(Sozomena 14) David Sider, Dirk Obbink (Eds.) - Doctrine and Doxography - Studies On Heraclitus and Pythagoras-Walter de Gruyter (20
(Sozomena 14) David Sider, Dirk Obbink (Eds.) - Doctrine and Doxography - Studies On Heraclitus and Pythagoras-Walter de Gruyter (20
(Sozomena 14) David Sider, Dirk Obbink (Eds.) - Doctrine and Doxography - Studies On Heraclitus and Pythagoras-Walter de Gruyter (20
Unauthenticated | 178.130.41.255
Download Date | 12/10/13 10:09 PM
Sozomena
Studies in the Recovery of Ancient Texts
Edited
on behalf of the Herculaneum Society
by
Alessandro Barchiesi, Robert Fowler,
Dirk Obbink and Nigel Wilson
Vol. 14
De Gruyter
Unauthenticated | 178.130.41.255
Download Date | 12/10/13 10:09 PM
Doctrine and Doxography
Studies on Heraclitus and Pythagoras
Edited by
De Gruyter
Unauthenticated | 178.130.41.255
Download Date | 12/10/13 10:09 PM
ISBN 978-3-11-033116-5
e-ISBN 978-3-11-033137-0
ISSN 1869-6368
Unauthenticated | 178.130.41.255
Download Date | 12/10/13 10:09 PM
Preface
The essays collected here, all here revised, were first presented in at a
bicontinental conference hosted in July, 2005, by Apostolos Pierris, to
whom we all express our great thanks, not only for the invitation, but
also for the magnificent settings: First on Samos, Pythagoras native
land, and then by chartered boat over to Kusadas, as close to Heraclitus
home town of Ephesus as modern facilities allow. We regret that the
original contributions by Serge Mouraviev, Arnold Hermann and
Dirk Obbink are not present here, and that it has taken so long to
bring these essays to print.
David Sider
Dirk Obbink
Abbreviations
The fragments of Pythagoras, Heraclitus, and the other Presocratics are
given as in DK (14 is DKs number for the former, 59 for the latter).
Frequently cited modern works are abbreviated as indicated below.
Bernab A. Bernab, Poetae Epici Graeci. Testimonia et Fragmenta.
2 vols. Berlin 1996 2004. T & F numbers for Orpheus
and Orphica as in pars 2, fasc. 1 3.
Dilcher, H. R. Dilcher, 1995, Studies in Heraclitus. Hildesheim 1995.
Diels, DG Hermann Diels, Doxographi Graeci. Berlin 1879.
DK H. Diels and W. Kranz, Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker 6.
Zurich 1952 [later editions are merely photographic
reprints; earlier editions were edited by Diels alone]
FGrHist Fragmente der griechische Historiker, ed. F. Jacoby. Leiden.
FHSG William Fortenbaugh, Pamela Huber, Robert Sharples,
and Dimitri Gutas, Theophrastus of Eresus: Sources for his
Life, Writings, Thought and Influence. 2 vols. Leiden 1992.
Guthrie, HGP W. K. C. Guthrie, A History of Greek Philosophy. Vol. 1
Cambridge 1962.
Kahn, H. C. Kahn, The Art and Thought of Heraclitus. Cambridge
1979.
K-G R. Khner and B. Gerth, Ausfrliche Grammatik der griechi-
schen Sprache. Hannover and Leipzig, 1904.
Kirk, H. G. S. Kirk, Heraclitus: The Cosmic Fragments. Cambridge,
1954.
KRS Kirk, G. S., J. E. Raven, and M. Schofield. The Presocratic
Philosophers. 2nd edn. Cambridge 1983.
Marcovich, H. M. Marcovich, Heraclitus: Greek Text with a Short Com-
mentary Merida 1967. 2nd ed., Sankt Augustin: Academia
Verlag, 2001.
Mouraviev, H. S. Mouraviev, Heraclitea: dition critique complte des t-
moignages sur la vie et loeuvre dHraclite dphse et des ves-
tiges de son livre, cited further by volume. Sankt Augustin
1999 .
Contents
I. Pythagoras
1. Catherine Rowett
Philosophys Numerical Turn: Why the Pythagoreans Interest in
Numbers is Truly Awesome . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3
2. Leonid Zhmud
Pythagorean Communities: From Individuals to a Collective
Portrait . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 33
3. Richard McKirahan
Aristotle on the Pythagoreans: His Sources and his Accounts of
Pythagorean Principles . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 53
4. Carl Huffman
Philolaus Critique of Heraclitus . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 121
II. Heraclitus
5. Aryeh Finkelberg
Heraclitus, the Rival of Pythagoras . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 147
6. Herbert Granger
Early Natural Theology: The Purification of the Divine Nature 163
7. Anthony A. Long
Heraclitus on Measure and the Explicit Emergence of Rationality 201
8. Gbor Betegh
On the physical aspect of Heraclitus psychology: With New
Appendices . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 225
9. Roman Dilcher
How Not to Conceive Heraclitean Harmony . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 263
X Contents
Contributors . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 335
General Index . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 339
Index Locorum Potiorum . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 345
1. Philosophys Numerical Turn
Why the Pythagoreans Interest in Numbers is
Truly Awesome
Catherine Rowett
4 Ibid. 381.
5 The mathematical interests are only one of the many kinds of wisdom attribut-
ed to Pythagoras. C. Huffman, The Pythagorean tradition, in A. A. Long
(ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy (Cambridge 1999),
66 87, 66 7, gives a judicious account of a general difficulty created by the
exaggerated reputation of Pythagoras, and the problematic source materials.
6 Catherine Rowett
6 For instance astronomy, in which Philolaus was arguably far more advanced
than his contemporaries such as Democritus, who appears to have rejected or
ignored the advances made by the Pythagoreans. See D. R. Dicks, Early
Greek Astronomy to Aristotle (London 1970) 80 81. Thanks to Carl Huffman
for suggesting this additional example.
Philosophys Numerical Turn 7
istotles reports about them), it invokes a contrast between limit and un-
limited, and leads to a classification of numbers that spills out into reality
more widely.7 For the second generation Pythagoreans, the unlimited is
evidently part of what makes number the basis of the whole of reality.
This then gets taken up into some of the more peculiar bits of Platonic
theory, in particular the so-called unwritten doctrines and the idea of
the one and the indefinite dyad.8
In our modern accounts of Pythagoreanism, we take the Pythagor-
eans to be talking about funny stuff, some kind of weird mathematical
nonsense, when they mention the unlimited or indefinite, and we dis-
miss it as so much garbage, despite the fact that some respected interpre-
tations take Philolauss apeira to be kinds of material stuff or qualities
rather similar to those that appear in other cosmologies of the time.9
Yet when we meet the apeiron in Anaximander we are not so quick
to diagnose something weird or mathematical. We treat it very different-
ly. In Anaximanders case we do not see a primarily mathematical no-
tion being used to create a metaphysical basis for reality, but we read
Anaximander as speaking of an unlimited material: physical stuff. We
read him as a materialist, and for that reason (it seems) the apeiron is de-
fused. It doesnt smack of funny stuff, as it does in the hands of the Py-
thagoreans. It looks instead like a primitive kind of prime matter, some-
thing that Aristotle could look back to, and in which he could trace the
origins of the material cause:
For all things are either an origin or derivative from an origin, but of the
apeiron there is no origin, but it seems to be the origin of the rest and
to encompass all things and control all things, as all those say who do
not make any other causes apart from the apeiron such as mind or friendship.
must be aware that larger and longer flutes make deeper notes, it would
be surprising if these numerical ratios did not also yield a sense that
lower pitch sounds would issue from the vents of the larger wheels at
the outer spheres of the cosmos.
When Pythagoras, or some Pythagoreans, posit harmonic propor-
tions, based on ratios of numbers, as the explanatory principles in deter-
mining the structures of the heavens, and do this on the basis of discov-
ering that physical sounds can indeed be analysed mathematically, as
systematically related to the size and shape of the physical object that
produces them, we generally dismiss their suggestions as idle specula-
tion.14 When Anaximander engages in some similar, though less well
15 The importance of this theory is that it is the first attempt at what we may
term a mechanical model of the heavenly bodies in Greek astronomy
Lloyd (above, n. 9) 17; His theory of equilibrium was a brilliant leap into
the realms of the mathematical a prioriKRS 134. Recent fashion has been
rather more low key in its estimate of Anaximander (e. g., The beginnings
of cosmology, in A. A. Long (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek
Philosophy (Cambridge 1999) 45 65, 55).
16 See Xenocrates fr. 9 Heinze, apud Porphyry Commentary on Ptolemys Harmonics
30 1 6 Dring.
Philosophys Numerical Turn 11
tue, at least Pythagoras can point to his work on harmony, which evi-
dently does have some empirical support.17
Why, then, do we cite Pythagorean harmony theory as a type of
worthless superstition, but cite Milesian science as an impressive fore-
runner of modern mathematical techniques in empirical science?
Could it be that the idea that something is beautiful, or that there should
be music in it, seems not to be a good reason for supposing it to be true?
But if that is so, we need to examine our preconceptions. For it seems,
first, that we are bringing to the enquiry a prejudice in favour of the idea
that nature is random, disordered or arbitrary, rather than systematic,
displaying patterns and orders at more than one level. Why should it
not be more likely that harmonic patterns figure in the structure of
the heavens? If so, the Pythagoreans have the better approach to the
task than, say, materialists such as the atomists.
Secondly, it seems plausible to suppose, as I have suggested, that
Anaximander too thought that the heavenly bodies uttered a flute-
like whistle. Perhaps he, too, was moved by that thought in composing
his theory about the sizes and shapes of the hoops that circle the earth.
So that even if we do, sadly, start from a post-enlightenment prejudice
in favour of seeing the world as random, meaningless and lacking in
beauty, still there seems to be some inconsistency in our preference
for the speculations of Anaximander over those of Pythagoras. Is that
just because we dont happen to have any texts on the music of the
spheresor rather wheelsin Anaximander?
Moving on from Anaximander to Heraclitus, let us ask a different
question, this time about logos. It has become customary in writing
about Heraclitus to leave the word logos untranslated even when writing
for a Greekless readership.18 Alternatively translators look for a standard
formulaic or non-committal translation (such as account or princi-
ple) 19 in order to avoid giving any specific meaning to the term in
17 Two key texts are Xenocrates fr. 9 Heinze, apud Porphyry Commentary on Ptole-
mys Harmonics 30 1 6 Dring; Aristoxenus fr. 77 Mller, in a scholiast on Plato
Phaedo 108d, Greene p.15.
18 R. Waterfield in the commentary in The First Philosopher, Oxford 2000; KRS;
R. McKirahan, Philosophy before Socrates, Indianapolis 1994.
19 Account in Barnes, Early Greek Philosophy, Harmondsworth 1987; T. M.
Robinson, Heraclitus; Fragments,Toronto 1987; and Kahn, H.; principle in
R. Waterfield in The First Philosophers, Oxford 2000. See also Long in this vol-
ume at n. 19.
12 Catherine Rowett
20 The motives for both practices are, of course, admirable in their way, in so far as
the translator tries to avoid imposing an interpretation by rendering the term
one way rather than another, or concealing the same term under unrecognisable
variant translations. I am not suggesting that there is a better solution, but rather
that translation is inherently unsatisfactory.
21 Logos occurs with the definite article in B 1, 2, 31b, 50; without in B 39, 45, 72,
87, 108, 115.
Philosophys Numerical Turn 13
ference? Is it that Heraclitus does not give us the numbers but only hints
tantalisingly at the existence of measures and ratios (the sea returns to
the same measure as was there before it became earth, B 31)? And is it
because the Pythagoreans tell us the numbers (that the number of the
heavenly bodies is ten, for example), but we suspect that their choice
of numbers is motivated by the desire for perfection, not the desire to
save the phenomena? And of course, we ourselves would never counte-
nance a practice of adjusting the observational results to comply with the
predictions of mathematics and theory.
Or is it that (by tradition) we systematically translate out, or interpret
out, the references to harmony and ratio in Heraclitus, so that we dont
see them as number mysticism, because instead we interpret Heraclitus
interest in logos as a kind of monotheismsomething in the tradition of
Xenophanes in which a Zeus-like divinity is rationalised and demythol-
ogised to become an immanent physical regulatory principle in the
world, a guiding principle that sees to it that we dont need to appeal
to weird metaphysical structures or mystical number patterns. It seems
that we try to see in Heraclitus a step on the route from Milesian ma-
terialism to post-enlightenment physics, and we therefore let him
have his logos in the guise of personified reasonexalted, but not tran-
scendent, much as Cartesian theism accounts for the existence and or-
derly functioning of a mathematically regular cosmos by assigning cer-
tain roles to a kind of god figure that is really not an object of cult
or mystery at all.
It is salutary to take a look at what Sextus Empiricus has to say. He
provides a lengthy analysis of the role of reason as a criterion of knowl-
edge in the Presocratic philosophers, an analysis heavily coloured by the
interests and concerns of Hellenistic epistemology. Having dealt with
Anaxagoras (the most physical of the Presocratics) 25 he introduces
the passage on the Pythagoreans thus:
ste b lm )manac|qar joim_r tm k|com 5vg jqit^qiom eWmai oR d Puha-
coqijo tm k|com l]m vasim, oq joim_r d], tm d !p t_m lahgl\tym
peqicim|lemom, jah\peq 5kece ja b Vik|kaor, heyqgtij|m te emta t/r
t_m fkym v}seyr 5weim tim succ]meiam pqr ta}tgm, 1pe_peq rp toO
blo_ou t floiom jatakalb\meshai p]vujem Gm d !qw t/r t_m fkym
tus be placed with the Milesian rational tradition, and sheltered from the pejo-
rative term mystic (which is doubtless reserved for those who fall into the Py-
thagorean mire).
25 Sextus Empiricus Adv. Math. 7.90.
Philosophys Numerical Turn 15
26 So that Anaxagoras said that the logos generally was the criterion. The Pythagor-
eans also say that it is the logosbut this time not the logos generally but the logos
that is acquired from studies (mathematics?)just as Philolaus also saidand
that given that it contemplates the nature of the universe, it has a certain affinity
with that nature, if like is by nature grasped by like But number was the prin-
ciple of the structure of the universe; hence the logos that is the judge of all
things is not devoid of this power, and would therefore be called number.
27 Text as in Huffman (above, n. 9) 199.
28 S.E. AM 7 92 140.
29 S.E. AM 7.126.
30 That is, B 1 and 2.
31 In defence of this selective use of Sextuss material, one might appeal to the fact
that we do have genuine fragments of Heraclitus in which he uses the term
logos, whereas there is no textual support for attributing that term in that
sense to Philolaus. But we should notice that Sextus is talking in terms that
are alien to the Presocratic discourse throughout, and this applies as much to
his search for a criterion of truth in Heraclitus as it does in Philolaus. On the
anachronism of the terms of the enquiry see Huffman (above, n. 9) 199 201.
16 Catherine Rowett
of Heraclitus, God or The Logos, just is the world, when alls said and
done:
God is day, night, winter, summer, war, peace, hunger satiety34
God is the processes that once seemed mysterious; but really (according
to this version) they are not so much mysterious as regular, not unpre-
dictable but reasonable. Reason, not religion, is the way to get control
of the physical events, we understand. That is what we take Heraclitus
to be saying, in his rather obscure and difficult way. So God turns out to
be no more than our picture of how the world works to a predictable
pattern. Harmony theory is then read not as a metaphysical thesis but as
a materialist one.
Conceivably this is correct as an interpretation of Heraclitus. In sup-
port, one might notice the way in which Heraclitus appeals to the no-
tion of measure in connection with specific physical processes that man-
ifest this kind of proportionalitythe notion that we find this logos in
the quantity of sea that you get back when earth has been turned
back into water (B 31), and that there are observable limits to the pas-
sage of the sun across the sky.35 It seems that, no matter how little evi-
dence Heraclitus gives for observing such regularities in nature, he does
mean that the regularities in question are part of nature. 36 Similarly, to
return to Anaximanders picture of the cosmos, those heavenly pipes
seem to be substantial and very concrete material chariot wheels revolv-
ing in the sky, invisible only because they cant be seen for the mist.
Anaximander too is giving us material explanations with numbers on
them, not numerical explanations with no matter to do the work.
34 Heraclitus B 67.
35 This is one traditional interpretation of the claim in B 94 that the sun will not
overstep its measures. The Derveni papyrus (which appears to combine what
we used to know as B 3 and 94) opens the possibility that the measures are the
suns size (a foot across, B 3) rather than its tropics. See G. Betegh, The Derveni
Papyrus: Cosmology, Theology and Interpretation (Cambridge 2004) 10 11. This
alternative is also compatible with the traditional reductionist interpretation
that I am sketching.
36 Here perhaps we assume too readily that the image of the Erinyes in B 3 (oth-
erwise the Furies, ministers of Justice, will find it out) is just a picturesque
metaphor to convey what we take to be a natural constraint on the behaviour
of the sun. Again the Derveni papyrus, with its obsession with the daimonic,
tells us that Heraclitus was not always read so rationalistically in antiquity (see
previous note).
18 Catherine Rowett
40 1090a34 5. Aristotle is bemused because they talk as though they are explain-
ing physical bodies, yet the elements they cite suggest that this cant be so. The
word seem in this sentence suggests that he thinks that to make sense of what
they are saying we need to adopt some hypothesis such as this.
41 Cf. Aristotl. Meta. A, 987b27 ja 5ti b lm tor !qihlor paq t aQshgt\, oR d(
!qihlor eWma_ vasim aqt t pq\clata, ja t lahglatij letan to}tym oq
tih]asim.
42 1090a30.
43 Aristotles comment at 1090a30 seems to conflict with the passage in Metaphy-
sics A (987b11) where he tells us that the Pythagoreans have a notion compa-
20 Catherine Rowett
I have suggested that there are striking similarities between the Pytha-
gorean concerns with number, ratio and harmony, and some of the ma-
terial that has been regarded as pioneering and profound in Anaximand-
er and Heraclitus. In asking why these moves should be considered
important and profound in the latter cases, I have suggested that they
meet with approval among modern scholars because the modern schol-
ars are assessing the Presocratic thinkers for their progress in a sequence
of developments in the direction of reductive materialist physics. Be-
cause they see the numerical patterns in the universe as immanent
p\hg of things, and do not presuppose a set of theoretical entities that
are numbers with properties of their own, the numerical fantasies of
these early Ionian thinkers are seen as an acceptableor even progres-
sive part of that generally materialist project.
It seems to me that this evaluation of the early Greek philosophers
displays an agenda that is built into our heritage of modern Presocratic
scholarship. The agenda is very evident in Barnes, but that is only be-
cause he is particularly blatant about expressing his prejudices in outspo-
ken terms. In practice he is following an existing tradition. One would
say that the tradition was Aristotelian in origin the rejection of fancy
metaphysical entities, the down-to-earth preference for specifying that
the world of particulars is what is real, the analysis of the Presocratics
as engaged in diagnosing the material cause, all these seem to be Aristo-
tles prejudices except that I think that it is a modern version of Ar-
istotelianism that has acquired a great deal of baggage from the Enlight-
enment, from logical positivism and from a more recent scientism that
equates truth with what can be proved by empirical methods. Aristotle
is certainly opposed to some of the things that he finds in Platonism,
such as the separation of Forms, but his opposition is not for quite
the same reasons as the reasons that modern Presocratic scholarship
would offer for why it doubts that Pythagorean numerology was a val-
uable contribution to Western Philosophys overall development.
number of works. See Quine, Ontological reduction and the world of num-
bers, in id., The Ways of Paradox and other essays (New York 1966), 199 207;
Ontological relativity, in id., Ontological Relativity and other Essays (New York
1969) 26 68; Propositional objects, in id., Ontological Relativity and other
Esays (New York 1969) 137 60. I am grateful to Nick Denyer for pointing
me to these references.
22 Catherine Rowett
would expect the experts in these sciences which are grouped together
because they work by theoretical manipulation of abstracted mathemat-
icals, not empirical data from physical bodies one would expect these
experts to be the ones who correctly discern the nature of things, and of
the universe as a whole. It is oqhm %topom, says Archytas, that these
people think correctly about things. But notice also the idea that they
do this jak_r they discern the workings of the universe beautifully.
And this surely links in to the idea that the workings of the universe
are themselves a fine object of attention.
That point is made more explicit by Plutarch in a passage in his
Quaestiones convivales:
psi lm owm to?r jakoul]moir lah^lasim, speq !stqab]si ja ke_oir
jat|ptqoir, 1lva_metai t/r t_m mogt_m !kghe_ar Uwmg ja eUdyka l\kista
d ceyletq_a jat tm Vik|kaom !qw ja lgtq|pokir owsa t_m %kkym
1pam\cei ja stq]vei tm di\moiam, oXom 1jjahaiqol]mgm ja !pokuol]mgm
!tq]la t/r aQsh^seyr. di ja Pk\tym aqtr 1l]lxato tor peq Eudonom
ja )qw}tam ja L]maiwlom eQr aqcamijr ja lgwamijr jatasjeur tm
toO steqeoO dipkasiaslm !p\ceim 1piweiqoOmtar, speq peiqyl]mour
d_wa k|cou d}o l]sar !m k|com, paqe_joi, kabe?m !p|kkushai cq
ovty ja diavhe_qeshai t ceyletq_ar !cahm awhir 1p t aQshgt pakim-
dqolo}sgr ja l veqol]mgr %my lgd( !mtikalbamol]mgr t_m !id_ym ja
!syl\tym eQj|mym, pqr aXspeq m b her !e he|r 1stim.
(Plat. Phaedr. 249c).52
Plutarch Quaestiones convivales 8.2.1, 718E (= DK 44 A 7a)
The thought developed by Plutarch in this passage is supposed to go
back to Philolaus in some sense,53 and indeed it is faintly reminiscent
of the passage from Sextus Empiricus which we noticed above,54
where Philolaus was said to have claimed that one gets an affinity
52 In all the so called (mathematical?) studies, the traces and images of the truth of
intelligible objects are reflected, as in even and polished mirrors; and most of all
geometry, according to Philolaus, being the source and mother-city of the
other studies, leads the mind up and converts it, like a mind purified and re-
leased effortlessly from perception. Hence Plato himself criticised the followers
of Eudoxus and Archytas and Menaechmus, who tried to divert the doubling of
the cube to instrumental and mechanical devices, as though they were trying to
obtain the two mean proportionals, however practicable, aside from rationality.
For this is to destroy and corrupt the good of geometry, when it is dragged back
to perceptible things and not carried up and not grasping eternal and bodiless
iconsthose things closeness to which makes god always be god.
53 The name Philolaus is not in the manuscript, but it is obtained by a plausible
emendation of a corrupt reading v_kaom in the manuscripts.
54 S.E. AM 7.92 (= DK 44 A 29).
Philosophys Numerical Turn 25
55 Huffman (above, n. 9) 193 194, takes the material from Philolaus to be very
brief, only the reference to geometry as the source and mother city, while all
the reflections on that are from Plutarchs Platonist context. On the other
hand it is not clear why Plutarch would be prompted to cite Philolaus at this
point if there were not some invitation to this line of thinking in the text to
which he is alluding. I think that Huffman is keen to exclude any hints of
proto-Platonism from Philolaus, and as a result he may be skimming the material
too hard.
56 There is something wrong with the story, though how exactly it has ended up
in this form in Plutarch is not entirely clear. In fact, it would appear that Archy-
tass solution to the problem of obtaining the two mean proportionals was more
theoretical and did not resort to practical methods as implied here. It makes no
sense to suggest that Archytas was one of the offenders against whom Plato
would have laid such a charge, therefore. The allusion does not seem to be
to any existing text of Plato, although the issue of the need for two mean pro-
portionals between cubic numbers figures in Platos Timaeus 31c-32b, and there
is a passage in the Republic 7.528a-d, which criticises stereometry for some fail-
ings that commentators have tried to link to the dispute mentioned by Plutarch.
See Huffman (above, n. 9) 344 401.
57 Plato Republic 527b.
26 Catherine Rowett
that learning mathematics and geometry helps us to turn our gaze up-
wards (meaning towards intellectual objects rather than corporeal or
perceptible ones), or to abstract the intelligible objects and intelligible
truths from material things. They are making a point about the useful-
ness of a particular kind of abstract discipline for intellectual exercise and
training. But in addition to that point, I would also want to add that
there is something important, even revolutionary, about the idea that
the most important reality might be the one that obeys the mathematical
rules, not the one that observably falls short, and approximates only
rather rarely to mathematical accuracy. In other words, Plato saw that
when mathematics talks about the p\hg that are numbers, it does not
treat them as p\hg of things (that is, of things that are more real than
their p\hg) but it treats the numbers as the most perfectly real things
(or at least the more perfectly real, as compared with bodily things).
This was an approach with which Aristotle was only partly out of
sympathy. It is true that he does not think that the Platonic separation
of mathematicals and forms from perceptible things is a good philosoph-
ical move. He prefers to think of the numbers as p\hg of bodies, and he
is pretty sceptical of the weird results when (as he supposes) the Pytha-
goreans imagine that things just are numbers or made out of numbers.
But the preference for the perfection of mathematics, and the location
of genuine truth and beauty in the intelligible world, is less alien to Ar-
istotles way of thinking than it is to the agenda with which modern
scholarship has approached the Pythagoreansthose prominent parts
of modern scholarship which have been responsible for relegating
them to the status of superstitious mystics.58
What do I mean? I mean that there is a seamless continuity between
Pythagorean awe at the perfect patterns in number, Parmenidess awe at
the eternity of Being, Platos awe at the Form of the Good, and Aris-
totles awe at the Unmoved Mover. All these are objects of love and ad-
miration, but their power is derived entirely from their beauty and per-
fection, not from any efficient or material causal efficacy.59 At the end of
the day, Aristotle too would locate the best and most perfect causal
power in the teleological cause, a cause discovered by abstract reasoning,
not by experimental science. The reason why Aristotle found the Pytha-
goreans puzzling was because he thought that they must be looking for
the material cause. He could not fit into his system a weird attempt to
explain bodies that have mass by appeal to entities that have no mass; but
his bemusement is created by the story that he has to tell about the de-
velopment of Presocratic philosophy. Presocratic phusikoi are (he thinks)
trying to answer the question Out of what, 1j t_mor, did the world
come? (or Out of what, 1j t_mor, is the world made?).60 Aristotle
glosses the stuff, out of which they suppose the world comes, as
their arche, and his account of his predecessors tends to be couched as
an analysis of their various attempts to cope with the logical complexity
of the notion of coming to be out of something, while supposing that the
something in question was logically playing the role of the material sub-
strate. So it makes sense that if he found the Pythagoreans saying that the
!qw^ is number (or saying what he took to be that claim), he would sup-
pose that something very weird was going on. But it was only weird be-
cause he was looking at their !qw^ as a material substrate. It is not at all
weird if you place it alongside the formal causes of the Platonists, or the
final cause that is so powerfully there in Aristotle. If, instead, you start by
wondering whether the Pythagoreans are talking about the explanatory
power of beauty, structure, form, and indeed teleology, in the universe,
the idea of appealing to patterns of numbers makes much more sense.61
If that was what they were doing, then their appeal to numbers as ex-
59 Some sources credit the Pythagoreans (Hippasus in particular) with the discov-
ery of irrational numbers, or particularly the incommensurability of the side and
diagonal in a square, and suggest that this was a challenge to their belief in the
mathematical perfection of the universe. (Porphyry Life of Pythagoras 246 7;
Clement Stromateis 5.58). But one might equally suppose that the fact that
the side and diagonal are commensurable when squared (effectively Pythagorass
theorem) would reveal a hidden rationality, a virtual rationality, in numbers that
were apparently irrational when treated as lines, and restore ones faith in the
idea of a mathematically coherent universe.
60 Aristot. Meta. 983b6 11; cf. Phys. 187a12 26.
61 Indeed there is evidence that Aristotle was partially aware of this alternative
construal, as for instance in his comments at Metaphysics N 1092b8, where
he admits that it is not clear in what sense numbers are explanatory of being,
and suggests (as the second alternative) that it is because harmony is (explained
as) a ratio of numbers and that this idea extends to explanations of other things.
28 Catherine Rowett
turn) is what is distinctive, and that is what first sets the debate about the
nature of reality and the status of the perceptible world going. Parme-
nides does this, and the Pythagoreans do it, but the materialists
dont.66 And that is one reason why one might want to say that philos-
ophy started in southern Italy, not on the coast of Turkey, and that Par-
menides was, after all, an honorary Pythagorean.67
Bibliography
Algra, Keimpe. The beginnings of cosmology, in A. A. Long (ed.), The Cam-
bridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy (Cambridge 1999) 45 65.
Barnes, Jonathan. The Presocratic Philosophers (2nd edn.; London: Routledge and
Kegan Paul, 1982).
Early Greek Philosophy. Harmondsworth 1987.
Betegh, Gbor. The Derveni Papyrus: Cosmology, Theology and Interpretation.
Cambridge 2004.
Burkert, Walter. Lore and Science in Ancient Pythagoreanism, trans. E.L. Minar Jr.
Cambridge, Mass. 1972.
Cornford, Francis MacDonald. Mysticism and science in the Pythagorean Tra-
dition, in Alexander P. D. Mourelatos (ed.), The Presocratics. (Garden City
1974) 135 60.
Couprie, Dirk L. Anaximanders discovery of space, in Anthony Preus (ed.),
Before Plato (Albany 2001) 23 48.
The Discovery of space: Anaximanders astronomy, in id., Robert Hahn,
and Gerard Naddaf (eds.), Anaximander in Context (Albany, 2003) 165
254.
Dicks, D. R. Early Greek Astronomy to Aristotle. London 1970.
Findlay, John N. Plato; The Written and Unwritten Doctrines. London 1974.
66 One feature of the prevalent view that presocratic philosophers were seeking
mechanistic and materialist explanations is the assumption that all or most of
the Presocratics were materialists in their metaphysics, and indeed that they
had no notion of the incorporeal at all. This is not the place to develop a
full defence of my claim that having a notion of the incorporeal is older and
more ordinary than the idea that there are no incorporeal entities. I see no rea-
son to suppose that it was hard for primitive thinkers to come up with an idea of
non-bodily powers and causes: assuming that there are such powers and causes
seems to me to be the norm in pre-scientific societies. I will develop this idea in
relation to the Presocratics in two further papers, as yet unpublished.
67 This paper was originally composed in 2005. The current version has not been
heavily revised to address more recent work, but it has benefited from discus-
sion with various audiences (in Samos and the B club in Cambridge in 2005,
and the pure mathematics seminar at UEA in 2006). Extensive written com-
ments from Carl Huffman on my first draft have been of immense value.
Philosophys Numerical Turn 31
Furley, David. The Greek Cosmologists. Vol. 1. Cambridge 1987.
Hahn, Robert. Anaximander and the Architects. Albany 2001.
Proportions and numbers in Anaximander and early Greek Thought, in
Dirk L Couprie, Robert Hahn, and Gerard Naddaf, Anaximander in Con-
text. (Albany 2003) 73 163.
Heidel, William A. The Pythagoreans and Greek mathematics, in David Fur-
ley and R.E. Allen (eds.), Studies in Presocratic Philosophy (London 1970)
350 81.
Huffman, Carl. Philolaus of Croton. Cambridge 1993.
The Pythagorean tradition, in A. A Long (ed.), The Cambridge Companion
to Early Greek Philosophy (Cambridge 1999) 66 87.
Archytas of Tarentum: Pythagorean, Philosopher and Mathematician King. Cam-
bridge 2005.
Kahn, Charles. Anaximander and the Origins of Greek Cosmology. New York
1960.
Kingsley, Peter. Ancient Philosophy, Mystery and Magic: Empedocles and Pythagor-
ean Tradition. Oxford 1995.
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. Correspondence with Clarke, in C. I. Gerhardt
(ed.), Die Philosophischen Schriften von Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (Berlin 1890)
7. 345 440.
Lloyd, Geoffrey E. R. Early Greek Science Thales to Aristotle. London 1970.
McKirahan, Richard. Philosophy before Socrates. Indianapolis 1994.
Naddaf, Grard, Anaximanders measurements revisited, in Anthony Preus
(ed.), Before Plato (Albany 2001) 5 23.
Nussbaum, Martha C. Eleatic conventionalism and Philolaus on the condi-
tions of thought, HSCP, 83 (1979) 63 108.
OBrien, Denis. Anaximanders measurements, CQ 17 (1967) 423 32.
Quine, Willard V. Ontological reduction and the world of numbers, in id.,
The Ways of Paradox and other essays (New York 1966), 199 207.
Ontological relativity, in id., Ontological Relativity and other Essays (New
York: Columbia University Press, 1969) 26 68.
Propositional objects, in id., Ontological Relativity and other Esays (New
York 1969) 137 60.
Robinson, Thomas M. Heraclitus: Fragments. Toronto 1987.
Vogel, Cornelia J. de. Pythagoras and Early Pythagoreanism: an Interpretation of Ne-
glected Rvidence on the Philosopher Pythagoras. Assen 1966.
Waterfield, Robin. The First Philosophers. Oxford 2000.
West, Martin L. Early Greek Philosophy and the Orient. Oxford 1971.
2. Pythagorean Communities
From Individuals to a Collective Portrait
Leonid Zhmud
3 Peq Puhacqou ja t_m cmyqlym aqtoO (fr. 11 25), Peq toO PuhacoqijoO
bou (fr. 26 32), Puhacoqija !povseir (fr. 33 41), )qwta bor (fr. 47 50).
4 S. White, Principes sapientiae: Dicaearchus biography of philosophy, in W.
W. Fortenbaugh and E. Schtrumpf (eds.), Dicaearchus of Messana (New Bruns-
wick 2001) 195 236.
5 See L. Zhmud, The Origin of the History of Science in Classical Antiquity. Berlin
2006.
6 W. Burkert, Lore and Science in Ancient Pythagoreanism (Cambridge, Mass. 1972).
7 B. L. van der Waerden, Die Pythagoreer: Religise Bruderschaft und Schule der Wis-
senschaft. Zrich 1979.
2. Pythagorean Communities 35
the Olympic victors Milon and Iccus, the botanist Menestor, the philos-
ophers Hippon and Philolaus, and the mathematicians Hippasus and The-
odorus all appear in our sources to be closer to Anaxagoras than to Em-
pedocles. There is no evidence even for their belief in metempsychosis.
They are as normal as they can possibly be. It is their normality that has a
strong appeal to me, for if these people were Pythagoras students and fol-
lowers, we can learn something important from them about him and the
society he founded. If, furthermore, the Pythagoreans that we know of
were not the superstitious ritualists who adhered to rules forbidding
them to travel on main roads, use public baths, speak in the dark, step
over a yoke, sit on a bushel measure, stir the fire with a knife, etc.,13
then who were these ritualists? If they are nowhere to be found, we
must abandon the idea that such Pythagoreans ever existed.
To be sure, some of the Pythagoreans known to us did perform
miracles of faithfulness for their friends, like Damon and Phintias (Aris-
tox. fr. 31 Wehrli), but this is not a kind of miracle with which we
should be concerned. Nor should we worry about the rather abnormal
behavior of the Pythagorean athlete and general Milon: Aristotle calls
him pokvacor, according to the late sources, he devoured about
nine kilograms of meat a day and just as much bread and drank ten litres
of wine.14 Now, these stories are not just amusing anecdotes. Taken se-
riously, they reveal quite an important distinction. Milon, this Pythagor-
ean of the Pythagoreans, behaves in exactly the opposite way to what
could be expected of a true follower of Pythagoras. But how do we
know what should be expected of a true Pythagorean? In other
words: what sources do we use to create a composite image of a true
Pythagorean? Are they the same as our sources on the individual Pytha-
goreans? No, they are not. If we collect everything that is known about
the individual Pythagoreans and compare this with what is known about
anonymous Pythagoreans, Pythagoreans as a particular collective identi-
ty, we get very different pictures. Sometimes even one and the same au-
thor produces a different picture: Aristotles individual Pythagoreans
differ radically from his Pythagoreans in general, this time not in
their behavior, but in their doctrines.15 This is one of many reasons
why we ought to be very cautious about referring to the Pythagor-
eans as a collective identity, for this is the very area of the classical tra-
dition where we can expect to encounter the grossest distortions.
In the modern as well as in the ancient world, the stories told about a
social, ethnic, or cultural minority are often quite different from the sto-
ries told about the individuals who constitute these minorities. Though it
is not that the first are necessarily false and the second always true, the dis-
tinction between the two is quite important. If we proceed empirically,
our collective portrait of the Pythagoreans should look more or less
like a sum total of the traits common to all the individual Pythagoreans,
as well as those specific traits which are irreducible to a common denom-
inator. Certainly, oR Puhacqeioi is often just a faon de parler, behind
which the real figures are discernible, e. g., Archytas, who stands behind
the Pythagoreans in Platos Republic (530a531c), or Philolaus, whose as-
tronomical system Aristotle ascribes to some anonymous Pythagoreans
(De caelo 293a18 ff.). But equally often, the collective Pythagoreans do
not correspond to any known individuals, e. g., the Pythagoreans of
Anaximander the Younger, or those of Aristotles Metaphysics, or those
of Aristoxenus work Puhacoqija !povseir. In the last case as well as
in Theophrastus Metaphysics (11a27-b10), they are very much like the
Platonists. One can dispute these examples and adduce others, but this
hardly affects my general thesis: if actions or ideas allegedly peculiar to
the collective Pythagorean identity do not find independent confirmation
at an individual level, we will stay on safer ground by preferring individual
to collective evidence. Accordingly, still more suspicious are those testi-
monies about the Pythagoreans in general which plainly contradict the evi-
dence about individual Pythagoreans.
Some examples follow, beginning with the rules of conduct. The
traditional sources on Pythagorean vegetarianism are divided.16 Some
say that Pythagoreans did not eat meat, others that they abstained
from particular kinds of meat or particular parts of the animals. On an
individual level, strict vegetarianism is not attested, whereas consump-
tion of meat is. This means we should rather conclude that some Pytha-
goreans did eat meat, even if some others probably did not. Secondly, let
us look at their doctrines. Aristotle, who was followed by Theophrastus,
who was followed by the entire later tradition, persistently claims that
the core of Pythagorean philosophy is that all is number. We do
not find this thesis held by any of the Pythagorean thinkers, though
we find other Pythagorean ideas on number that differ both from the
Aristotelian version and from each other. I believe, therefore, that all is
number is an Aristotelian interpretation of various Pythagorean phi-
losophical and scientific ideas.17 Thirdly, we look at institutions. The
story that the early Pythagorean society was divided into mathematikoi
and akousmatikoi seems to be ineradicable from the scholarly literature,18
even though this story is found first in Porphyry (VP 37) and Iamblichus
(VP 80 89), and even though the word lahglatijr is first attested in
Platos Sophist (219c), whereas !jouslatijr is first found six centuries
later, in Clement of Alexandria (Strom. 5, 59). There is obviously some-
thing persuasive about this story that has made it so enduring. Burkert,
who once tried to show that it originated with Aristotle, now admits
that this is impossible to prove.19 Even if this story were a part of the
fourth-century tradition, we would not find in the sixth or the fifth cen-
tury any counterparts to the mathematikoi as they are described by Iam-
blichus and even less to the akousmatikoi. Should we believe that these
people existed but left no individual trace, whereas their collective por-
trait was kept secret to be disclosed only by Porphyry? I think it is better
to see this story for what it really is: as a construct of the Imperial age.20
Admittedly, the methodological individualism that I am professing is
not entirely unproblematic. In a sense, it is easier to follow its alternative,
definitional essentialism, i. e., to define and discuss specific Pythagorean
qualities or theories. If we speak of the Pythagoreans in general, there
is no need to bother about every individual Pythagorean: a deviant case
can always be treated as an exception. However, if one starts from the in-
dividual level, every single Pythagorean counts. In this case, the question
who is to be counted as a Pythagorean and according to which criteria?
becomes crucial. This is not an easy question, and modern research offers
widely differing answers. If one believes the late sources, the written Py-
thagorean tradition starts only with Philolaus, who lived a century after
Pythagoras. Accordingly, the Pythagoreans before Philolaus did not
write books, which means that those who did, e. g. Alcmaeon, Menestor,
and Hippon, were not real Pythagoreans.21 If one does not trust the late
sources, but does trust Plato and Aristotle, the matter does not get any eas-
ier, for both of them avoided calling anyone a Pythagorean. Neither
Philolaus and his students in the Phaedo, nor Archytas in the Seventh Let-
ter, are called Pythagoreans. Was Platos teacher in mathematics, Theodo-
rus of Cyrene (43 A 2), a Pythagorean or a friend of Protagoras? Of
course, he could have been both, but Plato testifies only to the second.
Obviously he had his reasons to be reticent. Aristotles treatises are
quite densely populated with anonymous Pythagoreans and to a lesser de-
gree with individual Pythagoreans. He does mention by name Alcmaeon
(Meta. 986a27), Hippasus (Meta. 984a7), Hippon (Meta. 984a4; De an.
405b2), Philolaus (EE 1225a30), Eurytus (Meta. 1092b10), and Archytas
(Meta. 1043a21; Rhet. 1412a12; Pol. 1340b26), but he never tells us that
they were Pythagoreans.
