and judicial. 60 Modern Australian constitutional writing tends to
concede that the first two of these powers have merged in practice, due mainly to
the operations of the Cabinet system of government. Hence, in the constitutional
law literature, discussion about the doctrine of separation of powers tends to be
concerned primarily with the separation of the judicial power from legislative and
executive power.61
As I noted in Chapter 1, significant sites of social, economic and political
power are now to be found in the private sector, especially in corporations. The
broad idea of a separation of powers should therefore be applied not just to public
systems of government but also to corporate systems. 62 In doing this we must
59
J Locke, Two Treatises of Government (1960 ed); Montesquieu, The Spirit of the Laws
(A Cohler, B Miller and H Stone trans and ed, 1989) especially. Book XI, Pt 6;
Alexander Hamilton, James Madison, and John Jay, The Federalist Papers (1961 ed),
especially Nos 47-51.
60
The theological metaphor is noted (but dismissed) by Vile, above n 17, 15.
61
Sir Anthony Mason has pointed to the artificiality of this three-way division of powers,
because of ‘the impossibility of defining each of the three powers in a way that reveals
them as mutually exclusive concepts’. Sir Anthony Mason, ‘A New Perspective on
Separation of Powers’ (Reshaping Australian Institutions Australian National
University Public Lecture, 25 July 1996) 5.
62
On the importance of separations of private power and their role in corporations, see J
Braithwaite, ‘On Speaking Softly and Carrying Big Sticks: Neglected Dimensions of a
92 The Constitutional Corporation
list does indicate is that separations of powers are not limited to hierarchical top-
down monitoring, and they may involve overlapping skills and competencies (for
example, independent and executive directors). It is important not to be too
categorical when designing and instituting divisions and separations of powers
within a corporation. It is conceivable, for example, that at some times in some
corporations directors might take some hand in the day-to-day management of the
company. It is equally conceivable that, in the process of implementing board
policies, managers may create further ‘subsidiary’ policies. This overlap is
particularly apparent in the case of executive appointments to the board. So, the
aim is not to insist on predetermined separations of power in each and every
corporation. Instead, the aim, in each case, is to ensure a plurality of separations
that is appropriate to the particular corporation.
The purpose of insisting on these separations of powers is to achieve an
institutionalised system of checks and balances which makes it more likely that
abuses of power by one part of the corporate governance system can be identified,
restrained, corrected, and understood by other parts. 67 This involves a delicate
balance. We do not want the different sites of power or decision-making to be so
independent or autonomous that they are beyond effective control or scrutiny by
other sites. As Vile notes, the idea of checks and balances means that each branch
of power must exercise some control over the others by having a limited role in the
exercise of the other’s functions.68 That is, we should allow that some decision-
makers may have control over others by their partial participation in the others’
functions. At the same time, it is important that each site has sufficient
independence and autonomy to do its job, to act as an ‘outside’ monitor of other
relevant sites, with the result that that no site is dominated by another or abdicates
its responsibilities to another.
Another concern is that a governance system based on multiple
separations of powers might lead to institutionalised feelings of distrust. It could be
argued that a system in which all are being watched and all are watching, and in
which there is an over-emphasis on information reporting and monitoring, is likely
to breed distrust and thus be counter-productive. This state of affairs is not,
however, an automatic outcome of the separations argument: ‘[t]rust and control
are not polar opposites: they have to co-exist’. 69 Indeed, a system of multiple
separations can provide the reassurance necessary for relationships of trust. As
Phillip Pettit and John Braithwaite have each argued, a careful institutionalisation
of mechanisms of restraint, of challenge, and of accountability is actually
necessary to the fostering of trust within — and of — institutions.70 The purpose of
having separations of power is not the division and pigeon-holing of expertise and
67
Braithwaite, above n 62, 341-342.
68
Vile, above n 17, 18-19.
69
Philip Stiles and Bernard Taylor, Boards at Work: How Directors View Their Roles and
Responsibilities (2002) 80.
70
Philip Pettit, ‘Republican Theory and Political Trust’, John Braithwaite,
‘Institutionalising Distrust, Enculturating Trust’, both in V Braithwaite and M Levi
(eds), Trust and Governance (1998) 295 and 343 respectively.
94 The Constitutional Corporation
The need for separations in the allocation and exercise of board power has been a
prominent concern in the corporate governance literature. A major Australian case
serves as a convenient way of organising the discussion here. The case involved a
claim for negligence by AWA Ltd against its auditors and cross-claim by the
auditors. The facts centred on the actions of the corporation’s chief executive
officer/managing director, the non-executive directors, and the auditors. The case
was decided at first-instance in 1992 (AWA Ltd v Daniels) 71 and then in a
subsequent decision by the New South Wales Court of Appeal in 1995 (Daniels v
Anderson).72
At first instance Rogers J referred to a three-way separation of monitoring
power from management power. The first separation is between the board of
directors and the corporation’s senior managers.73 According to Rogers J:
A Board’s functions, apart from statutory ones, are said to be usually four fold:-
1. to set goals for the corporation
2. to appoint the corporation’s chief executive
3. to oversee the plans of managers for the acquisition and organisation of
financial and human resources toward attainment of the corporation’s goals,
and
4. to review, at reasonable intervals, the corporation’s progress towards
attaining its goals.74
Justice Rogers went on to note that in a large public company the dictates of
‘business necessity’ mean that the board cannot be involved in day-to-day
management of the corporation’s business. Directors must look to others to manage
the corporation, which means that those managers are required, amongst other
things to:
• carry out the day to day control of the corporation’s business affairs
71
(1992) 10 ACLC 933.
72
(1995) 13 ACLC 614.
73
(1992) 10 ACLC 933, 1013.
74
Ibid (references omitted).
Corporate Accountability 95
• establish proper internal controls, management information systems and
accounting records
• implement the policies and strategies adopted by the Board
• prepare proposals and submission[s] for consideration by the Board
• prepare a budget.75
75
Ibid 1014.
76
Daniels v Anderson (1995) 13 ACLC 614, 663 and 664 (quoting Pollock J in Frances v
United Jersey Bank 432 A 2d 814 (1981).
77
Ibid 662.
78
Statewide Tobacco Services Ltd v Morley (1990) 8 ACLC 827, 832, cited in ibid 661.
79
Corporations Act 2001 s 190.
80
Corporations Act 2001 s 189.
81
For a more critical assessment of the division of function between board and
management than that in the AWA case, see M Eisenberg, ‘Legal Models of
Management Structure in the Modern Corporation: Officers, Directors, and
Accountants’ (1975) 63 California Law Review 375.
82
AWA Ltd v Daniels (1992) 10 ACLC 933, 1014. Rogers J went on to distinguish
between the standard of care owed by non-executive directors and that owed by
96 The Constitutional Corporation
suggests that this separation has several dimensions. For example, the basic
distinction between executive and non-executive directors (NEDs) is not always
useful. In many corporations NEDs are unable to act effectively as a checking
mechanism because of past or present affiliations with management. Thus a further
distinction is drawn between affiliated and non-affiliated (or independent) NEDs,
where affiliation is determined by factors such as whether the NED is a substantial
shareholder, a recent employee, a professional adviser, or a significant supplier or
customer, to or of the corporation. 83 Internationally, corporate governance
guidelines and codes of conduct issued by stock exchanges, directors’ associations,
institutional investor organisations and other organisations have consistently
recommended that boards be comprised of a significant proportion or a majority of
independent non-executive directors. 84 The same guidelines also emphasise the
importance of establishing board sub-committees to deal with potential conflict of
interest issues such as executive and directors’ remuneration, the nomination and
selection of board positions, and the auditing of the corporation’s financial and risk
position. The usual recommendation is that those committees should be comprised
of independent non-executive directors. For example, in the wake of the Enron and
WorldCom collapses in 2001-2002, the New York Stock Exchange and NASDAQ
issued new listing rules that require listed companies to have a majority of
independent directors on their boards, and to have only independent directors on
their audit, remuneration, and selection committees. 85 The requirement for audit
committee independence in US listed companies has subsequently been reinforced
by s 303(3) of the Sarbanes-Oxley Act of 2002. Similar requirements are imposed
in Australia by the ASX Listing Rules. 86 As I argued earlier, the aim of this
separation of independent directors is not to pigeon-hole their expertise but to
focus attention on the relationship between those directors and the executive. In the
United Kingdom, the Higgs Review described this as creating ‘the potential for a
virtuous dynamic in which executive perceptions of the value of non-executive
directors’ experience and contribution encourage greater executive openness that,
in turn, allows for greater non-executive engagement’.87
executive directors. The Court of Appeal rejected this distinction — see Daniels v
Anderson (1995) 13 ACLC 614 at 662.
83
This list is taken from Australian Stock Exchange Corporate Governance Council,
Principles of Good Corporate Governance and Best Practice Recommendations
(March 2003) 20.
84
For example, ibid recommendation 2.1; Financial Services Authority (UK), The
Combined Code on Corporate Governance (July 2003) principle A.3.2; OECD,
Principles of Corporate Governance (2004) principle VI.E.1.
85
See now NYSE, Listed Company Manual (2003) ss 303A.01, 303a.07(b); NASDAQ,
Marketplace Rules (April 2004) rules 4350(c) and (d).
86
Australian Stock Exchange, Listing Rules (2004) rules 1.1 and 12.7, referring to its
Principles of Good Corporate Governance and Best Practice Recommendations, above
n 83, principle 4.
87
Derek Higgs, United Kingdom Department of Trade and Industry, Review of the Role
and Effectiveness of Non-Executive Directors (January 2003) 33.
Corporate Accountability 97
The AWA case noted the importance of a third separation, between the
role of the board chairperson and the executive directors (particularly the managing
director). As described by Rogers J, ‘[t]he Chairman is responsible to a greater
extent than any other director for the performance of the board as a whole and each
member of it’.90 In ASIC v Rich Austin J accepted that the chair’s role includes
leading the board in ‘the monitoring of management, the assessment of the
company’s financial position and performance and the detection and the
assessment of any material adverse developments’. 91 A study of Australian
directors’ attitudes towards corporate governance, conducted between 1990-91,
found widespread disapproval of executive chairpersons. As one director put it:
It is good to have distinct persons in this area. The chief executive is concerned
with the day-to-day running of the business and its improvement while the
88
See G Stapledon and J Lawrence, ‘Board Composition and Structure in the Top 100’
(1996) 12 Company Director 80; L Lin, ‘The Effectiveness of Outside Directors as a
Corporate Governance Mechanism: Theories and Evidence’ (1996) 90 Northwestern
University Law Review 898.
89
Helen Bird, ‘The Rise and Fall of the Independent Director’ (1995) 5 Australian
Journal of Corporate Law 235, 253.
90
AWA Ltd v Daniels (1992) 10 ACLC 933, 1015.
91
(2003) 21 ACLC 450, 464.
98 The Constitutional Corporation
chairmanship has to ensure honesty and look after the interests of shareholders.
The chairman is a moderating wise old head.92
The need for the board chairperson to be appointed from the ranks of the
independent board appointees has become an article of faith in the corporate
governance literature in Australia and the United Kingdom since the 1980s.93 As
argued in the Higgs Review in the United Kingdom, ‘[t]he separation of roles can
contribute to the greater achievement of the chief executive as well as being
important in creating the conditions for effective performance by the non-executive
directors’.94
Another aspect of separations of power in and around the board, not
relevant to the facts of the AWA case, concerns the role of the company secretary.95
The company secretary is now recognised judicially as the corporation’s chief
administrative officer.96 As described by the Institute of Chartered Secretaries and
Administrators in the United Kingdom, the company secretary has ‘a central role in
the governance and administration’ of the affairs of the corporation, and is in ‘a
powerful position of influence’. 97 For the purposes of defining legal duties and
liabilities the company secretary is classified in Australia and the United Kingdom
as an officer of the company. 98 Nevertheless, the secretary’s role in providing
‘independent impartial guidance and advice’ to the board in general and to the
independent directors and the board chairperson in particular,99 especially where
this involves briefing directors on the work of senior executive officers, suggests
that this is another point at which the separations argument should be considered.
That is, the secretary ought to stand separately from the senior executives and from
the board.100
92
R Tomasic and S Bottomley, Directing the Top 500: Corporate Governance in
Australian Public Companies (1993) 56.
93
The situation is different in the United States, where the CEO is usually also the chair
of the board. There are some calls to change this: see, eg, California Public Employees’
Retirement System, Corporate Governance Core Principles and Guidelines (1998)
<http://www.calpers-governance.org/principles/domestic/us/page01.asp> at 21 July
2004.
94
Above n 87, 24.
95
In Australia a public company must have at least one secretary: Corporations Act 2001
s 204A(2).
96
Club Flotilla (Pacific Palms) Ltd v Isherwood (1987) 12 ACLR 387.
97
Institute of Chartered Secretaries and Administrators (United Kingdom), Duties of a
Company Secretary Best Practice Guide (1998) 2.
98
Corporations Act 2001 (Aust) s 9; Companies Act 1985 (UK) s 744.
99
Higgs, above n 87, 51.
100
It is common in smaller public companies for the finance director to be appointed as the
company secretary: ibid 51.
Corporate Accountability 99
A further separation of power, which was a prominent aspect of the AWA litigation
but has been of greater significance since then, concerns the role of a corporation’s
external auditor. Corporations legislation requires public corporations to have their
financial affairs audited annually.101 The basic statutory requirement of an auditor
is to provide an independent and expert assessment as to whether the corporation’s
financial accounts comply with the relevant accounting and auditing standards and
give a true and fair view of the corporation’s financial situation.102 This statutory
framework is restricted to audits within the regular annual and half-yearly financial
timetable, and it does not involve any assessment of ‘the prudence of business
decisions made by management’.103
Crucially, as a matter of law the appointment of a corporation’s auditor is
a decision of the shareholders at an annual general meeting of the corporation.104
Furthermore, an auditor may only be removed from office by a resolution passed at
a general meeting, initiated by the directors or members of the corporation.105 It is
true that as a matter of practice the shareholders’ decision on auditor appointment
or removal will usually be determined by the recommendation of the board (acting
on the recommendation of the audit committee). It also appears, in Australia at
least, that the removal power is not often used. 106 Nevertheless, the strict legal
position continues to emphasise the auditor’s role as a key component in an
accountability process in which the members monitor the performance of the
directors and managers.
There is an obvious link between the ideas of accountability and audit,
that is, between providing information about the use of resources, and having that
information checked and verified by an independent expert. But we have seen that
the idea of accountability can go beyond simple processes of verification or
‘accounting for’; it can also be understood as a key part of democratic processes.
Just like accountability, the idea of auditing has many dimensions. Michael Power
points out that:
101
See, eg, Corporations Act 2001 (Aust) s 301 (mandatory audit for all corporations
except small proprietary companies); Companies Act 1985 (UK) s 235 (mandatory
audit report for all companies).
102
See, eg, Corporations Act 2001 (Aust) ss 307-308; Companies Act 1985 (UK) s 235
(true and fair view).
103
Ford, Austin, and Ramsay, above n 23, 589.
104
The directors may appoint the company’s initial auditor, who then holds office until the
first AGM (s 327(2)).
105
In Australia, see Corporations Act 2001 s 329.
106
A study of annual general meetings in 271 Australian listed companies found that the
removal of the auditor had not been an agenda item in any of the meetings held between
2001 and 2003: S Bottomley, The Role of Shareholders’ Meetings in Improving
Corporate Governance (Research Report, Centre for Commercial Law, Australian
National University, 2003) 36.
100 The Constitutional Corporation
distinctions can be formulated between ex post and ex ante auditing, between
verification and review, between the audit of transaction regularity and value for
money, between private and public sector audits, between financial and non-
financial audits, between auditing, evaluation, assessment and inspection, between
big and small audits, between auditing and other forms of assurance services,
between financial and environmental audits, between internal and external
audits.107
And just as accountability can have a democratic role, a similar role can be claimed
for audits — indeed, Power refers (albeit critically) to ‘the democratizing potential
of audit’. 108 That is, an audit report can provide the basis for questioning and
further investigation, for moving from ‘accountability as verification’ to
‘explanatory accountability’ and even to ‘accountability as responsibility’. In this
way, audits can form an important part of a framework of separations of power in
corporations. At the same time it is important not to over-emphasise or to be
idealistic about the ‘accountability value’ of the audit process. Although the
connection between audit and accountability may seem obvious, the two ideas may
also come into conflict. Power notes how the intention behind many audit reports is
to end scrutiny and inquiry, to bring the processes of accountability to a conclusion.
The irony, as he puts it, is that ‘the fact of being audited deters public curiosity and
inquiry. … Audit is in this respect a substitute for democracy rather than its aid’.109
Thus, when audit becomes tied to a narrow conception of accountability it can
impede broader conceptions of accountability.
One impediment to the capacity of audits to provide accountability within
a separations of power framework is the perception — and in many instances the
reality — that auditors are not independent of the corporations that they are
auditing. These are longstanding concerns. For example, in the 1970 case of
Pacific Acceptance Corporation Ltd v Forsyth, Moffitt J, in the NSW Supreme
Court, noted that while the statutory auditor is appointed by the shareholders, most
frequently it is the corporation’s managers who determine that appointment.
Moffitt J went on to observe that for the auditor:
there must often be a real and practical conflict ... between his duty to the
shareholders and his interest not to take action which may prejudice his
reappointment or his relations with those with whom he works.110
There were strong criticisms of audit practices and auditor independence after the
corporate crises of the 1980s.111 And, of course, the prominent corporate collapses
107
M Power, The Audit Society: Rituals of Verification (1999), 5-6.
108
Ibid 123.
109
Ibid 127.
110
(1970) 92 WN(NSW) 29, 131.
111
In addition to the AWA case, above n 71, see Commonwealth of Australia, Royal
Commission of Inquiry into the Activities of the Nugan Hand Group, Final Report -
Volume 2 (1985); National Companies and Securities Commission, Special
Investigation into Affairs of the Trustees Executors & Agency Company Ltd and
Corporate Accountability 101
that occurred between 2001 and 2002112 prompted renewed investigation into the
lack of auditor independence.113
In Australia the Federal Government-commissioned Ramsay Report on
auditor independence noted that independence is ‘an imprecise and ambiguous
concept’ but concluded, nevertheless, that ‘the terms “independent” and “auditor”
can no longer be separated - independence appears to be endogenous to
auditing’.114 The two key professional accounting bodies in Australia define audit
independence in terms of ‘freedom from bias, personal interest, prior commitment
to an interest, or susceptibility to undue influence or pressure’. 115 The Ramsay
Report noted several factors that may erode the independence, or the apparent
independence, of an audit116 including: the provision to the corporation by the audit
firm of other non-audit services (thereby building a broader commercial
relationship between firm and corporation); the employment of former auditors by
the corporation or appointment to the board (creating the possibility that continuing
auditors will then be dealing with ex-colleagues); and lengthy terms of
appointment (increasing the possibility that over time the auditor will become more
tolerant of the corporation’s practices). The Ramsay Report contributed to a
significant rewriting of the audit provisions in the Australian Corporations Act
2001.117
Different reasons are advanced for requiring auditors to be independent.
One rationale is that an independent audit adds value to the corporation’s financial
report:
Independent audits are also said to have a role in enhancing the integrity of
financial markets by aiding in the detection of fraud or malpractice and promoting
investor confidence. It is also argued that independent audits reduce the
information asymmetry that exists between corporate managers and shareholders,
improving the investment decisions made by the latter.119 Auditors thus serve as
‘reputational intermediaries’, assisting the efficient operation of the market for
corporate information,120 and so their perceived independence promotes confidence
in the audit process.
The argument advanced here is that alongside these claimed benefits,
auditor independence is a necessary component in an accountability framework
that is based on the idea of separations of powers. Having said that, it is also the
case that no matter how well-founded the concern about lack of auditor
independence is, a separations of power framework should try to ensure that
auditors do not become so independent that they are beyond effective scrutiny of
their work by others in the separations of power framework. There have been many
solutions offered to the problem of balancing auditor independence and
accountability. These include:
118
Statement of Auditing Practice AUP 32, quoted in Ramsay Report, above n 113, 4.09.
119
Ramsay Report, above n 113, 8.22.