If one looks not only to the ancient but to the modern authorities as
well, the situation appears less dramatic. But in Diels and in the other
modern collections of Pythagorean materials, we are faced with another
problem: there are too many Pythagoreans. Partly this is because the se-
lection criteria used are either not clear enough or not consistent. Diels
does not explain his criteria for considering someone a Pythagorean,
though he makes them quite visible, namely, by putting the evidence
from Aristoxenus catalogue of the Pythagoreans (Iamb. VP 267 = DK
58 A) at the beginning of part A. Except for one passing remark,22 I
have not found any explicit statements that he considered this catalogue
to derive from Aristoxenus and thus to be evidence of primary impor-
tance, although this is certainly what he believed. Further, Diels does
not always follow Aristoxenus. Thus, he places Cercops, Petron, Paron,
and Xuphus among the early Pythagoreans, though their names are lack-
ing in the catalogue. I think that he was wrong in all four cases.
According to Aristotle (fr. 75 Rose), the poet Cercops lived in Hes-
iods time, so he could not have been a Pythagorean.23 However, Epi-
genes, a grammarian of the Hellenistic age,24 in his book On the Writings
Attributed to Orpheus, calls Cercops a Pythagorean and ascribes two
poems to him: Zeqr kcor and EQr AVdou jatbasir (other authors at-
tributed these poems to Pythagoras). This evidence is not very reliable.
Orphic poetry was always pseudonymous and there was no way to fig-
ure out the names of its real authors. Epigenes attributions must, there-
fore, have been guesswork, as was most of the other evidence of this
kind. In Cicero the reference to Cercops is linked to a quotation
from Aristotle, who claimed that there had never been a poet called Or-
pheus: Orpheum poetam docet Aristoteles numquam fuisse et hoc Orphicum
carmen Pythagorei ferunt cuiusdam fuisse Cercopis. 25 Only the first part of
this evidence derives from Aristotle (as is confirmed by a quotation
from Philoponus), whereas the second part goes back to Epigenes.26 Ar-
istotle would not call Hesiods contemporary a Pythagorean; more
importantly, he never calls anyone a Pythagorean.
We know about Petron (DK 16) only from a certain Hippys of
Rhegium, whose testimony is quoted by the Peripatetic Phanias of Ere-
sos; it is very likely that this is a forgery.27 Paron (DK 26) owes his ex-
istence to Aristotles mistake in taking the participle PAQYM to be a
proper name.28 Xuphus (DK 33) is mentioned only once in Aristotles
Physics (216b22). In the commentary to this passage, Simplicius calls
him a Pythagorean but it is impossible to verify his claim.
In Maddalenas and Timpanaro Cardinis works,29 Epicharmus, Ion
of Chios, Damon, Hippodamus, Polyclitus, Oenopides, and Hippo-
crates of Chios are considered to be Pythagoreans. This goes even fur-
ther than Diels and is absolutely too far. Their names are not found in
the catalogue and, moreover, no classical source considers any of them a
Pythagorean or even a pupil of the Pythagoreans. Even if Oenopides or
Hippocrates studied mathematics with the Pythagoreans, this fact alone
does not make them Pythagoreans.
Of the fourth century Pythagoreans on Diels list, another three
have to be removed. Timaeus of Locri (DK 49) owes his existence to
the Platonic dialogue and, later, to a Pseudo-Pythagorean text.30 Ocellus
the same tradition, even if this view was not expressed by Hippasus and
Theodorus, who were not interested in medicine.
Admittedly, in Pythagorean science, i. e., in the four mathemata, the
situation looks different. There is such a common body of theories here,
and there are many more affinities among the views of different scien-
tists. Yet this consistency is not specifically Pythagorean; it is related to
the methods of the respective science. Hippocrates of Chios developed
Pythagorean geometry, Archytas solved the problem posed by Hippo-
crates, and Eudoxus studied geometry with Archytas, but neither Hip-
pocrates nor Eudoxus were Pythagoreans. What is specifically Pythagor-
ean in the exact sciences is the preoccupation with all four mathemata,
including arithmetic and harmonics. Indeed, before Pythagoras (or, if
you prefer, before Hippasus), theoretical arithmetic and mathematical
harmonics did not exist; and after Hippasus, the IoniansOenopides
and Hippocrates of Chios and to a certain degree also Democritusde-
veloped only geometry and astronomy, not the other two branches of
the quadrivium. This means, among other things, that Theodorus of Cy-
rene, who is mentioned in Aristoxenus catalogue and who taught all
four sciences (43 A 1, 4), was a Pythagorean and not just a friend of Pro-
tagoras. This means, furthermore, that Archytas predecessors, whose
knowledge of all four mathemata he praises at the beginning of his
work (47 B 1), were the Pythagoreans, and not Hippocrates of Chios
or the other Ionian mathematicians.34
This rather long digression was needed, I think, to make clear why
the question that I raised earlierabout how a Pythagorean can be de-
finedshould be settled on the basis of reliable classical sources. It is not
enough that a person calls himself a Pythagorean, like Lycon, the critic
of Aristotle, or the proto-Cynic Diodorus of Aspendus,35 for this is evi-
dence that they were not. But if someone was considered a Pythagorean
by his contemporaries or by the Pythagoreans themselves, this means
that he was judged by more complex and reliable criteria than we can
employ now. This means that he shared with the other Pythagoreans
not just one but many common features and at that it is these exact fea-
tures that define a Pythagorean, both from an internal and an external
point of view.
and of these eight at least three are rather dubious figures. I would like
to point out here that we should approach Aristoxenus list critically,
like any other historical document, especially taking into account that
it comes from Iamblichus, who lived 600 years later. Though it does
not contain the names of the individuals who lived after Aristoxenus,
it is possible that some of the famous names on the list were added
later, after Aristoxenus. Being on the list does not guarantee that the
person in question really was a Pythagorean. In several cases, doubt re-
mains and on occasion there is evidence to warrant deleting a person
from the list. However, if there is no evidence to this effect, we can
consider the data of the catalogue to be a sufficient proof that the person
in question can be seen as a Pythagorean.
Though it is our most important document, the catalogue is by far
not the only one. Theophrastus mentions Hicetas of Syracuse (50 A 2),
who is not on the list, whereas his compatriot Ecphantus is wrongly
placed among the Pythagoreans from Croton (DK I, 446.11). Pythago-
ras contemporary, the famous Crotonian doctor Democedes, who mar-
ried a daughter of the Pythagorean athlete Milon (Hdt. 3, 127 137 =
19 A 1), is not on the list either. Obviously, in the course of catalogues
transmission, some names have been lost. For example, Aristoxenus fa-
ther Spintharos is absent, as well as Amyclas, though Aristoxenus men-
tions both him and his friend Cleinias (fr. 131 Wehrli), who is on the
list. Absent from the list are also Philolaus students Simmias and
Cebes (44 A 1a, B 15). The name of Parmenides teacher, the Pythago-
rean Ameinias, appears only in the Hellenistic biographer Sotion (D. L.
9.21 = 28 A 1). These significant names need to be added (as pluses)
to the catalogue.
On the other hand, the catalogue contains some names that clearly
should be removedminuses. For example, there are the ancient
lawgivers Zaleucus of Locri and Charondas of Catane, who seemed
to be associated with Pythagoras by the Pythagorean communities in
Locri and Rhegium as early as the fifth century. This means that Aris-
toxenus sources (fr. 17, 43 Wehrli) reflect a respectful but unreliable
historical tradition. Another famous duo are the miracle-workers, Aris-
teas and Abaris. Aristeas of Proconnesus, a shadowy figure from the late
seventh century BC, was the author of the Arimaspea, a poem describing
his journey in search of the Hyperboreans. During his lifetime, Aristeas
disappeared twice, and, according to Herodotus (4, 13 15), after the
second time, he reappeared 240 years later in Metapontum and told
the citizens to set up an altar to Apollo and dedicate a statue to himself.
2. Pythagorean Communities 45
41 Von Fritz Pyth. Politics (above, n. 33) 80 ff.; Minar (above, n. 33) 36 ff.
42 Minar (above, n. 33) 69 70; M. Giangiulio, Ricerche su Crotone arcaica (Pisa
1989) 311 n. 52; M. Bugno, Da Sibari a Thurii: La fine di un impero (Naples
1999) 41 2.
43 C. Mann, Athlet und Polis im archaischen und frhklassischen Griechenland (Gttin-
gen 2001) 164 ff.
2. Pythagorean Communities 47
way of life. Democedes (19 A 1) and Alcmaeon were two other pro-
minent representatives of the Crotonian school of medicine, which
stressed the importance of dietetics and gymnastics in maintaining
good health.44 The botanical book of Menestor was related to medicine
(DK 32), just as were the natural-philosophical writings of Alcmaeon
(24 A 1, B 4) and later, those of Hippon (38 A 11).
Our fourth category is natural philosophers, physikoi, according to
the Aristotelian terminology. Here we have Alcmaeon, Brontinus
(one of the addressees of Alcmaeons book; 24 B 1), Hippasus (18 A
1, 12), and Menestor. Among those born around 480 470 BC, there
are two other physikoi, Hippon and Philolaus.
The fifth category is mathematikoi, i. e., people concerned with any
of the four mathemata or with all of them. Strangely enough, we know
the names of only two mathematicians from the first 100 years of the
Pythagorean school: Hippasus (18 A 4, 14 15) and Theodorus (43 A
3 5). There is no doubt that there were many more, because by the
time when Oenopides and Hippocrates of Chios were active, i. e.,
about 450 430 BC, the bulk of the first four books of the future Ele-
ments of Euclid had already been written,45 which was an impossible feat
for only one or two people. Regrettably, we cannot identify the other
mathematikoi. For example, Parmenides teacher Ameinias could have
been a physikos, or a mathematician, or both. Alcmaeon was interested
in astronomy (24 A 4, 12), but certainly was not a mathematikos. Philo-
laus fits this term much better, especially as an astronomer and a special-
ist in harmonics (44 A 16 21, B 6).
So far we have identified fourteen prominent Pythagoreans belong-
ing to five overlapping categories. Now, let us imagine that we know
nothing about Pythagoras himself and all we have is a collective portrait
of his students and followers and the students of these followers. What
would an individual portrait of Pythagoras look like if we had to con-
struct it solely on the basis of the available collective portrait? I believe it
would be both natural and legitimate to assume that he had something
to do with activities that, already during his lifetime, became so distinc-
tive to the Pythagorean society. Surely, we should not expect a perfect
match, because for all his pokulaha (Heracl. 22 3 40) and pokutqopa
(Antisth. fr. 51 Caizzi), Pythagoras could not have been involved in all
Bibliography
Bckh, August. Philolaos des Pythagoreers Lehren nebst den Bruchstcken seines
Werkes. Berlin 1819.
Boehm, Fritz. De symbolis Pythagoreis. Diss. Berlin 1905.
Bolton, James. Aristeas of Proconnesus. Oxford 1962.
Bugno, Maurizio. Da Sibari a Thurii: La fine di un impero. Naples 1999.
Burkert, W. Craft versus sect: the problem of Orphics and Pythagoreans, in
B. F. Meyer (ed.), Jewish and Christian Self-Definition, Vol. 3 (London 1983)
1 22.
Lore and Science in Ancient Pythagoreanism, tr. E. L. Minar, Jr.. Cambridge,
Mass. 1972.
senting view. I have not, however, written this paper mainly as a rebut-
tal of his arguments. Instead, after an introductory section (Section 1), I
present some passages which prove beyond reasonable doubt that he
used more than one source in some of his discussions of Pythagorean
doctrines (Section 2). I then present some of Aristotles claims about Py-
thagorean principles, particularly those that have to do with numbers
(Section 3), and the fragments of Philolaus that bear on principles (Sec-
tion 4),4 with a preliminary discussion of the relations between the Ar-
istotelian material and Philolaus (Section 5) and some chronological
considerations that support the likelihood that Aristotle had access to
other sources than Philolaus book (Section 6). I then translate and com-
ment on four passages from the Metaphysics that provide Aristotelian
context for many of the doctrines he ascribes to the Pythagoreans and
give important clues about how he understood those doctrines, and
whether they can be fitted into a coherent ontology (Section 7).
Next I return to the claims of Section 4 and attempt to determine
which of them are authentic Pythagorean views and which are Aristo-
telian interpretations (Section 8). On the basis of the claims I find to be
authentic, I offer a brief sketch of a way Pythagorean thought on prin-
ciples may have evolved down to the time of Philolaus (Section 9). In
the final substantive part of the paper I turn to Aristotles treatment of
Pythagorean principles and attempt to account for his evident frustration
and lack of sympathy with their views. I suggest that Aristotles difficulty
in making sense of that aspect of Pythagorean thought is due to a fun-
damental difference between his way of approaching philosophical issues
and theirs (Section 10).
reports (32, 63), and even mentions that he might have made use of other
writing (63), but he does not give serious weight to these other possibilities,
especially since he (wrongly, see n. 19) rules out Archytas as a possible source.
For discussion of individual points in Huffmans treatment, see nn. 5, 13, 14,
19, 42, 43, 50, 52, 109, 117, 133, and pp. 98 9.
4 Philolaus B1-B6, quoted and translated in Section 4. Huffman considers these
fragments authentic. See n. 12.
Aristotle on the Pythagoreans 55
5 The frequently made assertion that Aristotle commonly or often refers to the Py-
thagoreans as oR jako}lemoi Puhacoqe?oi (sometimes translated the so-called Py-
thagoreans) is false, e. g. Burkert (above, n. 2) 30. This expression occurs only six
times (Cael. 284b7, 293a20; Metaph. 985b23, 989b29; Mete. 342b30, 345a13) of
which four (those from De Caelo and Metaphysics) are found in contexts where
Aristotle refers to the Pythagoreans also as oR Puhacoqe?oi. By contrast, I count
thirty-nine occurrences of oR Puhacoqe?oi in the following works: Posterior Ana-
lytics, De Anima, De Caelo, Nicomachean Ethics, Magna Moralia, Metaphysics, Oeco-
nomicus, Physics, Problems and in the Fragments. Further, I see no reason to sup-
pose that Aristotle means oR jako}lemoi Puhacoqe?oi in the sense of the so-called
Pythagoreans. The passages cited by Huffman (Pol. 1290b40 and 1291a1, GA
734a19, De an. 410b28) equally support the view that the phrase means those
known as Pythagoreans, those I call Pythagoreans for my present purposes
or even those who call themselves Pythagoreans. The occurrences of jako}le-
moi in the Politics support this interpretation.
6 One: D.L. 8.85; three: Iamblichus VP 199. Huffman (above, n. 3) 12 14 rea-
sonably rejects the evidence for three books.
7 Timon F 54 (= DK 44 A8), D.L. 8.85.
8 D.L. 8.55 and other texts discussed by Huffman (above, n. 3) 15.
9 See discussion in Huffman (above, n. 3) 8.
10 D.L.s catalogue of Aristotle works (D.L. 5.25) names both Pqr tor Puhaco-
qe_our and Peq t_m Puhacoqe_ym. Burkert (above, n. 2) 29 n. 5 accepts both as
genuine.
11 D.L. 5.25.
12 Huffman (above, n. 3) 34 takes Fragments 1 7, 13, and 17, and Testimonia 9,
16 (part), 17 (part), 18 21, and 27 28 to be genuine.
56 Richard McKirahan
On the strength of these facts, Huffman has proposed that since Ar-
istotles work on Archytas will have been based on Archytas writings,
Philolauss writings will be the only written source of Aristotles refer-
ences to those called Pythagoreans and the Pythagoreans in the
summaries of Pythagorean thought in his extant works.13
If this is true, and in particular if the Pythagoreans whose views Ar-
istotle records from time to time do not include Archytas, two questions
immediately arise. First, why does Aristotle not speak of Philolaus, but
of the Pythagoreans as a group? And second, how do we account for
discrepancies between Aristotles accounts and Philolauss fragments?
Regarding the first question, it is difficult to find a plausible explanation
for Aristotles failure to name Philolaus in the relevant passages.14 The
answer to the second question depends on the magnitude of the discrep-
ancies. If they are small, we may simply say that Aristotle may have
thought he was representing Philolaus accurately and he may not
have noticed the discrepancies even though we do. Further, Aristotles
lack of sympathy for Pythagorean views and his evident failure to make
sense of them may have resulted in distortions. But clearly, the greater
the discrepancies prove to be, the harder it is to explain them away. In
what follows, I will argue that some discrepancies are very great indeed.
On the other hand, if we suppose that Philolaus was not Aristotles
only source, there are several straightforward ways to explain Aristotles
preference for speaking of the Pythagoreans and his avoidance of men-
tioning any single Pythagorean, Philolaus in particular. First, his ac-
counts of Pythagorean ideas may not be based on Philolaus at all, but
on one or more other Pythagorean sources, written or oral, that are un-
known to us. In this regard we must not neglect lost works on the Py-
thagoreans, such as the book of Aristoxenus, whose sources we are not
in a position to name or evaluate. Second, his accounts may be based on
Philolaus and on other Pythagorean sources as well. If there was more
than one Pythagorean source at hand, Aristotle need not have expound-
ed them separately. It would have been natural for him to give a single
13 Huffman (above, n. 3) loc. cit. Philolauss book is the only likely candidate
(32); it is hard to say who Aristotles sources would have been if not Philolaus
(58 9). But Huffmans argument, even if sound, will apply only to Aristotles
lost works on the Pythagoreans, not to what he says about Pythagorean doc-
trines in his extant treatises. I can find no reason to exclude the possibility
that some of his remarks on the Pythagoreans, in particular his account of Eur-
ytus, are based on Archytas (see n. 19).
14 Even Huffman (above, n. 3) 34 seems to register unease on this point.
Aristotle on the Pythagoreans 57
account stitched together from more than one source if he had thought
that the differences were not major, and especially if he thought it un-
important for his particular purposes to make fine distinctions among
the differing views.
I will proceed by giving some evidence that Aristotle used more
than one source (or a compendium of Pythagorean views, conceivably
one of his own works that was based on more than one source) for his
information on the Pythagoreans. In the subsequent treatment of Aris-
totelian passages on Pythagorean principles, I will point out some claims
that do not fit well with what we know of Philolauss views and which
may be easier to account for by supposing that they stem from different
sources. Later in the paper I will suggest (though it must remain only a
suggestion) that Aristotle did not even use Philolaus as his principal
source for Pythagorean doctrines, and that he may have regarded him
as somewhat out of the mainstream. If this is so, it is no longer myste-
rious that Aristotle did not identify Philolaus in particular as the source
of his information.
15 J. Barnes (ed.), The Complete Works of Aristotle. The Revised Oxford Translation, 2
vols. (Princeton 1984).
16 I translate t 6m as the one (in scare-quotes). In most cases I take it as equiv-
alent to the number one.
58 Richard McKirahan
things that are; those people suppose that numbers have magnitude. (tr.
based on the Revised Oxford Translation) 17
Meteorologica 342b29 33: t_m d( Ytakij_m timer jakoul]mym Puhacoqe_ym
6ma k]cousim aqtm eWmai t_m pkam^tym !st]qym, !kk di pokkoO te
wq|mou tm vamtas_am aqtoO eWmai ja tm rpeqbokm 1p lijq|m.
Some of the Italians called Pythagoreans say that it [sc. the comet] is one of
the planets, but that it appears at great intervals of time and only rises a little
above the horizon. (tr. based on the Revised Oxford Translation)
De Sensu 445a16 17: d d k]cous_ timer t_m Puhacoqe_ym, oqj 5stim euko-
com tq]veshai c\q vasim 5mia f`a ta?r asla?r.
What some of the Pythagoreans say is unreasonable. They declare that
some animals are nourished by odors alone. (my tr.)
I take it that Aristotle means one thing when he says that the Pythagor-
eans held a view and another when he says that some Pythagoreans
held a view, and what he means in the latter case is that other Pythagor-
eans held different views on the same subject, whether or not he tells us
what those other views are. In three instances he actually presents rival
Pythagorean views.
De Anima 404a16 19: 5oije d ja t paq t_m Puhacoqe_ym kec|lemom
tm aqtm 5weim di\moiam 5vasam c\q timer aqt_m xuwm eWmai t 1m t`
!]qi n}slata, oR d t taOta jimoOm.
The doctrine of the Pythagoreans seems to have the same idea; some of
them declared that the soul is the motes in the air, while others said that
soul is what moves them. (tr. based on the Revised Oxford Translation)
Meteorologica 345a13 18: t_m lm owm jakoul]mym Puhacoqe_ym vas_ timer
bdm eWmai ta}tgm oR lm t_m 1jpes|mtym timr !st]qym, jat tm keco-
l]mgm 1p Va]homtor vhoq\m, oR d tm Fkiom toOtom tm j}jkom v]qesha_
pot] vasim oXom owm diajejaOshai tm t|pom toOtom E ti toioOtom %kko
pepomh]mai p\hor rp t/r voqr aqt_m.
Of those called Pythagoreans some say that this [viz. the Milky Way] is the
path of one of the stars that fell from heaven during the alleged destruction
at the time of Phaethon, while others say that the sun once moved in this
circle; and so this region was scorched or met with some other affection of
this kind, because of the motion of these bodies. (tr. based on the Revised
Oxford Translation)
Metaphysics 986a15 17, a22 6: va_momtai d ja oxtoi tm !qihlm mol_-
fomter !qwm eWmai ja r vkgm to?r owsi ja r p\hg te ja 6neir, 6te-
qoi d t_m aqt_m to}tym tr !qwr d]ja k]cousim eWmai tr jat sustoi-
w_am kecol]mar, p]qar [ja] %peiqom, peqittm [ja] %qtiom, 4m [ja] pk/hor,
denim [ja] !qisteq|m, %qqem [ja] h/ku, AqeloOm [ja] jimo}lemom, eqh
[ja] jalp}kom, v_r [ja] sj|tor, !cahm [ja] jaj|m, tetq\cymom [ja]
2teq|lgjer.
Evidently, then, these thinkers consider that number is the principle both as
matter for the things that are and as their attributes and states. Others of
this same group say there are ten principles, which they arrange in parallel
columns limit and unlimited, odd and even, one and plurality, right and
left, male and female, resting and moving, straight and curved, light and
darkness, good and bad, square and oblong. (tr. based on Revised Oxford
Translation)
Did Aristotle derive this information from a single source? If he did, it
would almost have to be a compendium of their views rather than a sin-
gle original text such as that of Philolaus, which seems (like other pre-
socratic texts, as far as we can tell) to have set out its authors theory
without expounding other peoples contrasting views.
In one case Aristotle refers a particular doctrine to a Pythagorean
other than Philolaus.
Metaphysics 1092b10 12: ja r Euqutor 5tatte t_r !qihlr t_mor, oXom bd
lm !mhq~pou bd d Vppou, speq oR tor !qihlor %comter eQr t sw^-
lata tq_cymom ja tetq\cymom ovtyr !voloi_m ta?r x^voir tr loqvr
t_m vut_m.
This is how Eurytus decided what was the number of whate. g., this is
the number of man, that is the number of horse by imitating the figures
of living things with pebbles, like those who bring numbers into the forms
of triangle and square. (tr. based on the Revised Oxford Translation)
Since Eurytus is said to have been the student of Philolaus,18 it seems un-
likely that Aristotles source on this point would have been Philolauss
book. In fact, Theophrastus attributes this information to Archytas.19
I take it that these passages prove beyond doubt that Aristotle knew of
cases where different Pythagoreans held different views, and I take it as a
consequence that his information on at least these areas of Pythagorean
philosophy did not come from Philolaus or from any other single Pytha-
gorean source.20 This result establishes the possibility, if not the strong
likelihood, that Aristotle was indebted to a plurality of sources in other
cases where he reports disagreeing Pythagorean views, even where he
does not go out of his way to say that a particular view was held by
some Pythagoreans. In fact, we will shortly see that his accounts of Py-
thagorean views on the nature of first principles and on the relations be-
tween numbers and things contain a good deal of disagreement.
20 By saying this, I do not mean to exclude the possibility that he used a single
work, such as a compendium of Pythagorean views, that was itself based on
more than one source.
21 This designation refers to the translation and discussion of the passages in ques-
tion below, in Section 7. The translation given in these cases is my own trans-
lation.
Aristotle on the Pythagoreans 61
In fact they apply their propositions to bodies supposing that they consisted
of those numbers. (tr. based on Revised Oxford Translation)
Metaphysics 1090a22 3 (C4.4): 1po_gsam 1n !qilhl_m t emta.
They made the things that are, out of numbers. (my tr.)
Metaphysics 1090a32 (C4.6): poie?m 1n !qihl_m t vusij s~lata.
They make the natural bodies out of numbers. (tr. based on Revised Ox-
ford Translation)
N2 The things that are (or things) are numbers.
Metaphysics 986a21 (C1.13): !qihlor d], jah\peq eUqgtai, tm fkom oqqam|m.
The entire heaven, as has been said, is numbers. (tr. based on Revised Ox-
ford Translation)
Metaphysics 987b27 8: oR d( !qihlor eWma_ vasim aqt t pq\clata.
They say that the things themselves are numbers. (tr. Revised Oxford
Translation)
Metaphysics 1090a22 3 (C4.2): eWmai lm !qihlor 1po_gsam t emta.
They made the things that are, numbers. (my tr.)
N3 The things that are are number.22
Metaphysics 986a2 3 (C1.9): tm fkom oqqamm "qlom_am eWmai ja !qihl|m.
[They supposed] the entire heaven to be a musical scale and a number. (tr.
based on Revised Oxford Translation)
Metaphysics 1083b17 (C3.2): 1je?moi d tm !qihlm t emta k]cousim.
They say that the things that are, are number. (my translation)
N4 Things resemble numbers; the things that are, are by imitation of
numbers.
Metaphysics 985b27 31 (C1.3-C1.4): 1m d to}toir 1d|joum heyqe?m
bloi~lata pokk to?r owsi ja cicmol]moir, lkkom C 1m puq ja c0 ja
vdati, fti t lm toiomd t_m !qihl_m p\hor dijaios}mg t d toiomd
xuw^ te ja moOr 6teqom d jaiqr ja t_m %kkym r eQpe?m 6jastom blo_yr.
In these (viz. numbers) they thought they observed many likenesses to the
things that are and that come to be such and such an attribute of num-
bers being justice, another being soul and mind, another being the right
moment,23 and similarly for virtually all other things. (my tr.)
N11 The elements (stoiwe?a) of number are the even (which is unlim-
ited) and the odd (which is limited); the one is from the even and
the odd, and number is from the one.
Metaphysics 986a17 21 (C1.12) toO d !qihloO stoiwe?a t| te %qtiom ja
t peqitt|m, to}tym d t lm pepeqasl]mom t d %peiqom, t d( 4m 1n
!lvot]qym eWmai to}tym (ja cq %qtiom eWmai ja peqitt|m), tm d( !qihlm
1j toO 2m|r.
The elements of number are the even and the odd, and of these the former
is unlimited, and the latter limited. And the one is from both of these
(for it is both even and odd) and number is from the one. (tr. based on
Revised Oxford Translation)
N12 When the one had been constituted, the nearest part of the un-
limited immediately began to be drawn in and limited by the limit.
Metaphysics 1091a15 18: r toO 2mr sustah]mtor, eUt( 1n 1pip]dym eUt( 1j
wqoir eUt( 1j sp]qlator eUt( 1n m !poqoOsim eQpe?m, eqhr t 5ccista toO
!pe_qou fti eVkjeto ja 1peqa_meto rp toO p]qator.
When the one had been constituted (whether from planes or from a sur-
face or from seed or from things which they are at a loss to say), the nearest
parts of the unlimited at once began to be drawn in and limited by the
limit. (tr. based on Revised Oxford Translation)
N13 The sustoiw_a (parallel columns)
Metaphysics 986a22 6 (quoted in Greek above, pp. 58 9): Others of this
same group say there are ten principles, which they arrange in parallel col-
umnslimit and unlimited, odd and even, one and plurality, right and
left, male and female, resting and moving, straight and curved, light and
darkness, good and bad, square and oblong. (tr. based on Revised Oxford
Translation)
N13 contrasts with the rest, and is marked as being the view of others
of this same group, that is, other Pythagoreans. The remaining texts are
concerned with numbers as principles of other things and with the prin-
ciples of numbers. They are an untidy collection. Their untidiness lends
itself to two ways of treating them, either as reflections of a single co-
herent ontology or as derived from different sources that represent dif-
ferent and incompatible views.
The first approach points towards a system of at least three tiers,26 as
follows.
26 Burkert describes a system along these lines at Burkert (above, n. 2) 32 ff. I pres-
ent a five-tier system below, p. 101.
Aristotle on the Pythagoreans 65
Tier 1: the limited (or limit) and the unlimited, or the even and the odd
Tier 2: numbers
Tier 3: all things (that is, all things not included in Tiers 1 and 2)
No one of the claims N1-N12 sets out the entire system, but each of
them can be seen as revealing a part of it. The limited and the unlimited
(or the even and the odd) are the principles of numbers (some testimo-
nia favor the idea that the one is prior to and in some way a principle
of the other numbers27), which are in turn the principles of all things;
in a sense the limited and the unlimited are the principles of all things
too. The notion of principle involved is not spelled out or analyzed. It
may be metaphysical (in the sense of an essentially basic entity), genetic
(in the sense that the principles generate the things whose principles
they are), temporal (in the sense that the principles exist before the
things whose principles they are), material (in the sense that the things
are made up out of their principles), or a combination of these.
The overall picture that this approach produces is as follows. The
principles of numbers are the limited and the unlimited, or alternately
the even (which is unlimited) and the odd (which is limited). These
principles first generate (or compose or are the ingredients in the essence
of) the one. The one generates (or composes, etc.) the (other)
numbers. Numbers are the causes of the oqs_a of the remaining things,
which are generated by (or composed of, etc.) numbers, or are numbers,
or are by imitation of numbers. The variety of ways in which Aristotle
expresses the relation between numbers and things will reflect differen-
ces in his sources and also the difficulty he had in comprehending these
ideas and his fundamental lack of sympathy with them.
Where the first approach smoothes over disagreement among the
passages, the second approach emphasizes their discrepancies. Thus, it
is one thing to say (N2) that things are numbers, and quite another to
say (N1) that they are 1j numbers, whether that means that they are
constituted out of numbers as a statue is constituted out of bronze, or
that numbers generate them or something else. It is still another thing
to say (N6, cf. N5) that the principles or elements of numbers are the
principles or elements of all things, which is compatible with all things
being on the same level (whether ontological, causal, genetic or other-
wise) as numbers and not dependent on them at all. And yet another
thing to say (N4) that things are by imitation of numbers. We may
also doubt that N8s assertion that the oqs_a of all things is number and
N10s claim that numbers are causes of the oqs_a of the other things are
consistent. It is not clear how to unify N11s claim that the one is 1j
the even and the odd with N12s assertion that the Pythagoreans are at a
loss to say how the one was constituted. Or how the one is related
to the unlimited in N8: is the unlimited one of the principles of the
one, or is it identical with the one? Other inconsistencies are easy
to find in these claims as well. A straightforward way to account for
them would be to suppose that Aristotle is basing his accounts on several
sources which he considered to represent Pythagorean thought and that
they were broadly similar, yet importantly different.
These two approaches lead to two different assessments of Aristotles
treatment of his sources. On the first, the sources state their views im-
precisely and/or Aristotle does a poor job of understanding what they
say; on the second, the sources may well state their (contrasting)
views precisely and Aristotle may succeed in understanding their claims
or at least reporting them accurately (even though he finds it impossible
to make philosophical sense of them). The two approaches also lead to
two different assessments of early Pythagorean views on principles. The
first supposes that there is a Pythagorean orthodoxy behind Aristotles
various expressions (except for the outlier N13). A variation on this as-
sessment is that Aristotle is using only one source (perhaps Philolaus)
which is self-consistent. The second approach makes no such supposi-
tion. The different and inconsistent claims that Aristotle attributes to
the Pythagoreans are in fact more or less accurate expressions of different
Pythagorean beliefs.
This second approach is certainly worth considering and it is also
worthwhile to consider Philolaus in connection with it. If we do not
suppose from the start that Philolaus was Aristotles only source, or
that Aristotles source or sources, whoever or whatever they may
have been, need have told a coherent and consistent story, we are
free to look for variations, seeing Pythagoreanism as a movement rather
than as a monolithic theory (which would have been unique for its time;
we find no uniform set of doctrines among either the Milesians or the
Eleatics28) and even to evaluate Philolauss position within the move-
28 I name the two obvious candidates in early Greek philosophy for groups of
thinkers closely associated with one another. In fact, it is not infrequent even
now to read of the Milesian school and the Eleatic school of philosophy.
But the differences in the views of Thales, Anaximander, and Anaximenes are
Aristotle on the Pythagoreans 67
The main texts for Philolauss views on principles are the following.29
B1 " v}sir d( 1m t` j|sl\ "ql|whg 1n !pe_qym te ja peqaim|mtym, ja
fkor <b> j|slor ja t 1m aqt` p\mta.
Nature in the cosmos was joined from both unlimiteds and limiters, and the
entire cosmos and all the things in it.
B2 !m\cja t 1|mta eWlem p\mta C peqa_momta C %peiqa C peqa_momt\ te
ja %peiqa %peiqa d l|mom ouj !e. 1pe to_mum va_metai out( 1j peqaim|m-
tym p\mtym 1|mta out( 1n !pe_qym p\mtym, d/kom tqa fti 1j peqaim|mtym
te ja !pe_qym f te j|slor ja t 1m aqt` sumaql|whg. dgko? d ja t 1m
to?r 5qcoir. t lm cq aqt_m 1j peqaim|mtym peqa_momti, t d( 1j peqai-
m|mtym te ja !pe_qym peqa_momt_ te ja oq peqa_momti, t d( 1n !pe_qym
%peiqa vam]omtai.
It is necessary that the things that are be all either limiters or unlimiteds or
both limiters and unlimiteds; but not in all cases only unlimiteds. Now
since it is evident that they are neither from things that are all limiters
nor from things that are all unlimiteds, it is therefore clear that both the cos-
mos and the things in it were joined together from both limiters and un-
limiteds. The behavior of these things in turn makes it clear. For those
of them that are from limiters limit, those that are from both limiters
and unlimiteds both limit and do not limit, and those that are from unlim-
iteds will evidently be unlimited.
B3 !qwm oqd t cmyso}lemom 1sse?tai p\mtym !pe_qym 1|mtym.
well known: whatever the Milesians had in common, it was not that they ad-
hered to any specific doctrines. And the uniformity in the views of the Eleatics
is less than perfect. Notably, Aristotle is as impressed by the differences in the
views of Parmenides and Melissus as much as he is by their similarities (Aristotle
Phys. 184b16, 185b17 18; Metaph. 986b18 21).
29 I follow Huffmans text, but use my own translations, which differ from Huff-
mans in some respects.
68 Richard McKirahan
There will not be anything that is going to know at all, if all things are un-
limited.
B4 ja p\mta ca lm t cicmysj|lema !qihlm 5womti oq cq bti_m
<oX|m> te oqdm oute mogh/lem oute cmysh/lem %meu to}ty.
And in fact all the things that are known have number. For it is not possible
for anything at all either to be comprehended or known without this.
B5 f ca lm !qihlr 5wei d}o lm Udia eUdg, peqissm ja %qtiom, tq_tom d
!p( !lvot]qym liwh]mtym !qtiop]qittom 2jat]qy d t_ eUdeor pokka loq-
va_, $r 6jastom aqt sgla_mei.
In fact, number has two proper kinds, even and odd, and a third kind,
even-odd, from both mixed together.30 Of each of the two kinds there
are many forms, of which each thing itself gives signs.
B6 peq d v}sior ja "qlom_ar de 5wei " lm 1st t_m pqacl\tym !_dior
5ssa ja aqt lm " v}sir he_am te ja oqj !mhqyp_mgm 1md]wetai cm_sim
pkm ca C fti oqw oX|m t( Gm oqhem t_m 1|mtym ja cicmysjol]mym rv(
"l_m cem/shai l rpaqwo}sar tr 1stoOr t_m pqacl\tym, 1n m sum]sta
b j|slor, ja t_m peqaim|mtym ja t_m !pe_qym. 1pe d ta !qwa rpqwom
oqw blo?ai oqd( bl|vukoi 5ssai, Edg !d}matom Gr ja aqta?r joslgh/mai, eQ
l "qlom_a 1pec]meto timi_m #m tq|p\ 1c]meto. t lm m blo?a ja
bl|vuka "qlom_ar oqdm 1ped]omto, t d !m|loia lgd bl|vuka lgd
Qsotaw/ !m\cja t toiaOta "qlom_ sucjejke?shai, eQ l]kkomti 1m j|sl\
jat]weshai.
Concerning nature and "qloma this is how it is: the being (1st~) of things,
which is eternal that is, in fact, their very nature admits knowledge that
is divine and not human, except that it was impossible for any of the things
that are and are known by us, to have come to be if there did not exist the
being (1st~) of the things from which the cosmos is constitutedboth the
limiters and the unlimiteds. But since the principles are not similar or of the
same kind, it would be completely impossible for them to be brought into
order if "qloma had not come upon them in whatever way it did. Now
things that are similar and of the same kind have no need of "qloma to
boot, but those that are dissimilar and not of the same kind or of the
same speed[] must be connected together in "qlomai if they are going
to be kept in an orderly arrangement.
B7 t pqtom "qlosh]m, t 4m 1m t` l]s\ tr sva_qar, 2st_a jake?tai.
The first thing that was joined, the one in the middle of the sphere, is called
the hearth.
B17 b j|slor eXr 1stim, Eqnato d c_cmeshai %wqi toO l]sou ja !p toO
l]sou eQr t %my di t_m aqt_m to?r j\ty, <ja> 5sti t t %my toO
l]sou rpemamt_yr je_lema to?r j\ty. to?r cq j\ty t jatyt\ty l]qor
30 I follow J. Barnes, The Presocratic Philosophers 2 (London 1982) 632 n. 31, in de-
leting this phrase.
Aristotle on the Pythagoreans 69
that they resemble them (contrast N4), or that the being34 of a thing is
the first thing it happens to belong to (B6, contrast N9) or that the
one and the other numbers are the 1st~ of anything at all (B6, contrast
N10). Finally, the doctrine of the parallel columns (N13) is remote from
anything Philolaus says.35
Philolauss belief that all the things that are known have number
(B4) is importantly different from N1, N2, and N3, first because B4
concerns all the things that are known, not all things in general,
and second because B4 says that they have number, not that they
are or are constituted out of number or numbers. Nor does Philo-
laus talk of things imitating numbers or having likenesses to numbers
(N4). B4 gives the impression that having number is a necessary con-
dition for a thing to be known, but not a necessary and sufficient con-
dition for a thing to be, and for this reason Huffman sees the role of
number as epistemological rather than ontological.36 However, this
may be too strong; the one need not exclude the other. B4 makes it
plausible that Philolaus supposed that a thing that is known is known
because it has number and that it is known because of the number that
it has. Further, it is possible that he held that it is a things possession
of number (whatever that may mean and however the number it pos-
sesses may be related to the limiters and unlimiteds that constitute that
thing) that constitutes the thing as knowable. If this is correct, it leaves
open the possibility that number has an important ontological role
alongside its epistemological role.37 But even so, Aristotles reports on
the place of number in Pythagorean thought remain remote from
what we learn from B4.
Philolaus offers an ontology with at least two38 tiers: on the top tier
are the limiters and the unlimited, which are first principles, while the
bottom tier is constituted of what Philolaus describes as nature in the
cosmos and the entire cosmos and all the things in it (B1). The es-
sential question here is where do numbers fit inare they on the top
tier, the bottom tier, somewhere in between, or are they not included
in the entities B1 refers to? Unfortunately the fragments provide insuf-
ficient help. The terminology of limiters and unlimiteds is so abstract
that it is not at all certain what it refers to,39 and it is quite unclear
whether the entire cosmos and all the things in it includes numbers
in addition to (what we regard as) more concrete objects.40
Further on this point, N12 is usually taken to describe the genera-
tion of numbers by the action of limit on the unlimited. If this is the
correct interpretation, it has no connection with Philolauss surviving
fragments (although this does not prove that he did not hold the
view). In any case, in N12 the one and the other generated entities
are not principles, so that numbers cannot belong to the top tier. How-
ever, there are some difficulties. In the first place, as N12 says, how the
one is constituted was not made clear. Next, the nature of the relation
between the one and the subsequently generated entities is obscure.
More radically, it is not even certain that N12 describes the generation
of numbers at all. Huffman has proposed an interpretation according to
which N12 has nothing to do with numbers; the one refers to the
central fire, and the passage is an account of the first stage of a cosmog-
ony.41 And most importantly, to assume that there is any connection be-
tween N12 and Philolaus would beg the question, since this is the very
subject under investigation.
39 Huffman (above, n. 3) 40 1.
40 An interpretation which I hope to develop in the near future is that for Philo-
laus the number of a thing is (in a suitably general sense) the measure of the
magnitudes of the entities (limiters and unlimiteds) that constitute an entity.
If this is correct, then for Philolaus things are not constituted out of numbers
or identical with numbers and do not resemble numbers, but it is possible
that he held that in some sense the being of a thing is or involves its number.
41 Huffman (above, n. 3) 203 4 with 211 14. However, in Burkerts view, to
the Pythagoreans number philosophy is cosmogony (above, n. 2, 36 and dis-
cussion 31 40). The generation of the number series is identical with the gen-
eration of the cosmos. (Cf. Aristotle, Metaph. 986a2 3: They supposed the
entire heaven to be a musical scale and a number.) Burkert is in agreement
with Ross: The Pythagoreans are trying to describe at one moment the forma-
tion of the number system and that of the physical universe, which is just what
on their principles they were bound to do. The number One is identified with
the central fire, as two was with the earth and seven with the sun. See W. D.
Ross, Aristotles Metaphysics (Oxford 1924) vol. 2, 484.
Aristotle on the Pythagoreans 73
44 See p. 103.
45 D.L. 8.46.
Aristotle on the Pythagoreans 75
birth.46 This would provide 388 as a terminus post quem for his death, but
it offers no evidence at all for how much later than 388 he died. In fact
the evidence for dating his birth as early as 470 is weak. It consists prin-
cipally of statements that Philolaus was the teacher of Eurytus and that
he and Eurytus were the teachers of the last of the Pythagoreans, who
include Echecrates, who is a (younger? older?) contemporary of Plato
(born c. 428).47 Huffman discusses the evidence, but makes some as-
sumptions which, although they are in general reasonable, need not
hold in a given case. For example, he assumes that teachers are older
than their students, and allows a ten or twenty year age difference.
But it is not always true that teachers are older than their students,
and it frequently happens that if they are older they are not much
older. Moreover, it is not always clear what teacher and student
mean in ancient contexts. The claim is typically of the form so-and-
so heard (Ejouse or di^jouse) so-and-so or so-and-so was a hearer
(!jqoat^r) of so-and-so. If Philolaus had written a philosophical book
and expounded it to others, might that not be enough to qualify them as
having heard him, no matter what their relative ages? And is there
any good reason to think that Philolaus could not have written such a
book by the time he was twenty or thirty? So if Philolaus was in fact
born as late as 440, he would have had plenty of time to have been
heard by the people who are said to have heard him. In addition,
he would have been only 52 in 388, and only 73 when Aristotle
came to Athens in 367. He might have lived another twenty years be-
yond thatand attended Platos funeral.48 On this accounting there is
46 Huffman (above, n. 3) 2 5.
47 See Plato, Phaedo 57a-b.
48 The following true story is indicative of how far back we can go in time in only
a few steps. My fourteen-year-old daughter has an English friend who once told
me that her grandfathers grandmothers gardener, who was a very old man, re-
ported that his grandfather said that the admiral was a very great man indeed.
Then she asked me who the admiral in question was. I ventured a guess: Nel-
son? No, she said. It was Drake. So in a very few steps ( just four jumps in
time back from my daughters friend) we are back in touch not with the hero of
Trafalgar, whose two hundredth anniversary is being celebrated this year
(2005), but with contemporaries of the man who destroyed the Spanish Armada
in 1588. We can imagine how this works out without any stretch of the imag-
ination. My daughter was born in 1991. My daughters friend was born in 1924.
Her father was born around 1885. So her grandfather could have been born
around 1835. His grandmother could have been born eighty years earlier in
1755. The gardener could have been 85 years older than her, so born in
76 Richard McKirahan
no reason why Aristotle could not have met Philolaus himself. The case
is even easier to make for the possibility of his meeting later Pythagor-
eans such as Simmias, Cebes, and Echecrates, together with the other
members of the group known as the last generation of Pythagoreans, es-
pecially the long-lived Xenophilus, who for all we know was Aristotles
next door neighbor in Athens. In any case if Aristoxenus, whose birth is
placed in the period 375 360 (which makes him nine to twenty-four
years younger than Aristotle), met these last Pythagoreans, there can
be no objection to supposing that his teacher Aristotle could have
met them too. He surely had contact with Aristoxenus himself, and
in the context of the Academy and the Lyceum there may have been
no shortage of people who, if not Pythagoreans themselves, were famil-
iar with their views. Aristotle might even have used Aristoxenus book
on the Pythagoreans as his source.
Clearly, Aristotle found out about Pythagorean views from some-
where. Either he had access to written texts now unknown or he
may have found out from one or more people who claimed to know.
He knew about and reported some views that are unlikely to have
come from Philolauss book, for example the reports about Eurytuss
pebbles (which is in fact said to have been reported by Archytas49)
and the doctrine of the parallel columns. And it is far from clear that
Philolaus pursued the program of identifying numbers with such things
as justice, marriage, and the right moment (Metaph. 1078b22 3).50 If
the doctrine of the ten planets (including the counter-earth) moving
round the central fire belongs to Philolaus,51 then the view Aristotle at-
tributes to some Pythagoreans, that the comet is one of the plan-
1670. And his grandfather could have been born eighty years earlier in 1590.
When he was a boy he would surely have heard from his family and acquain-
tances about the greatness of the Admiral, who died in 1595. A similar concat-
enation of acquaintances could mean that Aristoxenus informant Xenophilus
and Philolaus as well could have associated with Pythagoreans who had
known Pythagoras personally.
49 See n. 19.
50 Huffman (above, n. 3) 286 8 floats the possibility, but his discussion is far from
proving the case.
51 Aristotle (attributes this cosmology to the Pythagoreans but Atius attributes
it to Philolaus in particular, Atius 2.7.7 (= Stobaeus, Ecl. 1.22.1d, DK 44 A16),
3.11.3 (= [Plutarch], Placita 895E; DK 44 A17), 3.13.2 (= [Plutarch], Placita
896 A, DK 44 A21).
Aristotle on the Pythagoreans 77
see how Aristotle put it together to form the interpretation that he uses
in his own discussions. The following account of the four passages from
the Metaphysics that contain Aristotles discussions (as opposed to isolated
remarks) of Pythagorean views on principles and on the relation be-
tween numbers and things (C1: 985b23 986a21, C2: 987a13 27,
C3: 1083b8 13 & b17 19 and C4: 1090a20 5, a32 5) aims to
offer a precise translation and a commentary that explicates Aristotles
train of thought in his account of Pythagoreanism. The interpretations
given in the commentary will provide the basis of the subsequent at-
tempt to understand Aristotles remarks on Pythagorean principles and
on the relations between numbers and things (N1-N13) and to assess
their trustworthiness (Section 8).
whole. This story is necessarily selective and leaves out important points in
order to preserve coherence; Huffman (above, n. 3) 179.
Aristotle on the Pythagoreans 79
the entire heaven, as has been said, is numbers. (tr. based on the Revised
Oxford Translation, with significant modifications)
C1 begins with the well known statement that the Pythagoreans were
the first to make serious progress in mathematics. The fact that that
modern scholarship has rejected57 this claim is a serious blow to the
credibility of Aristotles account of Pythagorean principles, since he
bases it on their alleged interest in mathematics. Still, one need not be
a serious mathematician in order to have a serious interest in numbers;
indeed a fascination with numbers and their power is widespread among
peoples who have not developed mathematics to any notable degree.58
Aristotle gives a tidy picture. The Pythagorean interest in mathe-
matics led them to conclude that the principles of mathematical entities
are the principles of all the things that are C1.1. They reasoned that
since numbers are the primary kind of mathematical entities C1.2 and
numbers are the first things in the whole of nature C1.7,59 the elements
of numbers are the elements of all the things that are C1.8, which is a
restatement of C1.1 (with elements apparently used as a synonym of
principles60). Aristotle mentions some of the connections the Pytha-
goreans discovered between numbers and things which could be used
in support of C1.7: first, likenesses between numbers and the things
that are C1.3, with examples C1.4, and second, attributes and ratios of
harmonic intervals which they discovered in numbers C1.5. Conse-
quently (d^)61 all other things appeared to be made in the likeness of
numbers C1.6, and numbers seemed to be primary in all nature C1.7.
The first thing to notice is that Aristotle presents two different kinds
of grounds for the view that the principles or elements of number are
the principles or elements of all things. First, C1.3-C1.4 that they
thought that they observed that some attribute of numbers was justice,
another attribute was soul and mind, and still another was the right
moment. Second, C1.5 that they saw the numerical properties of
harmonic intervals. How large was the difference between the second
kind of grounds and the first can be judged from Alexanders explana-
tion in his comment on this passage.
They supposed that requital and equality were characteristic of justice and
they found these features in numbers, and so declared that justice was the
first number that is equal-times-equal.They said that the right moment
is the number 7, since things which are natural appear to have their decisive
moments of fulfillment in birth and growth by sevens. Humans, for exam-
ple. They are born in the seventh month and teethe in as many months,
and reach adolescence in the second span of seven years and get a beard
in the third They said that marriage is the number 5, because marriage
is the union of male and female, and according to them the odd is male and
the even is female, and this number is the first which has its origin from 2,
the first even number, and 3, the first odd. They declared mind and sub-
stance to be the one,62 since he spoke of the soul as the mind. They said
that because it is stable and similar in every way, and sovereign, the mind is
the unit and the one; and substance is the first thing. (Alexander in Met-
aph. 38,10 39,15)
The ways in which justice, the right moment, marriage, soul/mind
and substance are associated with numbers are very different from one
another, and can justifiably be called fanciful (cf. Aristotles they thought
that they observed [1d|joum heyqe?m]). They have virtually nothing to
do with mathematics. It appears that the Pythagoreans were determined
to make things fit their theory by hook or by crook. On the other hand,
the attributes and ratios of the harmonic intervals (2:1 for the octave,
3:2 for the fifth, 4:3 for the fourth) are derived systematically, have a
basis in nature (cf. they saw [bq_mter] and can be used to make certain
kinds of mathematical calculations.63 On the basis of this kind of evi-
dence, goes Aristotles story, the Pythagoreans concluded that all
other things appeared in their entire nature to be likened after numbers
C1.6. This broad generalization is the kind of move Aristotle attributes
to other presocratic philosophers as well.64
The second thing to notice is that Aristotle says neither that the Py-
thagoreans held that justice is a number but that such and such an at-
tribute of numbers is justice,65 nor that they claimed that the attributes
and ratios of harmonic intervals are numbers, but that they saw those at-
tributes and ratios in numbers, by which I think he must mean that they
saw that numbers have the same attributes and ratios as are found in the
harmonic intervals. Passage C1 makes better sense if we keep this in
mind. At this point he is recounting the grounds on which the Pytha-
goreans founded their strange view that the principles of numbers are
the principles of all things. The numerical basis of the harmonic intervals
was a real discovery, not a fancy. Also, the common points between,
say, justice and the number four, although perhaps arbitrarily chosen,
are comprehensible; and these discoveries are described in a way that
does not commit the Pythagoreans from the outset to any strange
views at all. The strangeness comes in first with C1.6 and more so
with the conclusions in C1.7 and C1.8.
C1.6 is not simply a generalization of C1.3. The earlier claim that
numbers have likenesses (bloi~lata) to things is symmetric. If A is like
B in some respect, then B is like A too, in the same respect. In particular
if some thing and some number have some attribute in common, so that
the number has a likeness to the thing,66 then by the same token the
thing has a likeness to the number. But being made in the likeness of
(!voloioOshai) is an asymmetric relation: if A is made in the likeness
of B, then B is in some way the original and A the copy.
C1.7 contains an important element of Aristotles account. Since for
Aristotle nature involves change whereas numbers are unchanging,
numbers are not part of nature;67 for the Pythagoreans they are. This
distinctively Aristotelian use of nature appears here as a key word
in his description of the Pythagorean view; that they included numbers
as part of nature will follow from the view that they considered numbers
65 However, he says elsewhere that they identified opinion, the right moment,
injustice, decision, and mixture with particular numbers (Metaph. 990a23 24).
The difference corresponds to the differences between Stages 1 and 2 in the de-
velopmental account of Pythagorean thought about principles which I give
below, p. 101.
66 Note that C1.3 says that in these [viz. numbers] they thought they observed
many likeness to the things that are and not in the things that are they ob-
served many likenesses to numbers.
67 For example, Metaph. M.3, 1078a2 9: mathematics deals neither with sensible
things qua sensible but with sensible things qua lines and planes (a para-
phrase).
Aristotle on the Pythagoreans 83
Finally, C1.2 and C1.7 yield C1.8. Since by C1.2 numbers are the
first among mathematical entities, it follows that the principles of num-
bers70 are the principles of mathematical entities; since by C1.7 numbers
are the first things in the whole of nature, we reach the desired conclu-
sion C1.8 that the elements of numbers are the elements of all the things
that are, which is apparently intended as equivalent to the original thesis
C1.1 that the principles of mathematical entities are the principles of all
things.71
The immediately following claim C1.9 that the entire heaven is a
musical scale and a number, has no direct relation to the preceding dis-
cussion despite its immediate syntactical connection to C1.8.72 It is not
concerned with principles of things or numbers, and it is the only part of
passage C1 that identifies a physical entity with a number. In fact, it
identifies it as a number and a harmonia,73 which implies that it takes har-
monies to be numbers, an identification not found in C1.5. C1.9 intro-
duces C1.10, which gives an example of the way in which the Pytha-
goreans in question enthusiastically applied their mathematical ideas to
nature. The importance they gave the number ten led them to invent
a tenth celestial body since they could only find nine.
The final section of C1, C1.11-C1.13, is not a passage of continu-
ous exposition like C1.1-C1.10. It presents difficulties. The material
immediately preceding C1.11 suggests that Aristotle will state how
the Pythagorean doctrine on principles fits in with his own doctrine
of four causesbut that is the topic of only part of C1.11; C1.12 pro-
vides new information on their views on principles, and C1.13 repeats
material stated above whose connection with what is said in C1.11 and
C1.12 is not obvious.
70 There may be a shift here between two notions of principle: the principles of an
entity (number) and the principles of a science (mathematics). (See n. 54.) A
charitable reading would take C1.1 as speaking about the principles of mathe-
matical entities.
71 See above, p. 80.
72 C1.9 also introduces a thesis that will be important later on. See the discussion
of C1.13 below.
73 In C1.5 qlom_a is translated harmonic interval, referring, for example, to the
interval of the octave. Here, assuming that the reference is to the harmony of
the spheres, it refers to a system of harmonic intervals embodied in particular
musical notes, hence something close to a musical scale.
Aristotle on the Pythagoreans 85
which the even and the odd (which are somehow related to the unlim-
ited and the limited83) are ultimate principles. They are the immediate
principles of the one;84 the one is the immediate principle of num-
ber. And in all these cases the notion of principle in play is that of the
material cause.
C1.13 repeats C1.9 almost verbatim, except that it omits mention
of the musical scale and says that the heaven is numbers rather than
number.85 Following the claim in C1.12 that number is from (1j)
the one, C1.13 completes the ontology. By asserting that the entire
heaven is numbers it links the sensible world with the preceding levels.
Although it does not state so explicitly, it seems to indicate that numbers
are the principles of the sensible world; we already have something close
to this claim in C1.7, that numbers seemed to be primary in all nature.
There remains the problem raised by the assertion in C1.11 that
number is a principle as the attributes and states of things that are. As
with the first problem, it is possible to ascribe it to a separate Pythagor-
ean source, but there is no need for this expedient, since it can be seen as
recapitulating points made earlier in the passage. Since numbers are pri-
mary in nature C1.7 Aristotle might well call them principles of other
entities. And he might well have interpreted the thesis that other entities
are made in the likeness of numbers in their entire nature C1.6 to in-
clude their being made in the likeness of number in their attributes
and states, that is to say, that numbers have the same attributes and states
that other entities do. Thus, the principles of things would be numbers
as having the attributes of those things. Further, some of the things
identified in C1.4 with attributes of numbers ( justice, the right mo-
ment) are themselves attributes rather than substances, which is another
reason for saying that numbers are the principles of the attributes and
states of things. For these reasons I am inclined to see this claim of
C1.11 as an Aristotelian interpretation of Pythagorean views.
C2 Metaphysics 987a13 27
oR d Puhac|qeioi [C2.1] d}o
lm tr !qwr jat tm aqtm eQq^jasi tq|pom, tosoOtom
d pqosep]hesam d ja Udi|m 1stim aqt_m, fti [C2.2] t pepeqa- 15
sl]mom ja t %peiqom [ja t 4m] oqw 2t]qar timr ^hgsam
eWmai v}seir, oXom pOq C c/m E ti toioOtom 6teqom, !kk( [C2.3] aqt
t %peiqom ja aqt t 4m oqs_am eWmai to}tym m jatgco-
qoOmtai, [C2.4] di ja !qihlm eWmai tm oqs_am p\mtym. peq_ te
to}tym owm toOtom !pev^mamto tm tq|pom, ja [C2.5] peq toO t_ 1stim
20
Eqnamto lm k]ceim ja bq_feshai, k_am d( "pk_r 1pqacla-
te}hgsam. q_fomt| te cq 1pipoka_yr, [C2.6] ja pq~t\ rp\q-
neiem b kewher fqor, toOt( eWmai tm oqs_am toO pq\clator 1m|-
lifom, speq eU tir oUoito taqtm eWmai dipk\siom ja tm
du\da di|ti pq_tom rp\qwei to?r dus t dipk\siom. !kk( 25
[C2.7] oq taqtm Usyr 1st t eWmai dipkas_\ ja du\di [C2.8] eQ d l^,
pokk t 4m 5stai, [C2.9] d j!je_moir sum]baimem.
The Pythagoreans similarly [C2.1] posited two principles, but they added
something peculiar to themselves, that [C2.2] the limited and the unlimited
are not distinct natures like fire or earth or anything else of that kind,86 but
that [C2.3] the unlimited itself and the one itself are the substance
(oqs_a) of the things of which they are predicated. This is why [C2.4]
they call number the substance (oqs_a) of all things. On this subject,
then, they expressed themselves thus; and [C2.5] regarding the question
of what things are (t_ 1sti) they began to make statements and definitions,
but treated the matter too simply. For they would define superficially and
they thought that [C2.6] the first thing an indicated term applies to is the
essence (oqs_a) of the thing, as if one were to suppose that double and the
number two are the same because two is the first thing double applies to.
But surely [C2.7] to be double and to be two are not the same; [C2.8] oth-
erwise, one thing will be many[C2.9] a consequence which they actually
drew. (tr. based on the Revised Oxford Translation)
C2 occurs shortly after C1, still in the context of Aristotles discussion of
the principles and causes recognized by earlier philosophers. C2, which
concludes Metaphysics A5 and ends the treatment of the pre-Platonic
thinkers, is a brief appendix on two Pythagorean theses as yet unmen-
86 For this translation of v}sir, see LSJ s.v. vi. Contrast Rosss more interpretive
translation were not attributes of certain other things, e. g., of fire
Aristotle on the Pythagoreans 89
thing to recognize is that we are several steps further down the ontolog-
ical hierarchy from C2.3, no longer at the level of ultimate principles
but at the derivation of the lowest level from numbers. Where C1
said that number is the principle as matter for the things that are
C1.11, C2 says that number is the substance of all things. The difference
between these two claims mirrors the difference between C1s and C2s
statements about the unlimited and the limited that were noted at the
end of the previous paragraph.91
The second topic begins at C2.5. This topic is advertised in C2.5 as
the Pythagorean contribution to the study of essence and definitions (t_
1stim, bq_feshai), but these terms do not recur in the passage, which (in
continuation of C2.4) is principally concerned with the relations be-
tween numbers and things, specifically about the way in which numbers
are the substance of things. The issue of numbers as principles drops out
of sight. The present concern is the identification of things with numbers.
The example Aristotle provides us in C2.6 treats the identification of
double with the number two. The grounds for this identification
are that the number two is the first subject to which the attribute dou-
ble applies. It applies to the other even numbers as well, but it is iden-
tified with the number two, and hence the number two is its substance.
The wording suggests that it is not an example that the Pythagoreans
themselves used, but that Aristotle thought it was typical of the reason-
ing that they did use. It is hard to see how this account would work for
any of the explanations of the identification of justice, soul/mind, sub-
stance, and the right moment with numbers that Alexander provides
in the passage quoted above (p. 81), since it is unclear in what sense the
associated numbers are the first things to which the entities in question
apply. Moreover, if Aristotle is right, it is hard to see how more than
one thing could be identified with the same number: how can several
things be first? On the other hand, these considerations by no
means indicate that Aristotle was mistaken in attributing this kind of rea-
soning to the Pythagoreans. In fact, the by hook or by crook ap-
proach the they used in amassing evidence for their views92 and the spe-
cificity of Aristotles statement here makes it more likely that he is
correct than mistaken.
Aristotle next goes on to make an objection to the practice of iden-
tifying things with numbers. The objection is simply that to be double
and to be the number two are not the same C2.7. The expression to be
so-and-so (t eWmai followed by the dative) is one of Aristotles standard
technical ways of referring to essence. He means that the essence of
double is different from the essence of the number two, which entails
that the definition of two is different from the definition of double
which is indeed the case, even though the definition of double may
well contain the word two. And if they have different essences,
they are different. So when the Pythagoreans claim that the double is
the number two, they are saying that two different things are the
same, and therefore one C2.8. This objection does not depend on
the possibly non-authentic example of double and the number two,
or on the fact that two is the first number to which double applies,
even though it is stated in the terms of that example. The same result
will hold for the other identifications mentioned by Aristotle and ex-
pounded by Alexander (for example, that justice is the number four)
even if the kind of grounds for identifying double and the number
two that Aristotle describes in C2.6 does not apply in those cases. Aris-
totle can fairly object that to be justice and to be the number four are
not the same thing. This may be enough to justify the comment
C2.9 that the Pythagoreans are committed to this absurdity. But the
comment may also reflect the fact that in some cases several things are
associated with the same number, as Alexander says that soul/mind
and substance are identified with the one.
that are, are number. [C3.3] In fact [?at any rate] 93 they apply their prop-
ositions to bodies supposing that [?as if] they94 consisted of those numbers.
(tr. based on the Revised Oxford Translation)
C3 is an important passage for the relation between things and numbers.
In it Aristotle speaks of bodies, that is, physical objectsunlike the
things he mentioned in C1: justice, the right moment, and the
like. The absence of examples in C3 is sorely felt. It is clear from the
context that C3.1 represents a view Aristotle attributes to the Pythagor-
eans: that bodies are composed of (1j) numbers (N1). Also that C3.2
represents another such view: that the things that are, are number
(N2). The question is whether these are two representations of the
same view: did they hold both views or only one, and if only one,
which one. C3.3 has been taken to prove that the Pythagoreans at-
tempted to relate properties of number to properties of things, but
did not make the relation between numbers and things clear. Aristotle
sees the Pythagoreans applying mathematical speculations to bodies in a
way that suggests that they think that the bodies are composed of num-
bers, and on this basis he ascribes to them the thesis that all things are
numbers.95 The argument goes that C3.3 shows that Aristotle found
no clear statement that the Pythagoreans held N2. C3.3 gives Aristotles
reason for thinking that the Pythagoreans held N2, but in fact C3.3 re-
quires N1, not N2. N2 is simply Aristotles misunderstanding.
However, this interpretation is not decisive. It takes coOm as having a
limitative force (at least, at any rate) and r with the genitive abso-
lute as meaning as if (in effect, counterfactually). But coOm can also
have an emphatic force (in fact, indeed), and in several places in Ar-
istotle, in the Metaphysics in particular, it can well be translated in this
way. Also, r with the participle typically denotes the thought in
the mind of the subject of the principal verb without implicating
the speaker or writer96 and means in the belief that or supposing
93 The words in brackets here and in the following line are possible alternative
translations, which Huffman adopts. See discussion below.
94 I take s~lasim to be the antecedent of emtym. See H. W. Smyth, Greek Gram-
mar (Cambridge, Mass. 1956) 2072: The genitive of the participle [in the
genitive absolute] may stand without its noun or pronoun, and 2073a:
The genitive absolute may be used where the grammatical construction de-
mands the dative; cf. Thuc. 1.114.1 diabebgj|tor Edg Peqijk]our stqati
)hgma_ym Acc]khg aqt` fti
95 Huffman (above, n. 3) 61.
96 Smyth (above, n. 94) 2086.
Aristotle on the Pythagoreans 93
that. If these alternative ways of taking the two particles are adopted,
C3.3 does not express Aristotles grounds for supposing that they held
N2. Instead it expresses the idea that in addition to holding N2, they
also did something else that stems from their belief (to which Aristotle
does not subscribe) that bodies are composed of numbers. In this con-
nection it is worthwhile to note that as in C3.2 Aristotle typically ex-
presses N2 as the things that are (t emta) are numbers, not bodies
are numbers, so the references to bodies being composed of numbers
in C3.1 and C3.3 may be another indication that Aristotle is not infer-
ring N2 from the consideration advanced in C3.3.97
98 Aristotle acknowledges this much at 1090a30 31. On this score the Pythagor-
eans fare better than Plato and Speusippus (the latter of whom he treats briefly
at 1090a25 30).
Aristotle on the Pythagoreans 95
tributes or components of those bodies. Since one entity can have many
attributes, and since its different attributes may be due to different num-
bers, if a thing is simply identical with the numbers that cause its attrib-
utes, it may be identical with different numbers. But this would have the
impossible consequence that those different numbers are identical with
one anothera result that can be avoided by interpreting N2 as N1 and
allowing a thing to be composed of more than one number. C4 may
display traces of this progression of thought. First we have the thesis N2,
that the things that are, are numbers C4.2, which invites the question in
what way things are numbers. C4.3 states that the Pythagoreans did not
adopt one possible answer to this question, the Platonic answer that
numbers are separate entities, participation in which accounts for
the properties of things. C4.4 presents the answer Aristotle says they
did adopt. It is a surprising answer, since numbers may not seem to
be the right kinds of things to be components of sensible bodies.
C4.5, then, supports this answer by repeating a familiar Pythagorean
point (stated just above in C4.1), putting it in a slightly different way.
Where C4.1 said that attributes of numbers belong to (that is, are predi-
cated of: rp\qweim with dative) sensible bodies, C4.5 says that they are
present in (or belong in) (rp\qweim 1m with dative) the things that are, spe-
cifically, in harmonic intervals and in the heavens and in many other
things. It might be objected that the sensible bodies of C4.1 are not
identical with the things that are, on the grounds that some things
that are, are not sensible bodies. But shortly afterward C4.6, he repeats
C4.4 substituting natural bodies (which here is equivalent to sensible
bodies) for the things that are. Apparently, he does not here place any
weight on the difference between the things that are and sensible (or
natural) bodies, and he doubtless took the heavens and many other
things in C4.5 to include the latter class of entities.
This reading of C4 suggests that N2 was the basic Pythagorean for-
mulation and that N1 is a reformulation of N2 in a way that makes sense
of that claim when the entities in question are sensible bodies. (It is hard
to see how it would have been initially formulated with such things as
justice, soul/mind, and the right moment in mind.) Is it a Pythagor-
ean or an Aristotelian reformulation? Clearly enough, this is a question
which C4 by itself cannot answer; I shall return to it shortly.99
What conclusions can we draw from these passages about the Pytha-
gorean views on which C1 through C4 are based? Much of the discus-
99 Below, p. 98.
96 Richard McKirahan
103 C4 seems to repeat much of C1, but there are significant differences. C1 speaks
of things resembling numbers (N4), while C4 speaks of things being numbers
(N2) and being made from (1j) numbers (N1). Also, where C1 says that such
and such an attribute of numbers is justice, etc., C4 says that attributes of num-
bers belong to sensible bodies. Note that neither justice nor the other examples
given in C1 are sensible bodies, and further that C1 says that the Pythagoreans
saw the attributes and ratios of the harmonic intervals in numbers, while C4
says, vice versa, that the attributes of numbers are in them.
104 For an objection to N1, see Metaph. 1090a32 5 (= C4.6-C4.8) where Aristo-
tle complains that the Pythagoreans make the natural bodies out of numbers.
For N2, see Metaph. 1090a12 ff., where Aristotle objects that unlike the things
in the cosmos, numbers are eternal and unchangeable, and Metaph. 987a22 27
(= C2.6-C2.9) which points out that it follows for the Pythagoreans that if
things are identical with numbers, then one thing will be many.
105 Also compare C4.1 they saw many attributes of numbers belonging to sensible
bodies with C1.3 in these [viz. numbers] they thought they observed many
likenesses to the things that are and that come to be.
106 p. 95.
98 Richard McKirahan
exclusively (or even mainly, perhaps) with sensible bodies. Those like
myself who think that a good deal of this evidence sounds early (I be-
lieve this to be the majority view) will be disinclined to think that the
original formulation of the relation between numbers and things was re-
stricted to sensible bodies, and hence will find that these considerations
favor the authenticity of N2.
What, then, of N1? If it is not Aristotles erroneous restatement of
N2, is it genuine too? Would the Pythagoreans have asserted two such
similar (and yet such different) claims as N1 and N2? I believe they assert-
ed both theses, and that N1 is in effect a Pythagorean reformulation of
N2 in a way that makes it more applicable to sensible bodiesa particular
kind of things that are. Aristotle takes them to hold that sensible bodies
are numbers in that they are constituted of them in the same way that a
chair is wood and nails and a man is flesh and blood. It is certain that the
1j locution was Pythagorean: Philolaus uses it in B1, B2, and B6, so Ar-
istotle could have taken this formulation from a Pythagorean source. This
way of expressing the relation between things and numbers may explain
Aristotles insistence that the Pythagoreans must have been thinking of
material causes.107 Possibly this is behind the move from principles in
C1.1 to elements in C1.8, since Aristotle frequently uses stoiwe?om
in connection with material elements.108
However, it would be unwise to leave the matter at this point, since
Huffman has rejected both N1 and N2 as due to an Aristotelian misin-
terpretation of Philolaus.109 To be sure, these theses are not found in
Philolauss extant fragments. In fact, N1, which declares that things
are 1j numbers, is incompatible with B1s claim that they are 1j unlim-
iteds and limiters. Huffman proposes that N1 and N2 (he does not clear-
ly distinguish between the claims) are Aristotles ways of summarizing
Pythagorean (i. e., Philolauss) doctrine.110 The doctrine in question is
Philolauss cosmology, including specifically the stage discussed in B7
107 See C1.11 and 986b6 8: They seem to range the elements under the head of
matter, for they say substance is constituted and fashioned out of these and that
these are present in it (adapted from the Revised Oxford Translation).
108 See n. 77.
109 See n. 42. It is an Aristotelian interpretation of Philolaus; Huffman (above,
n. 3)63. But this is too confident. Earlier in the same paragraph Huffman says
more cautiously (and, I believe, correctly), It seems most likely that he [Aristo-
tle] had Philolauss book and perhaps some other writing or oral reports. Huffman
gives no reason for eliminating or ignoring the second and third possibilities.
110 Huffman (above, n. 3)63.
Aristotle on the Pythagoreans 99
(The first thing that was joined, the one in the middle of the sphere, is
called the hearth), which Huffman argues Aristotle mistakenly inter-
preted as the first stage in the generation of the number series, whereas
in fact it is an early stage in the generation of the cosmos. Huffmans ar-
gument is strong but I am not convinced that it overturns Burkerts
view that the Pythagoreans (or Philolaus) viewed the generation of
the cosmos as identical with the generation of the number series,111 so
that what B7 describes is both the first stage in the generation of the
number series and an early stage in the generation of the cosmos.
Huffmans other piece of evidence that Aristotle did not find N1 in
any Pythagorean text is also plausible but not decisive. It is Metaphysics
1083b17 19 (= C3.2-C3.3), which he paraphrases and translates as fol-
lows: Aristotle first states flatly that the Pythagoreans say that all things
are numbers, but then continues in the next sentence at least (coOm)
they apply heyq^lata to bodies as if they (the bodies) consisted of
those numbers. As Huffman understands the passage, the crucial
point is that the doctrine that all things are numbers is not presented
as something that the Pythagoreans explicitly stated, rather it is present-
ed as Aristotles own deduction from the way the Pythagoreans pro-
ceed.112 While this is a legitimate way to construe Aristotles words,
it is not the only way. On another way of understanding the particle
coOm, the sentence is translated They say that the things that are, are
number. In fact they apply their propositions to bodies supposing that
they consisted of those numbers. I defended this reading above.113 If
the sentence is taken this way, then far from showing that N1 and
N2 are Aristotles conjectures, it is actually evidence that his Pythagor-
ean sources, whatever they were, contained both N1 and N2.
As to the views on principles contained in C1 and C2 (especially
C1.12-C1.13 and C2.1-C2.4), all that remains to do is see whether
the doctrines of the two passages (treated above, pp. 89 90) can be
made into a coherent account, and if so, whether it is likely to be
based on a Pythagorean source.
I support an affirmative answer to the first of these questions.114 Ar-
istotle presents a Pythagorean ontology with several levels. C1.12 makes
the even and the odd (which are somehow related to the unlimited and
the limited; either they are identical or the latter pair are the principles
of the former) ultimate principles. They are the immediate principles of
the one; the one is the immediate principle of number. C1.13
completes the ontology by giving a hint that numbers115 are the princi-
ples of the sensible world. The notion of principle involved here is ex-
pressed by the 1j locution; we are dealing with something that Aristotle
thinks approximates to his notion of the material cause.
C2.1 clears up the relation between the pairs even/odd and unlimit-
ed/limited. C2.1 states that there is one pair of ultimate principles, and
C2.2 makes it clear that this pair consists of the unlimited and the limited;
not anything else such as fire or earth (or, we may add, even) that is un-
limited, but C2.3 the unlimited itself. C2.4 says more clearly than C1.13
that number is the substance (again, presumably, in the sense of the ma-
terial cause) of all things, which must mean everything with the excep-
tion of the entities that are higher up in the ontology: the unlimited and
the limited, the even and the odd, the one, and number.
There remains the question deferred from above (p. 72): what is the
significance of the change from talk of the unlimited and the limited in
C2.2 to talk of the unlimited and the one in C2.3? It is clear that in
C2.2 Aristotle is dealing with the ultimate principles. In C2.3, I think,
he is dealing with the one as a principle of number and is alluding to
something not made explicit in C1.12, that the one is not the only
principle on which numbers depend; they depend on the unlimited as
well. The most useful text on this subject is Metaphysics 1091a15 18
(quoted above as evidence for N12), which talks of generation116 subse-
quent to the generation of the one. Most scholars think that this passage
refers to the generation of numbers. First the one was generated and
then in some obscure way, the unlimited was drawn in (presumably
by the action of the one on it) to form the other numbers.117 If this
is right, then the unlimited is (along with the limited) a principle of
the one and (together with the one) a principle of the other num-
bers.
115 I note the change from number in C1.12 to numbers in C1.13, but I do
not see that any difference is intended. See n. 75.
116 I use generation for want of a better term. I take it that what is being descri-
bed is not a process of generation in time, but of ontological dependence.
117 Even if Huffman is correct in thinking that N12 refers to the generation of the
cosmos (above, p. 72), it seems likely that some analogous procedure (possibly
even the same series of events) could have been used to account for the gen-
eration of numbers. See n. 41.
Aristotle on the Pythagoreans 101
121 For (a), Metaph. 985b27 31 = C1.3-C1.4; for (b), ibid. 985b31 2 = C1.5;
for (c), ib. 985b32 3 = C1.6; for (d), ibid. 987b11 12.
122 See discussion of C1.6, p. 82.
123 See below, p. 116.
124 Evidently Aristotle knew the Pythagoreans had used the word l_lgsir Bur-
kert (above, n. 2) 44.
125 Cf. Plato, Soph. 259a7.
Aristotle on the Pythagoreans 103
similar or of the same kind). Philolauss \qwa_ are the limiters and the
unlimiteds, which are undoubtedly principles in some sense. Indeed
since Philolaus may offer a two-tier ontology,126 with limiters and unlim-
iteds as the principles of everything else (presumably including num-
bers127), N5 may refer to Philolauss system and may even derive from
Philolaus.
N6 repeats N5 almost literally, with two exceptions. First, it substi-
tutes stoiwe?a (elements) for !qwa_ (principles), which I take to be
an Aristotelian paraphrase, intended to bring out Aristotles view of the
way in which the Pythagoreans made numbers their material cause.128
Second, it substitutes numbers for these, where the latter refers
not yet specifically to numbers but to mathematical entities. N5 and
N6 are each stated in only once, in fact, in the same context, passage
C1. I view N6 (whose sole source is C1.8) as simply an Aristotelian re-
statement of N5 (whose sole source is C1.1).129
N7, however, which is witnessed only by C1.11, is heavily laden
with distinctively Aristotelian terminology (matter, vkg; attribute,
p\hor; state, 6nir). The passage presents problems which I discussed
above,130 where I concluded that the claim that number is a principle
as matter is based on a Pythagorean source because it probably employed
the 1j locution, and the claim that it is a principle as attributes and states
is also an Aristotelian interpretation of Pythagorean views. If it is an ac-
curate (albeit Aristotelian) description of Pythagorean ideas, those ideas
are not found in Philolauss extant fragments.
Whereas N1 through N7 mainly have to do with the importance of
numbers, N8 through N11 are chiefly concerned with ultimate princi-
ples and the relations between principles and the things whose principles
they are.
N8 (= C2.1-C2.4) contains five claims. First, C2.1 it states that the
Pythagoreans posited two principles; second C2.2 it identifies the prin-
ciples as limit and unlimited. There is no difficulty in seeing Philolauss
limiters and unlimiteds at the root of this claim and we can therefore
133 This interpretation is controversial. Huffman (above, n. 3) 130 thinks that it ap-
plies only to the principles, since he supposes that 1st~ means being in a
fused existential-cum-essential sense, and since B6 says that the 1st of
things is eternal. The things in the world around us are not eternal, so they
do not qualify for having an eternal existential being. But I do not find the argu-
ment for the fused sense compelling. The fact that the 1st~ is said to rp\qweim
does not tell any more in favor than against the view that 1st~ all by itself in-
cludes the notion of existence; if it included that notion, why bother to make
the assertion?
106 Richard McKirahan
that is equal-times-equal (i. e., four); the right moment is the number
seven; marriage is the number five, etc.137 There is nothing in Philo-
lauss fragments like these examples or the thesis that they illustrate.
An important point to bear in mind about N10 is that the single pas-
sage that attests it is not taken from Aristotles discussion of the Pytha-
goreans in Metaphysics A5, but is part of his treatment of Platos philos-
ophy in Metaphysics A6. It is part of a complex passage recently
explicated by Huffman,138 in which Aristotle speaks of Platos relations
to earlier philosophers, including the Pythagoreans. In particular, he says
that Plato used the word participation (l]henir) to express the relation
that the Pythagoreans expressed with the word imitation (l_lgsir)
(987b9 14, cf. N4), that like the Pythagoreans he had views on the na-
ture of mathematical entities, and that his views on this topic were like
those of the Pythagoreans in some ways and unlike them in others
(987b14 988a1). The subject of the sentence that witnesses N10 is
not the Pythagoreans, but Plato, understood from earlier in the
paragraph. The discussion is directed more at Plato than at the Pytha-
goreans and its vocabulary is more Aristotelian and Platonic than Pytha-
gorean. The passage, then, does not pretend to be closely based on any
Pythagorean source and can be expected to distort Pythagorean ideas in
order to make them comparable to Platonic theses.139
N10s first claim, that the one is oqs_a, can be interpreted in sev-
eral ways. (a) the one is oqs_a; (b) the one is an oqs_a; (c) the
one is the oqs_a of all other things (where of all other things is un-
derstood from 987b24 just below). The context shows that (c) is what is
meant; the previous sentence (987b18 21), which speaks of the Platon-
ic views that the Forms are causes of other things and that the elements
of the Forms are the elements of all things, also declares that Plato made
the great and the small principles as matter and he made the one prin-
ciple as oqs_a, which is best interpreted here as form in the Aristote-
lian sense, or essence. It is reasonable, then, to take N10 closely with
N8, which regards the one as a principle and declares the principles,
namely the unlimited and the one, to be the oqs_a of the things of
which they are predicated and number to be the oqs_a of all things.
The second claim of N10, that numbers are the causes of the oqs_a
of all other things shifts from talking about the one to talking about
numbers. (Cf. the change between the fourth and the fifth claims in
N8.). Where the fifth claim in N8 asserts that number is the oqs_a of
all things, N10 says that numbers140 are the causes of the oqs_a of the
other things.141 This is a different thesis from anything we have seen be-
fore, in particular from the claims that things are numbers (N2, N3) and
that numbers are the substance, matter, or essence of things (N1, N7,
N8, N9). While nothing precludes some Pythagoreans from having
made this rather careful claim, it sounds to me more like an attempt
on Aristotles part to make sense of such Pythagorean doctrines as the
ones reflected in N1 and N2, which were, from Aristotles point of
view, sheer and utter nonsense. It is hard to find anything in Philolaus
very close to the doctrines put forward in N10.
N11 and N12 must, I think, have authentic Pythagorean pedigrees
even though the passages that cite them they may contain some Aristo-
telian terminology. They are too specific and detailed for Aristotle to
have made them up or to have taken them to be the meanings of less
definite claims. The most striking thing about these two texts is how
different they are from one another. N11 seems to offer a kind of anal-
ysis of things into their constituents: number is composed of the one,
the one is composed of the even and the odd. It may even hint at an
argument: the elements of number are the even and the odd because
the one is composed of them and number is composed of the
one. On the other hand, N12 seems to describe the generation of
the number series by the operation of the one on the unlimited.
Even on Huffmans alternative interpretation of N12 as an account
of the first stage of a cosmogony, an account of the stages by which the
cosmos came to be over a period of time,142 the accounts in N11 and
N12 need not be incompatible, any more than a respectable cosmogony
today need be incompatible with current understanding of the physical
and chemical constituents of things in the universe. A cosmogony gives
a different kind of account of the universe than physics and chemistry
140 As elsewhere, I do not think that Aristotle intends any difference between
number and numbers; cf. n. 75.