120
See A Corbett, ‘The Rationale for the Recovery of Economic Loss in Negligence and
the Problem of Auditors Liability’ (1994) 19 Melbourne University Law Review 814,
850, referring to R Gilson and R Kraakman ‘The Mechanisms of Market Efficiency’
(1984) 70 Virginia Law Review 549.
121
D Kitney and R Buffini, ‘Directors target audit overhaul’ The Australian Financial
Review, 4 March 2002, 1. In the United States the Sarbanes-Oxley Act of 2002 (Pub. L.
No. 107-204, 116 Stat. 745 (2002)) prohibits auditors from providing certain non-audit
services contemporaneously with the audit (s 201).
122
s 300(11B).
Corporate Accountability 103
individual who plays a significant role123 in the audit of a listed corporation for
five successive years cannot play a significant role in the audit of that
corporation for another two years;124
• imposing a cooling-off period for ex-auditors who wish to join a former client
as a director or officer;125
• ensuring that audit committees are properly constituted and have clear
responsibilities for oversight of the audit function and, in particular, for
recommending to the board the appointment, remuneration or removal of the
external auditor;126
• requiring, or encouraging, the attendance of the auditor at the annual general
meeting, 127 and giving members a reasonable opportunity to ask questions
about the audit, the accounting policies used in preparation of the audit, and
the independence of the auditor.128
The Corporations Act 2001 in Australia also imposes general and specific
independence requirements for auditors. The general requirement focuses on the
need to avoid ‘conflict of interest situations’129 in which an auditor is not capable of
exercising objective and impartial judgement in conducting the audit, or a
reasonable person would conclude that this is the case. This involves looking at the
relationship between the auditor and the corporation, its current or former directors
and managers. 130 One implication of this general requirement is that an auditor
must have in place a quality control system that is reasonably capable of making
them aware that a conflict of interest situation exists. The specific independence
requirement focuses on particular relationships that constitute a breach of the
auditor’s independence when they are engaged in audit activity. The Act defines
nineteen such relationships. Some are role relationships (eg where the auditor is an
officer or employee of the audited corporation); others are property relationships
123
A person ‘plays a significant role’ if they are appointed and act as the auditor or
prepare the audit report for the company, or if they are the lead or review auditor for a
firm or company that is appointed as auditor (s 9).
124
Corporations Act 2001 s 324DA. If the auditor is a firm or a corporation, and the lead
or review auditor has played a significant role in audits for the past five successive
years, then the firm or corporation may continue to act as auditor, provided that it uses
another person in the lead or review capacity (ss 324DC and DD). See also Sarbanes-
Oxley Act of 2002 (Pub. L. No. 107-204, 116 Stat. 745 (2002)) s 203 (audit rotation
period of five years).
125
In Australia, the cooling-off period is two years – Corporations Act 2001 ss 324CI and
CJ.
126
Ramsay Report, above n 113, 6.59 and 6.105; Australian Stock Exchange, above n 83,
recommendation 4.4; United Kingdom, Financial Services Authority, The Combined
Code on Corporate Governance (July 2003) principle C.3.6.
127
See, for example, Corporations Act 2001 s 250RA (mandatory auditor attendance at
AGM of listed company), and s 249V (right of auditor to attend AGM).
128
Corporations Act 2001 s 250T.
129
ss 324CA-CC.
130
s 324CD.
104 The Constitutional Corporation
(eg where the auditor has an asset that is an investment in the audited corporation);
the remainder are financial relationships (eg where the auditor owes money to, or is
owed money by, the audited corporation).131
The independence requirements listed above are largely concerned with
what Power calls organizational independence. 132 That is, they define the
independence problem in terms of the relationship between the corporation and the
auditor, focusing, for example, on the auditor’s impartiality and the way in which
the auditor is appointed. A similar concern is expressed in the idea that the auditor
must be independent not only as a matter of fact but also in appearance.133
Power argues that there is a second dimension to audit independence —
operational independence — which focuses on the process of the audit rather than
on the auditor. 134 This idea is further sub-divided into what Power calls
informational and epistemic independence. Informational independence draws
attention to the fact that regardless of their degree of organisational independence,
an auditor must depend, at least to some extent, on information supplied by the
corporation that is being audited. This is the problem discussed in the Pacific
Acceptance case, noted earlier,135 and it has been a constant concern of the courts.
For example, in defining the common law duties of auditors, the courts have
concentrated on the obligation to look behind the corporation’s books and
determine its true financial position. 136 Acknowledging that auditors must be
dependent, at least to some extent, on information supplied by the corporation, the
second sub-category — epistemic independence — is concerned with whether the
auditor is nevertheless able to draw independent conclusions from this
information. 137 Power argues that for this to be possible, auditors must have a
knowledge base that is independent of the audited party on which to assess
information provided by that party.138 This reduces the impact of negotiations with
the audited party about what should and should not be noted in the audit report.
This aspect of operational independence highlights the use of auditing (and
accounting) standards. For example, the Corporations Act s 307A requires an audit
to be conducted in accordance with the auditing standards that are made by the
Auditing and Assurance Standards Board, a statutory authority.139
Each of the auditor independence mechanisms described above (and the
list is not exhaustive) has generated debate on questions of practicability and
effectiveness. Without rehearsing those debates here, my argument is that these
ideas should be assessed by their potential to contribute to a separation of powers
131
ss 324CE-CH.
132
Power, above n 107, 132.
133
See Ramsay Report, above n 113, 8.08.
134
Power, above n 107, 132.
135
Pacific Acceptance Corporation Ltd v Forsyth (1970) 92 WN(NSW) 29.
136
For example, Arthur Young & Co v WA Chip & Pulp Co Pty Ltd (1988) 13 ACLR 283;
AWA Ltd v Daniels (1992) 10 ACLC 933.
137
Power, above n 107, 132-133.
138
Ibid 133.
139
Established by s 227A Australian Securities and Investments Commission Act 2001.
Corporate Accountability 105
I argued earlier in this Chapter that shareholders, via the general meeting, occupy
one of the two key decision-making sites in a corporation. But the general meeting
is not the only mechanism through which shareholders can have contact with
directors and managers.140 We can therefore consider separations of powers within
the ranks of the shareholders outside the general meeting. Some shareholders have
the capacity to monitor and influence management. Indeed, institutional
shareholders (such as superannuation funds, insurance companies, managed
investment funds, and banks) are now being urged to play a role as catalysts for
improved governance practices in listed public companies. The OECD Principles
of Corporate Governance argue that:
The effectiveness and credibility of the entire corporate governance system and
company oversight will … to a large extend depend on institutional investors that
can make informed use of their shareholder rights and effectively exercise their
ownership functions in companies in which they invest.141
The OECD urges that institutions should ‘establish a continuing dialogue’ with
their portfolio corporations. Similarly, in the United Kingdom the Institutional
Shareholders’ Committee (a lobby group representing four major institutional
associations) has published principles that urge institutional shareholders to
monitor and, where necessary, enter into ‘active dialogue’ with the boards and
senior managers of portfolio corporations.142 In Australia the Federal Parliamentary
Joint Committee on Corporations and Financial Services has noted that:
140
Higgs, above n 87, 15.11.
141
OECD, above n 84, 37.
142
Institutional Shareholders’ Committee, The Responsibilities of Institutional
Shareholders and Agents – Statement of Principles
<http://www.abi.org.uk/Display/File/38/Statement_of_Principles.pdf> at 30 July 2004.
This Statement of Principles is supported in the FSA Combined Code, above n 126,
Principle E.1, and endorsed in the Higgs Review, above n 87, 15.25.
106 The Constitutional Corporation
there are growing expectations that institutional investors will take an active part
in monitoring and influencing the companies in which they invest especially
through exercising their vote at meetings. For example, the Australian Chamber of
Commerce and Industry urges institutional investors to be mindful of their
fiduciary duty to their clients and to ‘take a greater degree of active interest and
engagement in the affairs of those companies where they, on behalf of their
clients, have substantial economic interests’.143
143
Parliamentary Joint Committee on Corporations and Financial Services, Parliament of
Australia, CLERP (Audit Reform and Corporate Disclosure) Bill 2003 - Part 1 (2004)
168.
144
Investment & Financial Services Association Ltd, Shareholder Activism Among Fund
Managers: Policy and Practice, (2003) — submission to Parliamentary Joint
Committee on Corporations and Financial Services, Parliament of Australia, Canberra,
<http://www.aph.gove.au/senate/committee/corporations_ctte/clerp9/submissions/sub044a1.pdf>
at 30 July 2004.
145
I Ramsay, G Stapledon and K Fong, ‘Corporate Governance: The Perspective of
Australian Institutional Shareholders’ (2000) 18 Company and Securities Law Journal
110, 124.
146
Higgs, above n 87, 67.
147
J Coffee, ‘Liquidity versus Control: The Institutional Investor as Corporate Monitor’
(1991) 91 Columbia Law Review 1277, 1334.
148
Ramsay, Stapledon and Fong, above n 145, 121; Investment & Financial Services
Association Ltd, above n 144, 13.
Corporate Accountability 107
Whistleblowers
149
Eg, Parliamentary Joint Committee on Corporations and Financial Services, above n
143, recommendation 23. Research in the UK suggests that fund managers oppose the
public disclosure of voting: see above n 87, 13.
150
J Farrar, Corporate Governance in Australia and New Zealand (2001) 319.
151
P Ali, G Stapledon and M Gold, Corporate Governance and Investment Fiduciaries
(2003) chapter 3.
152
Corporate whistleblowing has many contexts, for example the employee who ‘goes
public’ regarding illegal dumping of toxic waste or price-fixing. This present discussion
concerns questions of corporate governance.
153
HIH Royal Commission, above n 113, 131. Encouragement for whistleblowing can also
be found in the Australian Stock Exchange’s corporate governance code, above n 83,
recommendation 10.1, and in the OECD Principles of Corporate Governance, above n
84, principle IV.E.
154
The Corporations Act 2001 (Aust) Part 9.4AAA gives qualified privilege and provides
immunity from civil or criminal liability for a disclosure made on reasonable grounds
and in good faith by an officer or employee of a corporation or by a person (or their
employee) who has a contract for the supply of services or goods with the corporation.
108 The Constitutional Corporation
one thing, corporate leaders would presumably prefer to reduce the need for
whistleblowing and encourage the prospect of detecting problems through regular
internal channels. 155 Another reason is that the choice facing a potential
whistleblower is always difficult, notwithstanding the positive attention that
whistleblowing often receives in the press. The personal consequences can be
significant, and many will consider the risks to be too high. Nevertheless,
encouraging whistleblowing can be an important supplement — a safety net that
may operate when other forms of accountability fail.156
The consequences when this is not done can be significant. As Alan
Greenspan, Chair of the United States Federal Reserve Board, commented in 2002:
In recent years, shareholders and potential investors would have been protected
from widespread misinformation if any one of the many bulwarks safeguarding
appropriate corporate evaluation had held. In too many cases, none did. Lawyers,
internal and external auditors, corporate boards, Wall Street security analysts,
rating agencies, and large institutional holders of stock all failed for one reason or
another to detect and blow the whistle on those who breached the level of trust
essential to well-functioning markets.157
155
M Miceli and J Near, Blowing the Whistle: The Organizational and Legal Implications
for Companies and Employees (1992), 282.
156
M Winfield, ‘Whistleblower as Corporate Safety Net’ in G Vinten (ed),
Whistleblowing: Subversion or Corporate Citizenship? (1994) 21, 22.
157
Statement to United States Senate Committee on Banking, Housing and Urban Affairs
(July 2002), quoted in P Latimer, ‘Whistleblowing in the Financial Services Sector’
(2002) 21 University of Tasmania Law Review 39, 42.
158
This is recognised in Corporations Act 2001 s 1317AA.
159
See Braithwaite, above n 62, 349ff for more detailed discussion of this point.
160
For example, in the United States s 10A(m)(4)(b) of the Securities Exchange Act of
1934 requires each audit committee to establish procedures for the confidential,
anonymous submission by employees of concerns regarding questionable accounting or
audit matters.
161
As an example, the Corporations Act 2001 (Aust) s 1317AA protects disclosures that
are made to the Australian Securities and Investments Commission, the auditor, a
director or senior manager, the corporate secretary, or to a person authorised by the
corporation to receive those disclosures.
162
This term comes from Miceli and Near, above n 155, 21.
Corporate Accountability 109
Conclusion
163
s 311. See also s 1289, giving an auditor qualified privilege in respect of a notification
under s 311.
164
Commonwealth of Australia, Department of Treasury, Corporate Disclosure:
Strengthening the Financial Reporting Framework (2002) 10.2; see also R Tomasic and
S Bottomley, Directing the Top 500: Corporate Governance and Accountability in
Australian Companies (1993) 107.
165
See the discussion in Parliamentary Joint Committee on Corporations and Financial
Services, above n 143, Chapter 2.
110 The Constitutional Corporation
166
Braithwaite, above n 62, 359.
167
Ibid.
168
Ibid 361.
Chapter 5
1
See, eg, Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) s 136(2); Companies Act 1985 (UK) s 9; Canada
Business Corporations Act s 173. In the United States, the power to amend a
corporation’s bylaws is usually shared between the directors and the shareholders: see,
eg, Revised Model Business Corporations Act s 10.20 (2002).
2
See, eg, Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) s 203D; Companies Act 1985 (UK) s 303;
Canada Business Corporations Act, RSC 1985, s 109.
3
See, eg, Bamford v Bamford [1970] Ch 212; Winthrop Investements Ltd v Winns Ltd
[1975] 2 NSWLR 666.
112 The Constitutional Corporation
liberal views to critical and radical perspectives.4 Deliberative theorists debate with
each other (as, of course, they should) the differences and the commonalities in
their perspectives. I do not propose to enter these debates or to offer a particular
theory of deliberation. Instead, I take some of these deliberative ideas and apply
them to the context of corporate decision-making. This is a context that has
received little, if any, attention from deliberative theorists. Nevertheless, my
reading of the literature suggests that deliberative ideas do have a role to play in
corporate governance. I have tended to borrow widely from the deliberative
literature. Particular deliberative theorists may baulk at some of what they read
here, but any damage I do to particular theories of deliberation is due to the unique
characteristics of the corporate context.5
In this part of the Chapter I make the general argument that the idea of deliberative
decision-making can be applied to corporations. Later on, I address some more
specific aspects of deliberative decision-making in board-rooms and the general
meetings.
I use the term ‘deliberative decision-making’6 to describe the idea that as
far as possible there should be processes prior to reaching decisions (whether in
the board-room or the general meeting) that are open and genuine, and that these
processes should lead to decisions that represent a collective judgement about the
issue at hand.
By open and genuine I mean that corporate decisions ought to be reached
as a consequence of processes of inquiry and be made in the light of all relevant
4
A useful review of the literature, written from a critical perspective, can be found in J
Dryzek, Deliberative Democracy and Beyond: Liberals, Critics, Contestations (2000).
5
In particular, the corporate context of countries such as Australia and the United
Kingdom.
6
I refer to ‘deliberative decision-making’ rather than ‘deliberative democracy’ because I
want to highlight the process of deliberation as a necessary prelude to decision-making.
That is, I do not want to characterise deliberation as a good in and of itself — a claim
that is sometimes associated with the term ‘deliberative democracy’. My ideas on
deliberative decision-making draw on a variety of sources, but in particular: Joshua
Cohen, ‘Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy’ in A Hamlin and P Pettit (eds), The
Good Polity: Normative Analysis of the State (1989); Bernard Manin, ‘On Legitimacy
and Political Deliberation’ (1987) 15 Political Theory 338; Philip Pettit,
Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government (1997) (hereafter,
‘Republicanism’); Cass Sunstein, The Partial Constitution (1993) (hereafter ‘The
Partial Constitution’); C Sunstein, Democracy and the Problem of Free Speech (1993)
(hereafter, ‘Democracy and Free Speech’); Iris Young, ‘Communication and the Other:
Beyond Deliberative Democracy’ in M Wilson and A Yeatman (eds), Justice and
Identity: Antipodean Practices (1995). This Chapter is an adaptation of these ideas
because none of these arguments has specifically applied the idea of deliberation to
corporate decision-making.
Corporate Decisions and Deliberation 113
arguments. Decision-making in the general meeting and in the board room ought to
involve ‘recourse to methods of discussion, consultation, and persuasion’ prior to
the counting of votes and the adoption of a resolution.7 Adapting Cass Sunstein’s
description, corporate decisions should be the outcome of processes of
‘deliberation and discussion, in which new information and new perspectives are
brought to bear’.8 The legitimacy of a decision is not determined simply by the
results that it produces. A decision ‘inherits most of its legitimation from the
preceding deliberation’. 9 This accords with wider research showing that people
evaluate their experiences in decision-making forums by focusing on the fairness
of the procedures, rather than on the personal consequences of the decision.10
The idea of deliberative decision-making emphasises process as much as
outcome. It also emphasises reason rather than authority.11 Deliberative decisions
are based on the critical assessment of reasoned argument, not on managerial edict,
deference to the authority or expertise of directors or to the votes of powerful
shareholders, nor by appeal to pre-existing assumptions about what is reasonable,
feasible, or appropriate. 12 Moreover, during deliberation there should be an
‘equality of input’. For example, the views of small or minority shareholders
should not be discounted simply because of the size of their potential vote. This
was put nicely in Re Compaction Systems Pty Ltd, where Bowen CJ in Eq pointed
out that:
[t]he right to receive notice of a meeting and to attend and to be heard is not an
insubstantial right. The right to advance arguments and to influence the course of
discussion may in some circumstances have an effect, even a decisive effect, on
the decision reached.13
The requirement that decisions be open and genuine entails, therefore, that
there should be practices and structures in place to ensure that participants in the
decision-making forum have the opportunity to have their point of view heard
before the decision is made. A brief note of caution is needed here: the argument
about deliberation should not be read as an argument about participation, except to
the extent that it insists that the general meeting and the board room should be
forums in which decisions are actually made, rather than being procedural
showpieces that merely formalise or ratify decisions that have effectively been
7
J Dewey, ‘The Public and Its Problems’, in D Morris and I Shapiro (eds), John Dewey:
The Political Writings (1993) 187. See also Sunstein, Democracy and Free Speech,
above n 6, 242.
8
Sunstein, The Partial Constitution, above n 6, 134.
9
A Tschentscher, ‘Deliberation as a Discursive Feature of Contemporary Theories of
Democracy: Comment on John S. Dryzek’ in A Van Aaken, C List, and C Luetge (eds),
Deliberation and Decision: Economics, Constitutional Theory and Deliberative
Democracy (2004) 72, 76.
10
See Tom Tyler, Why People Obey the Law (1990).
11
Young, above n 6, 136.
12
See Cohen, above n 6, 22; Young, above n 6, 137.
13
(1976) 2 ACLR 135, 142.
114 The Constitutional Corporation
14
See below n 36 and accompanying text.
15
The law prescribes that directors must act in the general corporate interest: see below n
36 and accompanying text.
16
This is discussed later: see below n 52 and accompanying text.
17
R Buxbaum, ‘Corporate Governance and Corporate Monitoring: The Whys and Hows’
(1996) 6 Australian Journal of Corporate Law 309, 312.
18
Young, above n 6, 143.
19
Young, above n 6, 137.
20
Sunstein, Democracy and Free Speech, above n 6, 244.
Corporate Decisions and Deliberation 115
important in transforming the several similar individual views into a group opinion.
There will, of course, be competing versions of what is in the corporate interest,
and different views of the criteria to be used in assessing it. Indeed, some
interpretations may require the articulation of other interests as well, eg employees,
consumers, the environment. It is one purpose of deliberative decision-making to
encourage this sort of debate.
21
There are issues to be addressed in the procedures used to achieve a decision by
majority vote: see Philip Pettit, ‘A Dilemma for Deliberative Democrats’ in Van Aaken,
List and Luetge, above n 9, 91.
22
Dewey, above n 7, 187.
23
Manin, above n 6, 359.
24
Above, n 10, 163 (Tyler’s research concerns people’s experience with decisions made
by police and courts).
25
These are similar to statutory provisions in other countries, eg the United Kingdom and
Canada.