141 Actually, the word translated causes in the standard English translations of the
Metaphysics is an adjective, not a noun: aQt_our (modifying !q_hlour), not aQt_a
or aUtiom. Numbers are responsible for the oqs_a of things. The idea is that if
you want to find the oqs_a of something, look to the relevant numbers.
142 See above, p. 72.
Aristotle on the Pythagoreans 109
do, just as N11 gives a different kind of account from N12. The fact that
we have different kinds of accounts does not prove that they came from
different sources. In fact, both have links with Philolaus. N12 could well
stem from the cosmology of which B7 and B17 are the only surviving
fragments, as long as we understand the one in N12 to be the same as
the one in the middle of the sphere, which B7 calls the hearth (that is,
the central hearth of the cosmos), as Huffman proposes.143
N11 has links to Philolauss general account of limiters and limiteds
as principles, if we assume that he admits principles of numbers. How-
ever, the parenthetical remark that the even is unlimited and the odd is
limited may conceal a further step in this analytic account (allowing for
the slippage that is inevitable since Aristotle does not speak of limiters
and limiteds). In the terminology of B2, the odd is from limiters
and the even is from unlimiteds. The one is from the even
and the odd: from both mixed together, as B5 tells us: it is an
even-odd number. And the remaining numbers are from the
one. The resulting ontology is incompatible with the ontology pre-
sented in Philolaus B1,144 but could be based on a different Pythagorean
source.
N13 is presented as a belief held by others that fall in the range of
the Pythagorean umbrella. I have used it already as a piece of evidence
that Aristotle used more than one source.145 It is surely genuine: again, it
is inconceivable that Aristotle made it up. Also, it conflicts with Philo-
lauss doctrine that limiters and unlimiteds are two kinds of principles,
not one. To be sure in the parallel columns limit and unlimited come
first (counting them as one principle, not two), but the nine remaining
oppositions are not derived from that primary pair; there are ten prin-
ciples not two (or twenty).
have expressed in a variety of ways, such as the things that are are com-
posed of numbers (N1) and the things that are, are number(s) (N2-
N3) or the things that are, are by imitation of numbers (N4). N7 and
the first part of N10 represent this stage, even if it is an Aristotelian re-
formulation as suggested above. Characteristic of Stage 2 is the identi-
fication of justice with the number four and the other identifications
mentioned in N4.
Finally (Stage 3), they turned their interest in principles to number
itself and developed views on what the principles of numbers are. Thus
N5 and N6 speak of the principles and elements of numbers and assert
that they (rather than numbers themselves) are the principles of all the
things that are, and N11 identifies the even and the odd as the elements
of numbers, and provides information about the derivatijon of numbers
from those principles. The derivation of numbers is also I think149 the
topic of N12. N10 is also relevant to this stage, though I think it also
reflects interests characteristic of Stage 2.
The interest in principles prevailed to the extent that numbers lost
their central role. The principles were identified as limit and the unlim-
ited (by Philolaus, as limiters and unlimiteds), and interest may have
shifted to accounting for things in terms of those principles rather
than doing so through numbers, which are themselves generated from
the same principles. The principles are said to be the oqs_a (or 1st~)
of the things that are dependent on them. This is the situation of N8
and N9, and perhaps the doctrine of parallel columns cited in N13. It
is also the situation of Philolaus.
All three stages are reflected in Aristotles testimony. He gives a
prominent position to the second stage, which struck him as importantly
different from the other early theories that he summarizes, and which
has connections with the topics of definition and essence, topics impor-
tant for Aristotle, especially in the Metaphysics. He does not claim that
there is a single Pythagorean orthodoxy, so he is not to be blamed if
he reports conflicting views in different places. Recall the passages
cited above in Section 2 that show him reporting that a particular
view was held by some of the Pythagoreans or by others. Even
so, and despite the differences he acknowledges, he evidently thought
that the Pythagoreans or those called Pythagoreans had enough
saying that one thing is like another and that one thing is another, even if the
former claim is the basis for the latter one.
149 For Huffmans disagreement, see p. 72.
112 Richard McKirahan
Aristotle says several times that the Pythagoreans (or some Pythagoreans)
made or constituted the heaven, or bodies, or natural bodies, or nature,
or the things that are out of numbers (N1). In his own system, this view
amounts to a claim that numbers are the material cause of things
which Aristotle finds obviously false. He also says that they said that
things (t emta, pq\clata) are numberswhich he finds equally
false. Armed with his distinctions between subject and predicate, be-
tween substance and attribute, between essence and accident, and in
particular in the light of his view that numbers are attributes, not sub-
stances, he cannot but regard these Pythagorean claims and most of
the other claims listed above (N1-N13) as arrant nonsense. No one
sharing these views of Aristotle would think of claiming that numbers
are the principles of things, let alone that things (including physical ob-
jects and other substances) are identical with numbers or made up of
numbers. On the other hand, the Pythagoreans put these ideas forward,
which suggests that they did not hold the Aristotelian views with which
they conflict.
Aristotle on the Pythagoreans 113
He may have got this idea from seeing that the nourishment of all things is
moist, and that even the hot itself comes to be from this and lives on this
and also because the seeds of all things have a moist nature and water is the
principle of the nature of moist things. (Metaph. 983b22 27)
Whether or not these were the grounds for Thales sweeping pro-
nouncement about the primacy of water, the fact that Aristotle thinks
they may have been says something about the kind of evidence he
thought the early natural philosophers used and the way they used it.
Closer to our time period is Heraclitus, who held that all things are one.
Heraclituss fragments associate several of his key concepts.151 For
example, he identifies the cosmos with fire and asserts that fire is
ever-living:
The cosmos, the same for all, none of the gods nor of humans has made,
but it was always and is and shall be: an ever-living fire being kindled in
measures and being extinguished in measures. (DK 22 B30)
He gives fire in its purest and most highly active form a controlling role
in the cosmos:
Thunderbolt steers all things. (DK 22 B64)
In the individual, the soul, which makes us alive and directs us, is fiery:
fire and soul are used interchangeably in DK 22 B36 and DK 22
B31:
It is death to souls to come to be water, death to water to come to be earth,
but from earth water comes to be and from water soul. (DK 22 B36)
The turnings of fire: first, sea; and of sea, half is earth and half fiery water-
spout. Earth is poured out as sea, and is measured according to the same
logos it was before it became earth. (DK 22 B31)
Further, fire as the all-controller seems to be identified with the logos,
according to which all things come to be:
For although all things come to be in accordance with this logos
(DK 22 B1)
The active nature of the universe is war and strife, which Heraclitus de-
clares is justice. Further strife and necessity are assigned the all-control-
ling role that also belongs to fire and the logos.
War is the father of all and king of all (DK 22 B53)
151 The following translations and discussion are taken from R. McKirahan, Philo-
sophy before Socrates 2 (Indianapolis 2011) 135 6.
Aristotle on the Pythagoreans 115
It is necessary to know that war is common and justice is strife and that all
things happen in accordance with strife and necessity. (DK 22 B80)
Events in the cosmos, including transformations of one substance into
another and changes between opposites, are a necessary and universal
war and struggle which is needed to maintain the cosmos in a stable
condition. Whatever results in a particular case, it is part of the overall
process that rules the universe with justice. Heraclitus identifies the jus-
tice and therefore the strife and war in the universe with fire:
For fire will advance and judge and convict all things. (DK 22 B66)
Fire is also associated with God:
God is day and night, winter and summer, war and peace, satiety and hun-
ger, but changes the way fire, when mingled with perfumes, is named ac-
cording to the scent of each. (DK 22 B67)
Both fire and God take on different appearances in different situations,
but keep their own nature. In a sense, fire is the one behind the many,
the unity in all the diversity of the cosmos. Law too may form part of
the same cluster of concepts:
It is law, too, to obey the counsel of one. (DK 22 B33)
Heraclitus thus associates the logos, fire, soul, war, justice, God, and per-
haps law. In some sense they are the same, the ruling element in the uni-
verse, but precisely how they are the same is not clear. For example,
when I strike a match and create some fire, I am obviously not bringing
the eternal logos or God into being. It will not do to demand strict con-
ditions of identity in this context any more than it does when Heraclitus
says that day and night are one (DK 22 B57). In different settings these
concepts take on a variety of relations to one another, sometimes being
virtually identical and sometimes being almost separate. For example,
the burning match is not God, but is related to the cosmic fire (as a
part? by likeness? as an imperfect specimen? as a copy?) and in its small
area of active existence it performs functions which both symbolize and
are a part of the war and justice that rule the world. Heraclitus lacked
conceptual tools and analytical techniques for analyzing such assertions.
Broad claims of sameness or identity were easy to make and hard to chal-
lenge. This state of philosophy and the Greek language suited Heraclitus
purposes: his approach to the unity of the cosmos through the logos re-
quired associating ideas rather than analyzing or separating them. He
needed to bring things together before bringing them apart again.
116 Richard McKirahan
From [the Pythagoreans and from Alcmaeon] we can learn this much, that
the contraries are the principles of the things that are; and how many these
principles are and what they are, we can learn from [the Pythagoreans].
How to bring these principles together with the causes we have named
has not been clearly articulated by them. (Metaph. 986b2 6, tr. based on
the Revised Oxford Translation)
Down to the Italian school, then, and apart from it, philosophers have
treated these subjects [viz. the question of causes] rather obscurely.
(Metaph. 987a9 11, tr. based on the Revised Oxford Translation)
Regarding the question of what things are they began to make state-
ments and definitions, but treated the matter too simply. For they would
define superficially and they thought that the first thing an indicated
term applies to is the essence of the thing. (Metaph. 987a20 3, tr. from C2)
[Platos] divergence from the Pythagoreans in making the one and
the numbers separate from things, and his introduction of the Forms,
were due to his inquiries in the region of definitory formulae (for the ear-
lier thinkers had no tincture of dialectic). (Metaph. 987b29 32, tr. based on
the Revised Oxford Translation)
That bodies should be composed of numbers, and that this should be
mathematical number, is impossible. For it is not true to speak of indivisible
spatial magnitudes; and however much there might be magnitudes of this
sort, units at least have not magnitude; and how can a magnitude be com-
posed of indivisibles? But arithmetical number, at least, consists of abstract
units, while they say that the things that are, are number; in fact they apply
their propositions to bodies, supposing that they consisted of those num-
bers. (Metaph. 1083b11 19, tr. based on the Revised Oxford Translation,
cf. 1090a32)
It is absurd to construct an account of the generation of things that are
eternal, or rather it is an impossibility. There is no need no doubt whether
or not the Pythagoreans construct such an account, since they say clearly
that when the one had been constituted the nearest parts of the unlim-
ited at once began to be drawn in and limited by the limit. But since they
are constructing a cosmos and wish to speak the language of natural science,
it is fair to make some examination of their physical theories, but to let
them off from the present inquiry; for we are investigating the principles
at work in unchangeable things, so that it is numbers of this kind whose
generation we must study. (Metaph. 1091a12 22, tr. based on the Revised
Oxford Translation)
11. Conclusion
In this paper I have presented reasons to think that Aristotle did not base
his account of Pythagoreanism, and of Pythagorean principles in partic-
ular, entirely on Philolaus, and that he utilized more than one source.
The possibility that he had live informants is not excludedeither peo-
Aristotle on the Pythagoreans 119
Bibliography
Barnes, Jonathan (ed.). The Complete Works of Aristotle. The Revised Oxford
Translation, 2 vols. Princeton 1984.
153 It would have taken too much space in this already long paper to discuss
Zhmuds important article (L. Zhmud, All is number? Basic doctrine of Py-
thagoreanism reconsidered, Phronesis 24 [1989] 270 292), which argues that
Pythagorean number philosophy is the invention of Aristotle. Briefly, I agree
with Zhmud (290) that the discovery of the numerical basis of the harmonic
intervals was early (Zhmud attributes it to Pythagoras himself). Apparently un-
like Zhmud, I suppose that this discovery became the catalyst for the grand
claim that number is (somehow) fundamental to everything, which motivated
further Pythagorean interest in numbers that was manifested in mathematical
discoveries as well as in fruitless numerology, and which eventually led to ac-
counts of the principles of numbers themselves.
120 Richard McKirahan
There have not been many attempts to connect the philosophical sys-
tems of Heraclitus and Philolaus. At first sight, there appear to be
good reasons for this failure to see a connection. The two thinkers
come from opposite ends of the Greek world. Heraclitus was from
Ephesus in Asia Minor and Philolaus from Croton in southern Italy, al-
though he also visited in Thebes on the Greek mainland and may have
spent his last years in a different southern Italian city, Tarentum1. More-
over, Heraclitus probably wrote his book ca. 500 BC, while Philolaus
did not write until some seventy years later. Philolaus immediate pred-
ecessors were figures like Empedocles and Anaxagoras, whereas Heracli-
tus belonged to a still earlier generation and is thus less likely to have
elicited a direct response from Philolaus. Heraclitus is, moreover, fa-
mous for his paradoxical theses that apparent stability is, in fact, based
on change and that apparent opposites are in some sense one. Neither
this doctrine of the unity of the opposites nor the emphasis on the
role of strife and change in the cosmos are to be found in the fragments
of Philolaus. There have been, in addition, scholarly obstacles to con-
necting the two figures. The fragments of Philolaus had been thought
of questionable authenticity until fairly recently, so that there was noth-
ing to compare to Heraclitus. Heraclitus himself has been interpreted in
radically different ways. Scholars cannot agree whether Heraclitus is
talking about the cosmos as a whole or about human behavior, nor, if
he is talking about the cosmos, whether he is an exponent of a doctrine
of radical flux or the champion of a stable order. Thus, it is hard to
know which Heraclitus to compare to Philolaus.
Now that a core of the fragments of Philolaus can confidently be
regarded as authentic2, however, these fragments can help us to under-
stand both Philolaus and Heraclitus. There is not space here to argue in
the empire is that of his enemy, Cyrus4. Similarly, to understand either the
world or Heraclitus words, it is necessary to be able to interpret the
signs5. Thus, one must value what the eyes and ears reveal to us of the
world, as Heraclitus says in B 55, but also recognize that the eyes and
ears give bad evidence for those who have souls that do not understand
the language6. Human beings must understand the language of the phe-
nomenal world, if they are to interpret the signs that it gives about the
true nature of things. This emphasis on the hidden nature of reality
that is nonetheless close at hand, for those who can read the signs, explains
Heraclitus constant lament about the failure of most people to see the
truth, which is presented as common to all7, and his comparison of
most people to those who are asleep8.
Heraclitus uses several images to describe the reality to which the
phenomena point. In B 54, he says that the harmonie which is hidden
is better than the one that is evident. Once again the emphasis is on
going beyond that with which our senses initially present us, beyond
what can be seen, to what is hidden. This time, however, we are told
that the nature that lies hidden is an harmonia, i. e. a fitting together
or attunement of disparate things into a unity. The Greek word has sev-
eral different connotations, all of which may be relevant in interpreting
Heraclitus. A "qlom_a comes to refer to the fitting together of notes into
a musical scale, so that B 54 might be stating the paradox that the music
that is not evident, that we do not hear, is better than the music that we
do hear. In typical oracular fashion, Heraclitus challenges us to figure
out what is meant by music that is not evident. Kahn9 suggested that
we might think of the Pythagorean music of the spheres, which accord-
ing to the reports of the later tradition only the master could hear10. He
rightly rejects this approach, both because it is not certain that the con-
ception of the harmony of the spheres did go back to Pythagoras and
thus had been promulgated by the time of Heraclitus, and more impor-
tantly because it would be surprising to see Heraclitus embrace such a
distinctively Pythagorean doctrine, given his virulent criticism of Pytha-
goras elsewhere in the fragments. Pythagoras is called the prince of im-
4 Herodotus 1.91.
5 Kahn, H. 123 4.
6 B 107.
7 B 3.
8 B 1.
9 Kahn, H. 202 4.
10 Por. VP 30, Iamb. VP 66.
124 Carl Huffman
posters and is said to have practiced a polymathy that led not to under-
standing but rather to an evil trickery (Frs. 81, 40, 129). It is surprising,
then, that Kahn goes on to argue that by the hidden harmony Heraclitus
is referring to another prominent idea in the Pythagorean tradition,
which may go back to Pythagoras himself and is certainly present in Phi-
lolaus, i. e. the correspondence between the musical concords (what we
today call perfect intervals) such as the octave, fifth and fourth and the
whole number ratios 1:2, 2:3 and 3:4. According to Kahn, Heraclitus
non-evident attunement, the music which we cannot hear, is constitut-
ed by these whole number ratios. Kahns previous argument would
seem to work against his own suggestion here. Does it make sense to
suppose that in praising the hidden harmonie Heraclitus is adopting
as a central feature of his system a distinctive idea of that Pythagoras
whom he treats with such contempt elsewhere? Moreover, it is going
far beyond any evidence we have to suppose that Heraclitus was refer-
ring to the whole number ratios that are connected to the musical con-
cords; these ratios appear nowhere in the fragments of Heraclitus.
In order to make sense of Heraclitus in his own terms, it is necessary
to remember that in a more basic sense "qlom_a refers not just to musical
structure, but to any fitting-together of elements into a whole. Thus the
verb "ql|fy is used already in Homer to describe Odysseus fitting-to-
gether of pieces of wood to create a raft, and the "qlom_ai are the
joints11. It is thus reasonable to translate "qlom_a in some contexts as
structure. Kahn indeed suggests that hidden structure might
thus be taken as a general title for Heraclitus philosophical thought12,
and Hussey translates "qlom_g !vam^r as latent structure13. B 51 sug-
gests that it is this more general sense of harmonia that is most relevant for
Heraclitus, although the musical meaning is present as well: They do
not understand how in differing with itself it agrees, a backward turning
structure ("qlom_g) just like that of a bow or a lyre. The image of the
bow and the lyre in this fragment is complex, and I will focus on just a
few aspects of it here. The evident structure of the bow and lyre is the
combination of wood and string to form an apparently stable and static
object. Most people do not understand that this agreement of the parts
of the lyre or bow is based on a difference between them; the difference,
11 Od. 5. 247 8.
12 Kahn, H. 203.
13 E. Hussey, Heraclitus, in A. A. Long (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Early
Greek Philosophy. (Cambridge 1999) 91.
4. Philolaus Critique of Heraclitus 125
the strife between the strings and the wood of the bow and the lyre, al-
though not evident, is nonetheless the true structure that underlies the
apparently static structure. It is not only the bow or the lyre that are held
together by such a structure, however. Heraclitus is arguing that there is
such a hidden fitting-together for everything in the world and indeed
for the world as a whole.
In our best source for B 51, Hippolytus, the harmonia of the bow and
lyre is described as backward turning (pak_mtqopor), while some
other sources report the common Homeric epithet for a bow, back-
ward stretched (pak_mtomor); scholars have been divided as to which
reading to accept. 14 Backward turning is clearly preferable as the lectio
difficilior. As Kahn15 has argued, however, this adjective is intended to
remind us of the tension on which the bow and lyre are based by an al-
lusion to the Homeric epithet, backward stretched. In the transmis-
sion of the text, this allusion was sometimes taken too seriously and
backward stretched was incorporated into the text instead of the
more unusual backward turning. At the same time, however, Kahn
argues that backward turning alludes to the turnings (tqopa_) or
changes of state of the cosmic fire, which are described in B 31 A:
The turnings of fire, first sea, and of sea the half is earth and the half
is lightning. B 51 thus indicates that the hidden harmonia of B 54 is
in part a reference to the constant transformation between opposites
such as the hot and the cold, which makes such opposites just phases
on a continuum of temperature. The hidden harmonia thus turns out
to be a reference to the famous Heraclitean unity of the opposites,
which asserts that apparent opposites such as hot and cold are, in fact,
one. What is real is not the transitory phases, hot and cold, but the uni-
fied continuum of temperature of which they are parts. Thus, in B 126,
Heraclitus asserts Cold things become hot, hot things become cold,
wet things dry up, dry things become damp.16
As Graham has suggested, it appears that Heraclitus is presenting a
critique of Ionian cosmology, which had mistakenly supposed that
powers and substances such as the hot or air were ultimate realities,
when they were just phases of the continual change, which is the
14 See, e. g., Kirk, H. 210 216, and G. Vlastos, On Heraclitus, AJP 76 (1955):
337 378.
15 Kahn, H. 199 200.
16 R. Dilcher, On the Wording of Heraclitus, Fragment 126, CQ 44.1 (1994)
276 277.
126 Carl Huffman
true reality.17 Graham puts it very well in saying, In effect each sub-
stance is not a permanent thing, a stable reality, but a stage in the se-
quence of transformations. What then is real? Only the process of trans-
formations itself.18 This then is the explanation of the role of fire in
Heraclitus. To quote Graham again, fire is the most changeable,
ephemeral, the least tangible and stable of things; thus it is the least sub-
stantial of all substances, the substance that is not a substance, the sub-
stance that is a process.19 I would suggest, then, that for Heraclitus
the opposites define and are united in continua in which powers,
such as different degrees of hot and cold, or substances, such as air
and water, are transitory phases. Thus the hidden harmonia is more likely
to be a reference to this famous Heraclitean unity of opposites than to
the whole number ratios that govern the musical concords. It is not
completely clear whether Heraclitus is arguing that there are a number
of different continua that unite opposites, e. g. a continuum of temper-
ature that unites hot and cold, a continuum of moisture that unites dry
and wet etc., or whether he is arguing that all oppositions are ultimately
united in one continuum. His assertions that all things, god, or the
wise are one suggest the latter interpretation.20 In B 67, god is descri-
bed as uniting a series of such continua: God, day night, winter summ-
er, war peace, abundance famine21.
At this point it is illuminating to turn to Philolaus in order to note
two similarities in approach with Heraclitus. First, Philolaus also empha-
sizes that human beings will not understand reality just by looking at the
phenomena presented to them by their senses. Things once again point
to a more basic reality. This theme is clearest in B 5. After identifying
two basic kinds of numbers, the even and the odd, Philolaus says, Of
each of the two kinds there are many forms, of which each thing itself
gives signs.22 The many forms of the even and the odd may just be the
series of even and odd numbers. Philolaus argues that each thing in the
world gives signs of or points to these numbers. He uses the same verb,
which Heraclitus used to describe the Delphic oracle as giving signs,
signs that are in need of interpretation. It is certainly not the case that
unlimited and out of things which are limiting, both the world-order as
whole and everything in it. This is an explicit assertion that nature, the
nature of the cosmos as a whole and of all things in it, is an attunement
of parts, is a structure. This intimate connection between nature and har-
monia is also seen in B 6 of Philolaus, which begins Concerning nature
and harmonia the situation is this This pairing of the two concepts
suggests that they are closely connected and that in order to understand
nature it is necessary to understand harmonia. Philolaus and Heraclitus
thus agree that things give signs of a harmonia. Again, however, the fur-
ther characterization of harmonia, which Philolaus will give in B 6a, as
having a numerical structure, the numerical structure of the diatonic
scale, shows that the ultimate nature of the harmonia is more explicitly
arithmetical in Philolaus than Heraclitus.
It is now time to turn from the broad similarities between Heraclitus
and Philolaus to the substantial differences that constitute Philolaus cri-
tique of Heraclitus. First, Philolaus appears to accept Heraclitus con-
ception of harmonia as a starting point but to move beyond it. For Her-
aclitus the hidden harmonie is constituted by his doctrine of the unity of
opposites, the surprising connection of opposites such as hot and cold,
up and down in one continuum. In part this connection is logical and
not empirical. Hot and cold, light and dark, up and down are only in-
telligible in terms of one another and thus cannot be separated logically
from one another. Heraclitus famous assertion of method that I
searched myself (B 101) may refer to his turning inward to examine
the logic of such opposites independent of experience. In the case of
the natural world, this logical connection becomes a physical connec-
tion through the doctrine of constant change, which makes hot and
cold, dry and wet, light and dark, just phases in larger continua. One
way of understanding Philolaus is to suppose that he has adopted Her-
aclitus point and accepts that the world is composed of an indefinite
number of such continua. Where do such continua appear in Philolaus?
I suggest that he made them one of the two basic types of components
of the cosmos and called them t %peiqa, the unlimiteds. In Heraclitus
unity of opposites doctrine, as I have sketched it above, the opposites are
one because they are parts of a constantly changing continuum. Such a
continuum is not made up of defined stable entities, but rather consists
of transitory phases. It is precisely because the parts of such a continuum
are not defined stable states that they can be said to be one. The contin-
uum of temperature cannot be labeled hot or cold or any other temper-
ature but is in itself without clear internal boundaries; this is the sense in
4. Philolaus Critique of Heraclitus 129
23 B 201.
24 Aristotle Fr. 201.
25 Philolaus A 27.
130 Carl Huffman
26 B 94.
4. Philolaus Critique of Heraclitus 131
limited, since in stating the third possibility, i. e. that things are both limit-
ing and unlimited, he adds pointedly, and not just unlimited. He ap-
pears to be correcting earlier thinkers, such as Heraclitus, who had sup-
posed that the world could be explained in terms of unlimiteds alone.
Philolaus argues that we must recognize that measures, limits and struc-
ture are features of reality, which cannot be eliminated, and that such
structure is not inherent in continua. The cosmos is not a fire alone,
but it has a central fire and other fires delimited within it.
The difference between Heraclitus and Philolaus regarding structure
can be further clarified by examining another Heraclitean image, the ky-
keon, a drink composed of barley, cheese and wine, which has to be stir-
red and still in motion when one drinks it in order to realize its full na-
ture. Mouraviev30 has raised important questions about the text of this
fragment, but appears to agree with most scholars that Heraclitus uses
the kykeon as an analogue to the cosmic order31; as constant motion is
necessary to keep the barley and cheese from settling out in the kykeon,
so constant motion is what maintains the celestial order of sun, moon
and stars, including the measures of the sun mentioned in B 94. Hera-
clitus thus appears to think that constant motion across a continuum is
all that is needed to explain the cosmos. The measures and order of the
cosmos somehow arise out of the constant change in the continuum,
analogously to the order that arises out of the ingredients of the kykeon
in motion32. It is this emergence of measures and limits out of the un-
limited continuum that Philolaus regards as unintelligible. In B 2, he
goes on to argue for the third logical possibility, that both limiters
and unlimiteds are first principles, by starting from our experience: it
is manifest that they [i.e. the cosmos and the things in it] are neither
from limiting things alone nor from unlimited things alone, i. e. in
the world around us, we easily identify continua like temperature,
water and earth, but also limits such as shapes. Heraclitus references
to measures and limits suggest that he would agree with Philolaus up
to this point. Philolaus goes on to argue, however, that it is clear
then that the world-order and the things in it were fitted together
from both limiting and unlimited things; the limiting and unlimited
features of the world we observe can only be explained on the assump-
30 S. N. Mouraviev, The Moving posset once again: Heraclitus Fr. B 125 in con-
text, CQ 46 (1996) 34 43.
31 Kahn, H. 194.
32 B 125.
4. Philolaus Critique of Heraclitus 133
tion that the world has as starting points, as !qwa_, both limiters and un-
limiteds. Philolaus continues, Things in their actions also make this
clear. For, some of them from limiting constituents limit, others from
both limiting and unlimited constituents both limit and do not limit,
others from unlimited constituents will be manifestly unlimited. Philo-
laus point is clearest in the last case, others from unlimited consti-
tuents will be manifestly unlimited. If the starting points are unlimited
what arises from them will be unlimited. From clay alone, all we get is
an undifferentiated quantity of clay, not a vase. It is not possible for limit
to arise from what is in its nature unlimited. Material in motion cannot
in itself explain the order that is observed in the cosmos. Heraclitus is
mistaken if he thinks that measures can arise from a burning fire.
Whereas Heraclitus tends towards monism, Philolaus always uses
plural nouns to describe his first principles, i. e. %peiqa, unlimiteds,
and peqa_momta, limiters. It would appear that he thought that the cos-
mos originated from an irreducible plurality of both limiters and unlim-
iteds. It is natural, then, to ask how many continua and how many struc-
tural principles there are. Philolaus, however, denies that this knowledge
is accessible to human beings. In B 6, when Philolaus focuses on the
most fundamental principles of reality, what he calls the the being of
things and nature in itself, rather than identifying a basic set of stuffs,
as, for example, Empedocles does, he says that such principles admit of
divine and not human knowledge. There is one large exception, i. e.
that it was impossible for any of the things that are and are known
by us to have come to be, if the being of the things from which the
world-order came together, both the limiting things and the unlimited
things, did not preexist. What human beings can know about ultimate
reality is precisely that the basic principles must include both continua,
unlimiteds, and also principles of structure, limiters, in order for the cos-
mos that we observe to have arisen. What humans cannot know is what
and how many unlimiteds and what and how many limiters are basic
principles. Philolaus does not see any way to determine that there are
just four elements, as Empedocles does. There may once again be a par-
tial similarity with Heraclitus on this point, since, on one interpretation,
Heraclitus also denies that it is possible to identify any one phase of the
changes in the material continuum that is the cosmos as more funda-
mental than any other. On this reading, he is not identifying fire as
the most basic of substances but rather uses fire as a symbol of the con-
134 Carl Huffman
yet Philolaus argues that these two radically different sorts of things must
work together in order to account for the cosmos. Thus, in B 6, Philolaus
asserts that since these beginnings [!qwa_, i. e., limiters and unlimiteds]
preexisted and were neither alike nor even related (of the same tribe,
bl|vukoi), it would have been impossible for them to be ordered, if a har-
mony had not come upon them. He supports this assertion by stating the
general principle that things that are unlike and not even related nor
even of the same order [reading Qsotac/], it is necessary that such things
be bonded together by a harmony, if they are going to be held in an
order. Thus, that master of paradox, Heraclitus, was dealing with some-
thing quite tame when he asserted that opposites such as hot and cold
were one. It is much more of a challenge to explain how center and
fire can be combined to form the unity known as the central fire. We
might well want to say that Philolaus is making some sort of category mis-
take in regarding center and fire as parts of the cosmos in anything like the
same sense, but Philolaus language in B 6 suggests that he is all too aware
of the seemingly unbridgeable gap between the sense in which fire is part
of our cosmos and the sense in which center is a part of our cosmos. He
emphasizes that limiters and unlimiteds are not just unlike (oqw blo?ai)
one another, they are not even of the same tribe (oqd( bl|vukoi). He
went on to use yet another adjective in order to indicate the vast differ-
ence between limiters and unlimiteds. He may well have used a neolo-
gism to highlight the difference, since the manuscripts provide the appa-
rently impossible reading not of equal speed (lgd Qsotaw/). Heidels
emendation lgd Qsotac/ (not of the same order) is perhaps the
most plausible. Philolaus would then, in fact, be recognizing that limiters
and unlimiteds do not belong even to the same category of being. Here is
a real gap, which we must bridge with some sort of attunement. Up to
this point I have avoided using the language of form and matter, and I
will continue to do so, in the belief that it is less misleading to understand
Philolaus insight in his own terms and those of his contemporaries and
predecessors. Nonetheless, it may be helpful to make the point by saying
that Philolaus is the first person to see that formal features are just as im-
portant as material features in explaining the world and is hence the first
person to grapple explicitly with the problem of how form and matter can
be related.
It is worth emphasizing one aspect of Philolaus answer to the prob-
lem of relating the limiting features of the world to the unlimited features.
As I have suggested above, since Philolaus can see no way in which limits
and measures can arise from what is unlimited, he argues that limiters no
136 Carl Huffman
cording to Meinwald, Plato then hoped that all forms might be defined
by such ratios of unlimiteds39.
Philolaus clear identification of harmonia with numerical ratios40
need not mean, however, as Meinwald suggests, that he envisioned
the ratios as ratios between limiters and unlimiteds. What he may
have been thinking can be most easily understood in terms of the proc-
ess of making something, e. g. a statue or a temple. Philolaus own ex-
ample seems to be the making of a musical scale, which at first sight ap-
pears unhelpfully abstract. Such an activity can be made concrete by
thinking of the tuning of an actual lyre or of experiments on a mono-
chord. I will use the monochord as an example, although there is no
good evidence that it was this of which Philolaus was thinking. The
string which is used to make the monochord is an example of something
that is unlimited, something that is a continuum. If a bridge is inserted
under the string somewhere, so that the whole string can no longer vi-
brate but only each of the parts, a limit has been imposed on the con-
tinuum. In the abstract the bridge could go anywhere along the contin-
uum, but once placed it defines a specific length of string. The two parts
of the string now have numbers, which are determined by the place-
ment of the bridge. If one part is twice as long as the other, then one
part has the number two in relation to the number one of the other.
Now bridges could be inserted at any point along the continuum but,
when placed in most positions, the intervals that arise from plucking
the two parts of the string will not be pleasing to the ear. If, however,
the bridges are placed so that the string lengths have the ratios 2:1, 3:2
and 4:3, the concordant intervals of the octave, fifth and fourth are pro-
duced. This example shows how it is that numbers do hold together
limiters and unlimiteds. In one sense, any time a limit is imposed on
an unlimited, any time a bridge is placed under a string, a number arises.
The string cut off by the bridge will have some length. If we are trying
to produce not just a random combination of limiter and unlimited, but
want to impose a limiter on an unlimited in a way that produces a pleas-
ing order, i. e. what the Greeks meant by a cosmos, then we will have to
impose a limit on the unlimited in a way that produces specific num-
bers. In the case of the octave, fifth and fourth these numbers are the
ratios 2:1, 3:2 and 4:3. The musical example may thus have suggested
to Philolaus that any time a limiter and an unlimited are combined, a
number results, and that thus it is a number that defines or fits together
the limiter and the unlimited, although the number is not the same as
either the limiter or the unlimited.
In studying Philolaus metaphysical scheme, it is easy to assimilate
numbers and limiters and to assume that limiters just are numbers. Ar-
istotle appears to make such an assimilation when he asserts that the Py-
thagoreans thought that things were made of numbers. In the surviving
fragments of Philolaus, however, numbers and limiters are clearly kept
separate. In statements of his central metaphysical principles, it is always
limiters and never numbers that are paired with unlimiteds. Thus B 1
asserts that nature in the world-order was fitted together out of things
which are unlimited and out of things which are limiting; it does not
assert that nature was fitted together out of things that are unlimited
and out of numbers. It is in B 6 that the connection between numbers
and limiters and unlimiteds becomes clear. The things from which the
world-order came together are again identified as both the limiting
things and the unlimited things with no mention of numbers. Philolaus
is thus pointing out that the world our senses reveal to us arises both
from continua such earth and also from limiters such as a spherical
shape. A sphere as a geometrical entity, however, need have no specific
size and hence is tied to no specific number. The propositions in Eu-
clids Elements that demonstrate the properties of spheres or circles are
never about spheres or circles with specific sizes but rather about a
sphere of whatever size. B 6 then goes on to point out, however,
that in order for a continuum and a limiter actually to be combined
to produce a physical entity, a harmonia or fitting-together must occur
and, when Philolaus goes on to discuss this fitting-together in B 6a, it
becomes clear that the continua and the limiter must be combined ac-
cording to a number: e. g. the sphere must be assigned a specific diam-
eter. Again, if the combination of limiter and unlimited is to produce a
cosmos, a pleasing order, the number that binds them will not be just any
number but one of a specific set of ratios such as those we find govern-
ing the concordant musical intervals. The crucial thing to recognize is
that the number is not identical with the limiter, but arises as limiter
and unlimited are combined in a specific entity.
When Philolaus asserts that it is a numerical fitting-together that
makes a limiter and an unlimited an ordered whole, he is not really ex-
plaining how it is that number serves to unite limiter and unlimited. In-
deed, in B 6, Philolaus admits his ignorance of how it is that this numer-
ical harmonia arises. He asserts of limiters and unlimiteds that it would
140 Carl Huffman
have been impossible for them to be ordered, if a harmonia had not come
upon them, but immediately adds in whatever way it came to be,
thus acknowledging that exactly how number combines limiter and un-
limited is beyond human knowledge. Despite this inability to explain
the precise mechanism of how number combines limiter and unlimited,
Philolaus is making an important and substantial point. He has observed
empirically that whenever a limiter and an unlimited are combined nu-
merical relationships emerge and that when the combination produces a
particularly pleasing order, such as that of a musical scale or indeed the
cosmos as a whole, the numerical relationships are of a specific sort, e. g.
whole number ratios. Philolaus project is thus ultimately to give an ac-
count of the world in terms of the numerical relationships to which
phenomena point. This project is taken over and significantly developed
by his successor Archytas, as I argue in my recently published edition of
the fragments of Archytas41.
It is now time to return to Heraclitus. My presentation of Heraclitus
and Philolaus critique of him takes a position in a long standing debate
about the essence of Heraclitus message. In my presentation the central
theme in Heraclitus is the paradoxical assertion of the unity of opposites,
which is in turn based on constant change across a continuum. This em-
phasis on the theme of constant change is in accord with the interpre-
tations of Guthrie, Popper, Vlastos, Stokes, and Barnes, among others.
The opposing side of the debate argues that Heraclitus emphasis is
not on change, but on the measure and order of the change in the
world. This view was advocated by Reinhardt and received its most
forceful presentation by Kirk42. In the epilogue to his book Kirk sum-
marizes Heraclitus achievement as follows:
The discovery of and emphasis on the arrangement of things, rather than
their gross material constitution is perhaps the most important one in
the history of archaic speculation. Heraclitus must be given full credit
for having developed this concept so as to produce the first reasonably co-
herent explanation of the world of experience.43
My argument suggests that Kirk is wrong on this point. Heraclitus great
achievement was precisely to give a sophisticated analysis of what Kirk
calls the gross material constitution of things. What earlier thinkers
44 B 1.
45 C. H. Kahn, Anaximander and the Origins of Greek Cosmology (New York 1960)
85 98.
46 B 80.
142 Carl Huffman
Bibliography
Betegh, Gbor. The Derveni Papyrus: Cosmology, Theology and Interpretation.
Cambridge 2004.
Burkert, Walter. Lore and Science in Ancient Pythagoreanism, tr. E. Minar. Cam-
bridge, Mass. 1972. 1st German edn., 1962.
Dilcher, Roman. On the wording of Heraclitus, fragment 126, CQ 44
(1994) 276 277.
Finkelberg, Aryeh. On Cosmogony and ecpyrosis in Heraclitus, AJP 119
(1998) 195 222.
Graham, Daniel W. Heraclitus Criticism of Ionian Philosophy, OSAP 15
(1997) 1 50.
Does Nature love to hide? Heraclitus B123 DK, CP 98 (2003) 175 179.
Huffman, Carl A. Philolaus of Croton: Pythagorean and Presocratic. Cambridge
1993.
Archytas of Tarentum: Pythagorean, Philosopher and Mathematician King. Cam-
bridge 2005.
Archytas, in E. N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
2008. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/archytas/.
Philolaus, in E. N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
2008. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/philolaus/.
Two Problems in Pythagoreanism, in D. Graham and P. Curd (eds.), The
Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy (Oxford 2008) 284 304.
Pythagoras, in E. N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
2009. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2009/entries/pythagoras/.
Hussey, Edward. Heraclitus, in A. A. Long (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to
Early Greek Philosophy (Cambridge 1999) 88 112.
Long, Anthony A. Heraclitus and Stoicism, in id. Stoic Studies (Cambridge
1996) 35 57.
47 B 1.
144 Carl Huffman
As Walter Burkert observed,1 towards the end of the first century of the
Christian era a change in the Verstndnishorizont of the epoch brought
about a new reading of old texts; Heraclitus and Empedocles had
come to be regarded as the predecessors of the Platonic-Pythagorean
doctrine of the descent of the soul into the corporeal world. The au-
thentic evidence at our disposal does not validate the Platonists percep-
tion of Heraclitus as an eschatological thinker on a par with Pythagoras,
Empedocles, and Plato.2 Yet, considering the random character of our
collection of Heraclitus fragments, the lack of authentic evidence of
a full-fledged eschatological doctrine does not indicate decisively that
he had none. Theophrastus silence about Heraclitus eschatological
teaching carries little weight as he passed over Empedocles myth of
the fallen daimn as well. The Platonists list of the eschatologists was
fixed, with no traceable attempts to incorporate additional thinkers.
Therefore, Heraclitus inclusion in it cannot be explained as accidental;
so denying the testimony evidential value for Heraclitus will beg the
question and, considering that the other philosophers on the list were
really eschatologists, a special pleading too. Consequently, we should
admit that in our collection of Heraclitus fragments the eschatological
facet of his teaching is underrepresented, and we have no prospect of
forming any adequate idea of Heraclitus eschatology if we confine
our discussion to the authentic evidence.
3 Consequently, if, as Clement Strom. 5.14.104.3 (= B 31) tells us, the heavens,
and things they encompass, i. e., the heavenly bodies, are produced by sea;
i. e., the sea exhalation, the bright and dry exhalation rises from sea, while the
opposite, the dark one, rises from earth. Accordingly, in Diogenes c_meshai d(
!mahuli\seir !p te c/r ja hakttgr, $r lm kalpqr ja jahaqr, $r d sjo-
teim\r, the opposition $r l]m $r d] is to be construed as a chiastic reversal of the
main clause: Exhalations arise from earth and from sea, those (i. e., the latter)
bright and pure and those (i. e., the former) dark (so, for instance, in R. D.
Hicks Loeb translation and in T. M. Robinson, Heraclitus (Toronto 1987) 168.
5. Heraclitus, the Rival of Pythagoras 149
the earth and the uppermost heaven, it must comprise both atmospheric
air and heavenly fire.