26
Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) s 250E (a replaceable rule). The comparable provision in
the Companies Act 1985 (UK) s 370(6) is said to be based on ‘a presumption of
equality between shareholders’: P Davies, Gower and Davies’ Principles of Modern
116 The Constitutional Corporation
on a resolution will be decided on a show of hands.27 This has long been common
corporate practice,28 and most resolutions are decided in this way.29 This suggests
that, initially at least, corporate decision-making places some value on the political
ideal of one person – one vote or, as Ratner puts it, the idea that ‘votes are
decisions, decisions are made by people, and one person’s decision should not be
given greater weight than another’s unless some important reason of policy
supports the distinction’.30 Of course there is a countervailing policy: corporate law
has an underlying preference for the principle of one share – one vote, which
directly correlates voting power to the size of a shareholder’s financial stake in the
corporation. 31 Voting at a general meeting ultimately becomes an expression of
economic interests; the shareholder who owns more share capital in a corporation
has a greater opportunity to have a say in the corporation’s affairs.32
The legislation provides that on or before the declaration of a result on a
show of hands, a specified proportion of shareholders may demand that the
resolution be decided on a poll (or ballot).33 When a poll is taken, each voting
shareholder is able to exercise the actual votes per share that they hold. 34 This
Company Law (7th ed, 2003) 618. The Australian Stock Exchange Listing Rules
require a listed company to allocate one vote per share as a prerequisite to listing:
Listing Rule 6.9. In an unlisted company, there is no legal impediment to the creation of
voting rights that are unrelated to the size of the member’s shareholding (see eg
Amalgamated Pest Control Pty Ltd v McCarron (1994) 12 ACLC 171, 173). Shares can
be given multiple voting rights that can operate either generally or on particular types of
resolution (see eg Bushell v Faith [1970] AC 1099).
27
s 250J (a replaceable rule). Unless the corporation’s constitution says otherwise, a
proxy may vote on a show of hands (s 249Y).
28
It was described by Lindley LJ in Ernest v Loma Gold Mines Ltd [1896] 1 Ch 1, 6 as a
‘well known mode of conducting business’.
29
S Bottomley, The Role of Shareholders’ Meetings in Improving Corporate Governance
(Research Report, Centre for Commercial Law, Australian National University, 2003),
38.
30
D Ratner, ‘The Government of Business Corporations: Critical Reflections on the Rule
of “One Share, One Vote”’ (1970) 56 Cornell Law Review 1, 19.
31
Earlier companies legislation provided a slightly different formulation. For example, in
New South Wales, the Companies Act 1874 s 84 provided that every member shall have
one vote unless the Articles said otherwise. The model Articles set out a variable voting
scale: one vote per share for the first 10 shares held; one additional vote for every extra
5 shares up to 100 shares; and one additional vote for every 10 shares over 100. This
appears to have been taken from the Companies Act 1862 (UK). In New South Wales
reference to one vote per share in the model articles was not introduced until the
Companies Act 1936.
32
See H Manne ‘Some Theoretical Aspects of Share Voting — An Essay in Honor of
Adolf A. Berle’ (1964) 64 Columbia Law Review 1427, 1430 for an explanation of the
relationship between what he describes as the voting and investment components of the
voting share.
33
The demand must be made by either the chairperson of the meeting, or by a sufficient
number of members as specified: s 250L
34
On a poll a member does not have to exercise all of their votes, nor need they cast all
their votes in the same way: s 250H.
Corporate Decisions and Deliberation 117
means that reference to ‘a majority vote’ at a general meeting may mean a majority
of the shareholders or it may mean a majority of the votes that were actually cast
(which, depending on the spread of shares, may or may not be the same as a
majority of shareholders).
One problem that may impede the effective operation of deliberative
processes in a decision-making system that is based on allocating votes per share
and in which voting is voluntary is that holders of large parcels of voting shares
may decide to exercise their voting power regardless of the deliberative process.
Because their vote will carry the day, they may shun deliberative input. My
response to this potential problem begins from the premise that shareholders
cannot — and should not — be forced to deliberate. Instead, shareholders should
be encouraged — in ways that I will describe — to consider the benefits for the
corporation as a whole that can result from quality deliberative input from as many
shareholders as possible. On some matters, as we will see in the case of minority
share expropriations, 35 the law supports this, setting firm guidelines that are
intended to encourage consideration by majority shareholders of the interests of
others.
35
See below n 65, and accompanying text.
36
Here I depart from some formulations of deliberative theory that require participation
by all those who are subject to the decision — eg Manin, above n 6, 352.
37
Young, above n 6, 142.
118 The Constitutional Corporation
example, which directors to vote for, whether to vote for or against a constitutional
amendment) can take a lot of work, and may require specialised knowledge. There
are many factors leading to shareholder passivity, not all of which will be
influenced or altered by deliberative structures and processes. On any given
occasion, a shareholder may not participate in decision-making for a number of
reasons: not being aware that a decision is being made; not understanding the
issues; not being personally affected by the issues; indecision; or plain indifference.
But while we can acknowledge the real pressures towards inaction, a
constitutionalist framework should have rules, structures and processes that permit
and encourage shareholders to exercise their capacities as members and to seek to
influence the decision-making process, rather than acting as purely passive
investors or ‘residual claimants’.
Thus, while one goal of deliberative decision-making is to improve the
quality of corporate decision-making by increasing the potential range of
viewpoints that are brought to bear on a decision, it can also have a broadly
educative function, whereby members learn that their personal interests are linked
to those of the corporation, and that as a consequence they are corporate as well as
private actors.38 Whatever reason shareholders have for not exercising their right to
vote, it should not be due to a feeling that there is no point, that passivity is
encouraged, and that general meetings are mere formalities or public relations
exercises.
38
This draws on Rousseau’s theory of participation, as discussed by Carole Pateman,
Participation and Democratic Theory (1970) 24-25. Pateman argues that the educative
function is the major purpose of participation — see 42-43. On the distinction between
instrumentalism and other goals such as political and moral education see G Parry, ‘The
Idea of Political Participation’ in G Parry (ed) Participation in Politics (1972) 19-31. It
is easy to overstate the impact of this educative function in the corporate context.
Membership of a widely-held public company does not tend to ‘produce strong
community ties constitutive of the member’s self-understanding’ — W Bratton, ‘Public
Values and Corporate Fiduciary Law’ (1992) 44 Rutgers Law Review 675, 695.
Corporate Decisions and Deliberation 119
39
This threefold categorisation is taken from William Rehg and James Bohman,
‘Discourse and Democracy: The Formal and Informal Bases of Legitimacy in
Habermas’ Faktizität und Geltung’ (1996) 4 The Journal of Political Philosophy 79,
86-88.
40
J Hill, ‘Visions and Revisions of the Shareholder’ (2000) 48 American Journal of
Comparative Law 39.
41
In Australia these debates were prompted by the High Court’s decision in Gambotto v
WCP Ltd (1995) 182 CLR 432. See, for example, Ian Ramsay (ed), Gambotto v WCP
Ltd: Its Implications for Corporate Regulation (1996); Peta Spender, ‘Guns and
Greenmail: Fear and Loathing after Gambotto’ (1998) 22 Melbourne University Law
Review 96.
120 The Constitutional Corporation
one set of values or perspectives will carry the day, but this should be an outcome
of a deliberative process rather than a predetermined conclusion or strategy.
Finally, we can expect a plurality of opinions and arguments on any given
issue, even amongst those who share a common discursive perspective. The greater
the range of conflicting opinions and arguments that are put, the more likely it is
that the resulting decision, reflected in a majority vote, will be acceptable to, and
can be said to be authored by, the general body of decision-makers.
What I have said so far about deliberative decision-making is, perhaps, an idealised
description that establishes a benchmark against which actual corporate practices
may be evaluated. Deliberation aims to enhance the quantity and quality of
information which is brought to bear upon a decision, thereby enhancing the
quality of the decision itself. But the reference to quantity does not imply that more
information is necessarily better. It is a characteristic of most deliberative systems
that ‘it is not possible to deliberate everything, or all the possibilities permitted by
a given situation’.42 Clearly there are practical limits to the number and range of
inputs that a decision-making process can sustain, and deliberative structures and
processes must allow for this. I explore some ways in which this might be done
later in this Chapter. There are also limitations imposed by the constitutional
framework within which deliberation occurs. Not just anything can go onto the
agenda of a general meeting or a board meeting, and not just anything can be
decided about the agenda items.
Similarly, the reference to quality does not mean that deliberative
processes alone will guarantee contributions of greater calibre, nor that decisions
will always be reasonable. Deliberative structures and processes are not of
themselves guarantees against the problems of domination, oppression or
unfairness in corporate affairs. Indeed, as Schauer has noted, it is possible that
sometimes deliberation:
lowers rather than raises the quality of consideration, increases the likelihood that
bad arguments will be accepted and good ones rejected, overly empowers the
rhetorician and the demagogue, and exacerbates the disempowerment of those
already disempowered on the basis of race, gender, class, wealth, physical
attractiveness, and all of the other features that distinguish the empowered from
the disempowered.43
42
Manin, above n 6, 356-357.
43
F Schauer, ‘Deliberating about Deliberation’ (1992) 90 Michigan Law Review 1187,
1200.
Corporate Decisions and Deliberation 121
certain forms and styles of contribution over others, and there will be differing
levels of expertise and differing capacities to put an argument.44 The processes of
corporate deliberation will not always be mannered and polite; they may be tense,
uneven, and at times, unpleasant. All of this reminds us, again, that deliberation is
only one aspect of the corporate constitutionalist framework; deliberation alone is
not sufficient, and other mechanisms, such as appropriate separations of power,
and avenues for contesting decisions (dealt with in the next Chapter), must also be
considered.
44
See Young, above n 6, 138-139.
45
Cohen, n 6, 21.
46
Manin, above n 6, 352.
47
See, eg, AWA Ltd v Daniels (1992) 10 ACLC 933, 1013-1014.
122 The Constitutional Corporation
48
This line of cases is usually taken to have begun with the judgement of Ormiston J in
Statewide Tobacco Services Ltd v Morley (1990) 8 ACLC 827 but note should also be
made of Kirby P’s dissenting judgement in Metal Manufacturers Ltd v Lewis (1988) 13
ACLR 357.
49
(1993) 11 ACSR 162, 170.
50
(1992) 10 ACLC 933, 1013.
51
(1995) 13 ACLC 614, 666 (emphasis added). See also Northside Developments Pty Ltd
v Registrar-General (1990) 8 ACLC 611, 645.
52
Greenhalgh v Arderne Cinemas Ltd [1951] Ch 286; Levin v Clark [1962] NSWR 686;
Re Broadcasting Station 2GB Pty Ltd [1964-1965] NSWR 1648.
53
Bell v Burton (1994) 12 ACLC 1037, 1038; see also Wagner v International Health
Promotions (1994) 12 ACLC 986.
Corporate Decisions and Deliberation 123
The purpose, in my view, is to ensure that directors taking part in a directors’
meeting are able to deliberate together concerning the affairs of the company and
ultimately resolve upon action to be taken. Deliberation in this sense, in my view,
involves each director:
(a) being able to know of the matters of fact and opinion articulated by all
other directors participating in the meeting; and
(b) being free to seek to persuade such other directors to particular views
with respect to the matters properly before the meeting.54
The separation of powers within the board — especially between the roles of
chairperson and CEO — is one way to encourage board decisions that are based on
reason rather than hierarchy. Of course this is not sufficient by itself. The basic
requirement, as Ford, Austin and Ramsay put it, is that directors are required ‘to
exercise an active discretion; they will be in breach of duty for letting things slide
or for improperly acting blindly at the directions of another person’.56
The case law on directors’ decisions therefore emphasises the processes
that should precede a decision. This can be reinforced by statutory requirements. In
Australia, for example, the Corporations Act contains a business judgement rule57
which provides that a ‘business judgement’ made by a director (or officer) of a
corporation will be taken to satisfy the duty of care and diligence, provided that the
judgement meets certain criteria. One criterion is that the director has informed
him or herself about the subject matter of the judgement to the extent they
reasonably believe is appropriate.58 Furthermore, the protection of the rule is only
available if the director actively makes a business judgement— that is, there must
be a decision to take or not to take action about a matter that is relevant to the
54
(1995) 13 ACLC 1047, 1050.
55
ABC Radio, ‘Ex NAB Board member Catherine Walter speaks out’, AM, Wednesday 1
September 2004,
<http://www.abc.net.au/am/content/2004/s1189565.htm> at 1 September 2004.
56
H Ford, R Austin and I Ramsay, Ford’s Principles of Corporations Law (12th ed,
2005) 373.
57
Section 180(2). This rule is based upon a similar provision in the American Law
Institute’s Principles of Corporate Governance: Analysis and Recommendations.
58
Section 180(2)(c).
124 The Constitutional Corporation
There is, if I may say so, no obligation on a shareholder of a company to give his
vote merely with a view to what other persons may consider the interest of the
company at large. He has a right, if he thinks fit, to give his vote from motives or
promptings of what he considers his own individual interest.61
There are, however, occasions on which the courts have imposed constraints on the
exercise of majority voting power in a general meeting, and the principles
enunciated in these cases are consistent with aspects of the deliberative ideal.
A court may declare that a decision made by a majority of members that
constitutes an abuse of power is void. This is done on the grounds that the majority
must not exercise its voting power for a purpose that lies outside the implied scope
of purposes for which that power was conferred by the corporation’s constitution.62
In one explanation of this doctrine Templeman J said that it applies when majority
shareholders ‘use their powers, intentionally or unintentionally, fraudulently or
negligently, in a manner which benefits themselves at the expense of the
company’.63 To this extent the doctrine enjoins the majority members to exercise
their votes by having regard to matters that lie outside, and may be inconsistent
with, their personal interests.
This requirement is also found in cases concerning the power of members
to amend the corporate constitution by special resolution. For many years the
courts circumscribed the power of the majority members in this situation by
requiring that their vote ‘must be exercised ... bona fide for the benefit of the
company as a whole’.64 This broad requirement proved to be unhelpful in situations
where the proposed constitutional amendment would alter or abrogate the rights of
some members against their will. In Gambotto v WCP Ltd, a case involving an
59
Section 180(3).
60
Peters’ American Delicacy Co Ltd v Heath (1939) 61 CLR 457, 504 (Dixon J).
61
(1877) 6 Ch D 70, 75-76.
62
Ford, Austin and Ramsay, above n 56, 618. This is sometimes referred to as the
doctrine of fraud on the minority.
63
Daniels v Daniels [1978] Ch 406, 414.
64
Allen v Gold Reefs of West Africa Ltd [1900] 1 Ch 656, 671 per Lindley MR.
Corporate Decisions and Deliberation 125
Disclosure of Information
65
(1995) 13 ACLC 342, 348.
66
See above n 41. There is also debate about the application of the test to the facts in
Gambotto, where the majority shareholder (with 99.7% of the shares) had refrained
from voting, the resolution being passed by a majority of the remaining shareholders.
67
The words quoted come from Pettit, Republicanism, above n 6, 55. There are
interesting similarities between the Gambotto test and Pettit’s idea of freedom as non-
domination.
68
In Australia, Chapter 2M of the Corporations Act 2001 specifies requirements for
preparation and publication of annual financial reports and conduct of annual audits.
69
For example, takeovers (Corporations Act 2001 Chapter 6), and public offers of
securities (Corporations Act 2001 Chapter 6D).
70
Australian Stock Exchange Listing Rule 3.1, backed up by Chapter 6CA of the
Corporations Act 2001 imposes continuous disclosure requirements on listed entities.
71
See the review of these debates in I Ramsay, ‘Models of Corporate Regulation: The
Mandatory/Enabling Debate’ in C Rickett and R Grantham (eds), Corporate
Personality in The 20th Century (1998).
126 The Constitutional Corporation
72
In certain circumstances, an unlisted corporation is required to make disclosure to the
Australian Securities and Investments Commission.
Corporate Decisions and Deliberation 127
price or value of the corporation’s securities73) means that disclosure can be tied to
the circumstances of the particular corporation. As explained by O’Loughlin J in
Flavel v Roget:
Much will depend upon the identity of the particular company; what one company
should advise the Stock Exchange might not have to be advised by a second
company; what should be advised by a company at one stage in its career might
not have to be advised at another stage of its career because of changed
circumstances.74
There are more specific statutory rules that are intended to give members the
opportunity to deliberate at the general meetings of public corporations. These
rules may be supplemented by provisions in a corporate constitution (and, in the
case of listed corporations, by stock exchange rules). The statutory rules seek to
ensure that members are given adequate notice of a meeting and of the business to
be conducted so that they can make informed choices about attendance and voting.
Typically there are requirements concerning the timing of annual general
meetings, 77 notice requirements, 78 as well as provisions dealing with voting
procedures, quorum, proxies and minutes.79 The Australian legislation also requires
73
See, eg, Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) s 674(2)(c).
74
(1990) 8 ACLC 237 243-245.
75
See Australian Stock Exchange, Guidance Note 8: Continuous Disclosure: Listing Rule
3.1 (2003); Australian Securities and Investments Commission, Better Disclosure for
Investors — Guidance Rules,
<http://www.asic.gov.au/asic/pdflib.nsf/LookupByFileName/better_disclosure.pdf/$file
/better_disclosure.pdf> at 1 September 2004.
76
Some professional and industry groups now give annual awards to corporations,
determined by reference to the quality of corporate continuous disclosure polices and
practices. See, eg, the Australasian Reporting Awards < www.arawards.com.au > at 18
February 2005.
77
Eg, Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) s 250N; Companies Act 1985 (UK) s 366; Canada
Business Corporations Act, RSC 1985, s 133.
78
Eg, Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) ss 249H – L (s 249R requires a meeting to be held at a
reasonable time and place); Companies Act 1985 (UK) s 369; Canada Business
Corporations Act, RSC 1985, s 135.
79
Eg, quorum: Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) s 249T, Companies Act 1985 (UK) s 370A,
Canada Business Corporations Act, RSC 1985, s 139; voting procedure: Corporations
Act 2001 (Cth) s 250J, Companies Act 1985 (UK) s 370, Canada Business
Corporations Act, RSC 1985, s 141; right to appoint proxy: Corporations Act 2001
128 The Constitutional Corporation
(Cth) s 249X, Companies Act 1985 (UK) s 372, Canada Business Corporations Act,
RSC 1985, Pt XIII; minutes: Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) ss 251A, 251B, Companies
Act 1985 (UK) s 382.
80
s 250S.
81
s 250T. The auditor is required to attend the AGM of a listed corporation (s 250RA).
82
In Australia, see Companies and Securities Advisory Committee, Shareholder
Participation in the Modern Listed Public Company, Final Report (2000); Joint
Statutory Committee on Corporations and Securities, Parliament of Australia, Report on
Matters Arising from the Company Law Review Act 1998 (1998); in the United
Kingdom, see Company Law Review Steering Group, Company General Meetings and
Shareholder Communication, Consultation Document (1999).
83
Company Law Review Act 1998 (Cth). Some of the new rules had been introduced in
the Senate by the Democrat and Labor Parties against the Government’s wishes.
84
See, eg, Catherine Fox, ‘Shareholders keeping their eyes glued on boards’ The
Australian Financial Review, 5 November 1999, 19. Another example is the forced
resignation of the chair of the board of AMP Ltd (one of Australia’s largest insurance
companies) in April 2000: The Australian Financial Review, 4 April 2000, 1.
85
For example, in 1999 the Australian mining company North Ltd faced legal action
brought by a group of shareholders (North Ethical Shareholders) to compel the
corporation to consider a resolution concerning the environmental impact of the
activities of one of its subsidiaries. The action was settled out of court after North
agreed to consider the resolution at the same time as its annual general meeting: The
Age (Melbourne) 13 September 1999. Shareholders in the transnational mining
company, Rio Tinto Ltd/Plc faced action from international union-backed shareholders
seeking changes to board structure and company compliance with ILO conventions:
The Australian Financial Review, 8 March 2000, 1; The Sydney Morning Herald
(Sydney) 12 May 2000, 10.
Corporate Decisions and Deliberation 129
the rules governing shareholder participation, through physical meetings or
electronic communications, should facilitate the efficient determination of the will
of the majority of shareholders in defined areas, with all proper safeguards to
ensure informed decision-making. All shareholders should have an equal right to
all appropriate information and an opportunity to express their views, with voting
rights proportionate to their shareholding.86
At one extreme there are arguments tending towards either the abolition of general
meetings87 or, less dramatically, limiting the role of general meetings in corporate
governance. Shareholder meetings are depicted as expensive, time consuming, and
often poorly attended events where the outcomes on key resolutions are usually
predetermined by proxy votes. 88 At the other extreme there are arguments that
favour the use of general meetings as forums in which members can voice both
corporate and wider economic, political, environmental, or social concerns. In this
view, shareholder meetings are seen as one method whereby the concerns of
majority and minority shareholders and other stakeholders in a corporation can be
brought to the attention of the corporation’s managers. The theoretical bases for
this argument are aligned with a variety of communitarian or stakeholder
theories.89
We are thus presented with a choice between privileging the efficiency of
decision-making at the expense of deliberation, or promoting vague notions of
86
CASAC Final Report, above n 82, 1 (emphasis added).
87
For example, ‘Commonwealth Bank chief executive David Murray told a group of
newspaper executives in 1998 that the important question about AGMs was not how
they were run, but whether they should be held at all.’ The Weekend Australian, 27-28
May 2000, 36 (the Commonwealth Bank is one of Australia’s largest listed
corporations).
88
See G Stapledon, S Easterbrook, P Bennett, and I Ramsay, Proxy Voting in Australia’s
Largest Companies, Research Report, Centre for Corporate Law and Securities
Regulation, University of Melbourne, 2000.
89
See, eg, D Millon, ‘Communitarianism in Corporate Law: Foundations and Law
Reform Strategies’ in L Mitchell (ed) Progressive Corporate Law (1995) 1.
130 The Constitutional Corporation
democracy at the cost of effective decision-making.90 Neither view has taken hold.
The image of corporations as democratic communities does not take sufficient
account of the great dispersion and diversity of shareholders’ interests in public
corporations. The abolitionist arguments underestimate the value (even if only
symbolic) that many shareholders and directors continue to place on the general
meeting as an occasion for accountability. The remainder of this Chapter attempts
to chart an intermediate path between these choices, avoiding the undesirable
extreme of general meeting minimalism and the unworkable ideal of town-hall
meeting inclusiveness. The challenge is to link the value of deliberation, the need
for effective decision-making, with the concept of corporate membership.
While I think that a good case can be made for the deliberative ideal as an existing
theme in current corporate law, the claim should not be overstated. The
deliberative prospects are greater for boards than for general meetings because
typically a board is a small,91 relatively homogeneous group that, in practice, has a
degree of control over its membership.92 A general meeting is a larger assembly of
often disparate membership interests.
There is ample evidence that general meetings in public corporations can
be desultory affairs, characterised by relatively low rates of member attendance
and input. A survey of 217 Australian public company annual general meetings
held between 2001 and 2003 (‘the AGM study’) found that in 98 per cent of
meetings shareholders attending in person or participating by proxy represented no
more than 20 per cent of all shareholders in the corporation.93 Even if higher rates
of attendance can be achieved, the deliberative options in a general meeting are
constrained by a number of factors. The formal agenda, which sets the decision-
making parameters of the meeting, is determined prior to the meeting. As Black
describes it, in large corporations, ‘[m]anagers control what the shareholders get to
vote on, when they get to vote, what order proposals are offered in, and when the
shareholders learn what’s on the agenda’. 94 Corporate decision-making is a
90
Rehg and Bohman, above n 39, 85.
91
The average board size in Australia is seven, with the majority of corporations having
between four and nine directors: Korn/Ferry International, Boards of Directors Study in
Australia and New Zealand (2003) 14. In the UK the average board sized for a listed
company is approximately seven: Derek Higgs, United Kingdom Department of Trade
and Industry, Review of the Role and Effectiveness of Non-Executive Directors (January
2003), 18.
92
In most corporations the board has the power to fill casual vacancies. Such an
appointment must then be confirmed by resolution of the shareholders at the next
annual general meeting, with the person at the advantage of having been given the
board’s imprimatur.
93
Above n 29, 25.
94
B Black, ‘Shareholder Passivity Reexamined’ (1990) 89 Michigan Law Review 520,
592.
Corporate Decisions and Deliberation 131
95
Parry, above n 38, 6.
96
Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) s 249N: members with at least 5 per cent of the total
votes, or 100 members with voting rights, may give notice of a resolution prior to a
meeting.
97
E Magner, Joske’s Law and Procedure at Meetings in Australia (8th ed, 1994) 46.
98
C Plott and M Levine, ‘A Model of Agenda Influence on Committee Decisions’ (1978)
68 American Economic Review 146.
99
As occurred, for example, at the 2001 AGM of Telstra Ltd:
<http://workers.labor.net.au/119/news93_telstra.html> at 17 December 2004.
100
I have observed meetings held in large auditoriums where members are required to
speak via microphones, with power to the microphone being controlled by the persons
running the meeting.
101
This is discussed below at n 117 and accompanying text.
102
The average length of a meeting in the AGM study was 1.25 hours, with 38 per cent
taking less than one hour: above n 29, 42-43.
103
The AGM study, above n 29, 36-37, found that 87% of AGM agendas dealt with no
more than four matters, although these may have been broken up into a larger number
of agenda items.
104
AGM study, above n 29. A United Kingdom study reaches the same conclusion: P
Stiles and B Taylor, Boards at Work: How Directors View Their Roles and
132 The Constitutional Corporation
threat of angry shareholders from the floor to hold directors accountable’. Another
described the value of the general meeting in the following terms: ‘if someone is
asking you a question, looking [you] in your eye, face to face, and you don’t want
to answer it, there’s some pressure there’. 105 Nevertheless, there should be
mechanisms that give members the opportunity to deliberate outside the general
meeting and, perhaps, influence the matters which might be decided prior to the
formulation of the agenda. Under the next heading I explore what this might mean.
Spheres of Deliberation
Responsibilities (2001) 93. See also Business Council of Australia, Company and
Shareholder Dialogue: A Discussion Paper (2004) <http://www.bca.com.au/
upload/Fresh_Approaches_to_Communication_Betweeen_Companies_and_their_Share
holders.pdf> at 2 December 2005.
105
AGM study, above n 29, 41-42.
106
J Habermas, Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law
and Democracy (1996) 308.
107
The Australian Securities and Investments Commission operates a Company Alert
service that enables a person to nominate companies in which they are interested and to
then be notified by email of changes to the Commission’s database on those companies.
Corporate Decisions and Deliberation 133
Since January 2000 the Australian Stock Exchange has conducted a free email alert
service that provides summaries of major announcements by participating companies.
See E Boros, ‘Corporations Online’ (2001) 19 Companies & Securities Law Journal
492, 501.
108
B Noveck, ‘Designing Deliberative Democracy in Cyberspace: The Role of the Cyber-
Lawyer’ (2003) 9 Boston University Journal of Science and Technology Law 1, 6-7.
109
This is an explanatory device, not a descriptive model of corporate organisational
structure. The image of concentric spheres (or circles) coincides with Habermas’
argument, but a pyramid or hierarchical model could just as easily be used.
110
Thanks to John Braithwaite for this observation.
111
Habermas, above n 106, 356.
112
B Peters, Die Integration moderner Gesellschaften (1993), quoted in Habermas, ibid.
113
This point is also prompted by an observation made by John Braithwaite.
134 The Constitutional Corporation
Thus, the general meeting should seek assurances about the quality of the board’s
deliberations; the board should monitor the quality of deliberation by the
corporation’s managers; and both the board and management will want to ensure
that deliberation in the business world is properly informed so that directors and
managers receive effective feedback about their decisions.114
To make this picture more concrete, consider the range of possibilities
that might arise when there is an issue to be decided at the general meeting of a
public corporation. We can begin with two extremes. Some (perhaps many)
shareholders, through reasons of indifference or the pursuit of a passive investment
strategy, will have no input at all. This can be consistent with the ideals of good
corporate decision-making, provided that a shareholder’s decision not to participate
is voluntary, that the shareholder has been adequately informed about the proposed
decision and is aware that there are realistic opportunities for involvement.115 This
means that on any given issue, deliberation will be incomplete to the extent that not
all shareholders will have their say. At the other end of the spectrum, some
shareholders will have a direct and formal involvement in the decision-making
process at the general meeting. This is consistent with good corporate decision-
making provided that the processes at the meeting are open and genuine, as I
explained earlier in this Chapter. But it is what happens between these two
extremes that is of greater interest. A deliberative corporate decision-making
model should allow for other possibilities. On a given corporate issue we may be
able to distinguish between three other groups of shareholders.
First, for some shareholders involvement in the decision-making process
will be informal and peripheral to the formal process of decision-making. These
shareholders will monitor corporate issues, seek information, participate in
informal discussions, and, possibly, debates. However they will not seek to exert
any direct influence on the outcome, nor will they participate in a formal way in
the decision-making process. This may be due to lack of time or other resources, or
because (after consideration) the issue is not one they wish to pursue. This is
consistent with the ideals of good corporate decision-making, provided that the
formal processes of decision-making are receptive to inputs from this informal and
peripheral sphere of corporate discourse.
A second group of shareholders comprises those whose involvement in
the corporate decision is informal but influential. The impact of institutional
shareholders on corporate decision-making is the obvious example here. As I noted
in Chapter 4, many large shareholders prefer to keep in regular contact with their
portfolio corporations as a way of monitoring financial matters and management
issues.116 This is consistent with good corporate decision-making provided that it
114
This can be done, for example, through the continuous disclosure requirements, and via
company websites. The majority of large public companies in Australia now have
websites: Boros, above n 107, 502. A 2004 discussion paper released by the Business
Council of Australia urges greater use of websites by corporations: above n 104, 49.
115
The purpose of rules requiring notice of meetings and of resolutions to be passed at
meetings is to ensure that decisions are not made without the knowledge of members.
116
See Chapter 4 n 144 and accompanying text.
Corporate Decisions and Deliberation 135
does not preclude the involvement of other shareholders, and provided that it does
not define the decision-making agenda or outcome in a conclusive or exclusive
way.
Thirdly, there is a group of shareholders who will participate in a formal
but limited way, through the use of proxy votes. Proxy voting has some anti-
deliberative consequences. There is evidence in Australia that most shareholders
do not give their proxies discretion about how to cast the votes. The AGM study
found that in 88 per cent of corporations more than half of the shareholders who
gave proxies specified the way in which the proxy-holder should vote.117 In that
situation the shareholder’s vote is not susceptible to change in response to any
arguments that might be put at the general meeting. Where voting discretion is
granted by the shareholder, the proxy holder is usually the chairperson of the
meeting, meaning that the votes are nearly always cast in favour of board-initiated
resolutions and against shareholder-initiated resolutions. 118 Despite this, proxy
voting can nevertheless be consistent with deliberative decision-making, provided
that shareholders who choose to attend the meeting and vote in person are not
denied reasonable opportunities to ask questions and obtain explanations, and
provided that those voting by proxy have had the opportunity for some form of
deliberation prior to appointing their proxy.
The first of these two provisos means that the weight of proxy votes
should not be used as an excuse to truncate the consideration of arguments at the
general meeting. This might happen where the chairperson discloses the state of
the proxy votes on a proposal before there has been any discussion. Proxy votes
will usually determine the outcome of resolutions at a general meeting; for
example, the AGM study found that in 99 per cent of corporations, shareholders
participating by proxy constituted more than half of all voting shareholders, and in
48 per cent of corporations proxies accounted for over 90 per cent of the voting
shares represented at the meeting. 119 As I have emphasised, deliberation is not
about counting votes; it is about exposing arguments to question and influence, and
testing the strength of each argument and counter-argument. In Australia the
Corporations Act contains a replaceable rule that requires the chair to inform the
meeting before the vote is taken whether any proxy votes have been received and
how they are to be cast.120 This leaves open the possibility that proxies may be
revealed to the meeting before there has been any discussion on a proposed
resolution.121 The AGM study found a range of practices and opinions concerning
the timing of proxy disclosures in meetings, although most corporate officers
117
Above n 29, 28. Even so, a proxy who is not the chair of the meeting need not vote on a
show of hands or on a poll: Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) s 250A(4). The draft
Corporations Amendment Bill (No 2) 2006 proposes to amend this.
118
Stapledon et al, above n 88, 21.
119
Above n 29, 28.
120
Section 250J(1A).
121
The CASAC Final Report recommended that the question of when proxy voting details
should be disclosed should be left as a matter of discretion for the chair of the meeting:
above n 82, 57.
136 The Constitutional Corporation
indicated a preference for disclosure by the chair after discussion but before the
vote is taken.122
The second proviso carries two requirements. First, the information sent
out with the proxy voting forms should present the full range of arguments on each
resolution as far as they can be identified ahead of the meeting. There is some
indication in Australia that the courts will insist on this. In Fraser v NRMA Ltd the
Federal Court dealt with a claim that information sent to members of NRMA Ltd,
concerning the proposed demutualisation of the corporation, was false and
misleading under the Trade Practices Act 1974. The Court held that members
should receive information about the disadvantages as well as the advantages of the
demutualisation proposal:
the failure to identify and inform the members about disadvantages of which the
directors making the recommendation were aware was to leave the members in a
half light which had the potential to lead them to think that the unidentified
disadvantages, whatever they might be, must be ones that they would not treat as
significant ...123
The second requirement is that a proxy should be required by statute to cast the
proxy votes, and where the proxy has received directions on how to cast the votes,
to do so in accordance with those directions.124
Where a shareholder stands on this continuum of involvement will vary
from one corporation to another, and within a given corporation, from one issue to
the next. It will also vary depending on the type of shareholder: large institutional
shareholders are likely to be located closer to the centre of decision-making
because of their de facto power to influence outcomes.125 In contrast, individual or
retail shareholders are more likely to be involved only in the informal processes
that operate at the periphery. The task, as I have noted already, is to encourage
these peripheral processes of opinion formation and to ensure that they have an
impact on the processes of decision-making in the board room and the general
meeting.
122
Above n 29, 39 (interviews were conducted with officers from 21 corporations).
123
(1995) 15 ACSR 590, 621.
124
In Australia this would require the amendment of s 250A(4) of the Corporations Act
2001, as per the draft Corporations Amendment Bill (No 2) 2006.
125
See I Ramsay, G Stapledon, K Fong, ‘Corporate Governance: The Perspective of
Australian Institutional Shareholders’ (2000) 18 Companies & Securities Law Journal
110, reporting that intervention by institutional shareholders on corporate governance
issues is common. See the discussion in Chapter 4 at ns 141-151 and accompanying
text.
Corporate Decisions and Deliberation 137
Deliberation on the periphery requires that shareholders should have timely access
to relevant information about the corporation and the decisions that they are being
invited to make, and that there are means whereby they can then engage in
discussion about this information in ways that will come to the attention of the
decision-makers in the ‘inner spheres’.
There are well known obstacles confronting individual shareholders in
achieving these aims. The costs involved in obtaining, understanding and acting
upon corporate information will often exceed the benefits to the individual
shareholder, making it less likely that individual shareholders will seek it out
themselves. One way of responding to this, discussed in the corporate governance
literature, is to encourage the work of ‘information intermediaries’ who collect
corporate information, analyse it, and then publicise their conclusions or
recommendations for shareholders to act upon. Auditors play their part here, but
the primary role is played by the market analysts, proxy advisory services and
internet services mentioned previously. 126 There are, of course, issues to be
confronted in maintaining an effective system of information intermediaries,
including questions about who will, or should, pay for the supply of information.127
I want to focus, however, on an issue that has received less attention: what
shareholders do once they have received the information.
The common assumption is that armed with the information supplied by
intermediaries, shareholders will then be in a position to make informed individual
choices about exercising their votes, either directly or by proxy. This two-step
process — the supply of information followed by voting (or other action)128 —
either omits or downplays the possibility of deliberation as an intermediate step. In
what follows I consider some ways in which shareholders might be encouraged to
deliberate outside the parameters of the general meeting. This is not intended as an
exhaustive or a prescriptive list: my aim is simply to explore briefly some of the
possibilities and acknowledge some of the difficulties.
Internet discussion sites for shareholders provide one option. These might
be run by the corporation on its own web-page, or by shareholder associations or
activist groups. They permit the exchange of information and opinions about the
corporation and its performance. Caroline Bradley notes the many hundreds of
bulletin boards and chat rooms specialising in corporate and investment issues that
126
See above n 107 and accompanying text.
127
Shareholders are unlikely to supply sufficient levels of funding to ensure an adequate
supply of information. An alternative is for the corporation to pay. The issue then
becomes how to give shareholders a say in how the corporation directs this funding.
There are various proposals about how this might be achieved: see below n 145.
128
There is evidence that the ready availability of information via the internet has
prompted retail investors to engage in more active and speculative trading, rather than
retaining their shareholdings: B Barber and T Odean, ‘Online Investors: Do the Slow
Die First?’ (2002) 15 The Review of Financial Studies 455.
138 The Constitutional Corporation
are available through the Yahoo internet portal. 129 She also points out that
notwithstanding the proliferation of these sites, not all shareholders utilize this
access to online information:
some investors are more comfortable with new technology than others; some
investors have the financial resources to invest in computers and software that
others do not have (or would prefer to spend on investing than on
technology)…Investors may have different levels of ability to evaluate the
information they can obtain about their investments.130
129
C Bradley, ‘Online Financial Information: Law and Technological Change’ (2004) 26
Law and Policy 375, 388.
130
Ibid 380.
131
Bradley, ibid; see also D Kingsford Smith ‘Decentered Regulation in Online
Investment’ (2001) 19 Companies & Securities Law Journal 532, 535.
132
See, eg, Symposium on Online Investing and the Online Consumer (2004) 26 Law &
Policy.
133
Australian law imposes licensing requirements on any person who conducts an
investment advice business — see Corporations Act 2001 Pt 7.6.
134
Australian Securities and Investments Commission, Interim Policy Statement –
Exposure Draft: Internet Discussion Sites, IPS 162, 15 August 2000.
135
Stapledon notes that trade associations are active in the UK, describing some as major
players in areas of shareholder protection and corporate governance: G Stapledon,
Institutional Shareholders and Corporate Governance (1996) 49ff.
Corporate Decisions and Deliberation 139
136
For example the Friends of ANI, a group of small shareholders in Australian National
Industries Ltd, formed in late 1996 in response to issues raised at the company’s annual
general meeting. See B Frith, ‘Friends of ANI make good case for pooling of votes’
The Australian (Sydney), 27 November 1996.
137
The term is prompted by I Ayres and J Braithwaite, Responsive Regulation:
Transcending the Deregulation Debate (1992) 56.
138
Eg, Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) s 249Y; Canada Business Corporations Act, RSC
1985, s 152(2).
139
The NSW Henry George Foundation v Booth (2002) 20 ACLC 736, applying
Corporations Act 2001 s 249X. See also Canada Business Corporations Act, RSC
1985, s 148(1); Companies Act 1985 (UK) s 372(1).
140
The labels are taken from L Bebchuk and M Kahan, ‘A Framework for Analyzing
Legal Policy Towards Proxy Contests’ (1990) 78 California Law Review 1071.
141
I Ayres and J Braithwaite, Responsive Regulation: Transcending the Deregulation
Debate (1992) 57.
140 The Constitutional Corporation
The same policy could be applied in the case of discussions with a CIG and any
subsequent grant of a proxy to that CIG.
There are also practical issues. As with information intermediaries, a key
question is ‘who pays for the work done by CIGs’? Proxy solicitation can be
expensive. Some interest groups may be self-sustaining (because of their
commitment to a particular cause, for example). Others will require financial input.
For the same reasons that individual shareholders may decide not to exercise their
voting rights, they may not supply sufficient financial support to sustain a
competitive field of CIGs. A number of commentators have explored options that
involve the provision of funding to intermediary groups by the corporation itself,
with the final allocation being determined by the shareholders (eg by resolution at
a general meeting, or through the operation of a voucher system).145 The idea of
corporate funding of CIGs is not as novel as it may first seem: corporations already
pay for or subsidise certain forms of intermediary activity, for example through
142
See, eg, the requirement for a ‘proxy circular’ in Canada Business Corporations Act,
RSC 1985, s 150.