According to Aristotle de An. 405a24 (=DK 22 A 15), Heraclitus
says that the principle is soul, if indeed soul is the exhalation of which
everything else is composed. Aristotles reasoning in equating fire, dry
exhalation, and soul is as follows: if soul is exhalation [and if exhalation is
the principle], then the principle is soul. Aristotle infers the sameness of
principle (fire) and soul from the synonymy of fire and exhalation, on
the one hand, and of soul and exhalation on the other. This inference
indicates that Heraclitus used the term soul synonymously with ex-
halation. Now, if Aristotle equates exhalation with fire, the exhalation
at issue must be bright and dry, and if this exhalation is the same as soul,
it forms soul on the cosmic scale, that is the divine world soul:
Heraclitus says that the soul of the world, which is an exhalation from moist
things in it, and the soul in living beings, which is from the exhalation that is
outside them and in them, are of the same kind (At. 4.3.12 = DK 22 A 15).
Commentators reject the report as crediting Heraclitus with a Stoic doc-
trine. This assessment, however, cannot be defended in view of Aristo-
tles testimony at de An. 405a24, and it is hardly consistent with B 36:
To souls it is death to become water, to water it is death to become earth,
but from earth comes water, and from water soul.
The shift from the plural souls to the singular soul in the otherwise
symmetrical statement must be deliberate and significant. The plural
souls are of course human ones perishing into water, whereas the sin-
gular soul into which water turns evidently refers to the bright and
dry exhalation that forms the soul of the world. This conclusion is re-
inforced by an Orphic imitation of the fragment (Clem.
Strom. 6.2.17.1 = 437 F Bernab = fr. 226 Kern): Water is death to
soul, an exchange for water, / and from water earth, and from earth
water again, / and from it soul, altering the entire sky.4 The traditional
view that Heraclitus souls come from water proves wrong: B 36 says
that while human souls perish into water, water itself is continually
transformed into soul-exhalation that forms the soul of the world and
not individual souls. Significantly, this reading avoids the inconsistency
which otherwise exists between B 36 and Macrobius report on the
heavenly origin of our soul.
Thus, Macrobius stellar essence is the bright and dry soul-exha-
lation gathered and set aflame in the bowls of the stars, which are the
heavenly bodies most distant from the earth. It follows that our soul
is a bit of the bright soul-exhalation, in effect a particle of the divine
soul, which comes from the farthest region of the heavens. And indeed,
if bright exhalation is the soul substance, it must be the substance of the
divine and the human soul alike, which, as Atius 4.3.12 (= DK 22 A
15) tells us, are of the same kind.
The soul of the world is divine by virtue of its physical nature, i. e.,
just because it is the dry fiery-airy body; consequently, if the human
soul is physically akin to the divine, it too must be divine. I turn now
to B 119, which has come down to us in three versions:
(i) Stobaeus Ecl. 4.40.23: Ghor !mhq~p\ da_lym.
(ii) Plutarch Quaest. Plat. 999D-E: Ghor !mhq~pou da_lym.
(iii) Alexander De fato 170.18 (= De an. 2.185.23): Ghor !mhq~pym da_-
lym.
Diels preferred Stobaeus !mhq~p\ and G. Bernardakis5 emended Plu-
tarchs !mhq~pou by the analogy of Stobaeus. However, as Cherniss6
pointed out, Plutarchs genitive is supported by Alexanders !mhq~pym;
a genitive form, probably Plutarchs singular, appears to be a superior
reading.7 Considering that elsewhere in Heraclitus Ghor means nature
(B 78: For the human nature has no insight but the divine does), the
preferred translation of the word in B 119 is nature, (non-moral) char-
acter.8 This, in turn, renders the traditional translation of da_lym as
sky (changing the whole aether, C. Osborne, Rethinking Early Greek Philo-
sophy (Ithaca 1987) 6: in being exhaled from water, soul either alters (in effect
forms) the entire heavens or joins them.
5 Plutarchi Moralia, Bibliotheca Teubneriana, 1888 96.
6 In the Loeb edition of Plutarchs Moralia, 13.1, 20 n 2.
7 Cf. J. Bollack and H. Wismann, Hraclite (Paris 1972) 328.
8 This is the sense in which Ghor occurs in Empedocles B 17.28 and probably in B
110.5. In Herodotus, the word never means moral character, disposition,
or the like; see J. E. Powell, A Lexicon to Herodotus, s.v. Ehea. In Plato,
Crit. 120D-121B the opposition t d !mhq~pimom Ghor:B toO heoO v}sir indi-
5. Heraclitus, the Rival of Pythagoras 151
fate irrelevant, the required sense being god, divine being, demi-
god. This is precisely how Plutarch Quaest. Plat. 999D-E understands
Heraclitus statement:
Is it then his own nature (v}sir), as more discerning than productive, that
he [sc. Socrates] called god (he|m), just as Menander said For our mind
(moOr) is the god and Heraclitus said Mans nature (Ghor) is a da_lym.
Heraclitus idea of the human being, then, is basically the same as that of
Empedocles, who imagined man as a da_lym dressed in an alien robe
of flesh (B 126).
As we recall, Atius says that according to Heraclitus our soul is
made of two exhalations, the external and the internal. The connection
of our soul with external exhalation is explained in Sextus Adv.
math. 7.127 130:
[T]hat which encompasses us (t peqi]wom Blr) is rational and sane
(129) By having drawn in this divine reason (k|cor) through breathing
we, according to Heraclitus, become endowed with a mind9 In
sleep the mind that is in us is separated from its union with the encom-
passing (t peqi]wom) the only attachment preserved being that by breath-
ing as if by a root (130) But on awakening, having peeped through the
sensory passages as through a sort of windows once again and come in con-
tact with the encompassing, it becomes invested with the power of reason
once again [T]he portion of the encompassing hosted in our bodies
by the union (with the encompassing) is made like in kind with the
whole (of it).
H. Diels DG 210 11 argued that since Sextus says that we breathe in
the encompassing k|cor, and since what we actually breathe in is air,
the k|cor, and therefore the principle itself, must be air; this, as we
learn from Sextus Adv. math. 10.233, is Aenesidemus interpretation.
As I have suggested above, however, since in Heraclitus the atmospheric
air must be part of dry exhalation, the latter is the substance we breathe.
cates the synonymy of Ghor and v}sir, a sense quite frequent in Galen (e. g., at
11.9.1: t Ghor toO puqetoO). Note further Pindars affirmation that neither fox
nor lion will ever change its 1lvur Ghor (O. 11.19 20; cf. succemr Ghor in O.
13.13). On the early uses of Ghor see S. M. Darcus, Daimon as a force in shap-
ing ethos in Heraclitus, Phoenix, 27 (1974) 391 94 (although I cannot follow
her interpretation of Theognis, 963 70).
9 moeqo cim|leha. The translation endowed with a mind is suggested by the
correlation between moeqo cim|leha as a result of our having drawn in the en-
compassing k|cor and the subsequent account of the states of b 1m Bl?m moOr,
the mind that is in us; cf. R. Polito, The Sceptical Road (Leiden 2004) 153.
152 Aryeh Finkelberg
in our bodies, enters us with our first breath. From Numenius (fr. 30
des Places) we learn what happens to souls on entering the body:
Heraclitus said that For souls it is pleasure or13 death to become wet [B
77] and that pleasure for them is falling into birth.
In falling into birth the soul becomes wet, evidently as a result of its
attachment to the body. The internal exhalation which, according to
Atius, is another constituent of our soul along with the dry exhalation
from outside, is thus the wet exhalation of the body. The soul is moeq\,
because it is a particle of the intelligent soul-exhalation and for this rea-
son it is best when it is most like it: A dry radiance: soul is wisest and
best (B 118). In becoming wet the soul grows different from the soul
substance, becoming, so to speak, less soul. As we learn from B 117,
wetness disrupts the souls activity: A man when he is drunk is led
by a beardless boy, stumbling, not perceiving whither he goes, having
his soul wet; and if the wetting impact of the body is unchecked,
the soul eventually perishes, turning into water (B 36). As the wetness
of the body damages the soul, Heraclitus figuratively portrays mortal
life as the souls death. Clement Strom. 3.3.21.1, 5.14.105.2 tells us
that Heraclitus calls birth death and that, according to him, the
path of the soul into the body is sleep and death..14 This is how
Philo and Sextus expound the meaning of B 62 and B 88, respectively;
I run their explanations parallel to Plato, Gorgias 492E-493A:
Philo, Leg. alleg. 1.108.1 5: Sext. Pyrrh. hyp. 3.230: Plato, Gorg. 492E-493A:
1. For he [sc. Heraclitus] says: But Heraclitus says that
We live their death, die their
life [B 62]
2. life and death are in us
both when we live and
when we die [B 88]:
3. I should not be surprised, if
Euripides was right when he said:
Who knows, is not to live to be
dead, and to be dead to live?
[fr. 638 Kannicht]. And we, in
truth, are perhaps dead.
For I myself already heard one of
the wise men saying that
4. since now, we are now
when we live, for when we live,
the soul is dead our souls are dead dead
and is buried in the body and buried in us, and the body is to us
as in a tomb; a tomb,
but if we be dead, while when we die
the soul would live the our souls return to
life of its own life and live
5. whereas that part of the soul in
which the desires reside happens
to be prone to seduction and
travels up and down.15
15 Philo, Leg. alleg. 1.108.2 5: Sext. Pyrrh. hyp. 3.230.2 6: Plato, Gorg. 492E-93A:
1. vgs cq [sc. Heraclitus]7 b d Jq\jkeit|r vgsim,
F_lem tm 1je_mym
h\matom, tehm^jalem d
tm 1je_mym b_om [B 62]
2. fti ja t f/m ja t
!pohame?m ja 1m t` f/m
Blr 1sti ja 1m t`
tehm\mai [B 88]
3. oq c\q toi haul\foil( #m eQ
Eqqip_dgr !kgh/ 1m to?sde
k]cei, k]cym t_r d( oWdem, eQ
t f/m l]m 1sti jathame?m, t
jathame?m d f/m; ja Ble?r
t` emti Usyr t]hmalem Edg
c\q tou 5cyce ja Ejousa
t_m sov_m
4. r mOm l]m, r mOm
fte f_lem, fte lm cq Ble?r f_lem,
tehmgju_ar t/r xuw/r tr xuwr Bl_m tehm\mai Ble?r t]hmalem
ja r #m 1m s^lati t` ja 1m Bl?m teh\vhai, ja t lm s_l\ 1stim
s~lati 1mtetulbeul]mgr, fte d Ble?r !pohm-sjo- Bl?m s/la,
eQ d !poh\moilem lem, tr xuwr !mabioOm
t/r xuw/r f~sgr ja f/m.
tm Udiom b_om, jtk
5. t/r d xuw/r toOto 1m
1pihul_ai eQs tucw\mei cm
oXom !mape_heshai ja
letap_pteim %my j\ty.
5. Heraclitus, the Rival of Pythagoras 155
It is evident that Euripides verses, which Plato has Socrates cite, draw
on Heraclitus. In (4) verbal parallels in the three independent sources
suggest a paraphrase of Heraclitus, which authenticates Philos and Sex-
tus explanation of Heraclitus meaning in B 62 and B 88. Platos that
part of the soul in which the desires reside is of course his own, but his
travels up and down validates the report of Iamblichus (ap. Stob. i 49,
39.40) and Aeneas of Gaza (Theophr. 5.12) that Heraclitus posits the
travel of the soul up and down.16 As Proclus (in R. ii 20.23) puts it,
presumably elaborating Heraclitus, souls travel a circular path not
only led by the destiny as the saying goes, pastured by blows [B
11], but also leading themselves.17
So in a way, our birth is the death of our soul, and conversely our
death amounts to its life: Immortals are mortal, mortals immortal, liv-
ing their death, dying their life (B 62). Because of the double, literal
and figurative, meaning of life and death, and of the related wak-
ing and sleeping, our soul can be described in both ways: The same
thing is in us living and dead, and awake and sleeping, and young and
old (B 88). As the newborn soul of a mortal creature, it is young,
alive, and awake, but as a particle of the divine, it is old, dead, and
asleep.18 It emerges that the famous equation of body (s_la) with the
16 This report is found in the passages of Iamblichus and Aeneas which run parallel
to Plotinus 4.8.1. Since Aeneas exposition of Heraclitus, Empedocles, and Pla-
tos theories goes beyond that of Plotinus, he must have drawn, not on Plotinus,
as is usually assumed, but on a source common to him and Plotinus. Burkert
(above, n. 1) suggests that Plotinus (hence also Aeneas) source was a first-cen-
tury Alexandrian compilation, used also by Plutarch, Clement, and Hierocles.
17 As for the transmitted text of B 77 (cf. above, n 13), h\matom, rejected by
E. Zeller, in Zeller-Nestle, Philosophie der Griechen 6, 1.2.890 n. 2) and I. Bywa-
ter, Heracliti Ephesii Reliquiae (Oxford 1877), fr. lxxii), followed by Burnet,
Gigon, and others, is supported by Numenius quotation of B 62 next to B
77, Proclus as Heraclitus says, it is death for souls to become wet [B 77]
(in Plat. Res. 2.270.30), and, most importantly, the paraphrase (4) in the
above synoptic table where Heraclitus equates incarnate life with the souls
death. This equation makes it clear that the transmitted t]qxim l h\matom
must be wrong; one should read, with H. Diels, E (W. Kranz ja_ is paleo-
graphically less likely). That Porphyry, who borrows here from Numenius,
read E (or ja_) is indicated by his paraphrase of B 77 (in Tim. i, fr. 13.10 Soda-
no): that part of the soul, which is the seat of desire, inundated by the mois-
ture incident to generation is enfeebled and sinks into the flows of matter, and
this is another death of intelligent souls, to become wet [B 77], says Heraclitus.
18 Consequently, the explanation offered in the next, epexegetic clause (for these
having changed round are those, and those having changed round again are
156 Aryeh Finkelberg
souls tomb (s/la) is Heraclitus. But this is not surprising: the idea is a
corollary of his view of incarnation as the souls death.19
It is evident that if on entering the body the soul, a particle of the
dry exhalation, becomes mixed with the wet exhalation, it will quit
the body moist. This means that death does not deliver the soul from
the impact of bodily wetness.20 So one would expect to find in Heracli-
tus the theory that the disembodied soul is encumbered with bodily ves-
tiges, and consequently needs to be purified of the body while still in
the body. Such a theory would range with the ascetic and cathartic
ideas of the Archaic Age, typified in the Orphic and Pythagorean doc-
trines of pure life.
For souls it is pleasure or death to become wet (B 77). Souls derive
delight from the bodily life which costs them their own life: It is hard to
fight against desire, for whatever it wants, it offers to buy at the price of
the soul (B 85).21 Most men willingly pay this price, living the brutish
life of gratifying appetites: The many stuff themselves with food,
like cattle, while the best prefer one thing over anything else, ever-
these) is quite irrelevant, and U. von Wilamowitz proves right, pace H. Diels, in
rejecting this clause. Besides, even if life and death in Heraclitus are reciprocal,
they are such not in one and the same thing, hence not in us, but between
things. As to young and old, these are not reciprocal on any account.
19 The s_la-s/la doctrine is usually regarded as Pythagorean and/or Orphic. The
former attribution is merely by default, the latter is at odds with Platos words at
Cratyl. 400C, as Wilamowitz, Der Glaube der Hellenen 2.199 and many others
since then have pointed out. (For a recent defence of this attribution see A. Ber-
nab, Una etimologa Platnica: s_la-s/la, Philologus 139 (1995), esp. 218
23.) Platos wording is not the only difficulty in assigning the s_la-s/la doctrine
to the Orphics: recent decades have witnessed growing awareness that the sharp
dualism of soul and body was not part of the Orphic worldview: A. Boulanger,
Le salut selon lOrphisme, (Paris 1940) 73; U. Bianchi, LOrphisme a exist,
in id., Selected Essays on Gnosticism, Dualism and Mysteriosophy (Leiden 1978) 190;
L. J. Alderink, Creation and Salvation in Ancient Orphism (Chico 1981) 62 64, 83,
88 89; G. Casadio, Adversaria orphica, Orpheus 8 (1987) 392; R. Parker,
The Early Orphism, in A. Powell (ed.), The Greek World. (London 1995) 499.
20 Here is the answer to the difficulty raised by P. Tannery, Pour lhistoire de la sci-
ence hellne (Paris 1887) 190: if the difference between the da_lym before the
incarnation and the human soul consists in the impurity of the latter as a result
of its association with the body, why did Heraclitus attach importance to our
conduct in earthly life, if death restores the souls purity?
21 hul` l\weshai wakep|m f cq #m h]k,, xuw/r me?tai. Offer to buy, bid is a
usual sense of m]olai in the present and imperfect (LSJ, s.v. 1; J.E. Powell, Lex.
Herod., s.v. 2), a sense which suits the purport of the statement better than the
traditional translation buys: to fight hul|r is to decline its tempting offers.
5. Heraclitus, the Rival of Pythagoras 157
lasting glory over mortal things (B 29). The everlasting glory alludes to
martial valour which Heraclitus praises in B 24 (Gods and men honour
those slain in battle) and evidently also in B 25 (Greater deaths win
greater destinies), which Plato (Cratyl. 398B) and Theodoretus (Gr.
aff. cur. viii 39) associate with B 24. Obviously, one who performs feats
of bravery and courage, laying down ones life, behaves in a way contrary
to gratification of the body.
At Strom. 4.4.14.4 Clement reports a theory of the ancients on the
difference between dying in battle and of disease:
And the ancients among the Greeks praise the death of those fallen in
war because he who dies in war passes away without fear of dying,
cut off from the body, without having suffered sickness in the soul nor
slackened, which men undergo in diseases. For they depart in a womanly
manner, longing to live on. For these reasons they let their soul go not
pure but carrying its appetites with itself, like weights of leadsave
those among them who have become renowned for goodness. There are
also those who die in war still with their appetites, and with them it
would make no difference whatsoever if they had died of disease.
Having set against these ideas his concept of purity as life in the knowledge
of God and in agreement with the Commandments, Clement proceeds:
Then Heraclitus says: Gods and men honor those slain in battle [B 24]
and Plato in the fifth book of the Republic [468E-69A] writes: Of those
who die in battle, whoever dies having distinguished himself shall we
not, first of all, say that he is of the Golden race?
The ancients among the Greeks whom Clement has in mind appear
to be Heraclitus and Plato. Since Plato never contrasts two kinds of
death or otherwise disapproves of death by disease, the theory must
be Heraclitus,22 the more so in that it involves the peculiar idea of
the disembodied soul burdened by bodily vestiges. This idea reappears
in Plutarch Rom. 28.8, who phrases it in distinctly Heraclitean physi-
cal terms, mentions Heraclitus by the name, and cites B 118:
For this [sc. soul] alone is from gods [Pindar, fr. 131b.2 3 Snell/
Maehler], for thence it comes thither it returns, not with the body, but
whenever it is most removed and separated from it and becomes complete-
ly pure and bare of flesh and holy. For this is a dry and best soul [B 118],
according to Heraclitus, darting out of the body like lightning out of a
22 As seen by G. Kirk, Heraclitus and Death in Battle (Fr. 24 D), AJP 70 (1949)
384 393.
158 Aryeh Finkelberg
cloud. But a soul mingled with the body23 and burdened with the body,
such as a heavy and misty exhalation, is hard to kindle and to carry up-
wards.
Clements and Plutarchs reports converge to produce a comprehensive
picture. Although a soul mingled with the body is still the dry exhalation
(for otherwise it would not be a soul at all, having perished into water),
it is literally fleshy because of an admixture of the wet exhalation of the
body and therefore heavy and misty, carrying its appetites with itself,
like weights of lead and is hard to kindle and to carry upwards. To
have ones soul pure one should make it bare of flesh, that is, dry.
This can be occasionally achieved through virtuous death in battle,
when one dies without fear of dying, cut off from the body, but oth-
erwise requires extraordinary goodness which consists in ones freeing
oneself from the attachment to bodily life. For when soul is removed
and separated of the body, it is darting out of the body like lightning
out of a cloud, altogether free of fear and desire, and therefore easy to
kindle and carry upwards.
Both Clement and Plutarch refer to the soul separated from the
body and free of appetites as jahaq\, pure. Heraclitus talk about
the purity and purification is confirmed by Iamblichus De myst. 5.15
(= B 69): There are two kinds of sacrifices: those by men wholly pu-
rified (!pojejahaql]mym pamt\pasim), as sometimes happens, though
rarely, to one man, as Heraclitus says, etc. Evidently, the completely
purified is one whose soul is as pure of the wet admixture as it was be-
fore it entered the body. If this is a rare accomplishment, the rest of the
souls must be impure in varying degree. As particles of the dry exhala-
tion, souls must become attached to different strata of the soul-exhala-
tion, and the purer they are, the higher they rise. Souls that are heavy
and misty and hard to kindle and to carry upwards must be situated
in the mixed, impure region, thus remaining close to the earth. By the
same token, a soul which is completely purified of wetness, darting
out of the body like lightning out of a cloud, reaches the pure and lucid
region of the heaven. Since this is the region of the sun and the stars,
arriving there the soul returns thither whence it came, hence recovers
its divinity. Incidentally, this sheds light on Heraclitus puzzling idea
of the heavenly bodies as bowls: these are the abode of fire-like
souls which otherwise would merge with the heavenly fire. If the size
23 s~lati pevuql]mg. v}qy = mix something dry with something wet, mostly
with a sense of mixing so as to spoil or defile (LSJ, s.v.).
5. Heraclitus, the Rival of Pythagoras 159
of the sun is just as we see it (the width of the human foot; B 3),24 the
same must be true of the stars, which makes it plausible to suggest that
each star is a soul-da_lym.
The conclusion that the pure soul recovers its divinity finds support
in B 63 5mha d( 1|mti 1pam_stashai ja v}kajar c_meshai 1ceqt f~mtym
ja mejq_m. Before him [sc. the god] there they rise and become guard-
ians of those wakefully living and those dead. Hippolytus quotes the
fragment to prove Heraclitus belief in resurrection, and there is little
doubt indeed that Heraclitus speaks here of the souls of the dead
which awake and become tutelary deities. Such deities would nor-
mally be called da_lomer, and in fact Heraclitus, as has been repeatedly
observed,25 draws on Hesiod Op. 121 123: Since the earth covered
up this [sc. Golden] race, they have been holy da_lomer guardians
of mortal men.
It emerges that Heraclitus teaching involved an eschatological con-
ception similar to that of the Orphic-Bacchic gold leaves, burial tablets
dating from ca. 400 BC on, discovered throughout the Greek world
(West Sicily, Magna Graecia, Crete, Achaea, Elis, Thessaly, Macedonia).
The doctrine that appears from these inscriptions can be summarized as
follows: the soul is of divine origin; having kept pure during life on
earth, it breaks away from the grievous circle of reincarnations26 and,
facing in Hades the decision of Persephone, pleads for deification,
which is granted: You will be god instead of mortal.27 Similarly in
Empedocles B 112.4: I, an immortal god in your eyes, no longer mor-
tal. Given the divine origin of the soul, deificationin the gold leaves
and in Empedocles alikeis the souls homecoming.
Heraclitus doctrine shows the same pattern of belief the divine
origin of the soul, the circle of births, pure life as the agent of salvation,
and the final return and deification. To recall Sextus paraphrase of Her-
aclitus words (Pyrrh. hyp. 3.230): When we live, our souls are dead
and buried in us, while when we die our souls return to life and
live; and since the body is the defiling tomb of the soul, when a
soul quits it and rises to life, the dead body is more fit to be thrown
out than dung (B 96). The inscription on the fifth-century Olbia
bone plate (463 T, Bernab) provides a concise parallel: Life, death,
life. Truth. Dio(nysus). Orphics.28
Given the state of our evidence, it seems wise not to attempt a de-
tailed comparison of Pythagoras eschatological ideas with those of Her-
aclitus. The typological coincidences between Heraclitus eschatology
and the Orphic doctrine as represented in the gold leaves prove thor-
ough and systematic; it therefore seems justified to infer a similar rela-
tion between Heraclitus and Pythagoras teachings. But although sim-
ilar typologically, these doctrines of course differ in the way they
moulded the shared eschatological beliefs. These differences may seem
secondary to us, but they were undoubtedly of paramount significance
for the proponents of these doctrines. Heraclitus deemed Pythagoras
the head of cheats (B 81) and threatened the initiates and bac-
chantsapparently the partisans of beliefs similar to those attested in
the gold leaveswith punishment for their impiety (B 14; cf. B 15).
Diogenes 9.6 (= DK A 1) tells us that Heraclitus book won such
great fame that devotees of his arose, called Heracliteans. There is no
suggestion in the report that the recognition was posthumous;29 in all like-
lihood, Heraclitus, like Pythagoras, was a renowned teacher of wisdom.
Heraclitus condemned Pythagoras as the head of cheats (B 81) and
called his wisdom artful knavery (B 129). This clearly distinguishes Py-
thagoras from other victims of Heraclitus abuse whom he censured as
silly, ignorant, and unworthy of their high reputation, but never as dis-
honest (A 22; B 40, B 42, B 56, B 57). As Pythagoras was famous for
Bibliography
Alderink, Larry J. Creation and Salvation in Ancient Orphism. Chico, Ca. 1981.
Baltes, Matthias. Die Todesproblematik in der griechischen Philosophie.
Gymnasium 95 (1988) 97 128.
Bernab, Alberto. Una etimologa Platnica: s_la-s/la, Philologus 139
(1995) 204 37.
Textos rficos y filosofa presocrtica. Materiales para una comparacin. Madrid
2004.
Orphicorum et Orphicis similium testimonia et fragmenta. Fasculus 1, Poetae epici
Graeci. Testimonia et fragmenta. Munich/Leipzig 2004.
Bernays, Jacob. Gesammelte Abhandlungen. Berlin 1885 (repr. Hildesheim 1971).
Betegh, Gbor. The Derveni Papyrus. Cosmology, Theology and Interpretation.
Cambridge 2004.
Bianchi, Ugo. LOrphisme a exist, in id., Selected Essays on Gnosticism, Dual-
ism and Mysteriosophy (Leiden 1978) 187 95.
Bollack, Jean, and Wismann Heinz. Hraclite ou la Sparation. Paris 1972.
Boulanger, Andr. Le salut selon lorphisme. Memorial Lagrange (Paris 1940)
69 79.
Burkert, Walter. Plotin, Plutarch und die platonisierende Interpretation von
Heraklit und Empedokles, in J. Mansfeld and L. M. de Rijk (eds.), Kepha-
laion. Festschrift de Vogel (Assen 1975) 137 46.
Bywater, Ingram. Heracliti Ephesii Reliquiae. Oxford 1877 (repr. Heraclitus of
Ephesus, Chicago 1969).
30 The similarity of Heraclitus style to liturgical formulae of the mysteries was dis-
cussed by G. Thomson, From religion to philosophy, JHS 73 (1953) 79, 83,
who labelled Heraclitus language hieratic. The Derveni papyrus appears to
support Thomsons observation: in col. 4.6 Heraclitus seems to be referred to
as speaking like one who relates a sacred discourse: fspeq Ujeka Reqok|c\ (cf.
col. 7.7). Proposed by D. Sider (above, n. 24) 135, this restoration is adopted
in R. Janko, The Derveni papyrus: an interim text, ZPE 141 (2002) 8,
and G. Betegh, The Derveni Papyrus (Cambridge 2004) 10. Alternative restora-
tions are luhok|c\, vusiok|c\, and !stqok|c\.
162 Aryeh Finkelberg
1 The references to Hecataeus are those of F. Jacoby, Die Fragmente der griechischen
Historiker, vol. 1 (Leiden 1957). The author is responsible for the translations,
although a heavy debt is owed to the translations of Heraclitus by C. H.
Kahn and to those of Xenophanes by J. H. Lesher.
2 In contrast with F. M. Cornfords enthusiasm for a connection between myth-
ology and Ionian natural philosophy, From Religion to Philosophy (London 1912),
J. Burnet, Early Greek Philosophy 4 (London 1930) 13-15, argues for the inde-
pendence of Milesian thought from theological speculation and for the sec-
ular character of the earliest Ionian philosophy. The Ionian natural philoso-
phers had purged their use of theos of its religious significance, which
always means first and foremost an object of worship, and these natural phi-
losophers used god only to indicate the eternity of their first principle, as
what is merely ageless and immortal. Burnet contends that this non-reli-
gious sense of theos already exists in Hesiod, who introduces gods no one
would worship, which are mere personifications of natural phenomena, or
even of human passions.
164 Herbert Granger
W. Jaeger, The Theology of the Early Greek Philosophers (Oxford 1947), argues
against Burnet, without pressing the target of his criticism, for the serious theo-
logical enterprise of the early natural philosophers. G. Vlastos, Theology and
philosophy in early Greek thought, PQ 2 (1952) 97-123, in his criticism of
Jaeger, in effect favors Burnets thesis. The early natural philosophers, according
to Vlastos, are not philosophical theologians, since their divinity provides no
justification for cult practices of any sort. Pythagoras, however, is a genuine phil-
osophical theologian, since he established a cult for his followers, which is based
upon his religious beliefs. The natural philosophers in effect assimilate nature and
divinity by attributing the divine features of traditional religion to nature, and
their primary object is to understand nature, not to reform religion. Contrary
to Aristotles report, Vlastos argues that Anaximander never used the word theos
or theion for a description of the apeiron (n. 75). See Guthrie, HGP 1.89 n. 1 for
convincing arguments against Vlastos and in favor of Anaximanders use of theion.
J. Barnes, The Presocratic Philosophers (London 1979) 1.99, has no appreciation of
the theological dimension of the Milesians, who, he contends, pay merely lip-
service to divinity; whereas W. Burkert, Greek Religion (Cambridge, Mass. 1985)
310 311, portrays the philosophers of the sixth century as engaged in serious
theological activity. They did not act with impiety when they broke with tradi-
tional religion, but in the expectation that a better understanding of reality
would yield a better understanding of divinity.
3 K. Algra, The Beginnings of cosmology, in A. A. Long (ed.), The Cambridge
Companion to Early Greek Philosophy (Cambridge 1999) 45-65, illustrates the dif-
ficulty of classifying the natural philosophers. He has argued that the Milesians are
neither philosophical in the modern sense nor strictly scientific in either the
Baconian or Popperian rendition of science, and that they may best be appre-
ciated as protoscientists who stood upon the threshold of that part of ancient
philosophy that came to be known as physics. P. Curd, The Presocratics as
philosophers, in A. Laks and C. Louguet (eds.), Quest-ce que la philosophie prsoc-
ratique? (Villeneuve dAscq 2002) 115-138, does not do much better for the status
of the Milesians as philosophers when she defends what she regards in its fun-
damentals as the traditional interpretation of the Presocratic philosophers as sys-
tematic thinkers who engaged in rational inquiry.
6. Early Natural Theology 165
4 Plato and Aristotle place their major deity beyond the natural world, although
Plato applies the word theos generously and speaks of other deities within the
natural world, such as the heavenly bodies, and even the earth (Ti. 40b-c). Ar-
istotles views upon divinity are less certain across his career. In his lost De phi-
losophia he credits the stars with divinity (Cic. De nat. deor. 2.15.42, cf.
Metaph. 1074a38-b10), and in Cael. 1.9 he describes the sphere of the fixed
stars, which is in eternal circular motion, as the first and highest divinity
(279a32-b3). When he made this statement, Aristotle had not yet presumably
arrived at his idea of the transcendent unmoved mover.
166 Herbert Granger
surviving Greek literature the role of a creator of the cosmos. This god
weaves a robe upon which he embroiders the visible features of earth,
including the ocean that surrounds the earth, and he gives this robe
to his divine bride, Chthoni, as her wedding present (B 2). When
she dons the cartographical robe she assumes the name G, a common
name for the goddess Earth (B 1), and the familiar earth of our cosmos
takes form with the goddess as its divine substructure. The pseudony-
mous Orphic poets provide another important set of actors in this
broad reaction against Hesiod, and they, like Pherecydes, devise theo-
cosmogonies with their own demiurgic dimension.5 All these authors
in their reform give a prominent place to theogony or theocosmogony
in their expositions, probably because the traditional pattern Hesiod fol-
lows and strongly reaffirms locates the essence of the gods in their birth
and heritage and in their positions in the world-order. The discovery of
the Derveni papyrus scroll in 1962 makes it possible for classical scholars
to date the earliest Orphic poems within the sixth century and closer to
the time of Pherecydes.6 There is a broad discontent with the theolog-
5 For Orphism, see W. Burkert, Lore and Science in Ancient Pythagoreanism (Cam-
bridge, Mass. 1972); M. L. West, The Orphic Poems (Oxford 1983); W. K. C.
Guthrie, Orpheus and Greek Religion 2 (London 1952); id. The Greeks and their
Gods 2 (Boston 1954); I. M. Linforth, The Arts of Orpheus (Berkeley 1941).
An excellent summary is provided by R. Parker, Early Orphism, in A. Po-
well (ed.), The Greek World (London 1995) 483-510.
6 The Derveni papyrus is the remains of a commentary by an unknown com-
mentator upon an Orphic theogony, of which some nineteen verses of the
poem the commentator quotes. The date of the commentary is put at around
the last quarter of the fifth century. Parker (above, n. 5) 484 suggests that the
Derveni papyrus makes it plausible that the earliest Orphic poems may be from
the second half of the sixth century, whereas H. S. Schibli, Pherekydes of Syros
(Oxford 1990) 35-36, believes that the main doctrines of Orphism may now
be placed at least closer to the middle of the sixth century, at around the time
Pherecydes composed his book. The text of the Derveni papyrus remains un-
settled, however. The best text for the moment is T. Kouremenos, G. M.
Parssoglou, and K. Tsantsanoglou, The Derveni Papyrus (Florence 2006), for
a review of which, see R. Janko, BMCR 2006.10.29. There is a helpful collec-
tion of essays on the papyrus, edited by A. Laks and G. Most, Studies on the Der-
veni Papyrus (Oxford 1997), and R. Janko provides a significant supplement,
The Derveni Papyrus (Diagoras of Melos, Apopyrgizontes Logoi?): A new trans-
lation, CP 96 (2001) 1-32. For additional important work on the papyrus, see
West Orphic Poems (above, n. 5) 75-101 and G. Betegh, The Derveni Papyrus:
Cosmology, Theology, and Interpretation (Cambridge 2004).
6. Early Natural Theology 167
ical tradition, and it draws together Pherecydes, the Orphic authors, the
Pythagoreans, and the sixth-century physiologoi. 7
In the sixth century the authority of the traditional poets was losing
its grip upon sophisticated imaginations for the reasons Hecataeus of
Miletus lays down in the proem of his Genealogiai, which is his inquiry
into the ancestry of the descendants of Heracles and Deucalion. Homer
and Hesiod had opened their great epics with an expression of their de-
pendence for their knowledge upon the Muses. Left to themselves hu-
mans know nothing and must rely upon rumor (Il. 2.486) for their
opinions about the great events in their history and about divinity. He-
cataeus challenges this poetic pessimism by opening his prose book with
a proud declaration of his epistemic autonomy. He takes credit for what
he writes, and he dismisses the stories of the Greeks because they are
many and absurd (F 1a). Hecataeus, whom Strabo identifies as a
student of Anaximander (14.1.7), finds the stories of the poets incredible
because they provide conflicting versions of the same events, but what is
more significant because the stories are in many cases just incredible in
themselves. Hecataeus finds Homers story of Heracles abduction of
Cerberus unworthy of belief (Il. 8.366 368), and he explains it away
as nothing more than Heracles capture of a snake that had come to
be called, the dog of Hades, because of its deadly bite (F 27, cf. F
25). Hecataeus does not lay down his opinions about the heroes dog-
matically, but he conjectures as it seems to me to be true, and propos-
es what he takes to be the probable truth of the matter.8
The credibility of the poets was judged lacking over two independ-
ent issues. In the one case, the poetic tradition does not provide a suf-
ficiently convincing portrayal of divinity. The Presocratic philosophers
in their revaluations of divinity offer a reassessment that assigns it a
more stately position in the cosmos or beyond. In the other case, the
poetic tradition offers dismal prospects for humans after death. Homer
envisions for human souls an impoverished half-life shorn of most
human qualities, and Hesiod offers nothing better for the mass of hu-
manity. The pseudonymous Orphic poets devise theocosmogonies
that provide for the survival of human conscious personality within a
framework of metempsychosis, and under the tutelage of certain deities
the soul may achieve release from the cycle of birth and death and find
eternal bliss in its deification. Orphism and related forms of spiritualism
depend upon rites of initiation and make demands upon the individuals
behavior, which in the case of dietary restrictions come in direct conflict
with traditional cult sacrificial practices.9 The thinking of the historical
Pythagoras, whose career as a teacher of esoteric doctrines spanned the
second half of the sixth century, is more in keeping with Orphic beliefs,
from what may be gathered from the akousmata credited to him and
from the testimonial record.10 The Orphic poets, however, are infamous
who would lie upon their back and raise their feet above them so that they may
shade themselves from the sun (F 327).
9 Plato reports that the Orphics prohibited the consumption of any animal flesh,
and for sacrifices they made do with cakes of meal and grain soaked in honey
(Lg. 782c-d). The Pythagoreans were more liberal and allowed the consump-
tion of sacrificial beasts (Iamb. VP 82).
10 Our knowledge of early Orphism and the early Pythagoreans is slim, although
there is good reason to believe that they have some large-scale features in com-
mon. The followers of Orpheus, like those of Pythagoras, took a strong interest
in rituals of purification (Plato R. 364b-365a). The Orphics, like the Pythagor-
eans, held to strict dietary regulations, although they were more demanding
than the Pythagoreans, since they upheld a complete prohibition on the con-
sumption of animal flesh (Plato Lg. 782c-d, Eur. Hipp. 952-954, and Aristoph.
Ra. 1032); see Burkert L&S (above, n. 5) 180-183; they also held to some pro-
hibition on beans (Pausanias 1.37.4; cf. 8.15.3-4). But, what is especially signif-
icant, the followers of Orpheus probably advocated metempsychosis (Arist. de
An. 410b28-30, Plato Cra. 400b-c, cf. Phd. 62b, 70c, Ep. vii 335a, Lg. 870d-
e); see Burkert L&S (above, n. 5) 126, 133. The rhapsodic theogony indicates
that metempsychosis is a feature of later Orphism (F 338-9 Bernab); see also
Guthrie Orpheus (above, n. 8) 182-187; Parker (above, n. 5) 500. Burkert
(above, n. 5) 131-132 believes that the oldest sources do not indicate any dif-
ference between Orphic and early Pythagorean doctrines, although he believes
6. Early Natural Theology 169
that the Orphics and Pythagoreans differed in their history and social circum-
stances. Guthrie, Greeks (above, n. 5) 311 n. 3 also does not think that Orphic
and Pythagorean religious beliefs may be separated, but he argues against the
suggestion that the followers of Orpheus were from the lower classes (326-332).
11 No full-blown arguments for the nature of divinity survive in Xenophanes re-
mains. Jaeger (above, n. 2) 49 says of Xenophanes opinions on divinity that
they are not really philosophical or based on logical proof, but arise
from an immediate sense of awe at the sublimity of the Divine. J. H. Leshers
view amounts to Jaegers: Xenophanes of Colophon: Fragments (Toronto 1992).
Xenophanes opinions upon the divine nature in B 23-26 are all dogma and
170 Herbert Granger
the best of the gods and the greatest in strength, v]qtat|r 1sti he_m
j\qtei te l]cistor (Hes. Th. 49). Even though Xenophanes writes in
verse, he calls upon no Muse for his authority. Instead, he offers a sharp-
er analysis of the nature of divinity, as he finds it in the poetic tradition,
and he formulates no proof of the greatest gods existence, which he
takes for granted, just as the Milesians do not undertake a proof of the
existence of their divine first principle.
When Xenophanes analyzes the traditional divine superiority in
goodness and in power, he finds the true nature of these features to
be often at odds with their poetic depictions. The tradition is riddled
with inconsistencies and inadequate renderings of divine properties.
Its depiction of the gods is incoherent when it maintains that the
gods are the deathless ones always existing, !ham\tym aQm
1|mtyv (Hes. Th. 21, Il. 1.290, 2.400, 3.296), and then insists upon
and recounts their birth. Aristotle reports that Xenophanes complains
that it is just as impious to speak of the birth as it is of the death of
the gods (A 12). Xenophanes theological task is to purify the idea of
the gods, and find pure words or purified words (jahaqo k|coi),
with which to honor them (B 1.14). The greatest god, as Homer
and Hesiod would agree, has exceptional power as an implication of
this greatness.12 Zeus is the most powerful of the gods (rpeqlem^r),
and many passages in Homer and Hesiod attest to his and the gods
great power (Il. 2.350, Th. 534). Zeus can make great Olympus
quake with the nod of his head, as Homer relates (Il. 1.528 530),
but Xenophanes improves upon this conception of divine power by
maintaining that the greatest god, without effort shakes all things by
the thought of his mind (B 25). Lesher takes this to be Xenophanes
outright rejection of the Homeric conception of the divine nature, as
what can accomplish great acts with little physical effort, and his replac-
ing it with a divinity that is causally efficacious without any physical ef-
all flat assertion (116), and Lesher is not sympathetic to the suggestion that
Xenophanes idea of divinity is based upon the Homeric tradition. Instead,
Xenophanes opinions arise from his new view of the nature of the divine
(113). For Xenophanes as a theologian, who very likely had metaphysical argu-
ments to back up his beliefs, see Barnes (above, n. 2) 84-94.