143
Rules governing takeovers and substantial shareholdings are examples, eg
Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) Chapter 6 (takeovers), Chapter 6C (substantial
shareholdings). The Corporations Act excludes proxies from the associate and relevant
interest provisions which form the basis of the takeover and substantial shareholder
provisions ss 16, 609(5).
144
Australian Securities and Investments Commission, Collective action by institutional
investors, Policy Statement 128, 14 January 1998.
145
See T Baums and P von Randow, ‘Shareholder Voting and Corporate Governance: The
German Experience and a New Approach’ in M Aoki and H-K Kim (eds), Corporate
Governance in Transitional Economies: Insider Control and the Role of Banks (1995)
405; S Choi and J Fisch, ‘How to Fix Wall Street: A Voucher Financing Proposal for
Securities Intermediaries’ (2003) 113 Yale Law Journal 269; M Latham, ‘Democracy
and Infomediaries’ (2003) 11 Corporate Governance 91.
Corporate Decisions and Deliberation 141
Conclusion
146
Eg Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) s 249O; Companies Act 1985 (UK) s 376;
147
See Business Council of Australia, above n 104, 19-20 (describing this practice in
Australian corporations).
148
The CASAC Final Report rejected the idea of advisory resolutions – see above n 82,
37. The Corporations Act 2001 has since been amended to require an advisory
resolution prior to the adoption of the remuneration report at a listed company’s AGM
(s 250R(2) and (3)).
This page intentionally left blank
Chapter 6
1
Examples can be found throughout corporate law statutes, including general meeting
approval mechanisms for reductions of share capital, share buy backs, and financial
assistance transactions.
144 The Constitutional Corporation
interested rule, or when an absence of debate or protest is misinterpreted as implied
consent.
The law’s response to the possibility of these problems is to impose
standards on decision-makers in particular circumstances and to require procedures
aimed at ensuring that each member’s consent continues as informed and that
majority voting power is exercised properly. For example, as I noted in previous
Chapters, corporate statutes impose mandatory disclosure and reporting
requirements and courts impose proper purpose requirements on majority
shareholders in certain instances. 2 These processes and standards are clearly
necessary but, equally clearly, they have a limited capacity to protect shareholders
(or directors) from the risk of arbitrary or self-interested behaviour by others.
A further legitimating mechanism is needed, and an appropriate
mechanism is found in the idea of contestability, which I have taken from Philip
Pettit’s work on republican political theory.3 In the remainder of this part of the
Chapter I explain the idea of contestability in more detail, and I explore how the
idea of contestability affirms the importance of shareholder ‘voice’ alongside the
‘exit’ as an appropriate response to corporate problems. In subsequent parts of the
Chapter I examine how corporate law already recognises the importance of
contestability, and how these existing mechanisms might be improved or given
greater effect.
2
For example, Gambotto v WCP Ltd (1995) 13 ACLC 342 (proper purpose and fairness
requirements when corporate constitution is amended in order to expropriate minority
shares).
3
Particularly P Pettit, Republicanism (1997); ‘Republican Freedom and Contestatory
Democracy’ in I Shapiro and C Hacker-Cordón (eds), Democracy’s Value (1999) 163;
‘Democracy, Electoral and Contestatory’ in I Shapiro and S Macedo (eds), Designing
Democratic Institutions: Nomos 42 (2000) 105.
4
Pettit’s idea of contestability is developed by reference to decision-making in larger
political communities. It therefore has different components and goes further than
contestability in a corporate context.
5
Although my focus is on contestation by members, in some instances a director may
want to contest a decision made by directors and members. In Talbot v NRMA Ltd
(2000) 18 ACLC 600 the court stated that before taking such a step, a director must
believe that the litigation will be in the corporation’s best interests and that he or she
would be in breach of his or her duties by not taking the action.
6
Compare Pettit Republicanism, above n 3, 63 and 184-185.
Contesting Corporate Decisions 145
that we want a form of decision-making that shareholders can ‘own and identify
with’ and in which they can see their interests furthered and their ideas respected.7
There is an important difference between this idea and the more
commonly encountered argument that those who control corporate decision-
making must be given incentives, through the threat of legal action, to act in the
best interests of the corporation. 8 The incentive argument is concerned with
persuading directors and managers to act in accordance with the shareholders’
interests by deterring undesirable managerial behaviour. Deterrence is said to work
either specifically, where legal action is brought against directors or managers for
actual instances of misbehavior, or generally, where the prospect or possibility of
legal action deters managers from misconduct. Either form of deterrence requires
that directors and managers should be monitored so that shareholders will know
when to take action. Moreover, the directors must know or suspect that they are
being monitored so that they are aware of the risk of action being taken. The
incentive/deterrence argument therefore takes the perspective of the directors and
managers. It is concerned with achieving decision-making legitimacy by
monitoring and controlling the actions of directors and managers who, it is
presumed, are otherwise apt to misbehave. As we will see later in this Chapter,
while the incentive/deterrence argument cannot be discounted it is difficult to
measure the extent to which it works in practice, and its effect is easy to overstate.
Recognising this, the argument developed here emphasises another reason
for insisting on contestability, one that is concerned with the legitimacy of
corporate decision-making processes as perceived by the shareholders. The
contestability argument emphasises that shareholders should know that action can
be taken if their interests are not being tracked. As a consequence shareholders can
have a measure of confidence in the decision-making process, and they will be
more likely to view that process as legitimate.9 This means that the contestation of
corporate decisions must be a real option for shareholders, and that avenues for
contestation not be overly restrictive, too cumbersome or remote.
There are four further points of clarification. First, contestability does not
mean giving each shareholder a right of veto over corporate business, and it does
not mean that minority interests must always be satisfied. Courts have confirmed
repeatedly that there is nothing oppressive about being a minority shareholder.10
Merely being out-voted on an issue does not activate the idea of contestability —
but having one’s interests (including interests in proper and fair decision-making
7
Ibid 184.
8
The managerial incentive argument has been adopted by many commentators on
derivative suit legislation, especially those writing from a law and economics
perspective. See, eg, D Fischel and M Bradley, ‘The Role of Liability Rules and the
Derivative Suit in Corporate Law: A Theoretical and Empirical Analysis’ (1986) 71
Cornell Law Review 261; R Romano, ‘The Shareholder Suit: Litigation Without
Foundation?’ (1991) 7 Journal of Law, Economics and Organization 55.
9
This aspect of the argument relies on Tom Tyler’s work on the importance of
perceptions about procedural fairness: see Chapter 5 n 24 and accompanying text.
10
See, eg, Re G Jeffrey (Mens Store) Pty Ltd (1984) 9 ACLR 193.
146 The Constitutional Corporation
procedures) improperly excluded from consideration does. Even then, as Pettit
notes, ‘not every contestation can be satisfied’; 11 the legitimate interests of a
dissenting shareholder (or group of shareholders) may properly be judged to be
secondary to the wider interests of the corporation.
Secondly, there need not be contestation of every corporate decision. For
one thing, actual contestation is not a necessary precondition to demonstrating that
all relevant interests have been tracked by a decision. What is required is that as
decisions are being made the possibility of contestation is realistic and that this is
understood by all involved. As Pettit says, what is important is ‘the possibility of
contestation’. 12 Furthermore, too much contestation would make corporate
operations unworkable. Corporations, perhaps more so than the wider political
systems at which Pettit’s argument is directed, are susceptible to the adverse
consequences of frivolous or vexatious challenges. These consequences include
financial costs, lost business opportunities, and damage to a corporation’s
reputation.
One way in which the risk of needless contestation can be avoided is by
ensuring that decision-making processes are properly open and deliberative in the
first place. Contestability is about ensuring that the corporation tracks the interests
and ideas of its members, and so those interests must be brought to the attention of
the decision-makers in the organisation. A key purpose of deliberation — as I
argued in Chapter 5 — is to give those who will be affected by a decision the
opportunity to inject their particular interests and ideas into the decision-making
process. In effect, deliberation can operate as a form of contestation prior to a
decision being reached.13 Another way of avoiding, or at least reducing, the adverse
consequences of unnecessary contestation is to encourage the use of options such
as general meetings rather than immediate use of options such as court process. I
explain this idea shortly.
The third point of clarification is that despite my reference to corporate
decisions as the focal point of contestation, it is just as feasible that a failure to
make decisions or to take action should be contestable. Patterns of managerial
behaviour that ignore or avoid relevant interests can give rise to the same concerns
as arbitrary or improper decisions and so should be subject to the corrective
influence that the possibility of contestation supplies.
Fourthly, it should not be thought that contestability is limited to the
pursuit of shareholders’ individual interests or the protection of their personal
rights. As will be seen later in this Chapter when I look at the statutory derivative
action, contestability can be concerned to protect the corporate interest in situations
where there is little or no immediate gain to the person who initiates the
contestation.
Contestability is important to the legitimacy of the corporate
constitutional system because it offers those who are in the minority the prospect
that a fairer or better result is achievable. It offers the possibility of change and
11
Pettit, Republicanism above n 3, 197.
12
Ibid 185.
13
Pettit, ‘Democracy, Electoral and Contestatory’, above n 3, 122.
Contesting Corporate Decisions 147
thus contributes to a sense that the corporate system merits support, despite any
perceived flaws. More importantly, a system that is open to the possibility of
change is more likely to command the respect of its participants than one that
appears to stand ‘pat, smug and self-satisfied’.14
… any attempt at all to change, rather than to escape from, an objectionable state
of affairs, whether through individual or collective petition to the management
directly in charge, through appeal to a higher authority with the intention of
forcing a change in management, or through various types of actions and protests,
including those that are meant to mobilize public opinion.16
Hirschman notes that there is a strong alignment between exit and economic
behaviour on the one hand, and voice and political behaviour on the other. Exit
involves shareholders using the market to defend or improve their position:
[Exit] is the sort of mechanism economics thrives on. It is neat – one either exits
or one does not; it is impersonal – any face-to-face confrontation … with its
imponderable and unpredictable elements is avoided and success and failure of the
organization are communicated by a set of statistics; and it is indirect – any
recovery on the part of the declining firm comes by courtesy of the Invisible
Hand…17
14
The quote and the argument in this paragraph comes from J Balkin, ‘Respect-Worthy:
Frank Michelman and the Legitimate Constitution’ (2004) 39 Tulsa Law Review 485,
496.
15
Albert O Hirschman, Exit, Voice, and Loyalty: Responses to Decline in Firms,
Organizations and States (1970).
16
Ibid 30.
17
Ibid 15-16.
18
Ibid 33 and 76. Exit is not always an easy option. Large or institutional shareholders
cannot readily liquidate or transfer their holdings. Small shareholders must consider the
costs of brokerage fees and other transaction costs.
148 The Constitutional Corporation
defence of one’s position. Hirschman describes voice as ‘political action par
excellence’.19
Voicing one’s concerns requires time and planning, and involves some
level of face-to-face interaction. The exercise of voice will therefore be
conditioned by the influence and bargaining power which shareholders estimate
that they can bring to bear on the corporation, and by the members’ willingness to
trade the certainty of exit for the uncertainties of improvement due to voice.20 As
Hirschman observes, in large business corporations the availability of the exit
option tends to drive out the voice option; voice is the subsidiary mode of
reaction.21
Provided that voice is a genuine option, I suggest that this balance
between exit and voice is appropriate. In fact it is necessitated by the business
environment in which most public corporations operate, taking into account the
necessary division of managerial functions, the need for directors to discharge the
managerial oversight function that shareholders have given to them, and the need
for managers to get on with the day-to-day job of management. And exiting a
corporation can, depending on the circumstances, send powerful signals to the
market and to the corporation’s managers about shareholder sentiment. In this
sense, exit can be an indirect means of voicing concerns. But this does not mean
that corporate law should ignore or abandon the direct exercise of voice, or that the
importance of voice options should be down-played. The task is to ensure that ‘the
art of voice’ (to use Hirschman’s phrase) 22 is not lost or underestimated. Why
should corporate law be built upon the presumption that shareholders are always
looking for reasons to exit the corporation? Why not allow for the possibility that
sometimes — perhaps quite often23 — shareholders have reasons to stay with a
corporation and, perhaps, voice their concerns in an effort to change the
corporation’s performance or behaviour? Why should we construct our corporate
law system around the assumption that exit is the best option, rather than allowing
for the possibility of voice?
19
Ibid 16.
20
Ibid 77.
21
Ibid 76.
22
Ibid 31.
23
Evidence in Australia suggests that many individual shareholders are not active market
traders. A survey found that 49 per cent of shareholders had not engaged in any trading
(selling or buying) during 2003; the other 51 per cent of shareholders had an average of
six trades during the same period: Australian Stock Exchange, 2003 Australian Share
Ownership Study (2004).
Contesting Corporate Decisions 149
contestation can be counterproductive. One way of responding to both of these
concerns is to have available a range of contestability options.
Corporate law is quite familiar with court-based forms of contestation.
These include the shareholders’ action for oppressive or unfair conduct, 24 the
statutory derivative action, 25 and actions for the protection of class rights. 26 But
corporate contestation does not always have to begin or end in the courtroom. An
over-reliance on judicial forums for contestation might, conceivably, have adverse
effects. For example, faced with too great an emphasis on external challenge and
review, a board of directors might develop a ‘groupthink’ mentality that fails to
explore alternatives and is not sufficiently critical about the performance of
individual members. 27 Conversely, a board might adopt an ‘every person for
themselves’ approach which impedes the interpersonal relationships that foster
good group decision-making.28
A system of corporate contestability can encourage shareholders to
consider non-judicial options, at least as a first resort. Depending on the nature of
the disagreement,29 other forms of contestation include: questioning directors and
senior managers at general meetings; proposing resolutions for consideration at the
annual general meeting; 30 or complaining to the relevant regulatory agency and
asking it to take action.31 The nature of the contestation — how it is conducted,
who controls the process, who decides the outcome, and what range of outcomes is
possible — varies with these different options. This will be another factor in the
choice of contestability method. With options such as courts, tribunals and resort to
regulatory agencies, the contestation becomes more public and control over the
outcome is removed from the hands of those whose actions are the subject of
complaint. There is an increased prospect of a final decision that is independent of
the self-interest of the contestants, and of an outcome ‘in which relevant interests
are taken equally into account and only impartially supported decisions are
24
In Australia, Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) Part 2F.1.
25
In Australia, Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) Part 2F.1A.
26
In Australia, Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) Part 2F.2.
27
As summarised by Bainbridge, the term ‘groupthink’ describes the psychological
phenomenon where ‘cohesive groups with strong civility and cooperation norms value
consensus more than they do a realistic appraisal of alternatives…[These] groups may
strive for unanimity even at the expense of quality decision-making.’ S Bainbridge,
‘Why a Board? Group Decisionmaking in Corporate Governance’ (2002) 55 Vanderbilt
Law Review 1, 32.
28
Ibid 49-50.
29
Other factors include the size and distribution of the shareholding in the corporation.
30
Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) s 249N (members with 5 per cent of total votes or 100
members may give notice of a resolution to be moved at a general meeting).
31
This option may have limited utility. A study of the court-based enforcement patterns of
the Australian Securities and Investments Commission found that penal enforcement
predominated over civil enforcement: H Bird, D Chow, J Lenne and I Ramsay, ‘ASIC
Enforcement Patterns’ (Research Report, Centre for Corporate Law and Securities
Regulation, The University of Melbourne, 2003).
150 The Constitutional Corporation
upheld’.32 This does not, however, rule out the use of ‘in-house’ options, such as
questioning at a general meeting. Recall that the underlying idea of contestability is
to encourage the deliberative resolution of issues against the background
possibility that other more independent and more public modes can always be
invoked. In this light ‘in house’ forms of contestation may produce effective results.
In the remainder of this Chapter I examine ‘in house’ and external forms
of corporate contestation. I do this by looking at how the idea has played out in
recent debates concerning extraordinary general meetings (an instance of ‘in-
house’ contestability), and the statutory derivative action (a form of court-based
contestation).
General meetings are not impartial forums of review and, as was seen in Chapter 5,
the course of deliberation at a general meeting can be constrained and manipulated.
Nevertheless, there are several reasons why it might be appropriate for contestation
to take place via a general meeting. The issue being contested may be one of
internal or commercial policy for which the law provides no effective remedy.
Even where legal remedies are available, disaffected shareholders may still prefer
to keep the matter ‘in house’ for reasons such as cost or to reduce reputational
damage to the corporation. Deliberating a matter within the corporation may help
to define the problem more clearly. Further, as I noted in Chapter 5,33 despite low
attendance by shareholders, many directors do take the threat of critical
questioning at a general meeting seriously. Finally, the courts continue to express a
long-held preference for the resolution of internal corporate disputes via general
meetings. As Lindley LJ put it in Isle of Wight Railway Company v Tahourdin,
‘this Court has constantly and consistently refused to interfere on behalf of
shareholders, until they have done the best they can to set right the matters of
which they complain, by calling general meetings’. 34 Much more recently,
Campbell J in the Supreme Court of New South Wales said that:
Questions of what is, or is not, in the interests of the members as whole are often
best left to be decided by the officers, organs and procedures of the company
itself, or by the court deciding, after events have happened, whether those events
fall short of a legally required standard of conduct…35
With these points in mind, I want to look at the clearest instance where a general
meeting can be used as a form of contestation: the right of members to require that
32
Pettit, Democracy’s Value, above n 3, 179.
33
See Chapter 5, n 104 and accompanying text.
34
(1884) 25 Ch D 320, 333; cited in NRMA v Parkin (2004) 22 ACLC 861, 868.
35
Turnbull v NRMA (2004) 22 ACLC 1094, 1105.
Contesting Corporate Decisions 151
an extraordinary (or special) general meeting of the corporation be convened. This
has been a topic of some debate in Australian corporate governance law reform.36
36
See below n 43 to 48 and accompanying text.
37
See Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) s 249D; Companies Act 1985 (UK) s 368; Revised
Model Business Corporations Act §7.02 (2002). While it is the directors’ responsibility
to call the meeting, it is the corporation which holds the meeting: ASIC v NRMA (2003)
21 ACLC 186, 190. In Australia it is also possible for the members to call and convene
a general meeting themselves, bearing the costs (s 249F).
38
Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) s 249Q.
39
NRMA v Parker (1986) 4 ACLC 609 (members cannot pass a resolution that purports to
control the exercise of power vested in the board of directors).
40
John J Starr (Real Estate) Pty Ltd v Robert R Andrew (Australasia) Pty Ltd (1991) 6
ACSR 63, 84.
41
Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) s 249E; Companies Act 1985 (UK) s 368(4)-(6).
42
As occurred with North Ltd in June 1999.
43
As occurred with Wesfarmers Ltd in July 1999, and Gunns Ltd in February 2003.
44
Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) s 249D(1). Prior to 1998, the statute required each of the
100 members to have an average paid-up capital of at least $200. In the UK the
152 The Constitutional Corporation
the statute be amended to make the sole criterion for requisitioning an
extraordinary general meeting that the requisitioning members hold five per cent of
the issued share capital.45 This recommendation was endorsed one year later by the
Companies and Securities Advisory Committee (CASAC). 46 The Parliamentary
Committee accepted arguments against the 100 members rule that were put by
some prominent publicly-listed corporations (including the mining corporations
Rio Tinto Ltd and North Ltd, and the large retailer Coles Myer Ltd) and by
organisations such as the Law Council of Australia, the Investment and Financial
Services Association Ltd,47 the Business Council of Australia, and the Australian
Institute of Company Directors. These arguments can be summarised as follows:
the 100 members rule is too easily satisfied, with the result that shareholders with
only a nominal or insignificant economic interest in a corporation can put the
corporation and other shareholders to the cost and disruption of holding a meeting,
distracting directors and managers from their core functions. Furthermore, the
procedure is open to abuse by disgruntled minorities, single-issue groups and
activists who are motivated by concerns that are at odds with the financial interests
of the corporation. Similarly, the CASAC recommendation was based on the
argument that eliminating the 100 members rule would ensure that ‘the cost of
convening an extraordinary general meeting is only incurred when it is
requisitioned by shareholders who collectively have a material economic interest in
the company’.48 The inability of would-be requisitioners to satisfy the remaining
five per cent shareholding test ‘would call into serious question the prospects of
their proposed resolution succeeding’. 49 In early 2005 the Federal Government
released the draft of its proposed amendments for public consultation, in which the
100 members rule was removed. 50 Following public hearings, a Parliamentary
requisitioning members must hold a minimum of ten per cent of the paid-up voting
shares in the corporation: Companies Act 1985 (UK) s 368(2); the Company Law
Review Steering Group, Final Report, Volume 1 (June 2001) recommended that this be
retained: 153-156.