12 See Lesher (above, n. 11) 99 for references: e. g. Od. 5.4; Hes. Th. 548. Above
all, there is the passage at Il. 8.17-27, in which Zeus boasts of his being might-
iest of all the gods and of his ability to hang from a peak of Olympus all the
gods, together with the land and the ocean.
6. Early Natural Theology 171
fort; Lesher (above, n. 11) 113. Instead, Xenophanes offers a more ad-
equate analysis of the divine power Homer deficiently articulates.
Xenophanes stresses that the attributes of divinity are those fitting
or seemly for it to possess (B 26), and these would include, besides
moral qualities, the divinitys absolute immobility or changelessness,
which may be a dimension of its absolute power, since the divinity
may accomplish what it wishes with its thought alone without any phys-
ical exertion. The Olympians are ageless, but in the traditional stories
they travel about, paying nocturnal visits, and staging epiphanies: in the
likeness of strangers from afar, assuming all sorts of shapes, they visit cit-
ies (Od. 17.485 486). Zeus, the most powerful of the gods and their
king, has his subordinates, Iris and Hermes, who bear his messages. The
centurion of the Christian Bible tells Jesus there is no call for his coming
to his unworthy home to heal his beloved servant, but say in a word,
and my servant shall be healed. For I also am a man set under authority,
having under me soldiers, and I say unto one, Go, and he goeth; and to
another, Come, and he cometh; and to my servant, Do this, and he
doeth it (Luke 7:7 8, King James Version). Kingly dignity, of the
sort proper to the mighty King of Persia, calls for the king to refrain
from running his own errands.
The divinitys immobility is one important reason Xenophanes pla-
ces it beyond nature, the domain of constant change and corruption.
The indignity of scurrying about after this or that objective is further
reason for prohibiting the divinity from busying itself with nature.
The traditional stories of the divinity that involve it intimately in the
day-to-day workings of nature foster popular depictions that are even
more degrading than those we find in Homer and Hesiod. Aristophanes
offers an instance of this indignity when he has his character Strepsiades
confess his belief that rain is just Zeus pissing through a sieve
(Nu. 373). When Xenophanes turns to nature he tries to show how
its workings on a daily basis are not those of divinity. A simple example
is his account of the rainbow, which is traditionally a messenger of Zeus
and an important omen of the divine will. Xenophanes acknowledges
the traditional religious status of the rainbow, when he identifies it as
she whom they call Iris, but he immediately purges the rainbow of
its religious significance by reducing it to mere cloud-stuff: a cloud
this too is by nature, j purple, red and greenish-yellow to behold (B
32). The rainbow is no longer an omen of the divine will, and two tes-
timonia bear witness to Xenophanes rejection of divination (A 52). Ac-
cordingly, his revaluation of divinity, which takes it beyond nature,
172 Herbert Granger
13 In B 34 god begot yellow honey, eQ l wkyqm 5vuse her lki, but Guthrie
HGP 1.376 takes these words to be a conventional phrase that means nothing
more than if honey had never existed.
6. Early Natural Theology 173
14 Diogenes Laertius 9.19 reports in his own rendition of B 24 that the embodied
god of Xenophanes also does not breathe, oqsam heoO svaiqoeid/, lgdm floiom
5wousam !mhqp\ fkom d bqm ja fkom !joeim, l lmtoi !mapme?m. Dio-
genes is also one of those who speak of this embodied god as spherical.
15 H. F. Cherniss, Characteristics and effects of Presocratic philosophy, JHI 12
(1951) 335. Barnes (above, n. 2) 84-94 is a notable exception, and he offers re-
constructions of what might have been Xenophanes arguments for divine
properties.
174 Herbert Granger
than natural philosophy, but they are unwilling to concede much in the
way of theological interests for the Milesians, Anaximander and Anax-
imenes. Barnes dismisses any theological-sounding language of the
Milesians as mere lip-service to the gods; Barnes (above, n. 2) 99.
Xenophanes, however, can be appreciated as having his antecedents
in the speculation of his predecessor Anaximander, who too should
be appreciated as placing divinity beyond nature, and who very likely
is the first to do so in a thorough way among the Greeks.16 Classical
scholars have not on the whole recognized the significant similarity in
the theological speculation of Anaximander and Xenophanes because
they have not given sufficient weight to the theological dimension in
Anaximanders thought. We have only one sure sentence-fragment of
Anaximanders book, and the rest of what we know of him comes large-
ly from Aristotle or sources dependent upon his student Theophrastus.
Nonetheless, a good case can be made for Anaximanders preoccupation
with theology and for his pious attitude towards the divine nature. And
the same may be said of his presumed student Anaximenes.
Anaximanders cosmogony has for its first principle the apeiron, the
boundless, and this word for the first principle may indicate its nature
as an unknown material substance, the indefinite, rather than its na-
ture as an infinite expanse of material. The apeiron may very well ex-
tend infinitely in space, just as it exists infinitely in time (A 15), and it
lies beyond and encloses the cosmos that arises from it. The testimonium
of Ps.-Plutarch expresses Anaximanders account of the coming-to-be
of the cosmos from the apeiron in vivid biological language:
what arose from the eternal and is germinative of hot and cold was sep-
arated off at the birth of this cosmos, and a kind of sphere of flame from this
grew around the air about the earth like bark around a tree (Strom. 2 [A 10]).
The cosmos comes to be when the apeiron, the eternal, throws off the
c|milom, a seed-like object that is germinative of hot and cold. Hot and
cold would exist in actuality only after they develop from the seed, and
thus neither the seed nor the apeiron from which the seed separates
off would actually be hot or cold. This conforms to those testimonia
that relate that the apeiron is neither water nor any other of the things
16 Pherecydes does not remove divinity altogether from the natural world, since
the goddess Chthoni serves as the divine substructure of the earth. For a com-
parison of Pherecydes and Anaximander, see H. Granger, The theologian
Pherecydes of Syros and the early days of natural philosophy, HSCP 103
(2007) 135-163.
6. Early Natural Theology 175
called elements (A 9, Arist. Ph. 204b22 29), since in these earliest days
of cosmology fire, air, water, and earth had yet to be sorted out from the
properties they bear of hotness, coldness and the like.17 The verb sepa-
rate-off (!pojq_meshai), which describes the way the apeiron throws off
the seed, enhances the biological character of the passage, since sepa-
rate-off is used in medical works for the ejection of seed in conception.18
Hesiod too follows a biological and a genealogical model of explanation,
in which Earth gives birth to Heaven and the Sea, and Earth and Heaven
together give birth to the Titans. Anaximanders biological rendition of
cosmic generation is far less anthropomorphic, and more abstract than
Hesiods theogonic generation, and thus the biological language of Anax-
imander may be merely metaphorical.
The apeiron, in addition to engendering the cosmos, has an influence
on its state. It encompasses all things and all things pilots, as Aristotle
reports (Ph. 203b10 15 [A 15]), and in his testimonium Aristotle also
reports that the apeiron is divine. We find also in separate testimonia
the apeiron described as ageless (Hippol. Haer. 1.6.1 [A 11, B 2])
and deathless (Arist. Ph. 203b13 [A 15, B 3]), and Homer often
pairs these two adjectives (!c^qyr t( !h\mat|r te) to underscore the di-
vinity of deities or their instruments (e. g. Od. 5.218, Il. 2.447, 8.539,
12.323). Although these adjectives are never together in the same testi-
monium, Anaximander may have used them together, but even if he did
not, he may still have used them to mark the divinity of the apeiron and
to express in the poetic words of Homer his homage to its divinity.19 He
may use these adjectives above all to stress that the apeiron under a Ho-
meric description replaces the gods of Homer and Hesiod.20
The impersonality of Anaximanders divine apeiron is the earliest un-
disputed recorded reflection of the sixth-century movement in theolog-
ical speculation, which is especially vivid in the thought of Xenophanes,
away from divine anthropomorphism. The apeiron is not burdened with
17 For the opposites of hot, cold, and the like as quality-things, see F. M. Corn-
ford, Principium Sapientiae: A Study of the Origins of Greek Philosophical Thought
(Cambridge 1952) 160-163.
18 See H. C. Baldry, Embryological analogies in Pre-Socratic cosmogony, CQ
26 (1932) 27 with n. 8, and Kahn Anaximander (above, n. 7) 156.
19 For Anaximanders use of these adjectives, see KRS 117; Jaeger (above, n. 2)
202 n. 39.
20 Kahn Anaximander (above, n. 7) 43 suggests that when Diogenes Laertius says of
Anaximanders view, ja t lm lqg letabkkeim, t d pm !letbkgtom eWmai
(2.1), the Homeric !cqyr has become unchanging.
176 Herbert Granger
the standard medium for the early philosophers.21 But our one sure frag-
ment from Anaximanders book is in prose, and Simplicius comment
upon the passage, or perhaps Theophrastus, that its language is rather
poetic (in Phys. 24.20 21), may signify nothing more than the com-
mentators opinion that Anaximander makes use of metaphors or images
drawn from the courtroom to describe the interaction between the cos-
mic opposites. Anaximander in all likelihood intends for his words to be
taken literally. Cosmic change is subject to the objectivity of disinterest-
ed justice, instead of the partiality of the fickle Olympians. Yet for all
that, Anaximanders prose may have possessed a high degree of artistry,
and he may borrow Homers poetic adjectives for divinity, !c^qyr and
!h\mator, for his apeiron. The authors of prose do not call upon the
Muses, who endow their minions with the power of versification.
Still these prose authors may endow their words with a certain majesty
for dealing with high topics. They may rise above the prosaic speech of
everyday life by making use of rhythmic expressions, assonance, striking
word-order, and vivid images, stylistic techniques that have their origin
in verse.22 Heraclitus brings this poetic prose to perfection. Dei-
chgrber argues convincingly for the pious character of the prose of
Anaxagoras when he writes of his principle Nous, and antiquity noted
his book for its pleasant and dignified composition (Bd]yr ja
lecakovq|myr Bqlgmeul]mom, D. L. 2.6). Deichgrber draws attention
to Anaxagoras use of solemn predication, in which there is a heap-
ing up of ponderous predicates upon the subject of Nous: unlimited,
self-controlled, alone, finest, purest (B 12).23 Heraclitus in his
pious prose does much the same when he describes his deity: The god
day-night, winter-summer, war-peace, satiety-hunger (B 67). These
grand, but conflicting, terms used to name the god also form a pair
of chiasmi in their stately progression. A chiasmus is a phrase constructed
on an abba pattern, in which the a-terms match in some fashion, as well
as the b-terms. In the first two pairs of terms the negative and positive
terms, winter and summer, are the inverse of the positive and neg-
ative terms, day and night, and the same arrangement holds for the
second two pairs of terms. The chiasmus has its provenance in poetry,
but it is also favored by the early authors of prose.24 When Aristotle de-
scribes Anaximanders apeiron as what encompasses all things and all
things pilots, this phrase, ja peqi]weim pamta ja p\mta jubeqmm,
is stylistically in the form of a chiasmus, in which the phrases two tran-
sitive verbs match, just as their plural objects correspond.25 This osten-
sible artistic feature might indicate that the passage records the words of
Anaximander, butwhat is also significantthe passage has a solemn
hymnal quality in its close repetition of all things; Jaeger (above,
n. 2) 30 31 with n. 43. Xenophanes makes conspicuous use of hymnal
language when he says of his supreme god, whole he sees, whole he
thinks, and whole he hears (B 24), in which the hymnal features consist
in the passages solemn, anaphoric repetition of whole and in the use
of the same basic grammar in all three phrases.26 The poetic artistry of
Anaximander may show itself after all in the words of B 1, 1n m d B
c]mes_r 1sti to?r owsi, ja tm vhoqm eQr taOta c_meshai jat t
wqe~m,27 which form a rhythmic balance between generation and de-
struction. At their core these words form an antithesis in the symmetry
of a chiasmus, in which the prepositional phrases from which things
and into these match as the a-terms, just as generation and de-
struction correspond antithetically as the b-terms.
A remark of Diogenes on the nature of Anaximanders book has
fostered the popular interpretation of his book as something less than
a finished, polished book, and as more of a handbook or an aide-mm-
oire. 28 Diogenes says of his book, t_m d !qesj|mtym aqt` pepo_gtai
24 For the prominent use of the chiasmus in early prose, see S. Lilja, On the Style of
the Earliest Greek Prose (Helsinki 1968) 133.
25 KRS 115 suggest that this phrase may form a single rhythmical unit.
26 In his examination of the hymnal qualities of the prose of Anaxagoras and Di-
ogenes of Apollonia, Deichgrber (above, n. 23) 360 cites B 24 of Xenophanes
as an example of hymnodic verse.
27 For what should count as the words of Anaximander in the context of Simpli-
cius quotation, see Kahn Anaximander (above, n. 7) 166-178.
28 An aide-mmoire could be a word-for-word rendition of what the performer re-
cites, but it might be merely notes that provide the performer with reminders as
he performs. Upon such an interpretation, Anaximanders book would be on a
par with lecture notes, which, as some scholars have thought, might just be
what his book is; i. e., nothing more than a basis for Anaximanders public lec-
6. Early Natural Theology 179
tures: e. g. H. Frnkel, Early Greek Poetry and Philosophy (Oxford, 1975) 257
n. 9; H. Thesleff, Presocratic publicity, in S.-T. Teodorsson (ed.), Greek
and Latin Studies in Memory of Cajus Fabricius (Gteborg 1990) 112; C. H.
Kahn, Writing philosophy: prose and poetry from Thales to Aristotle, in
H. Yunis (ed.), Written Texts and the Rise of Literate Culture in Ancient Greece
(Cambridge 2003) 146. If Anaximanders book were lecture notes, we should
expect less polish to be put into its composition. See A. Laks, criture, prose,
et les dbuts de la philosophie grecque, Methodos 1 (2001) 131-151, for a de-
fense of the importance of literary prose for the early Greek philosophers. The-
sleff, Scientific and technical style in early Greek prose, Arctos 4 (1966) 90-
92, however, also surmises that the philosophers who wrote in prose prior to
the treatise of Anaxagoras composed in a gnomic style, which he takes to
have its culmination in the writings of Heraclitus. Thesleff allows that com-
position in pithy passages without an intrinsic connection between them could
take an artistic form. M. S. Schofield, An Essay on Anaxagoras (Cambridge 1980)
25, offers a more plausible view of the nature of Anaximanders book than The-
sleffs proposal of a gnomic style when he suggests that Anaxagoras was writing
in an Ionian tradition of philosophy whose standard mode of exposition was the
cosmogonical narrative. The events of cosmogony and its aftermath would
seem to call for a narration, in which passages are clearly linked in chronological
sequence, just as we find in Hesiods theogony, and the gnomic style would
seem thoroughly inappropriate for this. Kahn Anaximander (above, n. 7) 199
has surmised that Anaximander developed his book chronologically, as a
kind of epic poem, with a clear beginning, middle, and end, which begins
with the coming-to-be of the primal forces of the cosmos from the apeiron and
ends in the appearance of man. This narrative form for cosmogony and its after-
math is what we would expect from authors who have before them for their
precedent Hesiods chronological narration of theogony.
29 Laks (above, n. 28) takes this to be the correct interpretation of Diogenes com-
ment; see also Thesleff, Scientific and technical style (above, n. 28) 90 n. 5.
Kahn Writing (above, n. 28) 145-146 also suggests that Anaximanders book
set the pattern for the standard topics and the order of their display in the books
of the natural philosophers. See also W. A. Heidel, Hecataeus and Xeno-
phanes, AJP 64 (1943) 262.
180 Herbert Granger
we still have some indication of his writing also in a high style for pious
reasons. Anaximenes is reported to speak of his first principle, like
Anaximander, as boundless, as an apeiron, but Anaximenes apeiron is
very different from Anaximanders. It is not unknown, but is air and
thus very definite in character. As air it might be thought to be the
least perceptible of what may be observed in nature, when it is most
even, it is invisible (Hippol. Haer. 1.7.2 [A 7]), unlike earth, or fire,
or water, and thus Anaximenes might have hit upon air as something
of a definite, knowable nature, but the least discernable of what is avail-
able in observable nature, of what is less definite itself, so that it may
serve as the basis for all else. Anaximenes, however, still shares a great
deal with his alleged teacher. His apeiron is eternal, always in motion,
possibly infinite too, and it too is divine (At. 1.7.13 [A 10]). Air too
encompasses all things and perhaps pilots all things as well, as is indi-
cated by a testimonium of Atius that scholars debate as something close
to the very words of Anaximenes: Just as our soul, being air, holds us
together, so the whole cosmos breath and air encompass, oWom B xuw^ B
Blet]qa !q owsa sucjqate? Blr, ja fkom tm j|slom pmeOla ja !q
peqi]wei (B 2).30 Air gives rise to the cosmos, and the cosmos itself is air
and everything in it is nothing but air in condensed or rarefied forms (A
7).31 Anaximenes depersonalizes the natural world through his deper-
sonalization of the divinity by his making it into a natural, commonplace
stuff that goes into the constitution of every cosmic object.
Diogenes Laertius tells us that Anaximenes used simple and unre-
markable Ionic speech, j]wqgta_ te k]nei Y\di "pk0 ja !peq_tt\
(2.3), which is a judgment that may go back to Theophrastus (or to Apol-
lodorus). As Osborne stresses, this description of Anaximenes style does
not rule out his writing in a plain form of verse; Osborne (above, n. 21)
29. Diogenes words, however, would hardly lead one to suppose that
Anaximenes wrote in verse, especially since if he had done so the doxog-
raphers who were accustomed for many generations to the predominance
of prose for the philosophical medium would certainly have noted his ex-
ception, along with those of Xenophanes, Parmenides, and Empedocles.
30 Atius reports these words as if they were Anaximenes. For the dispute over
the authenticity of these words attributed to Anaximenes, see Guthrie HGP
1.131-132, who takes the passage to be largely authentic.
31 D. W. Graham offers reasons for thinking that this standard interpretation of the
monism of Anaximenes is mistaken: A Testimony of Anaximenes in Plato,
CQ 53 (2003) 327-337.
6. Early Natural Theology 181
Thesleff, however, argues that the comment of Diogenes need not mean
that Anaximenes style was a dry and concentrated matter-of-factness,
but only that it did not possess the poetic fireworks of the prose of some-
one like Heraclitus; Thesleff (above, n. 28) 91 n. 6. Thesleff thinks that
possibly Anaximenes book possessed an elevation of style, and for
credible evidence he points to some of the phrasing in the testimonium
of Hippolytus, most likely an excerpt from Theophrastus, which could
make a plausible claim on being close to, if not exactly, the words of
Anaximenes.32 The pertinent part of the sentence reads: !]qa %peiqom
5vg tm !qwm eWmai, 1n ox t cim|lema ja t cecom|ta ja t 1s|lema
ja heor ja he?a c_meshai, t d koip 1j t_m to}tou !poc|mym
(Haer. 1.7.1 [A 7]). Although Thesleff makes nothing of it, other scholars
have noted the peculiarity of the word offspring (!p|comoi) for the
products of air, and have presumed that it is the word of Anaximenes,
which reflects the same biological model of explanation we found in
Anaximander and goes back to Hesiods genealogical explanations.33
The best candidates for the progeny of air, from which the rest
come to be, are the gods and divine things, which are most likely
the other elements (besides air) that go into the makeup of the cosmos,
fire, wind, cloud, water, earth, and stone, which arise most immediately
from the rarefaction and condensation of air. The list goes beyond the tra-
ditional four elements of fire, air, water, earth, but this narrowing of the
cosmic elements to these canonical four is probably due to Empedocles
who identifies them as the four roots of all things in his physics (B
6). Simplicius in his own paraphrase of what is probably the same excerpt
from Theophrastus also lists in the same order fire, wind, cloud, water,
earth, and stone as what emerge from air, and his wording makes it
clear that it is from these the other things come to be (A 5).
Thesleff finds notable the assonance and accumulation of the
opening of the sentence from Hippolytus, which is more art than
would be expected of the doxographers. But it is the peculiarity of
the accumulation that is especially striking, as the solemn invocation
of all that the first principle air is responsible for, namely, all things, in
the present, past, and future, as well as what counts as divinity, from
which come to be things now and things having been and things that
shall be and gods and things divine, with each component in the series
hammered forcefully by the reiterated particle ja_. The phrasing is not
that of a doxographer, but of Anaximenes who is praising his divine first
principle as the ground of all else that there is, and this phrasing can be
traced to a poetic ancestry. The phrasing of present, past, and future re-
calls closely the phrasing found in the poets for the extraordinary
breadth of the events prophets have access to. Homer uses similar phras-
ing to describe the great prophetic scope of the seer Calchas: dr dg t\
t( 1|mta t\ t( 1ss|lema pq| t( 1|mta, who knows things that are and
that shall be and that had been before (Il. 1.70). Hesiod uses exactly
the same wording as Homer when he describes the great scope of the
events the Muses have within their capacity to convey: eUqousai t\ t(
1|mta t\ t( 1ss|lema pq| t( 1|mta, relating things that are and things
that shall be and things that had been before (Th. 38, cf. 32). Anaxi-
menes may borrow this high-sounding language of poetry to express
his pious praise of the grandeur of the deity in its comprehensive re-
sponsibility for all that there is. In turn, he may be followed in his sol-
emn phrasing by subsequent natural philosophers for the same reasons.
Anaxagoras uses similar words to describe the great scope of the organ-
izing influence of Nous: ja bpo?a 5lekkev 5seshai ja bpo?a Gm ja fsa
mOm 1sti ja bpo?a 5stai, p\mta diej|slgse moOr, And whatever things
were to be both whatever were and as many as are now and whatever
shall be, all things mind ordered (B 12).34 Empedocles does the same
when he describes the great scope of what comes to be from his divine
elemental substances: 1j to}tyv cq p\mh( fsa t( Gm fsa t( 1sti ja
5stai, For from these all things as many as were and as many as are
and shall be (B 21.9).35 The language of Anaximenes may provide
the precedent for the pious phrasing of these two fifth-century natural
philosophers for their description of the great range of the productive
and organizing power of their first principles.
Anaximander proposes an eternal, impersonal divinity for the agent
that gives rise to our cosmos. This divinity remains largely mysterious,
and one of the few things Anaximander allows that we may know
about it is its state of eternal motion (A 9), which he may base upon
34 Simplicius quotes this line from the text of B 12 in four different ways. See
Schofield (above, n. 28) 145 n. 1 for the above version of the line.
35 Heraclitus uses a similar pattern when he speaks of the eternity of the cosmos as
fire ever living, Gm !e ja 5stim ja 5stai pOq !e_fyom (B 30).
6. Early Natural Theology 183
W\eor foveqo?o (814), and Chaos without any mate gives birth to the first
divine offspring, Erebus and black Night, who are male and female
twin versions of darkness (123).38 The darkness of Chaos and its engen-
dering forms of darkness may be meant to indicate that Chaos comes
from circumstances about which nothing can be known.
The apeiron, from which our cosmos emerges, remains largely beyond
the reach of human comprehension. Anaximanders book probably did not
dwell much on the divine apeiron, beyond what the testimonial record re-
lates, since little can be known about it. Xenophanes may be allied in his
thought with Anaximander, since he proposes a transcendent deity who
lies beyond what humans may know: and of course the clear and certain
truth no man has seen nor will there be anyone who knows about the gods
and what I say about all things (B 34, tr. Lesher). Both men posit a mys-
terious divinity behind the workings of the visible cosmos, and the verse of
Hesiod may provide a precedent for their position when it depicts the
emergence of the world-order from unknown conditions.
The views of Anaximander and Xenophanes are in sharp contrast
with those of Anaximanders alleged student Anaximenes. Anaximenes
characterizes his own apeiron as divine, just as Anaximander does, but
Anaximenes makes his divine apeiron observable air. He lays down an im-
manent, knowable divinity, whereas Anaximander and Xenophanes pro-
pose a transcendent, unknowable divinity. Heraclitus of Ephesus, who is a
younger contemporary of Anaximenes and Xenophanes, is closer in his
theological speculation to Anaximenes. Although Heraclitus is no panthe-
ist, as Anaximenes might be plausibly construed, he does posit a divinity
that is common to everything in the cosmos, which is the whole of reality
for Heraclitus, but this divine commonality is comparable to the way the
laws of a city are common to its citizenry (B 114).
Most scholars have little problem in conceding the significance of
Heraclitus theological concerns.39 Any rendition of Heraclitus divinity
must put at its center his comments on the logos, of which B 1 provides
his opening words on the topic, the first sentence of which reads: Al-
though this Word is always men are uncomprehending, both before
hearing it and once they have heard. The nature of this Word has
provided a topic of controversy, and Barnes and West take logos to sig-
38 Although Erebus is a neuter noun, the deity plays a masculine role as the consort
of Night.
39 Barnes (above, n. 2) 99 willingly acknowledges Heraclitus devotion to divin-
ity.
6. Early Natural Theology 185
40 M. L. West, Early Greek Philosophy and the Orient (Oxford 1971) 114-115;
Barnes (above, n. 2) 59.
41 Kahn, H. 92-95 argues convincingly for reading the always of the first sen-
tence of B1 with both clauses.
42 C. Sourvinou-Inwood, Delphic Oracle, OCD 3 445-446, suggests that the
ambiguity of Apolline oracles is not due to the Apolline prophets trying to
hedge their bets, but it is the acknowledgment of the ambiguity inherent
in the gods prophecy and of human fallibility in apprehending the future.
For the ambiguity of the Greek deities in communication and in nature, see
M. Detienne, Masters of Truth in Archaic Greece (New York 1996) 84-86.
43 Barnes (above, n. 2) 63 adopts Aristotles monistic interpretation of Heraclitus,
although he admits that the evidence is thin. Among others, D. W. Graham,
186 Herbert Granger
clude, Heraclitus outrages traditional reverence for the dead when he says
of corpses, in three words only, that they should be disposed of more
quickly than dung (B 96), where he picks the crudest word available
for dung (jopq_om). This is an insult and looks like a challenge to tradi-
tional piety, since it runs so counter to it: the funeral rites owed to the
dead are owed to the gods (Ant. 519, 1070 1076), and Creon and Anti-
gone, who in her own words dares a righteous crime (fsia pamouqc^-
sasa, 74), are contending over what is holy, eqac^r (521). The soul of
Patroclus appears in a dream to Achilles and urgently implores him to
bury his corpse quickly so that his agitated soul may pass the gates of
Hades and find repose (Il. 23.71). Heraclitus insult, however, offends
also the new beliefs of the Orphics, whose grave sites in southern Italy
and elsewhere indicate that the followers of Orpheus engaged in distinc-
tive burial practices.46 Xenophanes has nothing to match these harsh
words of Heraclitus. At most he reduces the goddess Iris to the stuff of
colored clouds. Yet what does Heraclitus criticism come to? Dung is
waste, offal, but also manure for new life. Is this insult less of an insult,
or not one at all? No matter what the event, it remains provoking.
Heraclitus might be thought to bring out the absurd features in tra-
ditional religious practice: They purify themselves in vain with blood
when defiled with it, as if a man who had stepped into mud were to
wash it off with mud. He would be thought mad if any man noticed
him acting thus (B 5).47 His pointing out the comparability of the ritual
practice of cleansing oneself of blood-guilt with a blood-sacrifice and of
the mad act of cleansing oneself of mud with mud looks like a reduction
to absurdity through an analogy. Blood, however, has opposing proper-
ties, polluting and purifying, which comes out neatly in Heraclitus
Greek by the double use of the single occasion of blood by the
two verbal forms flanking it: jaha_qomtai aVlati liaim|lemoi. Since
Heraclitus approves of the conjunction of opposing properties, one is
at a loss how to assess definitively the import of this passage. Yet he
does not approve of this bloody ritual, since he describes it as exercised
in vain (%kkyr).48
46 Parker (above, n. 5) 485, 496-498. Herodotus 2.81 reports that those who en-
gage in the rites of Orpheus cannot be buried in woolen garments.
47 This rendering of B5 is based on the proposal of Marcovich, H. 459.
48 C. Osborne, Heraclitus and the rites of established religion, in A. B. Lloyd
(ed.), What is a God? (London 1997) 40 n. 2, retains the %kkyr of the manu-
script, instead of the emendation of %kk\, which Kranz adopts, and she takes
190 Herbert Granger
this text to support her translation in a different way. The reversion to the
manuscript reading of %kkyr does not rule out the translation of in vain.
49 For the text for this rendering of Heraclitus B 14, see T. M. Robinson, Hera-
clitus: Fragments (Toronto 1987) 85-86 and Marcovich, H. 464. For the view
that Heraclitus has some regard for the mysteries, see Guthrie, HGP 1.476,
KRS 209-210, R. Seaford, Reciprocity and Ritual: Homer and Tragedy in the De-
veloping City-State (Oxford 1994) 226-228, 321-322.
50 Kahn, H. 254-256 is prominent among those who take B 63 to be evidence of
Heraclitus belief in the resurrection of the souls of some selected dead.
6. Early Natural Theology 191
watchers of mortal men (Op. 253). Yet a better case can be made for
these wakeful watchers as the wise who have awakened from the stu-
por of their sleepy ignorance, since Heraclitus equates ignorance with
the subjectivity of sleep (B 89).51
Both Xenophanes and Heraclitus are possibly polytheists. This is
perhaps more certain in the case of Xenophanes (B 23.1), but Heraclitus
allows himself to speak of gods now and again (B 5, B 24). Neither
theologian abandons the tradition altogether. Xenophanes may be ap-
preciated as in effect affirming the basic presumptions of tradition
when he undertakes his purification of traditional religious language
under the direction of his more astute estimation of what is entailed
by the traditional belief in the goodness and strength of the greatest
deity (Hes. Th. 49). But Xenophanes does not make any apparent use
of the old names or any of the traditional epithets for the gods. His
greatest god remains unnamed, and Xenophanes remains more abstract
in his discourse on the divine nature, on gods and the greatest god. Her-
aclitus does not abandon the names or the epithets, but he uses them
unconventionally or even paradoxically. He follows, but deviates in im-
portant ways from, traditional religious thought. Below are a few nota-
ble examples of Heraclitus unconventional use of conventional reli-
gious language, stories, and conceptions.
(1) Heraclitus designates Apollo indirectly as the lord whose oracle is
in Delphi (B 93), which is a description and not a traditional
name or epithet for the god. Heraclitus mimics the obliquity of
the Pythian Apollo himself, who gives a sign, and scholars gen-
erally take his analysis of Apolline speech to be an indirect analysis
of his speech and the logos that makes up the heart of reality.52
(2) Artemis is the twin sister of Apollo, and Diogenes reports that
Heraclitus deposited his book at her great temple in Ephesus
(9.6). His dedication of his book to the goddess may amount to
its publication and to his making his thoughts available to the pub-
lic, rather than, as some scholarse. g., Kahn, H. 2have pro-
posed, his secreting them away from the vulgar. Heraclitus
would not shun publicity, since he firmly believes that the truth of
the logos is common and open to anyone, and not a private posses-
sion of the privileged few. The twin children of Leto may have
furnished Heraclitus with the two sides of his display of the
truth: his medium of indirect expression and his public venue
for his publication.
(3) One, the wise alone, is not willing and is willing to be called by
the name of Zeus (B 32). The genitive Fgm|r may be used to al-
lude to the infinitive f/v to live,53 but at any rate this passage
brings sharply to the fore Heraclitus ambivalence towards tradi-
tion. He is willing to appropriate for his first principle a traditional
name of the supreme god of Homer and Hesiod, but he is not will-
ing to adopt it without qualification. There is no impiety in its use
and none in its neglect. The wise alone tolerates the use of Zeus
by mortals for its name, since the Zeus of tradition is the wisest and
the most important of the gods, but, like Xenophanes unnamed
deity, the wise in itself has no proper name.
(4) The only other surviving use of Zeus among Heraclitus frag-
ments is found in B 120 with an epithetical-like attribute: The
limits of dawn and evening is the Bear, and, opposite the Bear,
the watcher of luminous Zeus, AoOr ja 2sp]qar t]qlata B
%qjtor ja !mt_om t/r %qjtou owqor aQhq_ou Di|r. The star Arctu-
rus is the Bear-watcher or warder, b )qjtoOqor, and the Bear
Arcturus watches is the constellation Ursa Major, a mark for the
celestial pole-star. The time of rising of Arcturus is the middle of
September, and in Hesiod is a signal for fall and spring (Op. 566,
610); Kahn, H. 161 163. Zeus has a traditional association with
fire, as the wielder of lightning bolts, and as the hoarder of fire,
who will not share it with mankind. Hesiod recounts the theft
of Prometheus and describes the fire he steals as unwearying,
puqr l]mor !jal\toio (Th. 563), and this lack of fatigue might
be a feature of fire that Heraclitus found attractive in his efforts
to understand the limitless power of divinity.
(5) Heraclitus stresses the importance of fire as a guiding-principle in
Thunderbolt (jeqaum|r) steers all things (B 64), and the thunder-
power for lowering the famous and mighty and for raising the weak and
unknown:
fm te di bqoto %mdqer bl_r %vato_ te vato_ te,
Ngto_ t %qqgto_ te Dir lec\koio 6jgti.
N]a lm cq bqi\ei, N]a d bqi\omta wak]ptei,
Ne?a d !q_fgkom lim}hei ja %dgkom !]nei,
Ne?a d] t Qh}mei sjokim ja !c^moqa j\qvei
Fer rxibqel]tgr, dr rp]qtata d~lata ma_ei.
Through him mortal men alike are unnamed and named,
sung and unsung, by means of great Zeus.
For easily he strengthens, and easily the strengthened he crushes,
Easily the conspicuous he diminishes and the obscure he increases,
Easily he straightens the crooked and the arrogant he withers,
Zeus who thunders aloft, who in the highest halls dwells (Op. 3 8).
What is Heraclitus trying to achieve with the unconventional use of
conventional religious ideas and language?
Xenophanes in B 1 judges the traditional divine stories to be impi-
ous, and he puts his recommendations in the pious language of men
must hymn the god and make do with reverent stories and purified
words, eqv^loir l}hoir ja jahaqo?si k|coir. He calls upon his audi-
ence to make a libation and engage in prayer, and at the conclusion of B
1 he stresses that it is good always to be mindful of the gods. Nothing
of this sort of invocation of piety, which follows so closely traditional
language and practices, appears in Heraclitus. Yet in contrast with Xen-
ophanes, Heraclitus does not purge his speech of the traditional divine
names and epithets. Pythagoras too uses conventional religious termi-
nology and ideas for novel purposes, as the akousmata credited to him
would indicate,57 and perhaps he uses this conventional language to
some degree to reassure his auditors that he is still working within the
tradition, or not too far from it, and to soften the novelty of his opin-
ions. After all, the Pythagoreans make concessions to traditional practi-
57 For instance, the islands of the blest the Pythagoreans identified with the
Sun and the Moon (Iamb. VP 82), and Tartarus they also designated as a
place of punishment (Arist. Apo. 94b33). The sea is the tear of Cronos; the
Great and the Little Bear are the hands of Rhea; the Pleiades the lyre of
the Muses; the planets the dogs of Persephone; daemons can be trapped
in bronze (Porph. VP 41). The oracle of Delphi is identified with the tet-
ractys (fourness), which, in turn, is identified with the harmony the Sirens
sing within (Iamb. VP 82). Iamblichus records one akousma that identifies Py-
thagoras with the Hyperborean Apollo (140).
196 Herbert Granger
cannot abandon the traditional way of talking about the divine nature
for an altogether new way, although only through twisting the tradi-
tional religious stories and their language around in unexpected ways
can he find the proper way to reveal the divine truth. Homer is
wrong to have Achilles pray for the disappearance of strife between
gods and men (A 22, Il. 18.107), since Homer fails to appreciate that
the father of all, if properly understood, is War (B 53) and that
Justice is Strife (B 80). In accord with the reformed idea of divinity
initiated by the Milesians and taken up by Xenophanes, Heraclitus refa-
shions the old religious formulas so that they may reveal the true nature
of divinity and may furnish the proper litany for its praise.59
The transcendent or supernatural divinity of Anaximander and
Xenophanes aids in the depersonalization of the nature Hesiod popu-
lates with highly anthropomorphic gods and goddesses. As Hesiod
points out, even the best of seers can never know the mind of Zeus
(fr. 303 Merkelbach-West),60 and when natural events are under the
control of whimsical deities, science would not be possible. Even
though the immanent theism of Anaximenes and Heraclitus brings to-
gether nature and divinity, these theologians too are in a position to
provide an improved appraisal of nature, since, like Anaximander and
Xenophanes, they rid the divine nature of its cruder traditional anthro-
pomorphisms. They tame nature through their domestication of the di-
vinity that makes up the heart of nature. The depersonalization of the
divine nature in the rejection of traditional anthropomorphisms rids
the divinity of its human-like will and its predilection for falling into
capriciousness. Even though in immanent theism divinity and nature
are identified or intimately bound up together, as in the case of Hesiods
theology, divinitys depersonalization allows for predictable regularity in
nature, and this ushers in the stability of the cosmos which was the dom-
inating desideratum of Hesiod as well. Hesiod endeavors in his Theogony
to reassure his audience of the permanence of the current world-order
under the just rule of Zeus, who, after his violent ascension to sover-
eignty, has shown himself capable of overcoming all unsettling obstacles
59 Burkert Gk. Rel. (above, n. 2) 309-310 takes Heraclitus to rebuild the bridge
to tradition with his ceremonial prose or prose art after the Milesians, with
their matter-of-fact prose, had dismantled it.
60 Hes. Fr. 303 M-W ap. Clem. Alex., Strom. 5.14.129: lmtir d( oqd( eXr 1stim 1pi-
whomym !mhqpym, j fstir #m eQdeg Fgmr mom aQciwoio. It is uncertain to
what work this fragment belongs.
198 Herbert Granger
that may come his way. The natural philosophers who are among the
new thinkers of the sixth century provide, however, an assurance,
which is more convincing, of cosmic stability in their reassessment of
the divine nature.61
Bibliography
Algra, K. The Beginnings of Cosmology. In A. A. Long (ed.), The Cambridge
Companion to Early Greek Philosophy (Cambridge 1999) 45 65.
Baldry, H. C. Embryological analogies in Pre-Socratic Cosmogony, CQ 26
(1932) 27 34.
Barnes, J. The Presocratic Philosophers. Vol. 1. Thales to Zeno. London 1979.
Aphorism and argument. In K. Robb (ed.), Language and Thought in Early
Greek Philosophy. (La Salle 1983) 91 109.
Betegh, G. The Derveni Papyrus: Cosmology, Theology, and Interpretation. Cam-
bridge 2004.
Burkert, W. Lore and Science in Ancient Pythagoreanism. Trans. E. L. Minar, Jr.
Cambridge, Mass. 1972 [1962].
Greek Religion. Trans. J. Raffan. Cambridge, Mass. 1985 [1977].
Burnet, J. Early Greek Philosophy. 4th edn. London 1930.
Cherniss, H. F. Characteristics and effects of Presocratic philosophy, JHI 12
(1951) 319 345.
Cornford, F. M. From Religion to Philosophy. London 1912.
Principium Sapientiae: A Study of the Origins of Greek Philosophical Thought.
Cambridge 1952.
Curd, P. The Presocratics as philosophers. In A. Laks and C. Louguet (eds.),
Quest-ce que la Philosophie Prsocratiques? Cahiers de philosophie, 20 (Ville-
neuve dAscq 2002) 115 138.
Deichgrber, K. Hymnische Elemente in der philosophischen Prosa der Vor-
sokratiker, Philologus 88 (1933) 347 361. Repr. in id. Ausgewhlte Kleine
Schriften, ed. H. Gartner, E. Heitsch, and U. Schindel (Hildesheim 1984)
67-81.
Denniston, J. D. Greek Prose Style. Oxford 1952.
Detienne, M. Masters of Truth in Archaic Greece. Trans. J. Lloyd. New York 1996
[1967].
61 I owe a debt of gratitude to Apostolos Pierris for his generous invitation to par-
ticipate in the Fifth Symposium of Ancient Philosophy and for his thoughtful
organization of this conference, which brought together an international col-
lection of scholars, of the most congenial natures, from whose considerable
learning I benefited greatly, and for which I am deeply grateful. I also wish
to express my gratitude to David Sider and Dirk Obbink for their collecting
and editing the papers of the conference and for their bringing them to publi-
cation.
6. Early Natural Theology 199
Frnkel, H. Early Greek Poetry and Philosophy. Trans. M. Hadas and J. Willis.
Oxford 1975 [1951].
Graham, D. W. Heraclitus criticism of Ionian philosophy, OSAP 15 (1997)
1 50.
A Testimony of Anaximenes in Plato, CQ 53 (2003) 327 337.
Granger, H. Deaths other kingdom: Heraclitus on the life of the foolish and
the wise, CP 95 (2000) 260 281.
The Theologian Pherecydes of Syros and the early days of natural philos-
ophy, HSCP 103 (2007) 135 163.
Poetry and prose: Xenophanes of Colophon, TAPA 137: 403 433.
Guthrie, W. K. C. Orpheus and Greek Religion. 2nd edn. London 1952.
The Greeks and their Gods. 2nd edn. Boston 1954.
Heidel, W. A. Hecataeus and Xenophanes, AJP 64 (1943) 257-277.
Hussey, E. Epistemology and meaning in Heraclitus, in M. S. Schofield and
M. C. Nussbaum (eds.), Language and Logos (Cambridge 1982) 33-59.
Jaeger, W. The Theology of the Early Greek Philosophers. Trans. E. S. Robinson.
Oxford 1947.
Janko, R. The Physicist as hierophant: Aristophanes, Socrates and the author-
ship of the Derveni Papyrus, ZPE 118 (1997) 61-94.
The Derveni Papyrus (Diagoras of Melos, Apopyrgizontes Logoi?): A new
translation, CP 96 (2001) 1-32.
Review of The Derveni Papyrus by T. Kouremenos, G. M. Parssoglou,
and K. Tsantsanoglou, BMCR 2006.10.29.
Kahn, C. H. Anaximander and the Origins of Greek Cosmology. New York 1960.
Writing Philosophy: Prose and Poetry from Thales to Plato, in H. Yunis
(ed.), Written Texts and the Rise of Literate Culture in Ancient Greece (Cam-
bridge 2003) 139-161.
Kingsley, P. Ancient Philosophy, Mystery and Magic: Empedocles and the Pythagorean
Tradition. Oxford 1995.
Kouremenos, T., G. M. Parssoglou, and K. Tsantsanoglou. The Derveni Papy-
rus. Edited with Introduction and Commentary. Studi e testi per il Corpus dei pa-
piri filosofici greci e latini, vol. 13. Florence 2006.
Laks, A., and G. Most. Studies on the Derveni Papyrus. Oxford 1997.
criture, prose, et les dbuts de la philosophie grecque, Methodos 1 (2001)
131-151. http://methodos.revues.org./document139.html.
Lesher, J. H. Xenophanes of Colophon: A Text and Translation with a Commentary.
Toronto 1992.
Lilja, S. On the Style of the Earliest Greek Prose. Helsinki 1968.
Linforth, I. M. The Arts of Orpheus. Berkeley 1941.
Northrup, M. D. Hesiodic personifications in Parmenides A 37, TAPA 110
(1980) 223-232.
Osborne, C. Was verse the default form for Presocratic philosophy? In C.
Atherton (ed.), Form and Content in Didactic Poetry (Bari 1997) 23-35.
Heraclitus and the rites of established religion, In A. B. Lloyd (ed.), What
is a God? Studies in the Nature of Greek Divinity (London 1997) 35-41.
Parker, R. Early Orphism. In A. Powell (ed.), The Greek World (London
1995) 483 510.
Robinson, T. M. Heraclitus: Fragments. Toronto 1987.
200 Herbert Granger
Heraclitus made remarkable contributions to the idea and the ideal of ra-
tionality. In particular, he prefigured many of the distinctive ways by
which Plato and subsequent Greek philosophers conceptualized this car-
dinal notion. These are the two propositions I intend to substantiate in
my paper. No one, I presume, needs to be persuaded that Heraclitus
logos involves rationality in some sense or senses of that word.1 The in-
terest of the inquiry turns entirely on what Heraclitus himself was seek-
ing to express with the term logos and on why, in recounting his own
logos, he uses such words as l]tqom, m|lor, "qlom_g, j|slor, d_jg,
cm~lg, syvqos}mg, num|r, and blokoce?m; 2 for I assume that Heraclitus,
rather than invoking any pre-existing concept of rationality connoted by
the word logos, found himself largely in the process of discovering that
very thing. This is not to say that he created it from nothing. He had
available to him, as we see from the inherent meanings of logos, such
concepts as meaningful discourse, account, ratio, and reckoning; and
he also had available, as we see from the other Greek terms I have listed,
such further concepts as measure, proportion, balance, law, structure,
order, arrangement, judgment, plan, moderation, commonality, and co-
herence. His logos is or has or bespeaks all of these notions, and accord-
ingly it comprises much that we moderns associate with rationality. My
thesis, in essence, is that Heraclitus discovered an idea and ideal of ra-
tionality by incorporating such notions in his logos, something that no
one, to the best of our knowledge, had done before.
If there is a single term that captures the essence of rationality, as
Heraclitus conceived of it, we should opt for the word l]tqom, measure.
Heraclitus focus on measure, and on the conceptual relations and im-
plications of measure, whether for cosmology or mind or ethics,
was his most salient contribution to providing an explicit formulation
of rationality. I emphasize explicit, to avoid giving the impression that
I take Greeks before Heraclitus to have implicitly lacked rationality or
rational practices. The metrical form and structure of Homeric epic,
Hesiods catalogues of divine genealogy, social practices for settling dis-
putes by means of witnesses and the citation of evidence, the political
convention of making speeches pro and contra, counting and measuring
all of these, like human language as such, are implicit manifestations of
rationality. Long before Heraclitus, too, the Greeks had an intuitive un-
derstanding that behavior is normative (syvqome?m) precisely to the ex-
tent that it is sensible or moderate or orderly (jat j|slom or jat lo?qam).
What Heraclitus discovered, so I propose, was not how to make all of
this explicit, but how to articulate rationality in terms of measured or
proportional processes both in (what we would call) non-animate nature
(including, specifically, the unity of opposites) and also in analogous dis-
course, mental disposition, and day-to-day conduct.
Notice, too, that what I am attributing to Heraclitus is an idea, not a
complete account, much less an analysis, of rationality. Rationality com-
prises much more than we find in Heraclitus, including, for instance,
formal proof, rules of logic, or the best means to achieve a given end.
It also involves procedures, such as reductionism and economy of ex-
planation, which he uses but which are probably not presupposed by
his explicit interest in measure and proportion. Heraclitus conceptual-
7. Heraclitus on Measure and the Explicit Emergence of Rationality 203
3 Plato, Aristotle, and Stoics frequently signify the normative sense of rationality
with the expression aqhr k|cor, Translators typically render this phrase by
right reason or correct rule, but they would do better, in my opinion,
to opt for correct ratio or right proportion, in line with what I take to
be Heraclitus seminal conception of rationality.
4 Xenophanes B 17, 40, 42, 57, 67.
204 Anthony A. Long
12 With Grg. 492e10 493a3 (Platos citation of Euripides, Who knows if living
is being dead, and being dead is living? and the s_la/s/la identification), cf.
Sextus Empiricus, PH 3.230, who attributes something very similar to Heracli-
tus, as noted by Dodds in his edition ad loc.
208 Anthony A. Long
13 See M. Burnyeat, Plato on why mathematics is good for the soul, PBA 103
(2000) 1 81, for brilliant suggestions in response to this question.
7. Heraclitus on Measure and the Explicit Emergence of Rationality 209
What does Heraclitus mean by doing things that are true? Kahn,
H. 122 puzzles over this curious and seemingly unparalleled expression.
He suggests that Heraclitus wants to say that the man whose thinking is
sound will not hide the truth but signify it in his actions as in his words.
This suggestion does not go far enough, in my opinion. Taking our lead
from Plato, we shall hardly go wrong if we endow Heraclitus !kgh]a
with connotations of straightness, balance, and due proportion. Thus
his truths, as the context of B 112 requires, are norms of properly
measured action as much as they are norms of thought and speech.
Plato regularly couples balanced (l]tqior) with such commenda-
tory words as s~vqym, jak|r, jahaq|r, %qistor, and b]baior.15 In the
Republic (3, 412a5) the most musical and harmonious person is the
one who best combines physical and musical education and applies
them to his soul in the most measured way (letqi~tata). The mark
of an unmusical and unshapely soul is !letq_a (6, 486d5). These con-
texts are in line with the passage I already discussed from the Gorgias,
but the Republic proposes still more precise connections between ration-
ality and balance or proportion.
Reviewing the newly formulated community, Socrates invites his in-
terlocutors to agree that it could be called s~vqym and master of itself
if its better constituent rules over its worse one (4, 431b-c). He continues:
You all would also find especially among its children and women and slaves
a multitude of all kinds of desires and pleasures and pains but simple
and moderate ones, which are guided by logismos in association with intel-
lect and correct opinionthese you would encounter only among a few
people, ones with the best natural constitutionand the best education.
ja lm ja t\r ce pokkr ja pamtodapr 1pihul_ar ja Bdom\r te ja
k}par 1m pais l\kista %m tir evqoi ja cumain ja oQj]tair tr d] ce
"pkr te ja letq_ar, aT d let moO te ja d|ngr aqh/r kocisl` %comtai,
1m ak_coir te 1pite}n, ja to?r b]ktista lm vOsim, b]ktista d paideuhe?sim.
Moderate or balanced emotions are the outcomes of reasons rule, or, to
be more precise, the rule of calculation. We may translate kocisl|r by
reason or rationality, but, in doing so, we shall miss Platos own insights
if we overlook the mathematical connotations of the word. kocisl|r is
the disposition or faculty in virtue of which a soul has the capacity to
rule itselfthat is to say, impose order and balance on its emotions
16 Note also Prt. 326b on the educational need for eqquhl_a and eqaqlost_a, and
Phlb. throughout, especially 25e, 26a, and 65a.
212 Anthony A. Long
The moral of the story is that human beings should align themselves
with God. How So? 17
There is only one way so to act, and only one account thereof, viz. the ancient
logos that like is friend to like, provided that they conform to measure; things
that do not conform to measure, on the other hand, are friend neither to
themselves nor to those that do conform. For us it is God who must
pre-eminently be the measure of all things, much more so than any
human being, as they say [implicitly correcting Protagoras celebrated dic-
tum]. To become befriended to one of this sort, it is necessary to become as
like to it as possible, and that means according to this logos that whoever of
us is sphrn is Gods friend, because such a one is like God.
T_r owm d pqnir v_kg ja !j|kouhor he`; l_a, ja 6ma k|com 5wousa
!qwa?om, fti t` lm blo_\ t floiom emti letq_\ v_kom #m eUg, t d %letqa
oute !kk^koir oute to?r 1ll]tqoir. b d her Bl?m p\mtym wqgl\tym l]tqom
#m eUg l\kista, ja pok lkkom E po} tir, r vasim, %mhqypor tm owm
t` toio}t\ pqosvik/ cemgs|lemom, eQr d}malim fti l\kista ja aqtm
toioOtom !macja?om c_cmeshai, ja jat toOtom d tm k|com b lm
s~vqym Bl_m he` v_kor, floior c\q. (716cl-716d2)
This passage is replete with intertextuality. It corrects Protagoras and it also
strongly recalls Hesiods Zeus whose rule over mortals in the Works and
Days (256 85) is assisted by his daughter Justice and her inexorable atten-
tion to human conduct. But Plato is not simply parroting Hesiod. His di-
vinity in this passage (as in book 10 of the Laws, the Timaeus, and the Phil-
ebus) is characterized in language that resonates with scientific overtones.
Plato seems to identify divinity with the worlds natural revolutions; and
the idea of divinity as the principle of cosmic order is reinforced by the
focus on measure. With all this leading on to characterization of the person
who is s~vqym, we are clearly within a conceptual context that can recall
Heraclitus and his prescription to follow a divine law.18
17 Ti. 90c-d is similar in thought and expression; see Long Eudaimonism, divin-
ity and rationality in Greek ethics, PBACAP 19 (2003) 134 137.
18 Plato echoes Heraclitus linguistically as well as conceptually: note especially the
repeated instances of logos and also jat v}sim and he?or m|lor. England [1921,
ad loc.] on the authority of the scholiast and Eusebius, identifies Platos ancient
logos with an Orphic saying: Zeus is beginning, Zeus middle, and from Zeus
are all things accomplished, Zeus foundation of earth and starry heaven. Plato
clearly had a hallowed saying in mind, but we should not assume that he cited it
as being specifically Orphic. The sentiment that Zeus encompasses all things oc-
curs in Greek tragedy (cf. Aes. Ag. 160 ff., and Sophocles Tr. 1278) and Hera-
clitus gives his own expression to it in B 67. As with Gorgias 503d ff., I do not
claim that Plato had Heraclitus in mind here, but I see no reason to exclude that
as a possibility.
7. Heraclitus on Measure and the Explicit Emergence of Rationality 213
the term l]tqom. He applies this word to the worlds constantly balanced
changes (B 30), to the suns due and regular behavior (B 94), and, in its
verbal form, to the equivalence in quantity of the change from sea water
to earth and back again (B 31). These are instances of measure in the
sense of (i) determinate quantity; (ii) proportion or ratio; and (iv)
limit. For measure in the sense of (iii) moderation we have syvqos}mg;
for (v) rule or standard m|lor; and for (vi) judicial decision d_jg.
Heraclitus own words and their striking affinity to Platonic usage
establish the cardinal importance of measure to the connections he
intuited between three fundamental domains: 1, the way the world is
structured as a physical system; 2, the worlds divine governance and
governor; and 3, the norms of human conduct. Should we, then, use
measure as our translation of the Heraclitean logos? At least one scholar
has done so, but that translation, tempting though it is, does not capture
Heraclitus creative use of the term in his most programmatic passages.19
He did not discover the importance of measure as a criterion for acting
appropriately. That notion was already present in his culture. His great
innovation was to take measure as the key to understanding structure,
balance, and good order. Perhaps the best English word to translate
his logos is rationale. As such, it incorporates the measures of language
and thought, if these are deployed objectively in the interests of truth.
With this in mind, I now review Heraclitus most important state-
ment (B 1):
Of this rationale that is so always people are not in touch, both before hear-
ing it and after they have first heard it.
toO d k|cou toOd( 1|mtor !e !n}metoi c_momtai %mhqypoi ja pq|shem C
!joOsai ja !jo}samter t pq_tom.
I translate !n}metoi by not in touch in order to register what I take to
be Heraclitus punning allusion to num|r, common, His audience, as
he says in B 2, lives in a private world, unheeding of the common
19 Kirk, H. 39 finds measure, the most common meaning, judged purely by stat-
istical criteria in the extant fragments. Referring to K. Freeman, Ancilla to the
Pre-socratic Philosophers (London 1956) 116, he writes [She] has well stressed
that the concept of measure is implicit in the Logos of Heraclitus, but rightly
observes that it makes but little sense to translate it thus in fr. 1, as Freeman
does. Kirk himself favors formula for B 1, 2, and 50. Other translations he
surveys include word (Burnet) meaning of Heraclitus teaching (Snell),
argument (Verdenius), and account(ing) (Minar). See also Rowett at n.
19 in this volume.
7. Heraclitus on Measure and the Explicit Emergence of Rationality 215
20 The single ms. of Hippolytus (the source of B 50) was unsure whether d|c-
lator or k|cor was correct in the quotation. So Kirk, H. 66, who gives com-
pelling reasons for accepting the latter reading.
216 Anthony A. Long
and in the next fragment is that the soul is potentially boundless, which I
take to mean unlimited in its capacity to measure, i. e., understand na-
tures rationale. The more the soul expands, as it were, the more it is
capable of putting itself in touch with the common logos. 21
k|cor
In its epic usage, k|cor, far from connoting rationality, pertains to dis-
course that is deceptive rather than true, as in the formula aRl}kioi
k|coi. Calypso tries to soothe Odysseus with such words (Od. 1.56),
a usage that looks forward to the enchanting powers of logos advanced
by Gorgias in the Encomium of Helen. Pindar, by contrast, tends to associ-
ate k|cor with such words as !kgh^r and oq xeud^r.22 His usage suggests
that, though k|cor has begun to acquire normative connotations, its truth
or correctness needs to be specified as such, as in Herodotus 2.17.1 where
aqhr k|cor refers to the correct reckoning concerning the flooding of
the Nile.23
The tally of k|cor in Presocratic philosophers other than Heraclitus
is surprisingly meager. Setting aside instances where the term means
simply what is said or the familiar antithesis of k|cor/5qcom, the
21 Cf. Kahn, H. 130: A logos so profound and limitless can scarcely be distinct
from the universal logos, according to which all things come to pass.
22 E.g. Pi. O. 1.28, 4.21, 7.68, P. 1.68.
23 Guthrie HGP 1.420 424, gives numerous examples of the usage of k|cor, but
most of them, in the nature of the evidence, are from authors later than Her-
aclitus.
7. Heraclitus on Measure and the Explicit Emergence of Rationality 217
only instances worth reporting are Parmenides B 7.5 jq?mai k|c\ and
Leucippus B 2 oqdm wq/la l\tgm c_metai, !kk p\mta 1j k|cou te
ja rp( !m\cjgr (nothing occurs at random but all things from logos
and by necessity).24 If this latter citation is authentic, it would represent
the closest parallel to Heraclitus conception of the worlds rationale or
determinate measure.
There seems to be no fifth-century parallel for Parmenides instru-
mental dative.25 In its context, the command judge by k|cor is in-
tended to detach his audience from reliance on their senses. What
they are to judge is the goddesss contentious elenchos. Taking elenchos
to mean proof, it is tempting to interpret the command as the re-
quirement to assess the goddesss argument by discussing it. Parmenides
gives an extraordinary demonstration of rationality in action, so to
speak. He offers nothing comparable to Geraclitus on the conceptual
connections between k|cor, l]tqom, syvqos}mg, and so forth. The
later Presocratics, according to our record, had still less to say.
l]tqom
The world of Homer and Hesiod conforms to measure. We may think, for
instance, of the five scenes represented on the Shield of Achilles (Il. 18.
478 ff.), especially the first scene depicting earth, sea, and heavens, or the
equidistance from earth of sky and Tartarus (Theog. 719).The expanse of
the sea is actually conveyed by the word l]tqa (e. g., Op. 648). As the
world at large is a measured or balanced structure, so in the human domain
the concept of measure or due proportion serves archaic thought as its prin-
cipal ethical norm. Thus Hesiod tells his farmers to preserve measures
(l]tqa vuk\sseshai), glossing his injunction by saying that jaiq|r (propor-
tion) is best in everything (Op. 694)26
Here we have a classic statement of the ethics of syvqos}mg, which
Homer likes to express in such phrases as jat j|slom or jat lo?qam.
He characterizes the recalcitrant Thersites as someone unmeasured in his
27 Note also Solon fr. 13. 52 West on the craftsman who knows the l]tqom of
lovely sov_a.
7. Heraclitus on Measure and the Explicit Emergence of Rationality 219
As early as Homer and Hesiod the Greeks showed their awareness that
the physical world is an orderly system. They did not then call it a
j|slor, but they envisioned it as a limited and tripartite structure of
heaven, earth and seas, and underworld, with each of these three do-
mains under its own divine manager.29 They also envisioned the
world and its inhabitants as a regulated system, with its regulation some-
times assigned to Zeus and sometimes to Moira. Without sharply distin-
guishing these regulative powers from one another, in referring to Zeus,
they emphasized foresight and intelligence, while their references to
Moira implied necessity and an embryonic sense of causal connected-
ness.
This conception of the world, though imprecise in its details, was
rationalistic in presupposing that events do not happen for no reason.
Myth and religion provided explanations, albeit personalist ones, such
as the anger of Zeus or the resentment of Poseidon, or invoked vaguely
impersonal agencies, such as fate. The conception was also rationalistic
in the prudential sense reflected in the value of syvqos}mg, which sig-
nified the wisdom of self-restraint, especially with regard to ones appro-
priate attitude to the controlling divinities.
What this archaic outlook completely lacked, so far as one can see,
was the idea that human intelligence might be able to enter the orderly
cosmos it already intuited and discover laws of nature for itself, gaining
some authentic access, as it were, to the operations of the divine men-
tality. Hence the epistemological pessimism we find in Hesiod, Solon,
and Xenophanes. All three authors agreed that, while the supreme di-
vinity itself is far seeing and controlling, human beings can achieve
29 Cf. Il. 15.187 189, the division of the world into three domains for Zeus, Pos-
eidon, and Hades; and Hesiod, Theog. 720, which makes heaven as high above
earth as the underworld is below earth.
7. Heraclitus on Measure and the Explicit Emergence of Rationality 221
30 The difference between the gods and humanity, traditionally almost unbridge-
able, is for Heraclitus inessential, Hussey (above, n. 1) 103. As Hussey observes
(ibid. 104), in reference to such fragments as B 78 79, which contrast the di-
vine and the human: this is a matter of character not of nature . That human
nature is perfectly capable of achieving real understanding is shown by B 113
and B 116.
31 Long, H. & Stoicism (above, n. 1) 273.
32 Long, Finding oneself (above, n. 9) 10 13.
222 Anthony A. Long
Bibliography
Barnes, Jonathan. The Presocratic Philosophers. 2 London and New York 1982.
Burnyeat, Myles F. Plato on why mathematics is good for the soul,
Proc.Brit.Acad. 103 (2000) 1 81.
Freeman, Kathleen. Ancilla to the Pre-socratic Philosophers London 1956.
Hussey, Edward. Heraclitus, in A. A. Long (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to
Early Greek Philosophy (Cambridge 1999) 88 112.
Irwin. Terence. Plato. Gorgias. Oxford 1979.
Long, Anthony. A. Finding oneself in Greek philosophy, Tijdschrift voor Fi-
losofie 54 (1992) 255 79.
Heraclitus and Stoicism, in id., Stoic Studies (Cambridge 1996; repr. Ber-
keley 2001) 35 57.
Eudaimonism, divinity and rationality in Greek ethics, Proc. Boston Area
Colloquium Anc. Philos. 19 (2003 [2004]) 123 43.
Naddaf, Grard. The Greek Concept of Nature. Albany 2005.
Vlastos, Gregory. Solonian justice, CP 41 (1946) 65 83. Repr. in id., Studies
in Greek Philosophy (Princeton 1995) 32 56.
Wardy, Robert. The unity of opposites in Platos Symposium, OSAP 23
(2002) 1 61.
West, Martin L. Early Greek Philosophy and the Orient. Oxford 1971.
participate, and also to Dorothea Frede for giving me the further opportunity to
present my views at the Hamburg conference on Leib und Seele in der antiken
Philosophie. I thank the conference participants for their responses and also An-
drea Nightingale and Chiara Robbiano, who sent me written comments on the
paper. The version that appears here has previously been published in D. Frede
& B. Reis (ed.), Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy (Berlin 2009) 87 110.
8. On the physical aspect of Heraclitus psychology1
With New Appendices
Gbor Betegh
1 This paper has grown out of ideas I first presented at the Symposium Philoso-
phiae Antiquae Quintum organized by Apostolos Pierris and then at the Jubilee
meeting of the Southern Association of Ancient Philosophy in Oxford. A ver-
sion was published in Phronesis 52 (2007) 3 32, which is reprinted here slightly
revised. I added a series of appendices in which I present the discussions to
which I referred to as forthcoming in the Phronesis paper. For the research
contained here I received support from the ERC_HU BETEGH09 research
grant. At the Symposium, Aryah Finkelberg read a paper (in this volume)
that overlaps with my discussion at some points, although his main interest is
in Heraclitean eschatology. I am grateful for the audiences in Ephesos and Ox-
ford. Comments by David Charles, Christopher Gill, Katalin Farkas, Aryah Fin-
kelberg, Charles Kahn, Tony Long, Stephen Menn, Malcolm Schofield, and
David Sedley were particularly helpful. I owe much to discussions with
Roman Dilcher. I would like to express my gratitude to David Sider for all
his help with the present version.
2 See especially M. Nussbaum, Xuw^ in Heraclitus, Phronesis 17 (1972) 1 16,
153 170; and M. Schofield, M. Heraclitus theory of the soul and its antece-
dents, in S. Everson (ed.), Companions to Ancient Thought. Vol. 2: Psychology
(Cambridge 1991) 13 34.
226 Gbor Betegh
human beings, on the other hand, are intimately linked. In such a com-
plex, epistemologically oriented and reflexive approach the center of
cognition will naturally acquire a place of prominence; and Heraclitus
takes xuw^ to be the center of cognition. The joint effect of these de-
velopments resulted in a new, and in a sense strikingly modern, concep-
tion of the self that has sometimes been compared to Thomas Nagels
objective self.3
If this is the most momentous feature of Heraclitus philosophical
psychology, why should we bother too much with the seemingly less
exciting physical aspect of his conception of xuw^? The answer, I main-
tain, is that Heraclitus seems to hold at the same time that self-reflection
and introspection, although important, are not sufficient to gain knowl-
edge about the soul. The soul is integrated into the physical world, and
reflections about the physical world can lead us to some crucial insights
about the nature and working of the soul. Understanding the soul is the
key to understanding human nature and the world, and the interrelation
of the two; but, on the other hand, understanding the cosmic order and
the major physical processes is vital to gaining knowledge about the
soul.4 Heraclitus thus appears to agree with the implication of Socrates
rhetorical question in the Phaedrus: Do you think it is possible to un-
derstand the nature of the soul in a worthwhile manner without under-
standing the nature of the whole? (Phdr. 270c1 2).5 The soul is part of
the whole, and cannot be properly understood without having a grasp
on the way it is integrated in the physical world.
In what follows, I shall approach Heraclitus views on the xuw^ from
the side of its physical and metaphysical aspects. I shall concentrate first on
the metaphysical framework which allows the souls integration into the
physical world and creates the conceptual space for its physical identifica-
tion. Second, I shall turn to the physical characterization of the soul and
to the way it is integrated into physical processes. In this part, I shall try
to tackle the vexed question whether the soul for Heraclitus is fire or air,
say something about the philosophical advantages of the option taken by
Heraclitus, and briefly discuss Sextus report of Heraclitus psychology.
Finally, I should add a methodological point. It has sometimes been
urged that because of Heraclitus mode of expression, the intentional ob-
scurity of his pronouncements and his apparent refusal to expound his
views in continuous, argumentative prose, the interpreter ought not try
to impute a clear-cut doctrine or theory to him. I would certainly
agree that the interpreter has to show the utmost sensitivity to the formal,
literary and linguistic features of the Heraclitean fragments. Yet I would
still not renounce the idea that Heraclitus by his pronouncements ex-
pressed a set of fairly worked out and specific views about the topics
he dealt with. The celebrated B 93 states that the lord whose oracle is
the one in Delphi neither declares nor conceals, but gives signals (b
%man ox t lamte?|m 1sti t 1m Dekvo?r oute k]cei oute jq}ptei !kk
sgla_mei) and this statement has customarily been taken to describe Her-
aclitus own mode of expression as well. But the implication of the
apophthegm is neither that Apollo does not have a clear and specific
view on the matter at hand, nor that the recipient should renounce dis-
covering what the lord of the oracle thinks about the mattereven if one
cannot hope to arrive at a definitive answer and dissipate all ambiguity.
B 36 is the central fragment for locating the souls place in physical proc-
esses:
5 Xuw/r owm v}sim !n_yr k|cou jatamo/sai oUei dumatm eWmai %meu t/r toO fkou
v}seyr;
228 Gbor Betegh
6 E. Hussey, Heraclitus on living and dying, The Monist 74 (1991) 518 519
gives a very helpful concise review of the Homeric and Hesiodic occurrences
of the word h\mator. By this overview Hussey seeks to show, to my mind suc-
cessfully, that h\mator usually refers not to a state but to a process or event, and
should hence be translated by dying rather than death. Hussey does not dis-
cuss B 36, which he thinks originally consisted only of the four words xuw0sim
h\mator vdyq cem]shai (529, n. 18), which he translates as It is death to souls
to become moist.
8. On the physical aspect of Heraclitus psychology 229
not the xuw^ that does the living, but the organism is thought to live as
long as the xuw^ is present and active in it. Correspondingly, it is the
organism, not the xuw^, which dies when the xuw^ departs from it.7
Similarly, it is highly unusual to speak about the birth of the xuw^ as
such, distinct from the organism it is part ofjust as we would not nor-
mally speak about the birth of either the mind or the brain as such.8
The interpreter can respond to these challenges by depleting the sig-
nificance of the words dying and being born to arrive at the innoc-
uous meanings cease to exist and come into being. The more in-
teresting alternative, however, is to accept that Heraclitus attaches
(some form of) life to stuffs that are not usually conceived as living.
When this latter option is taken, it becomes significant that the formu-
lation of the cycle is not symmetrical. Describing the way down, from
xuw^ to water, from water to earth, Heraclitus speaks about dying
into the next phase of the process, whereas on the way up, from
earth to water, from water to xuw^, he does not mention dying, only
becoming or birth (c_metai). When, on the way down, souls transform
into water, the souls die and this is how water comes into being (or is
born). When, on the way up, water transforms into soul, soul comes
into being and is born. By this transformation water ceases to bebut
I doubt that Heraclitus would describe the same transformation as the
dying of water; water dies only on the way down, when earth is
born from it, but not on the way up, when it is transformed into
soul. Dying characterizes the way down.9
Incidentally, if it is true that only things that live can die, xuw^ in
Heraclitus ceases to be the bearer of life. For water is distinct from
xuw^, yet it has to have some form of life if it is to die when earth
comes into being from it.
7 This has been excellently brought out by Nussbaum (above, n. 2). For the same
point in Plato, see F. Karfk, Die Beseelung des Kosmos: Untersuchungen zur Kos-
mologie, Seelenlehre und Theologie in Platon Phaidon und Timaios. Leipzig and Mu-
nich, 2004. For further elaboration on this point, see Appendix 1.
8 See Appendix 2.
9 B 36 has many variants and paraphrases, fourteen listed in Marcovich H. ad loc.
(his fr. 66). Among these, there are only three that speak about dying on the
way up as well: Plut. de E 392c; Marc. Ant. 4.46.1, and Max. Tyr. 41.4, all
three listed by Diels under B 76. I agree with those commentators like Marco-
vich H. ad loc., Kahn H. ad loc., and Dilcher H. 67 n. 1, who take these to be
(Stoicizing) paraphrases; contra J.-F. Pradeau, Hraclite: Fragments (Paris 2002)
284 285, 296.
230 Gbor Betegh
12 For the most recent defence of the survival of individual souls, see Finkelberg in
this volume.
13 The shift from the plural to the singular must pose a problem also for interpret-
ers like Marcovich H. 362 and Dilcher H. 67 69, who take the fragment to
refer exclusively to processes within human beings. If the fragment describes
the microcosmic cycle within the living human being, it is unclear to me
why it speaks about the death of souls in the plural and then switches to soul
in the singular. Dilcher thinks that the only alternative to the microcosmic in-
terpretation is eschatological, one that ascribes to Heraclitus the view that the
soul first leaves the body, lingers around for a while and then dies into
water. It may well be that the first phase of transformation, from souls to
water, happens within the human being, but that does not oblige us to say
that all the transformations described in the fragment occur within the micro-
cosmos: the fragment speaks about these transformations in general terms. For
a critique of Marcovichs physiological interpretation, see Schofield (above, n.
2) 15 21. Kirk H. 341followed by Marcovich H. 361states that even if
the main thrust of the fragment would suggest that xuw^ stands for cosmic
fire, parallel to the other two cosmic masses, the plural xuwa_ rules this out. I
agree that to be the case at the beginning of the fragment, but nothing hinders
that things change with the second, singular, occurrence of the word.
232 Gbor Betegh
provide a detailed survey of the relevant texts within the limits of the
present paper, let me only mention some notable examples. Anaxagoras
clearly uses the word moOr as a mass term when he says in B 12 ad fin.
mind is all alike, both the larger and the smaller [of it] (moOr d pr
floi|r 1sti ja b le_fym ja b 1k\ttym).14 Similarly, when Diogenes
of Apollonia maintains in B 4 that human beings and the other animals
live by means of the air as they breathe. And this is for them both soul
and intelligence (%mhqypoi cq ja t %kka f_ia !mapm]omta f~ei t`
!]qi. ja toOto aqto?r ja xuw^ 1sti ja m|gsir) he treats air as a stuff
that enters the body with breathing, but which, on the other hand,
functions as soul and intelligence in us. It is more striking to see that
Socrates, in both Xenophon and Plato, entertains a similar conception
of soul and mind. In the Memorabilia, Socrates tries to corner the irreli-
gious Aristodemus by the following salvo of questions:
Do you think you have some intelligence (vq|milom),15 but there is nothing
intelligent anywhere else at all? And this, when you know that you have in
your body only a tiny measure of earth which is so huge, and a little bit of
the large extension of waters, and that your body was constructed by re-
ceiving only a minute portion of all the other things which, surely, exist
in great quantities? But as to mind (moOr), which is thus the only thing
that does not exist anywhere else, you think you managed by some
happy chance to snatch it, and you believe that those immensely great
and infinitely many masses are in such a well-ordered state due to some-
thing lacking intelligence? (1.4.8)
Just as our bodies contain some measure of the stuffs earth and water, we
also have a measure of mind in us. Much like Anaxagoras, Xenophons
Socrates treats mind as a mass term that we can have a measure of.
Platos Socrates develops a strikingly similar argument in the Philebus
to the effect that just as fire, earth and other material components of
14 So also S. Menn, Plato on God as Nous (Carbondale 1995) 26: We may begin
by recalling the undeniable fact that Anaxagoras uses nous as a mass term.
Menn argues that expressions like moOm 5weim are not Greek for have a mind
but rather for something like have reason or be reasonable, so that nous
for Anaxagoras and other authors is reason (a mass term) and not mind (a
count noun). My point is rather that Anaxagorasjust as some of his predeces-
sors, contemporaries, and successorscould use words like moOr and xuw^ as
both count-nouns and mass terms. I shall continue to translate moOr as mind
even if the English word cannot capture this double usage.
15 My translation follows the text in M. Bandini and L.-A. Dorion, Xnophon:
Mmorables. Vol. 1, Paris 2000, who, following Muretus, based on Bessarions
Latin version, delete the words 1q~ta coOm ja !povqimoOlai.
8. On the physical aspect of Heraclitus psychology 233
us come from, and are nourished by, the respective cosmic masses, so
our soul comes from its cosmic counterpart.16 Finally, we can think of
the Timaeus as well, where the imagery of soul stuff, its mixing, mould-
ing, and portioning by the Demiurge is particularly conspicuous.
The gist of what I have said about Anaxagoras, Diogenes of Apol-
lonia, and Socrates argument in the Memorabilia may be present already
in Anaximenes. The only relevant text is B 2: oWom B xuw^, vgs_m, B Ble-
t]qa !q owsa sucjqate? Blr, ja fkom tm j|slom pmeOla ja !q
peqi]wei (Just as our soul, which is air, keeps us together, so do the
breath and air encompass the whole world); yet the wording, authen-
ticity and interpretation of this fragment is too contested to draw any
firm conclusions.17
From the point of view of terminology, these passages are largely in-
congruent as they speak about xuw^, moOr, vq|milom, and m|gsir. What
connects them is the underlying metaphysical assumption according to
which that which is the bearer of mental functions in us is a stuff that oc-
curs also elsewhere in the world in smaller and larger quantities. Human
beings show mental functions, and live, in so far as they have a share in
that stuff. In this respect xuw^ and moOr are like other elemental constit-
uents in us, and can be used as mass terms just like fire or earth. xuw^
and moOr at the same time function as count nouns in the same texts in
referring to individuated portions of xuw^ and moOr stuff.
A possible corollary of this approach is that the stuff in question does
not need to be in a human, or animal, body to show mental functions.
More exactly, if a theorist wants to hold that this stuff shows mental func-
tions only when it is in a human (or animal) body, he needs to provide
specific reasons why this should be so.18 A further corollary is that the cos-
16 Phlb. 29a-30d, esp. 30a about the soul. The relationship between the arguments
in the Memorabilia and the Philebus, and the possibility that they go back to the
historical Socrates, are interesting questions that cannot be discussed here. See
D. Frede, Platon. 3.2. Philebos (Gttingen 1997) 215 n. 183 and D. Sedley, Cre-
ationism and Its Critics in Antiquity (Berkeley 2007) 82, 217 19.
17 The most detailed discussion of this fragment is in K. Alt, Zum Satz des Anax-
imenes ber die Seele: Untersuchung von Aetios Peq )qw_m, Hermes 101
(1973) 129 164, who concludes that it has mistakenly been attributed to Anax-
imenes. For a much more optimistic view, see, e. g., A. Laks, Soul, sensation,
and thought, in A. A. Long (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Phi-
losophy (Cambridge 1999), esp. 252. Schofield (above, n. 2) 23 24 provides a
balanced assessment of the fragment and compares it to Heraclitus views on the
soul. See also below, Appendix 3.
18 Aristotle makes this point explicit in De An. 1.5 411a8 23.
234 Gbor Betegh
mic mass of soul (or mind) can be assigned cosmological roles because it
can also be described as the greatest individuated portion of soul, or mind,
stuff. Indeed, from this aspect the cosmic mass of this stuff can function as
a cosmic divinity. The ambiguity between an elemental mass and a cor-
responding cosmic god is a familiar phenomenon that we can observe for
example in the cases of Oceanus and Gaia, or water and earth. The char-
acteristics of this cosmic god will be those that we assign to soul, or mind,
in a human being: control, motor and cognitive functions and so forth.
It is time to come back to Heraclitus. By analyzing B 36, I hope to
have been able to make a case for the point that the fragment starts out
by speaking about individual souls, but ends in speaking about soul con-
ceived as a stuff. A very brief historical survey has shown that such a
conception is fully in line with some representative theories of the ar-
chaic and classical periods. This constitutes the general metaphysical
framework for the physical interpretation of the Heraclitean soul.
B 36 indicates that Heraclitus agrees with those who think that soul
can transform into other stuffs, but apparently stands apart in describing
that process in terms of dying. The central questions that have
emerged from the preceding discussion are the following: (Q1) What
is xuw^ in physical terms? and (Q2) How can we conceive the shift from
soul to souls?
II
not described as dying and being born, but referred to as the turnings
(tqopa_) of fire. Moreover, accepting that pqgst^q, notoriously diffi-
cult to translate, refers to some fiery atmospheric phenomenon,23 we
have yet again a cycle in which the first and last terms are closely related
but are not quite identical. Earth is common to B 31a and 36, whereas
seawater in B 31a refers to the cosmologically most prominent part of
water mentioned in B 36.
All these fragments seem to deliver a coherent image according to
which the third element beside water and earth is fire. The word !^q
only occurs in the different variants listed under B 76, of which I
quote here only the version transmitted by Maximus Tyrius:24 f0 pOq
tm c/r h\matom ja !q f0 tm puqr h\matom, vdyq f0 tm !]qor
h\matom, c/ tm vdator (Fire lives the dying of earth, and air lives
the dying of fire; water lives the dying of air, and earth that of water).
This text, however, has customarilyand I think with good rea-
sonsbeen described as a Stoicizing paraphrase of B 36.25 Shall we con-
clude, then, that air is missing from Heraclitus system altogether?
Against such a conclusion, some powerful arguments have been raised.
To begin with, it is unclear how one could claim that water immediately
turns into fire in B 36.26 Moreover, I think that Charles Kahn is simply
right in insisting that Heraclitus cannot have offered a theory of the
natural world in which the atmosphere was omitted.27 And this is es-
pecially so, I would add, for someone writing after Anaximenes, who
made air his principle, and Xenophanes, who was pre-eminently inter-
ested in various atmospheric phenomena and clouds. Simply ignoring
what he does not agree with is, I think, wholly uncharacteristic of Her-
aclitus. It remains true, on the other hand, that the relevant fragments
consistently list only three stages in the cycle, and I do not think that
adherents of the four element interpretation of Heraclitus have been
able to address this question in a satisfactory way. The ideal solution
should be able to account for the fact that Heraclitus prefers to speak
about three terms in the processes of transformation without, however,
excluding atmospheric air. But how could that be done if the places of
fire, water, and earth have already been secured?
When we come to the more specific question whether the human
soul is air or fire, prima facie it seems more probable that it is to be iden-
tified with fire. First of all, we have just seen that fiery phenomena, such
as a gleam of light and the thunderbolt, have psychic functions. There is
also the force of analogy with other ancient theories. In all other early,
and not so early, theories, when there is a primary form of matter, the
xuw^, or the bearer of the most important psychic faculties, is identified
with that form of matter.28 This interpretation can also align some an-
cient doxographical reports on its side.29
Yet, once again, the alternative view can refer to some ancient in-
terpretations, including that of Philo of Alexandria.30 Just as important,
it can also present some powerful internal arguments supporting the
view that soul is air and not fire. First of all, there are fragments in
which we hear about wet souls, such as the soul of the drunken man
in B 117: !mq bj|tam lehush0, %cetai rp paidr !m^bou svakk|le-
mor, oqj 1pa@ym fjg ba_mei, rcqm tm xuwm 5wym (A man when he is
28 Some further arguments of less force have also been adduced. For example, G.
Vlastos, On Heraclitus, AJP 76 (1955) 364 365, referred to the observable
fact that the living body is warm whereas the corpse is cold. This, however, is
not based on any of the surviving texts of Heraclitus. KRS 204, on the other
hand, state that while Anaximenes built on the Homeric view of the xuw^
being some kind of breath, Heraclitus abandoned this idea in favour of another
popular conception of the soul, that it was made of fiery aither. I was unable to
find any clear evidence for such an assumedly popular conception prior to Her-
aclitus.
29 Theodoret. Gr. aff. cur. 5.18 Paqlem_dgr d ja ^ppasor ja Jq\jkeitor
puq~dg ta}tgm (sc. tm xuw^m) jejk^jasim.
30 Philo, De Aet. Mundi 21 quotes the first part of B 36 and then states that: xuwm
cq oQ|lemor eWmai t pmeOla tm lm !]qor tekeutm c]mesim vdator jtk. Aene-
sidemus also thought that the soul is air for Heraclitus. On this point, see below.
238 Gbor Betegh
31 See Schofield (above, n. 2) 29: When the soul becomes moist or wet its fire is
put outit dies (fr. 36) either entirely or in part, as in drunkenness, fr. 117, or
in sleep, fr. 26. On the interpretation of xuw^ as fire Heraclitus does not need to
be seen as committed to the absurd concept of wet fire.