45
Joint Committee on Corporations and Securities, Parliament of Australia, Report on
Matters Arising From the Company Law Review Act 1998 (1999) 164.
46
Companies and Securities Advisory Committee (CASAC), Shareholder Participation
in the Modern Listed Public Company (June 2000).
47
The Investment and Financial Services Association Ltd represents most major
institutional investors in Australia.
48
CASAC, above n 46, 11-12.
49
Ibid 12.
50
Corporations Amendment Bill (No. 2) 2005 Exposure Draft. Prior to this, in April 2000
the Federal Government introduced a regulation (under s 249D(1A)) that reflected these
recommendations. The regulation was disallowed by the Senate in June 2000. In
response the Federal Minister for Financial Services and Regulation released a proposal
in December 2000 that retained the five per cent requirement but added, as an
alternative, a minimum number requirement calculated as the square root of the total
number of shareholders in the corporation. The proposal was later withdrawn from
consideration.
Contesting Corporate Decisions 153
Committee recommended that this be enacted and in December 2005 the
Government announced its intention to proceed in this way.51
Despite these reforms, there is no evidence, in Australia at least, of
widespread ‘abuse’ of the right to requisition a general meeting. The AGM study
referred to in Chapter 5 found in a sample of 217 corporations that there were only
five extraordinary general meetings requisitioned by shareholders in the four years
between July 1998 and June 2002.52 The 1999 Parliamentary Committee inquiry
heard (but chose not to act on) submissions from organisations including the
Institute of Chartered Accountants in Australia, the Australian Society of Certified
Practicing Accountants, and the Association of Superannuation Funds of Australia
Ltd that the 100 members rule had not given rise to any significant problems, and
that the threshold was in fact difficult to achieve (the latter argument being put by
shareholder groups in certain corporations, such as the Boral Green Shareholders,
Amcor Green Shareholders, BHP Shareholders for Social Responsibility, and
North Ethical Shareholders). Concerns about the disruptive potential of the 100
members rule overlook the fact that it is just as feasible for a corporation to be
needlessly disrupted by the self-interest of a single shareholder who controls a five
per cent parcel (or more) of shares. Indeed, the impact of either the five per cent
rule or the 100 members rule varies depending on the total number of shareholders
in the corporation. For example, in a corporation with 1000 members the five per
cent rule is more easily satisfied than the 100 members rule. The reverse is true for
a corporation with more than 2,000 members. 53 There is, in other words, no
‘correct’ threshold requirement that can apply to all corporations and in all
situations.
The debate about the threshold is really one about control over
management of the corporation, and about the proper place of shareholders in that
process. The arguments for a more restrictive threshold have strong echoes of the
political arguments put by Joseph Schumpeter and Max Weber (discussed in
Chapter 4)54 according to which the job of voters is to elect their leaders and then
refrain from interfering with the job of running the polity. In the corporate context
this is translated into the maxim ‘let the managers manage’ or, in the specific
context of the debate about the 100 members rule, ‘let only those voters with
significant economic interests have a say’.
In the absence of any evidence that the 100 members threshold is being
abused in any significant way there is no reason to change it. Indeed, the fact that it
51
Joint Committee on Corporations and Financial Services, Parliament of Australia,
Inquiry into the Exposure Draft of the Corporations Amendment Bill (No. 2) 2005
(2005) 6; Hon. Chris Pearce MP, ‘Pearce Announces Corporate Governance Reforms’
(Press Release, 8 December 2005).
52
S Bottomley, The Role of Shareholders’ Meetings in Improving Corporate Governance
(Research Report, Centre for Commercial Law, Australian National University, 2003)
47.
53
M Whincop, ‘The Role of The Shareholder in Corporate Governance: A Theoretical
Approach’ (2001) 25 Melbourne University Law Review 418, 449.
54
See Chapter 4, n 46 to 55 and accompanying text.
154 The Constitutional Corporation
attracts the attention of corporate managers demonstrates its usefulness in
contestability terms. Recall, it is the factual possibility of contestation 55 that
provides the legitimating mechanism for corporate decisions. A threshold that is
perceived (with or without any empirical basis) to be too low or too ‘easy’ can
supply a constraining effect on managerial behaviour. More significantly, the 100
members threshold appeared to achieve the right balance between offering a
realistic avenue for contestation (to the extent that the 100 members rule is easily
met) while not resulting in over use of this contestability option (as evidenced by
its low level of use).
Many countries make statutory provision for a derivative action (SDA),57 allowing
a person to commence proceedings on behalf of a corporation against those who
have caused harm to the corporation in a situation where the corporation is unable
or unwilling to bring the action itself. 58 The SDA is used to pursue the
corporation’s interests, with any remedy that is awarded by the court going to the
corporation. The standard case arises where directors have breached their duties
causing loss to the corporation, with the board declining to cause the corporation to
bring an action to recover that loss. More generally, the SDA is appropriate where
the majority’s control of the corporation prevents the minority from effective
contestation through internal means such as the general meeting.
The statutory provision of a right of derivative action thus provides a
mechanism for contestation, emphasising the exercise of ‘voice’ rather than the use
of ‘exit’. However, as I will argue, while it is necessary for good corporate
governance the SDA works best by not being used with great frequency.
55
Pettit, Republicanism, above n 3, 185.
56
This part develops ideas from S Bottomley, ‘The Relative Importance of the Statutory
Derivative Action in Australia’ in F Macmillan (ed) International Corporate Law
Annual Vol 2 (2003) 141-166.
57
B Welling, Corporate Law in Canada: The Governing Principles (2nd ed, 1991) 534
and 544, prefers the term ‘representative actions’. Similarly Wedderburn describes this
form of action as representative: K W Wedderburn, ‘Shareholders’ Rights and the Rule
in Foss v Harbottle’ [1957] Cambridge Law Journal 194 and [1958] Cambridge Law
Journal 93.
58
Eg Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) ss 236-242; Canada Business Corporations Act, RSC
1985, s 239; in New Zealand the Companies Act 1993 (NZ) ss 165-168. In the United
Kingdom the Company Law Reform Bill, introduced in November 2005, makes
provision for a derivative action. In the United States provisions for derivative actions
are found in State corporations legislation, with variations between States. Rule 23.1 of
the Federal Rules of Civil Procedure regulates derivative actions brought in federal
courts; it is also a model for some State statutes: L Ribstein, Business Associations, (2nd
ed, 1990) 578. The American Law Institute’s Principles of Corporate Governance
(1994) Part VII contain standards and procedures for derivative actions.
Contesting Corporate Decisions 155
The Statutory Derivative Action in Australia
In this section I use the Australian legislation to outline the main features of the
SDA. This will set the basis for assessing the role of the SDA as a mechanism for
contestability.
In Australia the SDA expressly replaces the limited and uncertain
common law rules regarding the availability of derivative actions as exceptions to
the rule in Foss v Harbottle.59 The statute defines a derivative action as one in
which a person either brings proceedings on behalf of and in the name of a
corporation, or intervenes in proceedings to which the corporation is a party for the
purpose of taking responsibility for those proceedings on behalf of, and in the
name of, the corporation. This can be done by a current or former member of the
corporation or a related body corporate (or someone entitled to be registered as a
member), or by a current or former officer of the company.60
The statute does not define or limit the type of matter which can be the
subject of a derivative action.61 The only prerequisite to commencing a derivative
action is obtaining leave from the court. The court must grant leave if five criteria
are all satisfied.62 The criteria are as follows:
1. It is probable that the corporation will not bring the proceedings itself
or take responsibility for them. One way of determining this is to look at how the
board of directors has responded if the applicant has served on the corporation a
notice of intention to apply for leave (discussed at point five, below). Another
factor to take into account is the extent to which any decision by the corporation
against commencing an action has been influenced by the people whose conduct is
the subject of the potential derivative suit.
2. The applicant is acting in good faith. The purpose of this requirement is
to rule out suits in which the applicant’s substantive goal is a personal rather than a
corporate remedy. The applicant must demonstrate an honest belief that there is a
good cause of action that has a reasonable prospect of success, and that there is no
59
Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) s 236(2). The rule in Foss v Harbottle (1843) 2 Hare 461;
67 ER 189 states that (i) the corporation is the proper plaintiff in any situation in which
a wrong is alleged to be done to the corporation, and (ii) the actions which constitute
the alleged wrongdoing can be made binding on the corporation by a majority vote at a
general meeting of shareholders. The classic discussion of the rule and its exceptions is
found in Wedderburn, above n 56.
60
See Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) s 236. An officer is defined to include a director,
secretary, executive officer or employee of the company (s 82A).
61
This is similar to Canada and New Zealand. In contrast the UK Company Law Reform
Bill Law (see above n 58) restricts the statutory derivative action to breaches of
directors’ duties or directors’ negligence: cl 239(3).
62
Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) s 237(2). The Canada Business Corporations Act, RSC
1985, s 239(2) specifies three criteria, similar to points 2, 3 and 5 in the text. In New
Zealand the Companies Act 1993 specifies either criterion 1 or 3 as alternative
prerequisites to bringing a derivative action: s 165(3). The UK Bill (see above n 58)
lists five criteria, three of which are similar to points 1, 2 and 3 in the text (proposed s
242(3)).
156 The Constitutional Corporation
collateral purpose in bringing the action.63 To the extent that this catches frivolous
or vexatious suits, this overlaps with the ‘serious question’ criterion, discussed at
point four below.
3. It is in the corporation’s best interests for the court to grant leave.64
This criterion lies at the heart of the derivative action because it is the corporation’s
separate and independent interests which are at stake rather than those of the
applicant or any group of directors or shareholders.65 Welling’s description of the
equivalent Canadian provision puts it nicely: ‘what the complainant is really doing
is presenting the court with ‘a corporation in need of protection’.66 This criterion
encourages the court to regard the corporation ‘as a continuing concern which must
encompass the interests of past, present and future shareholders, creditors and (one
would hope) employees’. 67 It is not left to either the board of directors or the
general meeting of shareholders to decide what is in the corporation’s best interests.
While the views of these two groups are clearly relevant, the corporation’s interests
in commencing legal action are a matter for judicial determination, taking into
account the character of the corporation, its business (if any), whether redress can
be achieved by other means, and whether the defendant can meet any judgement
made in the corporation’s favour. 68 This emphasises the point that corporate
governance is not to be regarded solely as a matter of private intra-corporate
agreement.
The ‘best interests’ criterion has a further implication. Even if the
corporation has suffered a wrong which could, in theory, be subject of a derivative
suit, it may nevertheless not be in the corporate interest for action to be taken. For
example, it may be that the benefit to the corporation of the potential remedy will
be significantly outweighed by the financial or reputational costs of the action.69 It
may also be that the actions of the directors, whilst constituting a breach of duty,
have not had a material effect on the corporation.
4. There is a serious question to be tried. This criterion is intended to
import the test which is used regularly by Australian courts in determining interim
injunction applications. 70 In other words, the court must determine whether the
applicant’s claim is frivolous or vexatious, whether it has a real prospect of
succeeding, and whether the balance of convenience favours granting leave.71
63
Swansson v Pratt (2002) ACLC 1594, 1601.
64
In Canada the Court must be satisfied that the proposed action ‘appears to be’ in the
corporation’s interests: Canada Business Corporations Act, RSC 1985, s 239(2)(c). In
New Zealand the Court must ‘have regard to’ the interests of the corporation:
Companies Act 1993 s 165(2).
65
Charlton v Baber (2003) 21 ACLC 1671.
66
Welling, above n 57, 535.
67
M A Maloney, ‘Whither the Statutory Derivative Action?’ [1986] 64 Canadian Bar
Review 309, 328.
68
Swansson v Pratt (2002) 20 ACLC 1594, 1604-1605.
69
Metyor Inc v Queensland Electronic Switching Pty Ltd (2002) 20 ACLC 1517, 1523.
70
Explanatory Memorandum, Corporate Law Economic Reform Bill 1998 (Cth) para
6.46.
71
Nicholas John Holdings Pty Ltd v ANZ Banking Group Ltd [1992] 2 VR 715, 722-723.
Contesting Corporate Decisions 157
5. Whether the applicant has notified the corporation of the application.
Although this is the last criterion in the list, as a matter of procedure it precedes the
others. Before applying for leave, the applicant should give the corporation
fourteen days written notice of the intention to apply, together with the reasons for
the application. Obviously this notice will give the board of directors the
opportunity to decide whether the corporation should commence the action in its
own right, thereby avoiding the need for a derivative suit. Alternatively, receipt of
the notice might lead to the settlement of the dispute out of court, thereby avoiding
the need for any litigation. The Court may still grant leave in the absence of such
notice provided that it is ‘appropriate’ to do so,72 and provided that the other four
criteria have been satisfied. This will be appropriate where giving notice ‘is not
practical or expedient, thus allowing for an ex parte hearing where there is a need
for urgent litigation’.73
Neither the right to apply for leave to commence a derivative action, nor
the right to bring the action once leave has been granted, is determined by the fact
that a majority of shareholders in the corporation has voted to ratify or approve the
conduct in question.74 The court may take a ratification into account in deciding
what order to make in the leave application or in the resulting proceedings, but it
must be satisfied that the ratification or approval was well-informed and that the
members were acting for proper purposes. This reverses the common law position
in which a proper ratification by members had the effect of negating the possibility
of derivative suit.75 The message here is that the principle of majority rule does not
necessarily provide a justification for corporate actions, and that ‘in some
circumstances judicial action is preferable to action by the shareholders’.76
There are two rationales that are commonly given for providing shareholders with
a right of derivative action.77 One is that the SDA is concerned with compensating
the corporation for harm that has been caused by corporate wrong-doers. The
second rationale is that the derivative action deters directors and managers from
wrongful or improper behaviour. Commentators seem to agree that, of these two
rationales, ‘[d]eterrence is the major reason for and principal effect of derivative
72
Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) s 237(2)(e).
73
Explanatory Memorandum, Corporate Law Economic Reform Bill 1998 (Cth) para
6.50.
74
Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) s 239. The Canada Business Corporations Act, RSC
1985, s 242 is similar. In contrast the proposal in the UK is that the court must refuse
leave if the act or omission has been ratified: Company Law Reform Bill cl 242(2).
75
Hogg v Cramphorn [1967] Ch 254.
76
Companies and Securities Advisory Committee, Report on a Statutory Derivative
Action, July 1993, 21.
77
J Coffee and D Schwartz, ‘The Survival of the Derivative Suit: An Evaluation and a
Proposal for Legislative Reform’ (1981) 81 Columbia Law Review 261, 302-309.
158 The Constitutional Corporation
suits’.78 This is not to say that compensation is an ‘illusory or insignificant goal’.79
Indeed it has been emphasised by the courts; in Karam v ANZ Banking Group Ltd,
for example, Santow J noted that ‘the statutory derivative action … was intended to
be remedial’. 80 However, the argument goes that the SDA is an imperfect
compensation device because, for example, of the dissonance between the
corporation’s gains and losses and those of the shareholders. Deterrence was
certainly the accepted motivation behind the Australian reforms. The 1999
legislative amendments which enacted the SDA were based on a recommendation
of the Federal Government’s Corporate Law Economic Reform Program
(CLERP). 81 They were apparently introduced as a trade-off for shareholders in
light of the enactment of a statutory business judgement rule that was intended to
protect directors. The policy and concerns which underpinned the CLERP
recommendation can be seen in the following passage:
78
D Schwartz, ‘In Praise of Derivative Suits: A Commentary on the Paper of Professors
Fischel and Bradley’ (1986) 71 Cornell Law Review 322, 331. See also Coffee and
Schwartz, ibid, 302.
79
Coffee and Schwartz, above n 77, 305. Compensation supplies the primary rationale
when, as in some Australian cases, the SDA is brought by shareholders of a corporation
that is in liquidation to recover property – see, eg, Charlton v Baber (2003) 21 ACLC
1671.
80
(2000) 18 ACLC 590, 597.
81
Corporate Law Economic Reform Program (CLERP), Directors’ Duties and Corporate
Governance: Facilitating Innovation and Protecting Investors, Paper No 3 (1997). The
CLERP recommendation was the latest in a number of reform proposals: Companies
and Securities Law Review Committee, Enforcement of the Duties of Directors and
Officers of a Company by Means of a Statutory Derivative Action, Report No 12
(1990); House of Representatives Standing Committee on Legal and Constitutional
Affairs, Parliament of Australia (the Lavarch Committee), Corporate Practices and the
Rights of Shareholders (Canberra, AGPS, 1991); Companies and Securities Advisory
Committee, Report on a Statutory Derivative Action, July 1993; Commonwealth
Attorney-General’s Department, Proceedings on Behalf of a Company (Statutory
Derivative Action) Draft Provisions and Commentary (1995).
82
Corporate Law Economic Reform Program, above n 31, 31 (emphasis added).
Contesting Corporate Decisions 159
As I argued earlier in this Chapter, however, contestability is not just
about providing deterrence-based incentives towards proper managerial
performance. It is also about establishing mechanisms that allow shareholders to
‘own and identify with’ decision-making processes such that they can see their
interests furthered and their ideas respected.83 There is, then, a third rationale for
the SDA: it offers a legitimacy mechanism for decision-making processes.
I want to assess how the SDA measures up on this legitimacy rationale by
looking at three criticisms that have been directed at the statutory right of
derivative action. They are: that institutional shareholders are a better means of
correcting poor managerial behaviour; that the SDA increases the risk of wasteful
strategic litigation by minority shareholders; and that the SDA is not important
because it is rarely used and is ineffective.
83
Pettit, Republicanism, above n 3, 184.
84
Above n 8, 271.
85
See G Stapledon, Institutional Shareholders and Corporate Governance (1996) 271ff
discussing the impact of laws on insider trading and takeovers. In Australia, the
Australian Securities and Investments Commission has granted limited relief from the
application of the takeover provisions in cases of collective action by institutional
investors: Collective action by institutional investors, Policy Statement 128, 14 January
1998.
86
See Chapter 4 n 144 to 146 and accompanying text.
160 The Constitutional Corporation
and transparent. Thirdly, as I also noted in Chapter 4, there is no reason to assume
that the interests and concerns of institutional shareholders will necessarily accord
with those of other shareholders.
Action by institutional investors does have a role in corporate governance,
as was seen in Chapter 5, but it is not a substitute for contestability via the SDA.
Along with intervention by institutional shareholders, the SDA should operate as a
necessary component of a larger scheme comprising formal and informal, internal
and external contestability mechanisms.
The ‘institutional investor as monitor’ argument usually includes two
further claims: it is argued that minority or small shareholders either have ‘very
little incentive to consider the effect of the action on other shareholders’, preferring
to engage in strategic or selfish litigation87 or, conversely, that minority or small
shareholders lack sufficient incentive to bring any actions. These criticisms of the
SDA are considered under the next two subheadings.
The criticism here is that providing a statutory mechanism for bringing derivative
actions increases the risk of frivolous, self-serving, or strategic law suits by
minority shareholders, distracting corporate managers from their proper tasks. 88
While this risk cannot be discounted entirely, it is easily overstated, at least in the
Australian context. The risk of strategic lawsuits is met by the effective use of
judicial screening devices such as the good faith, best interests of the company, and
serious question criteria found in the Australian SDA, described above. The
cumulative effect of these criteria is to limit the occasions on which leave is
granted. In the words of one judge: ‘[i]t is clearly the intent of [the Act] that leave
to bring a derivative action must not be given lightly’.89
In the United States, where most of the concerns about overuse and
misuse of the derivative procedure have been raised, 90 some incentive towards
shareholder suits is provided by cost rules 91 and the use of contingency fee
arrangements whereby the plaintiff lawyer’s fees are calculated as a percentage of
the amount awarded by the court in a successful action. 92 Contingent fee
87
Eg, Fischel and Bradley above n 8, 271.
88
For example, ibid 272; Romano above n 8, 55-56.
89
Swansson v Pratt (2002) 20 ACLC 1594, 1600.
90
One explanation for this is that ‘the US is more permissive towards derivative
litigation’ in the framing of its procedural rules – G Miller, ‘Political Structure and
Corporate Governance: Some Points of Contrast Between the United States and
England’ (1998) Columbia Business Law Review 51, 52.
91
See J Coffee, ‘The Unfaithful Champion: The Plaintiff as Monitor in Shareholder
Litigation’ (1985) 48 Law & Contemporary Problems 5, 16.
92
J Macey and G Miller, ‘The Plaintiffs’ Attorney’s Role in Class Action and Derivative
Litigation: Economic Analysis and Recommendations’ (1991) 58 University of Chicago
Law Review 1.
Contesting Corporate Decisions 161
arrangements of this sort are not permitted in Australia. 93 Furthermore the
Australian legislation gives the court full discretion regarding costs orders in
relation to the initial leave application and the subsequent derivative action. This
includes discretion about the timing of any such order. 94 Thus a shareholder
plaintiff faces the risk of having to bear at least some of the legal costs of the
derivative litigation. Of course, assurances that the SDA will not result in a flood
of strategic lawsuits raise a potentially more telling criticism.
Recall that the SDA is said to be a deterrence mechanism, both specifically, when
liability rules are applied by courts in derivative actions, and generally, through the
threat that such cases might be brought. Some critics point out, however, that
shareholder litigation is a relatively rare occurrence. Shareholders are regarded as
investors who seek to maximise the returns on the capital that they have invested,
who are keen to protect that investment, and who therefore weigh the costs and
benefits of legal suits according to a criterion of net personal return. The argument
goes that shareholders are discouraged from using the SDA by the fact that any
benefits from a derivative action will flow to the corporation while the risks of the
suit remain with the applicant shareholder. Furthermore, the amount recovered by
the corporation will translate into relatively small benefits on a per share basis.
Shareholders will also be discouraged by the prospect of other inactive
shareholders getting a free ride on any benefits (however small and indirect) that
do flow through to shareholders.95 Derivative actions, it is argued, therefore have
little direct effect because of under-use and consequently, contrary to the claims
about the role of the SDA noted earlier, the deterrent effect is also reduced. One
assessment of the Canadian experience thus concludes that ‘the statutory derivative
action has, on balance, not made the impact on Canadian corporate law which
might have been expected’. 96 Even in the United States research shows that
shareholder litigation is ‘an infrequent experience’.97 Romano’s study found ‘little
evidence of specific deterrence’ and concluded that ‘it is virtually impossible to
identify a general deterrent effect’ from the prospect of litigation.98 Similar results
have been predicted for the SDA in Australia and the United Kingdom.99
93
G Dal Pont, Lawyers’ Professional Responsibility in Australia and New Zealand, (2nd
ed, 2001) 400. It is permissible for a lawyer to enter a speculative fee arrangement,
whereby the lawyer acts on a ‘no win, no fee’ basis.
94
Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) s 242.
95
For a discussion of these and other perceived disincentives, see I Ramsay, ‘Corporate
Governance, Shareholder Litigation and the Prospects for a Statutory Derivative
Action’ (1992) 15 University of New South Wales Law Journal 149.
96
B Cheffins, ‘Reforming the Derivative Action: The Canadian Experience and British
Prospects’ [1997] Company Financial and Insolvency Law Review 227, 256.
97
Romano, above n 8, 59.
98
Ibid, 84 and 85.
99
For the United States see Romano, above n 8. For Australia, see Ramsay, above n 95,
175. For the United Kingdom see Cheffins, above n 96, 260.
162 The Constitutional Corporation
These criticisms are significant if deterrence is assumed to be the only
rationale for the SDA. If, however, we accept that it is the existence of the right to
commence an SDA which is important in legitimating decision-making processes
then low levels of specific deterrence do not present such a problem, provided that
this is not a product of overly restrictive procedural rules, or unduly expensive or
drawn-out legal processes. The SDA must have the potential to make the exercise
of corporate decision-making power answerable to the interests of the corporation
as a whole. This requires that there should be some evidence of specific deterrence,
that there be some instances where the SDA is used to defend the corporate interest.
But it does not require high levels of specific deterrence. As I noted earlier,
compared to exit, voice is the subsidiary mode of reaction. By imposing
preconditions which limit the use of the SDA we underline the significance and
magnitude of those occasions when such actions are commenced. Hirschman notes
that there is a paradox at work here: the ease with which the exit option can be
used undermines the extent to which the voice option is used, but on the other hand
the ready availability of exit can strengthen the effectiveness of the voice option
when it is used. 100 As Fischel and Bradley concede, voice, in the form of the
derivative action, has a ‘limited, albeit important’ function.101
The argument above supports the relative importance of the SDA. The
SDA is important because it offers a legitimating device for corporate decisions
through the mechanism of contestability, and because it offers an avenue for
arguments about the corporate interest to be voiced by members. It is relatively
important because the SDA should not be regarded as the centrepiece of an
effective corporate governance and accountability system. Indeed, as Rostow
warned three decades ago:
[t]he stockholders’ suit is not a uniformly effective remedy for the misdeeds of
directors – indeed, it is not often an effective remedy for such misdeeds at all.
Sporadic in its incidence, costly in its procedures, it has been, from time to time, a
vehicle for extortion as well as for purification.102
100
Hirschman, above n 15, 83.
101
Cheffins, above n 96, 287.
102
E Rostow, ‘To Whom and for What Ends is Corporate Management Responsible?’ in E
Mason (ed), The Corporation in Modern Society (1960) 46, 49.
103
Hirschman, above n 15, 31.
Contesting Corporate Decisions 163
The SDA and Corporate Regulation
Thus far I have considered three rationales for the SDA — compensation,
deterrence, and legitimation — and I have argued that the latter requires more
emphasis than it has received. There is a fourth rationale that I want to consider
briefly: the SDA can also have a regulatory function. This suggestion stems from
the discussion back in Chapter 3 about the state’s role in protecting and furthering
public values and, consequently, putting limits on the power of private
organisations. From this perspective corporations are regarded not solely as private
arrangements, but also as key participants in the public economic and social arena.
In that argument I suggested that a system of corporate law should be concerned to
enhance public values such as the avoidance of oppressive or unfair behaviour and
improving the accountability of corporate decision making.104 The SDA can play a
role here by preserving the possibility that such values can be applied through the
medium of judicial decision.
The question, then, is whether the SDA should be regarded exclusively as
a private self-help mechanism or whether it also has a role in the public regulation
of corporations. 105 Can the SDA, as Whincop and Keyes suggest, support the
emergence of a ‘new corporate law’ based on public law-like standards of fairness
and propriety, in which public review and regulation are emphasised alongside
private ordering of affairs?106
There are some hints about this possibility in the history of SDA in
Australia. The idea of introducing a derivative action into the corporations
legislation was put forward by the Companies and Securities Law Review
Committee (CSLRC) in its 1990 inquiry into the standards of conduct and
performance of company directors and officers. 107 The CSLRC recommendation
was driven partly by a concern about the unsatisfactory nature of the common law,
but it was also prompted by the Committee’s belief that a new regime of civil
proceedings:
104
See Chapter 3 n 18, and accompanying text.
105
See D Sugarman, ‘Reconceptualising Company Law: Reflections on the Law
Commission’s Consultation Paper on Shareholder Remedies’ (1997) 18 The Company
Lawyer 226, 281.
106
M Whincop and M Keyes, ‘Corporation, Contract, Community: An Analysis of
Governance in the Privatisation of Public Enterprise and the Publicisation of Private
Corporate Law’ (1997) 25 Federal Law Review 51, 92.
107
Companies and Securities Law Review Committee, Enforcement of the Duties of
Directors and Officers of a Company by Means of a Statutory Derivative Action, Report
No. 12 (1990). The Committee used the derivative action provisions in the Ontario
Business Corporations Act 1982 as the model for its recommendations.
164 The Constitutional Corporation
members might provide enforcement in cases which the regulatory authorities are
unable to prosecute because of competing demands on limited resources.108
Alongside the idea that shareholder-initiated derivative actions could play a part in
a wider system of corporate regulation, the CSLRC also recommended that the
Australian Securities and Investments Commission (ASIC) should have standing to
seek leave to bring derivative actions. In this way the SDA would ‘assist in the
recognition of the Commission as a protector of the broader public interest in the
orderly administration of the affairs of companies’.109
In the end this overt regulatory perspective was abandoned. The CLERP
recommendations, which led to the resulting legislation, stated that the SDA was
‘not intended to be regulatory in nature but to facilitate private parties to enforce
existing rights’.110 The CLERP proposal did not include ASIC in the list of persons
who can apply for leave to bring a derivative action.111 Nevertheless, the statutory
provision of a right to seek leave to bring a derivative action retains strong public
enforcement elements. 112 This is evident in the use of a model that depends on
judicial leave, giving the court the power to grant or refuse leave and, within that,
the power to override an express ratification by majority shareholders.
Of course, the SDA is not the only contestability mechanism found in modern
corporate law statutes. There are other mechanisms that can have the same
potential effect as the SDA. The most commonly encountered example is the
statutory remedy for oppressive or unfair conduct.113 As an example, the Australian
108
Companies and Securities Law Review Committee, Enforcement of the Duties of
Directors and Officers of a Company by Means of a Statutory Derivative Action,
Discussion Paper No. 11 (1990) para [2].
109
Ibid para [63].
110
Above n 31, 35. CLERP relied on s 50 of the Australian Securities and Investments
Commission Act 1989 which gives the Commission power to commence proceedings in
another person’s name. This discretion only arises as a result of an investigation or
examination conducted by ASIC, and the power can only be exercised if ‘it appears to
the Commission to be in the public interest’. One view is that Australian courts have
implied a ‘Foss v Harbottle consideration’ into the public interest pre-requisite by
inquiring into the company’s ability to make a decision about the proceedings: P
Hanrahan, ‘Distinguishing Corporate and Personal Claims in Australian Company
Litigation’ (1997) 15 Companies & Securities Law Journal 21, 32.
111
The Commission’s standing to seek leave had been removed from proposals for an
SDA in the 1991 Lavarch Committee report: see above n 31, 202 (rec 26) and 194-195.
It was then re-instated in the 1993 CASAC proposal: above n 31.
112
See S Bottomley, ‘Shareholder Derivative Actions and Public Interests Suits: Two
Versions of the Same Story?’ (1991) 15 University of New South Wales Law Journal
127.
113
For example, Companies Act 1985 (UK) s 459; Canada Business Corporations Act,
RSC 1985, s 241.
Contesting Corporate Decisions 165
Corporations Act 2001 permits a court to make a variety of orders where it is
proven that the conduct of the affairs of a corporation or a members’ resolution is
either contrary to the interests of the members as a whole, or is oppressive to,
unfairly prejudicial to, or unfairly discriminatory against, a member or members.114
The court can make any order it considers appropriate, including an order that the
corporation be wound up, that the corporate constitution be modified or repealed,
or that a member’s shares be purchased.115 The court can also order a derivative
form of action, authorising a member to institute proceedings in the name of the
corporation.116
If, as many commentators contend, the remedy for oppression or
unfairness (‘the oppression remedy’) will continue to be the main form of
shareholder action, 117 then the question is whether it is necessary to preserve a
separate derivative action in the statute. The oppression remedy clearly operates as
a means for contestability, and it offers the opportunity for members to voice their
concerns rather than simply exiting the corporation.
In practice it is often difficult to maintain a clear distinction between
actions for oppression or unfair conduct and derivative actions. In Australian courts
the primary method of distinguishing between derivative and personal actions is to
examine the nature of the legal right or duty which is alleged to have been
infringed.118 Derivative suits are said to be concerned with breaches of officers’
duties such as diversion of corporate opportunities from the corporation, the
improper use of corporate information, self-dealing, or negligent management,119
while personal actions are concerned with issues such as the wrongful
expropriation of shares, or the deprivation or manipulation of voting or other rights
of members. Even though a member’s statutory right to bring an action for
oppression is personal and is not derived from the corporation, the substance of
many of these actions has a strong derivative quality. 120 For example, the
oppression remedy has been used in cases where corporate controllers have
exercised their powers for an improper purpose,121 awarded themselves excessive
remuneration,122 or have made uncommercial loans to a director’s company.123
114
Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) s 232. The UK Act refers only to conduct that is unfairly
prejudicial: s 459.
115
Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) s 233.
116
Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) s 233(1)(g).
117
J Poole and P Roberts, ‘Shareholder Remedies – Corporate Wrongs and the Derivative
Action’ (1999) Journal of Business Law 99, 117; Cheffins, above n 96, 260; Sugarman,
above n 105, 243.
118
Hanrahan, above n 110, 34. An alternative approach, common in the United States, is to
look at whether the direct effect of the wrongful conduct is on the company or the
shareholder – see T Brandi, ‘The Strike Suit: A Common Problem of the Derivative
Suit and the Shareholder Class Action’ (1993) 98 Dickinson Law Review 355, 359.
119
These are derivative wrongs because the duties are owed to the company or the
members as a whole.
120
CSLRC, above n 107, para [251]; Hanrahan, above n 110, 38.
121
For example, Re Bagot Well Pastoral Co Pty Ltd (1992) 11 ACLC 1.
122
For example, Roberts v Walter Developments Pty Ltd (1992) 10 ACLC 804.
166 The Constitutional Corporation
In a survey of Australian cases Ian Ramsay found that the most common
ground of shareholder litigation was oppression (thirty five per cent of reported
judgements). 124 In a separate study of oppression actions, Ramsay reported that
twenty six per cent of cases concerned action for breach of fiduciary duties, twenty
per cent concerned the misappropriation of corporate assets, and twelve per cent
concerned excessive remuneration. 125 In other words, a significant number of
oppression cases concerned the enforcement of corporate rights and duties.
The usual remedy in oppression actions is an order requiring another
shareholder or the corporation itself to purchase the plaintiff member’s shares.126
So, although it serves the purpose of providing contestability and voice, in practice
the oppression remedy ‘has largely become an exit remedy’.127 In the jurisprudence
of the oppression remedy, the use of voice is oriented towards exit. In contrast, the
use of voice in the SDA is tied to the plaintiff’s wish to remain within the
corporation and to improve the way in which it operates. The SDA thus operates as
a dedicated voice — loyalty response.
There is another important feature of the SDA that is highlighted by the
comparison with the oppression remedy. The derivative action is not and never has
been intended as a personal form of action designed to yield direct benefits to the
individual shareholder/investor. By definition, the derivative action presumes that a
shareholder is willing to act as a ‘corporate-interest plaintiff’ in pursuit of a goal
that will yield benefits for the corporation as a whole.128 In short, the SDA is a
mechanism for ‘corporate-regarding’ behaviour. It would, of course, be naïve to
suppose that SDA applicants will always be devoid of self-interest, and there will
be different degrees of corporate-regarding motivation. Actions such as the
misappropriation of corporate property by directors, the foregoing of a corporate
opportunity, or abandoning a corporate claim against a third party — any of which
123
Re George Raymond Pty Ltd (2000) 18 ACLC 85. See further examples in E Boros,
Minority Shareholders’ Remedies (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1995), 231-232.
124
I Ramsay, ‘Enforcement of Corporate Rights and Duties by Shareholders and the
Australian Securities Commission: Evidence and Analysis’ (1995) 23 Australian
Business Law Review 174, 175.
125
I Ramsay, ‘An Empirical Study of the Use of the Oppression Remedy’ (1999) 27
Australian Business Law Review 23, 33.
126
Ramsay’s survey shows that in nearly 49 per cent of cases the plaintiff sought an order
for the sale of shares, and this was granted in nearly 31 per cent of cases: ibid 35-36. In
Australia this is because the remedy is used primarily by minority shareholders in
proprietary (that is, private) companies, where there is usually no market for the sale of
shares. The research also shows that 70 per cent of plaintiffs are minority shareholders
in proprietary companies: ibid 31.
127
United Kingdom Law Commission, Shareholder Remedies, Report Law Com No 246
(1997) para 6.11, referring to s 459 of the Companies Act 1985 (UK).
128
The benefits of a successful derivative action may also flow to other stakeholders in a
company, such as secured and unsecured creditors and employees: Hanrahan, above n
110, 30. A derivative action may also directly satisfy a plaintiff’s non-financial personal
goals, such as a concern to see that rules are followed, or a concern for fairness.
Contesting Corporate Decisions 167
might be the subject of derivative action — will involve some element of personal
grievance and redress on the part of the applicant shareholder. The point remains,
though, that the derivative action is oriented towards collective outcomes. At a
minimum it requires shareholders to consider how the pursuit of the wider
corporate interest might also be in their own interests. This echoes the deliberative
requirement that corporate decisions should represent a collective judgement about
the issue at hand.129 In this way the statutory derivative action symbolises an aspect
or dimension of corporate law and corporate life that has been drowned out by the
volume of wealth maximisation/managerial incentive arguments. In 1960 Eugene
Rostow summed up the precarious status of this dimension in the following way:
[O]ne would expect those concerned for the integrity and future of private
business institutions to applaud the intrepid souls who ferret out corporate
wrongdoing, and risk their own time and money against a contingency of being
rewarded, if in the end sin is found to have flourished. Not at all. Such men are not
treated as honored members of the system of private enterprise, but as its
scavengers and pariahs. … At best they are viewed as necessary evils, the Robin
Hoods of the business world, for whom a patronizing word may sometimes be
said, when they succeed in revealing some particularly horrendous act.130
Similarly, consider Kirby P’s dissenting judgement in the New South Wales Court
of Appeal in Parker v National Roads and Motorists Association:
[The plaintiff’s] cause was at no time one for personal gain or for his own
financial profit. It appears to have arisen from an anxiety about unequal treatment
of company directors. It blossomed into a concern about the lawfulness of the
conduct of his fellow directors and the companies in their charge. It came to full
fruit in a determination to seek out the shield of the law when his fellow directors
(as he saw it) attempted, by oppression, to suppress his complaints and to get rid
of him. The judges should not deny that shield of the law. They should support
corporate gadflies when their cause is the correction of apparently unlawful and
self-interested action by directors, defended by oppressive conduct.131
129
See Chapter 5 above, n 15 and accompanying text.
130
Rostow, above n 102, 49.
131
(1993) 11 ACLC 866, 877-878. The case involved an action under the statutory remedy
for oppressive conduct in which the plaintiff sought orders that he be allowed to
conduct proceedings in the name of the respondent companies. See also Wallersteiner v
Moir (No. 2) [1975] QB 373, 389 per Denning MR.
168 The Constitutional Corporation
apply to the SDA. Even though ‘there is room for doubt whether the Australian
statutory ‘oppression’ remedy covers cases which only involve a wrong to the
company’132 it would be preferable for the legislation to be drafted to ensure that
solely derivative wrongs are channelled through the SDA.
Conclusion
In this Chapter I have argued the importance of having clear and accessible
mechanisms for shareholder contestation to ensure that shareholder interests are
properly taken into account in corporate decisions, and to protect the corporate
interest. In part — but only in part — this is important because of the
compensation and deterrence effects that contestation can have. But I have argued
that contestability also has a legitimating function: shareholders, knowing that
action can be taken if their interests are not being tracked, can have a measure of
confidence in the decision-making process and be more likely to view that process
as legitimate. This does not require that there be lots of actual contestations, but it
does require that contestability be a realistic option.
The two examples that I have used to illustrate this argument — the right
to request an extraordinary general meeting, and the right to seek leave to bring a
derivative action — reveal just some of the issues in trying to achieve this balance.
Neither form of contestation has been widely used in Australia. Curiously this fact
has led to different conclusions in the literature and policy debate. The relative
absence of shareholder-requested general meetings has not placated concerns about
abuse by shareholders and has resulted in more restrictive criteria. By comparison,
the perceived under-usage of the SDA has been seen by some critics as proof of a
legislative failure or the purely symbolic nature of this statutory provision. This
may simply illustrate the point that there are no pre-determined thresholds or
criteria that can be applied in all cases and contexts. The maintenance of effective
mechanisms of contestability requires continuous debate — and deliberation.
132
R Simmonds ‘A Summing Up and a Search for Solutions’ in M Gillooly (ed), The Law
Relating to Corporate Groups (1993) 239.
Chapter 7
1
Borrowing John Uhr’s description: see Chapter 3 above, n 5 and accompanying text.
2
See for example, the Australian Stock Exchange Corporate Governance Council,
Principles of Good Corporate Governance and Best Practice Recommendations
(March 2003) Recommendation 2.1; Financial Services Authority (UK), The Combined
170 The Constitutional Corporation
corporation’s external auditor provide another example. 3 Deliberation can also
enhance accountability within the corporation, in so far as it enhances ex ante
explanations of proposed actions. Moreover, effective deliberation depends on the
effective supply of information, and so a commitment to deliberation has the
potential to encourage accountability through attention to the flow of corporate
information and provision of explanations.4 And, drawing on Tom Tyler’s work, I
argued in Chapter 5 that deliberation also has the potential to reduce the risk of
needless contestation; members who feel that their voice has been given an
adequate hearing in the processes leading up to a decision are more likely to accept
the outcome of the decision-making process and will have less cause to voice their
concerns through external means.5
A particular example of all three principles at work is found in the
statutory right of members of a corporation to requisition a special general meeting,
which was discussed in Chapter 6.6 A special general meeting that is requisitioned
in this way is likely to be a form of, and forum for, contestation in which, through
processes of deliberation, the corporation’s directors are required to account for
their actions with regard to the matters on the agenda. The effectiveness of this
particular mechanism as a corporate constitutional device depends, amongst other
things, on how widely or restrictively the threshold requirements are specified.
That will involve consideration of factors such as cost, which must be balanced
against considerations of accountability, deliberation and contestability. I come
back to these questions in a moment.
The second way in which the three principles can work together is that, in
a given corporate setting, shortfalls in the operation of one principle can potentially
be addressed and remedied by the other two. For example, it will not always be
feasible for a corporation to implement particular separations of power. There may
not be any available or suitable independent candidates for appointment to the
board; the incumbent directors may be insufficiently qualified to form an effective
audit committee; or the founder and chief executive officer of the business may
insist on retaining control by also holding the position of chair of the board. 7
Are these the only principles that might be assembled within a constitutional
framework for corporate governance? Undoubtedly not. This book has presented
an exploratory argument, not a definitive catalogue. There will be — and should be
— debate about the relevance of these and other values. Should, for example, the
ideas of representation and participation also have a role in shaping our system of
corporate law and corporate governance? What about the idea of equal opportunity
for input into corporate decisions? Consider too the importance of different
corporate settings. It has not been the purpose of this book to investigate the
implications of corporate constitutionalism for all types of corporation. I have
concentrated on what is perhaps the easiest example: the widely-held public
9
W Bratton, ‘Does Corporate Law Protect The Interests of Shareholders and Other
Stakeholders? Enron and the Dark Side of Shareholder Value’ (2002) 76 Tulane Law
Review 1275, 1283.
10
Corporate Law Economic Reform Program (Audit Reform and Corporate Disclosure)
Act 2004.
11
Companies (Audit, Investigations and Community Enterprise) Act 2004.
12
Against this, as discussed in Chapter 6 above, n 50, the draft Bill also proposes to
restrict the threshold allowing members to requisition a special general meeting,
removing the ‘100 members rule’ and leaving only the ‘members with 5 per cent of
votes’ rule. In the UK, the Company Law Reform Bill 2005 similarly addresses,
amongst wide-ranging reforms, the right of shareholders to requisition meetings, and to
circulate statements prior to a general meeting: see eg cls 279 and 290.
The Prospects for Corporate Constitutionalism 173
corporation. There is no reason to think that the principles of accountability,
deliberation and contestability cannot apply in smaller, proprietary corporations or
other corporate forms, although we should expect that these ideas will be played
out differently in those different corporate contexts. In small closely-held
corporations, for example, where there is no neat separation between membership
and management, it is likely that decision-making involvement by members will
extend beyond periodic voting at general meetings. Indeed, in these corporations
voting may well be regarded as a mere formality, something that is done for the
sake of the required corporate records. Exit options in such corporations are likely
to be limited — indeed we may need to consider ways of fostering exit where the
use of deliberation and voice have run its course (as in the case of a deadlock).
Separations of powers and other accountability mechanisms may also be more
difficult to sustain. The point is that with different corporate contexts decisions
need to be made about the interaction and balance between the principles discussed
in this book.
And, of course, there will always be criteria or desiderata drawn from
other frameworks to be weighed up. This is part of the plurality of discursive
perspectives that I referred to in Chapter 5.13 As an example, I argued above that
the right of a small group of members to requisition a special general meeting
demonstrates the joint operation of all three principles. There are obvious
competing concerns here, some of which come from an economic perspective:
there can be considerable financial cost in calling a special general meeting,14 along
with the opportunity costs of diverting management’s attention away from ‘getting
on with the job’ of running the corporation. A related concern, owing as much to
political as to economic considerations, is the risk that the right to requisition
general meetings might be abused by sectional minority groups in the corporation’s
membership who are pursuing their own special interests (the ‘tyranny of the
minority’ argument).
My concern, and one of the reasons for writing this book, is that while
they deserve attention, economic or financial arguments such as these are too often
assumed to have precedence over other considerations. Moreover, to the extent that
more politically-oriented arguments have been taken into account, this has only
been done within the parameters set by those economic arguments. For example,
when it recommended the repeal of the statutory rule that allowed 100 members in
a corporation to requisition the directors to call a general meeting, the Australian
Parliament’s Joint Committee on Corporations and Financial Services did so on the
basis of arguments that the rule exposed large corporations and their members to
significant costs and that it gave economically disproportionate influence to
13
Chapter 5, above n 39 and following text.
14
In a study of 217 Australian listed corporations in 2003, the median cost of an AGM
was A$15,000: S Bottomley, The Role of Shareholders’ Meetings in Improving
Corporate Governance (Research Report, Centre for Commercial Law, Australian
National University, 2003), 45.
174 The Constitutional Corporation
minority shareholders. 15 Again, my argument is not that these are irrelevant or
inappropriate considerations. It is, rather, that they should not be assumed to be the
only relevant or appropriate considerations; on a given issue they may ‘win the
day’ but this should be in light of a serious consideration of other concerns such as
those examined in this book.
But, it may be asked, do shareholders in public companies really care
about the protection of accountability structures? Do they want to deliberate?
When dissatisfied with corporate performance or managerial behaviour, would
they prefer to contest improper decisions rather than simply selling their shares in
the company? These questions require empirical investigation, but a safe
hypothesis is that for many shareholders in many public corporations the answers
are likely to be: ‘to an extent’, ‘maybe’, and ‘no’ respectively. Does this mean that
the arguments presented in this book are irrelevant? Not surprisingly, I do not think
that they are. I do not think that corporate constitutionalism fails in its job of
assisting us to understand and promote better corporate governance even if, in
practice, its ideas do not touch numbers of shareholders. I explain why under the
next heading.
In Chapter 1, I explained that this book takes the shareholder primacy model as its
reference point. This is for practical reasons: for better or for worse, the
shareholder primacy model has proven to be resilient (notwithstanding its
imprecision and malleability) and it seems to me to be a better strategy to work
with it rather than try to overthrow it (in a single move, at least). But, as I also
explained, it is important to re-visit the shareholder primacy model because often
its adherents give it a very narrow reading. Too often, shareholder primacy is
distorted by a pre-occupation — on the part of directors, managers and
shareholders — with short-term profit maximisation.16 This, in turn, translates into
arguments about the need for greater managerial discretion: 17 shareholders are
investors, their interests are directed at earning profits on their investments, and the
15
Joint Committee on Corporations and Financial Services, Parliament of Australia,
Inquiry into the Exposure Draft of the Corporations Amendment Bill (No. 2) 2005
(2005), paras. 2.6-2.10; see also Companies and Securities Advisory Committee,
Shareholder Participation in the Modern Listed Public Company: Final Report, (2000)
para 2.6 (pointing to the costs of calling a meeting and to the risk of giving small
groups of shareholders ‘undue leverage in negotiating’ with the corporation).
16
On the impact of short-termism, see L Mitchell, Corporate Irresponsibility: America’s
Newest Export (2001).
17
Culminating, sometimes, in arguments for ‘director primacy’: S Bainbridge, ‘Director
Primacy: The Means and Ends of Corporate Governance’ (2003) 97 Northwestern
University Law Review 547.
The Prospects for Corporate Constitutionalism 175
best way to achieve this is to let corporate managers get on with the job (within
basic fiduciary constraints) of keeping the shareholders happy.18
It should be apparent by now that, as I see it, the shareholder primacy
model does not, as a matter of law, restrict the concerns of corporate managers to
the financial interests of shareholders (short-term or otherwise). 19 The model
permits attention to be given to shareholders’ non-financial concerns (such as
concerns for the social or environmental impact of their corporation’s activities)
and, through the medium of the shareholders, the model can also take account of
the interests of non-shareholders. 20 By giving greater attention to the role of
shareholders as members of (as opposed to their role as investors in) a corporation,
by encouraging and then taking seriously their input through processes of
deliberation, by investigating the use of corporate interest groups, 21 it is quite
feasible that shareholders — of all types — can be a means whereby the concerns
and interests of corporate employees, of tort victims, of consumers and others can
be factored into corporate decisions. Corporate law should encourage shareholders
to be active as members, to consider and make use of the options offered by
deliberation and contestation rather than those offered by passivity and exit. In this
way shareholders can act as conduits to introduce other ideas and interests into
corporate deliberations.
There is reason to believe that at least some shareholders would respond
to this encouragement. An indication is found in the growing interest in socially
responsible investments (SRI) in Australia, the UK, the US and other countries.
Institutional investors in particular have demonstrated a willingness to screen
investment opportunities against ethical, social and environmental criteria. 22
According to one estimate, in Australia in 2002 approximately A$2.18 billion was
invested by institutions pursuing SRI strategies. 23 Another Australian study of
shareholders’ responses to ethical issues shows that a majority of shareholders
surveyed would be likely to sell their shares in a corporation that was discovered to
have engaged in certain ethically contentious practices (such as using child labour,
causing environmental problems, or giving large bonuses to directors). 24 This
18
See Bratton, above n 9.
19
David Millon makes a similar argument in his response to Mitchell’s book (above, n
16): D Millon, ‘Why Is Corporate Management Obsessed With Quarterly Earnings And
What Should Be Done About It?’ (2002) 70 George Washington Law Review 890.
20
Similarly, see Millon, above n 19.
21
See Chapter 5 above, n 137 to 146 and accompanying text.
22
Editorial, ‘Corporate Governance, Institutional Investors and Socially Responsible
Investment’ (2002) 10 Corporate Governance 1.
23
P Ali, G Stapledon, M Gold, Corporate Governance and Investment Fiduciaries (2003)
193.
24
D Hanson and B Tranter, ‘Who Are the Shareholders in Australia and What Are Their
Ethical Opinions? An Empirical Analysis’ (2006) 14 Corporate Governance 23,
reporting that, given the choice of keeping or selling their shares, in a sample of 2087
shareholders 88.2 per cent of shareholders would probably or definitely sell in response
to the use of child labour; 70.9 per cent would do so in response to a major
environmental problem. The figure for payment of large bonuses to executives was 60.1
176 The Constitutional Corporation
speaks well of the willingness of shareholders to bring ethical considerations to
bear on their investment choices. On the other hand, it also demonstrates the
continued orientation towards exit as the preferred response to dissatisfaction with
corporate performance. But, as I argued in Chapter 6, while exit in such situations
can send a clear message to the corporation, it is also important that our systems of
corporate law and governance should give clear recognition and encouragement to
the option of remaining and voicing one’s concerns.25 The Royal Commission of
Inquiry into the collapse of HIH Insurance recognised this point, albeit in a limited
context:
I would add, going beyond concerns with board composition and corporate
performance, that shareholders can, and should, also be encouraged to take
responsibility — in a moral sense — for the actions of the corporations whose
shares they own.27
I do not want to overstate the case for greater shareholder involvement.
There are questions to be asked about the capacity of shareholders (including
institutional shareholders) to influence the course of corporate events. The
passivity of institutional shareholders has been the subject of widespread
comment.28 So too has been the low success-rate of those shareholders in getting
SRI resolutions passed at general meetings.29 And it is true that some shareholders
may use their deliberative options and their contestability mechanisms simply to
pursue their own short-term investment concerns. But, as I have argued elsewhere
in this book, we need not assume that self-interested investors are the only or the
preferred inhabitants of the corporate world. There is no reason why the model
should not, and cannot, encourage a different vision — of shareholders who, while
mindful of their investments, also have other concerns and who take steps to bring
them to the attention of directors and managers.
percent. Other scenarios were: producing military weapons – 58.2 per cent; investing in
genetically modified food or crops – 67.5 per cent; and being prosecuted for racial
discrimination – 48.5 per cent.
25
See Chapter 6 above, n 15 to n 23 and accompanying text.
26
HIH Royal Commission, above n 8, vol 1, 121.
27
See, eg, R Warren, ‘The Responsible Shareholders: A Case Study’ (2002) 11 Business
Ethics: A European Review 14.
28
See, eg, I Ramsay, G Stapledon and K Fong, ‘Corporate Governance: The Perspective
of Australian Institutional Shareholders’ (2000) 18 Company and Securities Law
Journal 110.
29
See, eg, M Haigh and J Hazelton, ‘Financial Markets: A Tool for Social
Responsibility?’ (2004) 52 Journal of Business Ethics 59.
The Prospects for Corporate Constitutionalism 177
It is, of course, important to think about moving beyond the parameters of the
shareholder primacy model. There are other corporate actors who lie outside these
strict parameters, and who are clearly implicated in how the model operates and
how it conforms with the ideas of accountability, deliberation and contestability.
There are two ways that this might be done. Read strictly, that model
confines our attention to the relationship between shareholders and directors,
mediated through the separate legal entity of the corporation. So we can ask, first,
whether there are others outside the boardroom who ought to be subject to legal
duties or expectations which might enhance the prospects of accountability,
deliberation or contestability. Secondly, we can consider expanding, beyond the
shareholders, the list of people to whom those duties are owed.
On the first point, there are already ways in which Australian corporate
law looks beyond the boardroom. Auditors, as we have noted, have a statutorily
mandated role in corporate accountability processes. The Corporations Act now
requires auditors of listed companies to attend the company’s AGM at which the
audit report is to be considered.30 The chair of the meeting must allow a reasonable
opportunity for the members as a whole to ask questions at the meeting about the
conduct of the audit, the preparation and content of the audit report, and the
auditor’s independence. 31 Moreover, members of a listed company may submit
written questions to the auditor prior to the meeting about the content of the
auditor’s report or the conduct of the audit. 32 The role of non-board corporate
officers has also been noted at various places in this book. In the wake of
prominent corporate collapses between 2001 and 2002, attention has turned to the
question of whether, and to what extent, legal duties and liabilities should be more
explicitly imposed on corporate officers and employees who operate outside the
boardroom.33 In Australia the HIH Royal Commission made the obvious point that
‘in larger companies many significant decisions are made by management without
reference to the board’, and found that many of the practices that formed part of the
HIH collapse were undertaken by employees in ‘middle management’. 34 The
extension of duties and liabilities, similar to those presently imposed on directors,
to other corporate officers is one means (but only one) by which processes of
accountability, deliberation and contestability can be shifted from the board room
into the wider corporate managerial framework.35
30
Corporations Act 2001 s 250RA.
31
Corporations Act 2001 s 250T (also permitting questions about the accounting policies
used by companies).
32
Corporations Act 2001 s 250PA.
33
See Australian Government, Corporations and Markets Advisory Committee,
Corporate Duties Below Board Level, Report (2006).
34
HIH Royal Commission, above n 8, vol 1, 121-122.
35
This was recommended by the HIH Royal Commission: see ibid, recommendation 2.
Similar recommendations have been made by Australian Government’s Corporations
and Markets Advisory Committee: see above n 33.
178 The Constitutional Corporation
The second point — expanding the list of people to whom those duties are
owed — takes us to ‘stakeholder theory’ and wider debates about corporate social
responsibility. I do not intend to enter these debates here, but it is worth noting that,
in Australia at least, there appears to be a loose correlation between periods of
significant corporate collapse and a renewal of concern about standards of
corporate social responsibility. For example, even before the spate of corporate
collapses in the late 1980s had concluded, the Australian Senate conducted an
inquiry into the social and fiduciary obligations of company directors
(recommending that directors’ duties not be expanded to include environmental
and similar matters).36 Some twenty years later, in the wake of the HIH Insurance
and other collapses, simultaneous but separate inquiries into corporate social
responsibility were conducted by the Australian Government’s Corporations and
Markets Advisory Committee 37 and by the Australian Parliament’s Joint
Committee on Corporations and Financial Services. 38 The Parliamentary
Committee’s recommendations echo the point made earlier in this Chapter: that is,
the existing legal model does not preclude the consideration of stakeholder
interests, and that attention should be given to various ways in which corporate
responsibility can be encouraged on a voluntary basis.
It appears, then, that concerns about accountability failures and questions
about broader corporate responsibilities are never far apart. My view, elaborated at
length in this book, is that as important as issues of corporate social responsibility
are, they must be built upon a robust and searching examination of the ways in
which the role of shareholders can be revitalised. In Chapter 1 I expressed
pessimism about the prospects for a serious consideration of broader perspectives
on corporate governance and corporate responsibility by directors and managers
until they can be convinced that a broader approach is consonant with the ideas that
underlie the standard legal model. Put more bluntly, I wonder what hope there can
be for stakeholders if corporate laws and practices do not take the roles and
interests of shareholders seriously.
I said in Chapter 1 that the purpose of this book is to use the lens of corporate
constitutionalism to offer a fresh perspective on the way in which we view the
36
Senate Standing Committee on Legal and Constitutional Affairs, Australian Parliament,
Company Directors’ Duties: Report on the Social and Fiduciary Duties and
Obligations of Company Directors (1989).
37
The Advisory Committee, established under Part 9 of the Australian Securities and
Investments Commission Act 2001, operates as a specialized corporate law reform body.
It released a discussion paper in November 2005: see Corporations and Markets
Advisory Committee, Corporate Social Responsibility: Discussion Paper (November
2005).
38
Parliamentary Joint Committee on Corporations and Financial Services, Australian
Parliament, Corporate Responsibility: Managing Risk and Creating Value (2006).
The Prospects for Corporate Constitutionalism 179
processes of governance within public corporations. The metaphor of ‘looking at
things through a different lens’ is appropriate. Corporate constitutionalism does not
introduce us, to borrow Philip Pettit’s expression, to ‘a new-fangled idea’. 39
Instead, it reminds us of, and revives our interest in, some important principles that
are already there to be found in our system of corporate law.
Through the lens of corporate constitutionalism we are able to emphasise
aspects of, and issues in, corporate governance and corporate law that are
otherwise likely to be overlooked or down-played in prevailing legal and economic
analyses (for example, the importance of decision-making processes, the role of
separations of powers in corporate decision-making; and the value of encouraging
shareholders to voice their concerns).
The arguments in this book also remind us that the language we use in
debates about corporate governance is important. When we choose to refer to
‘members’ rather than ‘investors’, our choice conveys a particular set of
assumptions and expectations about the roles and interests of those corporate actors.
The same is true when we choose between ‘contract’ and ‘constitution’ as the
underlying framework for thinking about corporate governance. Having reminded
us of these things, corporate constitutionalism then invites us to consider how we
might re-think some core questions of corporate governance — questions such as:
what is the purpose of the corporate endeavour? In whose interests should the
corporation be run? And who should participate in deciding the answers to these
questions?40
39
P Pettit, ‘Democracy, Electoral and Contestatory’ in I Shapiro and S Macedo (eds),
Designing Democratic Institutions: Nomos 42 (2000) 105.
40
I have adapted these questions from Lyman Johnson, ‘The Social Responsibility of
Corporate Law Professors’ (2002) 76 Tulane Law Review 1483, 1494.
This page intentionally left blank
Index
Uhr, John 78