32 So, e. g., O. Gigon, Untersuchungen zu Heraklit (Leipzig 1935) 106.
33 J. Mansfeld, Heraclitus on the psychology and physiology of sleep and on riv-
ers, Mnemosyne 20 (1967) 9.
8. On the physical aspect of Heraclitus psychology 239
(Q4) How could we account for the fact that some manifestations of xuw^ for
Heraclitus are fiery whereas others are wet?
III
When we contrast the terms of the modern discussion about the phys-
ical identification of the Heraclitean soul with the earliest and most de-
tailed ancient testimonies, one point becomes striking. The earliest ac-
counts do not identify the Heraclitean xuw^ with either air or fire, but
say that soul, for Heraclitus, is exhalation (!mahul_asir).34 And they do
so even when one would really expect them to identify soul as one of
the elements. This is a conspicuous feature of Aristotles account of
the physical characterization of the Heraclitean soul in De Anima 1.2:
Diogenes, like some others, [held the soul to be] air because he believed it
to be the most finely grained and the principle; this is the reason why the
soul knows and moves, in so far as it is primary, and the other things are
from this, it knows; in so far as it is the most finely grained, it originates
movement. Heraclitus says too that the principle is soul, since it is the ex-
halation from which the others are composed. (De An. 1.2 405a21 6)
Aristotle is entirely happy in this context to say that for Diogenes the soul
is air, just as for Democritus spherical atoms, for Hippo water, for Empe-
docles the organ of cognition is a mixture of the four elements. He even
says that for Heraclitus, just as for Diogenes, xuw^ is the principlewhat
he does not say is that it is fire, even though elsewhere (e. g. in Meta. 1.2
984a7 = Her. A 5 DK) he identifies Heraclitus principle as fire. On the
other hand, he does not say that soul for Heraclitus is air, even though it
would have been quite an obvious move considering that he is just point-
ing out the strong parallels between Heraclitus and Diogenes on the ques-
tion of the material identification of xuw^. Aristotle could jolly well iden-
tify Heraclitus soul with either air or fire in this context, but he did not
do so. Instead, he said that soul for Heraclitus is exhalation.35
34 Arist. De An. 1.2 405a24; Aet. 4.3.12.; Cleanth. apud Ar. Did. fr. 39.2 Diels =
Her. B 12.
35 This feature of Aristotles testimony has clearly caused some uneasiness for Kirk.
After having quoted Aristotle, he continues by saying that This occurs in a con-
text in which Aristotle is anxious to find a common term for soul and !qw^; by
!mahul_asir here he means a kind of fire, but has deliberately chosen a vague
term for it (Kirk H. 275). But why would Aristotle prefer to use a vague
term in this context, where fire or air would clearly better suit his purposes?
240 Gbor Betegh
At this point, I need to discuss very briefly what Aristotle may have
meant when he stated that soul for Heraclitus is exhalation. Exhalation is
a central concept in ancient meteorology in general, but is particularly
important in Aristotles theory. Indeed, Aristotle explained most atmos-
pheric and meteorological phenomena by taking exhalations to be the
material cause of these phenomena.36 Aristotle famously distinguished
between two kinds of exhalation, dry and moist, both starting from
the earth.37 Dry exhalation arises from the earth heated by the sun
and reaches up to the fiery sphere in the sky, situated between the
sphere of air and that of aither. Moist exhalation, in contrast, arises
from the water in and on the earth and, being heavier, rises only up
to the sphere of air (Mete. 1.3). On this view, then, exhalations extend
from the level immediately above the earth, through the layer of air, up
to the uppermost fiery region which is contiguous with the divine aith-
er. Moreover, different fiery phenomena in the sky, such as shooting
stars, lightning, torches (dako_), and goats (aWcer), are explained
as ignition of dry exhalations.
Clearly, not all of Aristotles own theory of exhalations can be ascri-
bed to Heraclitus. To begin with, Aristotles insistence that exhalations
arise from earth is in obvious contrast with what we have seen in B 36: if
Heraclitus xuw^ is indeed exhalation, this exhalation must arise from
water and not from earth. B 31a, quoted above, also implies that trans-
formations to and from earth must go through a liquid state of matter,
water or sea, and that the fiery atmospheric phenomenon of pqgst^q
again comes from water/sea and not earth.
A further complication comes from Diogenes Laertius doxographical
report in 9.9 11, going back to Theophrastus, according to which Her-
aclitus had not only a bright exhalation arising from the sea and nourish-
ing the sun, but also a dark exhalation coming from the earth so that this
dark exhalation produces the darkness of night and winter. But as Kirk
(1954) 270 6 has, to my mind, convincingly shown, the ascription of
an earthly exhalation to Heraclitus is the result of some confusion with
the Aristotelian theory.38 The main objection to Diogenes report, I
36 For the most recent comprehensive discussion, see L. Taub, Ancient Meteorology
(London 2003) 88 92.
37 There is a discussion in the literature whether both exhalations are hot, or the
moist exhalation is cold, but this point does not need to concern us here.
38 We encounter a further level of confusion in Atius 2.17.4 = Her. A 11 DK,
who says that it is the exhalation coming from the earth that nourishes the
8. On the physical aspect of Heraclitus psychology 241
think, is the same as above: the fragments that speak about the transfor-
mations between elemental masses show that earth only transforms into
water and then water transforms into further fiery atmospheric phenom-
ena and xuw^. Diogenes testimony, on the other hand, contains an addi-
tional piece of information, not mentioned by Aristotle. Diogenes says
that the celestial bodies are bowls (sj\vai) in which some part of the ex-
halation coming from the sea is burning.39 This doctrine corresponds to
the idea that exhalations extend from the mist lingering on the surface
of waters to the fiery phenomena in the upper sky.
Retaining the core of Aristotles testimony, but stripping off what is
incompatible with what we find in Heraclitus original fragments, we
get that xuw^ for Heraclitus is the exhalation that rises from water ex-
tends to the sky and the fire of the celestial bodies.40 The first part of this
conclusion is reinforced by the apparently independent information
provided by Cleanthes, preserved by Arius Didymus, that, according
to Heraclitus, souls, too, come out of moisture by exhalations ja
xuwa d !p t_m rcq_m !mahuli_mtai, Ar. Did. fr. 39.2 Diels =
Her. B 12), whereas the connection between xuw^ and stellar matter,
is supported by the testimonies of Macrobius and Galen.41
stars, even though in 2.20.16 he says that the sun is nourished by the exhalation
arising from the sea, and in 2.28.6 he says that both the sun and the stars are
nourished by the bright exhalation coming from the sea. The idea that the
stars are nourished by dark exhalations is also contradicted by D.L. 9.10. One
may wonder whether this confusion comes from that part of the doxography
that connects the dark exhalations with night.
39 Kirk H. 269 279 and Kahn H. 291 293 come to opposite conclusions about
the different elements of the Theophrastean doxography. For Kirk, the doctrine
of celestial bowls is a secure piece of information, because this is such an un-
usual idea, so different from the sort of thing which would be invented by The-
ophrastus (270), whereas in Kahn view one must suspend judgment on the
authenticity of the doctrine of sj\vai. Kirk, on the other hand, tries to refute
the double exhalations, whereas Kahn says that this is what seems most authen-
tic in Theophrastus report (H. 293). As should have become clear, on the as-
sessment of this part of the doxography in D.L., I tend to side with Kirk.
40 In a way, the line of interpretation I am taking is closest to the one proposed by
Robert B. English in a paper published in 1913: Heraclitus and the soul,
TAPA 44 (1913) 163 184. Englishs paper, as far as I am aware, is completely
ignored in more recent discussions.
41 Macr. S. Scip. 14.9 = Her. A15: (animam) scintillam stellaris essentiae. Galen 4.786
Khn, not in DK. For the possible eschatological implications of this doctrine,
see Finkelberg in this volume.
242 Gbor Betegh
43 So I cannot agree with Kahn H. 251 when he says that What he [sc. Heracli-
tus] probably meant, therefore, but what would be difficult to say (since psych
means life) is that the passage of the psych into celestial fire might be both the
death of psych and at the same time its attainment of the highest form of life.
44 Galen omits the last word of the fragment (ja !q_stg) presumably because he
concentrates on the cognitive capacities stemming from dryness.
8. On the physical aspect of Heraclitus psychology 245
IV
There is only one question from our list that has not as yet received an
answer: (Q2) How can we conceive the shift from soul to souls? The gist of
the answer, I would maintain, may come from a doxographical report
by Sextus. The first part of the most elaborate ancient discussion of Her-
aclitus psychology in M. 7.127 30 runs as follows:
(127) But what this [Heraclitus common and divine reason] is must be ex-
plained concisely. It is a favourite tenet of our Physicist that that which sur-
rounds us is rational and intelligent. (128) [Sextus lists poets who assumedly
held the same doctrine before Heraclitus] (129) According to Heraclitus it
is by drawing in this divine reason (k|com) in respiration that we become
endowed with mind (moeqo cim|leha), and in sleep we become forgetful,
but in waking we regain our senses. For in sleep the passages of perception
are shut, and hence the mind (moOr) in us is separated from its natural unity
with the surrounding medium; the only thing preserved is the connection
through breathing, which is like a root. So when separated, our mind loses
its former power of memory. (130) But when we awake it goes out again
through the passages of perception as through so many windows, and by
contact with the surrounding medium it regains its rational power. Just
as coals that are brought near the fire undergo a change and are made in-
candescent, but die out when they are separated from it, just so does the
portion of the surrounding medium which resides as a stranger in our bod-
ies become nearly irrational (%kocor) as a result of separation, but by the
natural union through the multitude of passages it attains a condition
which is like in kind to the whole. (trans. based on Polito and Kahn)
It has usually been maintained that this testimony contains practically
nothing that we could attribute to Heraclitus. Kahn H. 293 6 discusses
the text in an Appendix and concludes that the heavily Stoicizing inter-
pretation preserved by Sextus is without any authority for the modern
interpretation of Heraclitus (p. 269). In the most recent extensive
treatment of this passage, Roberto Polito,45 on the other hand, lists
powerful arguments, some of which go back to Diels, against the idea
that the Heraclitus doxography in Sextus is of Stoic origin. Admitting
that the idea of a cosmic Reason (logos) is indeed Stoic, he points out
that there is no reason why a Stoic would interpret this cosmic Reason
to be air or attribute such an idea to Heraclitus. Moreover, it is not a
Stoic idea that we partake in the rational principle by breathing in the
atmospheric air that surrounds us. Finally, the view that in sleep we
are separated from Reason and our minds are inactive is un-Stoic,
and indeed there is evidence that the Stoics had a different interpretation
of the state of sleep in Heraclitus.46 Polito then argues forcefully that the
source of Sextus is Aenesidemus interpretation of Heraclitus. Polito
seeks to explain the admittedly Stoic elements in the text (such as divine
Reason) by suggesting that Aenesidemus himself was working not on
Heraclitus book, but on an authoritative, systematic, word-by-word
commentary on Heraclitus, for which he thinks Cleanthes exegesis of
Heraclitus is the most plausible candidate.47
Now what is it that we can still attribute to Heraclitus from this ac-
count? In particular, how shall we assess the role assigned to breathing?
Is there anything Heraclitean in it? Although Polito provides a detailed
analysis of the Hellenistic medical pedigree of the breathed-in-soul doc-
trine, and the reasons why Aenesidemus espoused it, he tentatively
leaves open the possibility that it was present in Heraclitus as well.
He, however, points out that it is somewhat problematic to square
this with the idea that soul for Heraclitus is fire or fiery.48 But this is
not any longer a problem when we accept that everything from the
lowest part of atmosphere to the heavenly fire counts as soul for Hera-
clitus. And we can know from Diogenes of Apollonia B 4 and Aristotle
that there were pre-Hellenistic versions of the idea of a breathed-in-
soul.49 The doctrine of breathed-insoul, together with the idea that dif-
ferent layers of exhalation show different levels of intellectual powers in
connection with the differences in the relevant physical properties, can
explain the description of sleep in Sextus as well. Because in sleep we are
only in connection with the lowest layers of air through breathing, our
souls are only nourished by the least intelligent part of external soul stuff.
It is sufficient to keep us alive, and to maintain our souls in a stand-by
position, as it were. Note also that when the text says that through
breathing we become moeqo_, it cannot mean that we become intelligent
in the strong sense of the word. As the rest of the passage makes it clear,
to become intelligent it is not enough to keep breathing. I thus agree
with Polito (above, n. 22) 153 that the expression must mean something
like breathing supplies us with psychic matter or endowed with mind;
in other words breathing is a necessary but not a sufficient condition for
fectly compatible with what I have tried to reconstruct from other sour-
ces.
52 I use the somewhat awkward formulation bearer (or bearers) of mental func-
tions because different Presocratics use different words (such as xuw^, moOr,
m|gsir, and vq^m) to describe this entity, and may distribute different psychic
and cognitive functions among more than one of these. Materialism and physi-
calism is sometimes used interchangeably. For some authors, materialism is the
broader term because it applies also to some pre-theoretical views (see below).
Physicalism, by contrast, is broader in the sense that it accommodates forces etc.
which are physical but not necessarily material.
53 Cf. J. Barnes, The Presocratic Philosophers (London 1982) 475; and Gill (above,
n. 3) 170.
8. On the physical aspect of Heraclitus psychology 249
angle. They start from the assumption that there is a stuff in the world
that is responsible for mental functions and life, and that we show men-
tal functions and live because this stuff, along with other stuffs, is present
in us.56 The ancient authors then formulate alternative hypotheses about
what this stuff is and how it works in human beings and in the world at
large. Some authors, e. g., Diogenes of Apollonia and probably Anaxi-
menes, identify this stuff with an elemental mass, whereas other authors
such as Anaxagoras and the Socrates of the Memorabilia and Philebus,
treat mind and soul as stuffs apart. A connected point of contention is
whether or not the stuff responsible for vital and mental functions par-
ticipates in the transformations among different stuffs. Diogenes of
Apollonia and Anaximenes think that it does, whereas Anaxagoras, Soc-
rates and Platos Timaeus hold that it is insulated from transformations
among other stuffs. The central question of the ancients is not how a
physical stuff can under certain conditions show also mental properties,
but rather they take it for granted that there is such a stuff, material or
otherwise, and that it inheres in us as well.
Heraclitus, more specifically, has repeatedly been called an identity
theorist.57 As must have been clear from what I have said above, I also
agree that, for Heraclitus, ones moral and intellectual condition is iden-
tical with the physical state of ones soul. But due caution, and some
qualification, are in order here as well. Modern type-identity theorists
are generally interested in the relationship between the mental proper-
ties of intentional states and sensations, such as having a certain thought
or having a certain sensation, and the corresponding bodily states. Her-
aclitus, in contrast, seems to be much more concerned with more or less
standing conditions or dispositions such as being wise, being morally ex-
cellent and so forth, which can be expressed on the dry-wet axis. He
certainly treated drunkenness in this context, but I wonder if he went
any further and analyzed particular mental states, such as having a par-
ticular thought, desire or sensation in terms of the physical properties
of the soul. It may be significant in this respect that Theophrastus has
56 As Tim Crane has reminded me, the closest modern analogy may be Henri
Bergsons vitalism.
57 So, e. g., G. S. Kirk, Heraclitus and death in battle, AJP 70 (1949) 392, fol-
lowed by Kahn H. 249, quoted also by Schofield (above, n. 2) 15.
8. On the physical aspect of Heraclitus psychology 251
Appendix 1
On the life and death of the soul and the elements
58 The point about Theophrastus has been made by Laks (above, n. 17) 254. The-
ophrastus only claim, i. e., that Heraclitus, together with Anaxagoras, thinks
perception to be by contraries, seems to be a possibly unwarranted inference
from the role of opposites in Heraclitus.
59 Nussbaum (above, n.2) 153 4.
252 Gbor Betegh
for itself or, which seems the more probable option, for the human
being to whom it belongs.
Pindars verse brings us in turn to the adjective !h\mator applied to
xuw^. The earliest text in which the soul is said to be !h\mator is the
famous passage in Herodotus where he describes the Egyptian and Py-
thagorean doctrine of reincarnation (2.123). When applied to the xuw^,
it is not immediately obvious what the opposite of !h\mator is, exactly
because of the problematic relationship between xuw^ and death as dis-
cussed above. It seems that in this early context the opposite of an
!h\mator xuw^ is not merely, and not even primarily a xuw^ which
dies. Rather, it is opposed to a xuw^ which, as in Homeric eschatology,
continues to exist after the death of the individual, but goes to Hades
and stays there indefinitely, and therefore ceases to be the soul of a living
being. A xuw^ might then be qualified !h\mator in so far as it continues
to be present in, and bring life to, (different) living organisms.
This body of evidence, both positive and negative, strongly suggests
that in speaking about the xuw^, death and life are not simple opposites,
and are not simply equivalent with the existence or non-existence of the
xuw^. Similarly, ascribing death or destruction to the xuw^, on the one
hand, and claiming it to be !h\mator, on the other, are not simple op-
posites and do not create a complete disjunction. This is so precisely be-
cause in the traditional, Homeric, conception the xuw^ continues to
exist, without however bringing life to a living organism.
B 36 appears thus to redefine the scope of application of the terms
death and birth, by applying them to the xuw^ and the elements. If
so, B 36 can provide a coherent interpretative context for B 62:
!h\matoi hmgto_, hmgto !h\matoi,
f_mter tm 1je_mym h\matom,
tm d 1je_mym b_om tehme_ter.
Immortal mortals, mortal immortals,
living the death of these,
and dying the life of these.
This fragment is often praised for its perfect composition, and, at the
same time is often called one of the most enigmatic of Heraclitus say-
ings.60 Without intending to dissipate all its magnificent obscurity, let
Appendix 2
Anaximenes and Heraclitus on the soul
There is one important fragment from the period before Heraclitus that
appears immediately relevant to the physical aspect of Heraclitus theory
of xuw^. This is Anaximenes B 2:
oWom B xuw^ B Blet]qa !q owsa sucjqate? Blr, ja fkom tm j|slom
pmeOla ja !q peqi]wei.
Just as the xuw^, which being our air, keeps us together, so do the breath
and air encompass the whole world.
8. On the physical aspect of Heraclitus psychology 255
64 G. Whrle, Anaximenes aus Milet (Stuttgart 1993) 15: Ob sich also Anaximenes
tatschlich ber die Seele in irgendeiner Weise geuert hat, lt sich kaum mit
Sicherheit sagen.
65 K. Reinhardt, Kosmos und Sympathie (Munich 1926) 213, followed by, among
others, J. Kerschensteiner, Kosmos (Munich 1962) 83.
66 Alt (above, n. 17) 157 64.
67 Vlastos in the same paper also emphasizes the importance of Anaximenes B 2
for the understanding of Heraclitus, although I derive different conclusions
from this evidence.
256 Gbor Betegh
ture that Heraclitus own views are to some extent dependent on, and
contain a critical reaction to, Anaximenes theory.
Let us see then in what way Heraclitus reacted to Anaximenes in
formulating his own views on the soul, starting with the general char-
acteristics of the two doctrines and their place in the respective physical
theories they form part of. First a point of contact: in accordance with
the general tendencies of Ionian physics, both Anaximenes and Heracli-
tus allowed that different forms of matter turn into each other. But then
comes the contrast in the description of the transformation: condensa-
tion and rarefaction for Anaximenes, cooling and warming, moistening
and parching for Heraclitus (cf. B 126).
The second point of comparison concerns the role of the soul in
both human beings and the cosmos at large. Here things become tricky,
especially regarding Anaximenes. This is so because there are good rea-
sons to think that the word sucjqate? that describes the function of the
air in human beings, is not Anaximenean.68 If it still carries over some-
thing of the sense of the original, it seems that the function ascribed to
air in both roles is something like holding together.69 With respect to
Anaximenes, anything further is a matter of conjecture. Thus, one may
think that the air also governs or steers both the cosmos and the human
being.70 Yet it is an open question whether sucjqate?, or whatever
stood in its place in Anaximenes original, had anything to do with gov-
erning or steering. It seems to me just as possible that, closer to the Ho-
meric meaning of the word xuw^, what the air does is keeping the cos-
mos together and keeping it functioning. The fact that pmeOla is
emphasized on the cosmic side may support this interpretation in so
68 As many have pointed out this verb is suspicious because it is only attested
much later, first in Plutarch, and even then rather rarely. It is unclear what
may have stood in its place in Anaximenes text. But it is just as unclear to
me why one found this word appropriate to inflict on Anaximenes and thus
create a less than obvious analogy with peqi]wei.
69 The best attested meaning of sucjqat]y is to keep something together by au-
thority or force (as a general keeps together his troops in Plut. Phoc. 12), so
when one tries to find a common denominator between sucjqat]y and
peqi]wei, the best bet I think is still that the air holds together and keeps in a
functional state both the world and the human beings. The cosmos would
fall apart and stop functioning without the encompassing air, just as the
human being disintegrates and stops functioning when the soul leaves it. Hold-
ing the living being together is a distinct function of the soul also in Aristotles
discussion towards the very end of De Anima 1 at 411b7 9.
70 See the different possibilities lined out in KRS 160.
8. On the physical aspect of Heraclitus psychology 257
far as blast or wind is the active manifestation of air. As long as the air is
there and remains active, the human being and the cosmos remain func-
tional and do not decompose.
Some interpreters went further and claimed that Anaximenes air
must also be intelligent. Interestingly, this claim is based not on the
function of air in human beings, but on the assumption that the air
also governs Anaximenes cosmos.71 This, however, seems to me a rath-
er bold interpretative leap, for the text does not even say in so many
words that the air governs the cosmosit only says that it encompasses
it. This stronger interpretation, I suggest, reads back to Anaximenes a
move that was made by Heraclitus in reaction to Anaximenes. What
makes this move possible is precisely the novelty of Heraclitus concep-
tion of xuw^, which consists in making the xuw^ the center of both
motor and cognitive functions.72
So Heraclitus critical assessment of Anaximenes position on the
soul thus far would be something like this. Anaximenes was correct in
conceiving the soul as a portion of some stuff, which also has cosmic
functions and which can turn into other stuffs. But he is not quite
right in describing the role of this stuff in both the cosmos and the in-
dividual human being. For the main function of the xuw^ in both con-
texts is cognition and intelligence, and closely related to it, control. It
does not merely hold things together, but determines the behavior of
both the cosmos and individual human beings.
Now what about the physical identification of the soul? On the in-
terpretation I suggest, Heraclitus critical attitude towards Anaximenes
turns out to be more complex than either simple refusal or agreement.
He can agree with Anaximenes in saying that the soul, in the large ma-
jority of people, is atmospheric air. He can nevertheless point out that
Anaximenes is hubristically overoptimistic when he considers that that
form of matter which in most human beings functions as soul is the
most important, nay, divine form of matter that fullfils the central cos-
mic functions as well. It is sheer hubris to identify the souls in these peo-
ple with the highest state of soul stuff. These souls, though parcels of the
same cosmic mass, are qualitatively different from the highest form of
soulthey are wet, approaching water, whereas soul in its ideal state
is dry and fiery.
71 So e. g. Laks (above, n. 17) 252: and air was probably also responsible for what
we call thought, since it governs Anaximenes universe.
72 On this, see above pp. 225 6.
258 Gbor Betegh
Appendix 3
Heraclitus and the Orphic writings on the soul
the standard Stoic list of the four elements (as in some versions of B 36), and,
despite the evidence of Arius Didymus fr. 39 = SVF 2.821, the mention of the
aQh^q is not conspicuously Stoic either.
76 For a recent discussion of this text, see C. Megino, Aristteles y el Liceo ante
el orfismo, in A. Bernab & F. Casadess (eds.), Orfeo y la tradicion rfica (Ma-
drid 2008) 1281 1306; and id. Presence in Stoicism of an Orphic doctrine on
the soul quoted by Aristotle (De Anima 410b 27 = OF 421), in M. Herrero de
Juregui et al. (eds.), Tracing Orpheus (Berlin 2011) 139 146.
260 Gbor Betegh
telian evidence ensures that the author of the Orphic writing in question
adopted this view independently of any Stoic influence.
There is of course no guarantee that the Orphic rephrasing of B 36
and the Orphic doctrine reported by Aristotle ever formed parts of a co-
herent and explicit Orphic theory of the soul.77 Yet I find it remark-
able that they correspond perfectly to the respective parts of the Hera-
clitean theory as I have tried to reconstruct it. Naturally, one can come
up with different scenarios to explain this body of evidence. For in-
stance, one could speculate that first some Orphics espoused the doc-
trine of the breathed-in soul from whatever, non-Heraclitean, source,
then the Stoics mistakenly attributed the same view to Heraclitus, and
then some later Orphics accepted this Stoicizing (mis-)interpretation
of Heraclitus, and this in turn gave them the motivation to adapt Her-
aclitus B 36. Yet, I find it just as conceivable that we dont need to pre-
suppose such zigzags, and hypothesize that some relatively early Orphics
were impressed directly by the Heraclitean theory of the soul, both that
the xuw^ can be identified with the element that extends from the at-
mospheric air to the heavenly fire and that we receive shares of it by
breathing it in.
Bibliography
Alt, K. Zum Satz des Anaximenes ber die Seele: Untersuchung von Aetios
Peq )qw_m, Hermes 101 (1973) 129 164.
Bandini, M., and L.-A. Dorion, M. Xnophon Mmorables. Vol. 1. Introduction
gnrale, Livre I. Collection Bud. Paris 2000.
Barnes, J. The Presocratic Philosophers, 2nd ed. London and New York 1982.
Bernab, A. Textos rficos y filosofa presocrtica: materiales para una comparacon,
Madrid 2004.
Bollack, J., and H. Wismann. Hraclite ou la sparation. Paris 1972.
Bossi, B. Acerca del significado del Fragmento B 62 (D.-K.) de Herclito, in
E. Hlsz (ed.), Nuevos Ensayos sobre Herclito. Actas del II Symposium Heracli-
teum Mxico 2006 (Mexico 2009) 285 314.
English, R. B. Heraclitus and the soul, TAPA 44 (1913) 163 184.
Frede, D. Platon. Vol.3, part 2. Philebos. Gttingen 1997.
Gigon, O. Untersuchungen zu Heraklit. Leipzig 1935.
Gill, C. La psychologie prsocratique: quelques questions interprtatives, in
P.-M. Morel and J. F. Pradeau (eds.), Les Anciens savants (Cahiers Philoso-
phiques de Strasbourg, 12). Strasbourg (2001) 169 190.
1 For a discussion of the textual problems see Kirk, H. 203 21; Kahn, H. 195.
2 For a more thorough discussion I may refer to my own book (Dilcher, H.), ch.
V. A slightly different account why Heraclitus does not use the term opposites is
given by T. Buchheim, Die Vorsokratiker (Munich 1994) 78 ff. From the per-
spective of the history of interpretations, it was Karl Reinhardt who succeeded
in shifting attention away from the flux doctrine to the problem of opposites as
being the central issue in Heraclitus: Parmenides und die Geschichte der griechischen
Philosophie (Bonn 1916) 220.
264 Roman Dilcher
the opposites is usually said to amount not to strict identity (e. g.,
day is night), but rather to some sort of underlying unity. According
to this interpretation, day and night are one in respect of something
else, for instance of the continuum of time they both occupy. Hon-
orable though this solution may be, it has the flaw of turning Hera-
clitus surreptitiously into a premature Aristotelian. The term un-
derlying which is so frequently und unhesitatingly used in
scholarship has its origin in Aristotelian physics and metaphysics,
which becomes plain once it is rendered in Greek: rpoje_lemom
(from which come Latin sub-stratum and sub-stantia).3
In Physics Alpha, Aristotle develops for the very first time this notion of
rpoje_lemom by starting with the traditional (i. e., Presocratic) ways of
accounting for movement through opposites and showing that some
third principle underlying movement from one opposite to the other
is needed. Interpreting Heraclitus along such Aristotelian lines will
not only spoil Aristotles innovative point but will also deprive Heracli-
tean unity of its most characteristic trait which in B 51 is expressed as a
back-stretched fitting. No underlying substratum will be able to possess
that tension that bow and lyre are meant to display.
As long as the formula of unity of opposites cannot be matched with
Heraclitus own conceptualization (of unity as well as of those phenom-
ena we usually class as opposites), such as can be gathered from B 51, it
will be a mere phantasma of scholarship. It may after all not be incidental
that Heraclitus does not directly introduce his notion of "qlom_g. What
he says is first of all that they do not understand it. So harmony seems
to be a special instance of the general human tendency to incomprehen-
sion. In addition, B 54 tells us that an unapparent fitting is stronger than
an apparent one ("qlom_g !vamr vameq/r jqe_ttym). While it is not
clear what bearing this distinction has on understanding the back-
rather plain. This may partly explain why this fragment has been so
thoroughly neglected. Still, if Heraclitus is presenting what he has to
say about cognition in the form of a riddle, or more precisely through
a story containing a riddle, then we have here the same enigmatic style
as a literary genre that in other fragments is displayed on the semantic
level. If Heraclitus thought as a whole presents itself as difficult to un-
derstand like an enigma or even like an oracle, then surely B 56 is sup-
posed to provide some clue for finding a way to understanding.
This story is given as an explanation for a general human cognitive
failure. Given the selective state of transmission, it could well have hap-
pened that only the first sentence would have been transmitted: People
are mistaken in respect to knowledge of apparent things. In this case,
our fragment would have been a perfect example of a general saying
(such as one often finds for instance in Stobaeus). The range and specific
application of such a saying, bereft of its explanatory context, is neces-
sarily open, and it would have been left to the interpreter to find a suit-
able context for it. Our fragment would then appear as just another re-
petition of those attacks against peoples misunderstanding with which
Heraclitus discourse began. While in many instances there is simply
no other choice than resorting to guesswork, B 56 offers the more or
less unique opportunity to determine the specific point of the saying
by referring to Heraclitus own explanation. The Homeric legend is
presented explicitly and pointedly to highlight the specific way in which
people are mistaken.
B 56 works by comparison. People are said to 1ngp\tgmtai, to be
mistaken, or more literally to be deceived or to deceive themselves.
This shortcoming is to be understood not as just as, speq or similar,
but as nearing, being about equal to, paqapkgs_yr, that which hap-
pened to Homer. The legend thus provides no full parallel but just an
approximation. On both sides of the comparison the verb 1napatm is
used, so that what can be understood about Homers situation is to be
transferred to that of men in general. The point of comparison is Hom-
ers inability to solve the riddle which, in Heraclitus view, comes close
to the general human lack of understanding. Although !patm is usually
translated as deceiving (this meaning here even strengthened by the
prefix 1n-), this will not adequately describe Homers state of mind.
He is in fact not deceived by the boys into believing something that
is untrue, but is rather put into puzzlement. Instead of a straightforward
answer such as: No, we had no luck with fishing, we have just spent
our time getting rid of lice, the boys utter their enigmatic words. In
268 Roman Dilcher
amount to something like opening ones eyes and taking a straight look
at what allegedly is apparent before us. So what is meant by apparent
would consequently not be apparent in the vulgar sense, but only to the
philosophers eyes. Heraclitean insight would thus have to be reached
by some sort of direct intuition, but we would not gain any indication
as to how to achieve it. On this reading, the fragment would be unin-
formative on the crucial point.
Furthermore, and more importantly, this reading would positively
spoil the point of the riddle. Within the situation of the legend, it fol-
lows that Homer would have been able to understand the riddle if only
he still had had sight. This way he would have been able to observe the
doings of the fisher-boys and just see they had been catching lice. How-
ever, if Homer, or anyone else, had visual access to what was going on
there would be no need for a riddle in the first place. If the solution is
available visually, then a riddle has no point. A riddle calls for sagacity,
not for better observation or gaining more external information. The
fact that Heraclitus here calls Homer the wisest of the Greeks serves
to underline that what it takes to solve a riddle is above all wisdom. So
in highlighting the basic human failure this fragment gives an indirect
clue as to how to be wise.
Riddles are there to be solved by thinking about them, by finding the
right answer through listening to the words and making sense of them.
It is for this reason that the form of a riddle is congenial to the character
of Heraclitus thought. When confronted with a riddle one is prompted
to reconsider the implicit preconceptions one has about what is at issue.
Often the solution can be found if the words are taken in an unusual
way whereas if one clings to the normal expectations it remains enig-
matic.8 So, not being able to solve a riddlethe situation of
Homerindeed comes close to what is said of men in B 1: they hear
the logos but they remain uncomprehending. What they hear from
Heraclitus is certainly not just noises, but words they understand and
sentences they can follow. What they hear even has a meaning to
them but they still cannot make sense of it. Or rather, precisely because
they can make some sense of the sentences they read they conclude
that it seems to be nonsense. It all appears absurd to them just as the
boys riddle seemed to Homer. This allows for the conclusion that B
56 is actually meant to provide, by means of a comparison to a tricky,
8 Cf. the extensive material of ancient riddles collected by K. Ohlert, Rtsel und
Gesellschaftsspiele der alten Griechen, Berlin 1886.
270 Roman Dilcher
9 Even those interpreters who have dealt with B 56 usually shy away from ana-
lyzing the riddle. Cf., e. g., Uvo Hlscher, Anfngliches Fragen (Gttingen 1968)
138, Auf die Lsung des Rtsels kommt nichts an, es geht lediglich um die
Form als Rtsel, und die besagt: auch die Dinge stellen ein paradoxes Geheim-
nis dar, das gleichwohl am Tage liegt; sie sind selber ein Rtsel, das zu lsen ist
man mu nur die Chiffre lesen knnen, das heit, man mu das Sichtbare als
Zeichen verstehen lernen, als das Sich-Anzeigen des Unsichtbaren. Yet how
could we learn to read the chiffre without attending to the riddle? Without
a k|cor for solving the riddle the solution would amount to sheer intuitional
guesswork.
9. How Not to Conceive Heraclitean Harmony 271
10 LSJ s.v. A I 9.
272 Roman Dilcher
11 H. Frnkel, Early Greek Poetry and Philosophy (Oxford 1975) 372 3. Frnkel ap-
pears to be the only interpreter who has tried to analyze the riddle itself.
9. How Not to Conceive Heraclitean Harmony 273
by catching lice on oneself, as against hunting for fish or any other ob-
jects in the world.
The second conclusion from B 56 is more perplexing. The riddle also
shows how the nature of what is to be known has implications for the
right way to deal with it; in the imagery of the legend, lice are not caught
in the same way as fish. Now, the appeal to go in search of oneself could
be understood as retreating from the outward world and concentrating
on the state of the soul or some inner self. While we do find in Hera-
clitus much attention to the soul and its states (for the first time in philos-
ophy), Heraclitus logos apparently does not exclude consideration of the
cosmos and the so-called physical world. B 56 may help to get the point
right. The riddle indicates that for Heraclitus it is not any form of intro-
spection that is called for, but rather a different mode of understanding
of oneself as well as of the world one lives in. The boys action involves
not only a reversal of direction by turning to oneself, instead of reaching
out into the world. While it is conceivable that lice (or anything similarly
close to oneself) are to be caught simply by laying hands on them and
keeping them, the crucial point that causes the delusion is that the lice
are caught in order to get rid of them. This may appear natural in respect
to lice, but it is not natural any more if this action is to serve as the clue for
understanding what understanding oneself is about.
While self-knowledge is in some way or other a standard theme in
the philosophical tradition, it is this reversal of the action of gaining such
knowledge which requires explanation. As the riddle so pointedly and
effectively puts it, the knowledge in question is nothing that after
being taken can be had and as it were be carried along (v]qolem).
Self-knowledge not only cannot be gained in the same way as knowledge
of external objects, it is, according to Heraclitus, not even something
that can be gained in the strict sense at all, in the sense of making it
ones own and possessing it; rather, it is to be left behind (!poke_polem).
So whatever the procedure is like, in the end nothing is left in our
hands, and the effort will be in vain; at least so it will necessarily appear
to standard beliefs.
When turning to Heraclitus claims to knowledge, our first (and to
many interpreters also the lasting) impression appears to be that he be-
lieved himself to have discovered the one and only truth which all man-
kind fails to recognize. This universal claim seems to be presupposed by
his many attacks against men in general and almost all intellectual au-
thorities in particular (B 56 appears to be just another instance of this
on first reading). Yet, on closer inspection it is rather difficult to sub-
9. How Not to Conceive Heraclitean Harmony 275
13 This important discovery was already made by B. Snell, Die Ausdrcke fr den
Begriff des Wissens in der vorplatonischen Philosophie (Berlin 1924) 66 7. See
also his pertinent remark in Die Sprache Heraklits, in his Gesammelte Schriften
(Gttingen 1966) 136 n. 3: Erkennen kann fr Heraklit hchstens eine gtt-
liche cm~lg, menschliches cicm~sjeim bleibt immer im Unzulnglichen steck-
enaber darin zeigt sich, wie schwach in ihm der Impuls zum Erkennen war
und der Glaube, damit an ein wertvolles Ziel zu gelangen. Eine Resignation
gegenber dem ihm wesentlichen Wissen liegt Heraklit durchaus fern.
276 Roman Dilcher
ing but hearing in its full sense:14 what is heard is primarily not noises
but words, and not just words, but words meaningfully strung togeth-
erin Greek, k|cor. It is therefore misleading to construe Heraclitean
insight by way of a model of sensory perception; that is, by any sort
of immediate awareness or direct intuition. As both B 1 and 56 tell
us, what is to be achieved is understanding and making sense of
words deliberately strung together, and the suitable Greek word for
this is numi]mai, to bring together.15 People remain uncomprehending
(!n}metoi, in B 1) as they fail to bring together the words of the Hera-
clitean logos, just as Homer failed to make sense of the boys riddle. Also
the word num|m in B 2 ought to be interpreted in the same direction.
And a failure to bring it together (oq numisim) is what happens to people
also in respect to the back-stretched harmony of B 51. In the light of B
56, it appears that these are different manifestations of the same mistaken
attitude. Therefore, not comprehending the back-stretched fitting(B
51) can be read as another comment on what it specifically is that
makes the Heraclitean logos difficult to understand; for if they fail to
bring together those artfully und deliberately composed words of Hera-
clitus this failure concerns the adjustment of those words, their connec-
tion and specific structure, in Greek their "qlom_a. Thus, the problem of
conceiving Heraclitean harmony is in fact coupled with the basic human
problem of coming to grips with the logos, and an explanation for this
predicament is offered by B 56.
Now, the main factor for not understanding could be determined as
the tendency to make what was seen and taken ones own so as to
possess it. There is another fragment that may shed further light on
what this may amount to, B 28: doj]omta cq b dojil~tator cim~sjei,
14 B 101a Eyes are better witnesses than ears has often been taken as the basis for
a Heraclitean epistemology. Given the lack of context, however, it is difficult to
determine the scope of this saying. Rather than valuing one sense over another,
this fragment is presumably concerned with criticizing the reliance on hearsay
(cp. K. Robb, The Witness in Heraclitus and in early Greek law, The Monist
74 (1991) 664 ff). As B 107 demonstrates, sense perception as such is for Her-
aclitus something that needs interpretation. So we are in any way led back to
the problems of properly understanding a language.
15 Cf. Snell Ausdrcke (above, n. 13) 48: diese Beziehung zum menschlichen
Geist ist durch sumi]mai deswegen gegeben, weil es von der Wahrnehmung
durch das Ohr ausgeht. Dessen Objekt ist menschliche vernnftige Rede, wh-
rend das Auge auf die Gegenstnde des Raumes gerichtet ist, deren Ordnung es
erkennt. According to Snell 41, the basic meaning in Homer is to be rendered
as etwas durch das Gehr in sich aufnehmen und ihm geistig folgen.
278 Roman Dilcher
vuk\ssei. Whatever the correct wording may be,16 the gist of the frag-
ment is again criticism of knowledge, here expressed by the paradoxical
phrase doj]omta cim~sjei: he, whoever this dojil~tator is supposed to
be, recognizes what is only doj]omta. As everyone familiar with Parme-
nides knows, the translation of doj-words is notoriously difficult, as it
can range from d|na in the plain sense as view, opinion to more neg-
ative senses such as seeming, mere belief. The latter meaning occurs
for instance in B 17, there in opposition to cicm~sjeim: they do not
learn and know, but they form beliefs of their own, oqd lah|mter
cim~sjousim, 2yuto?si d doj]ousi. Again, we encounter the idea of
having something for oneself (2yuto?si), which here can be understood
as leading to the fabrication of doxa. It is likely that doj]omta in B 28
should be understood on the same lines. Now, the interesting informa-
tion in B 28 is that cicj~sjeim is here coupled with vuk\sseim, which is
the exact opposite of !poke_peim. It is therefore advisable to take vuk\s-
seim here as specifying this epistemic activity. Normally one guards and
protects something from getting lost, one cares for it so that it may re-
main intact. Not to let go but to guard something one has taken in
cognition will accordingly mean that it is transformed into a doxa, a
firm view one entertains about the matter in question. Such a fixed be-
lief is what one can carry along and thereby become a d|jilor among
menjust as, for instance, Pythagoras who, Heraclitus says, contrived
even a wisdom of his own (1poi^sato 2autoO sov_gm, B 129).
A recurrent epistemological theme emerges in Heraclitus criticism
of human incomprehension. The contrast between letting go and
carrying along is vital to understanding the Heraclitean logos. The
mistaken, though common and in fact natural attitude leading to incom-
prehension results in forming beliefs and con-cepts by which what
has been seen and taken can be carried along. If this way of under-
standing as making something ones own ends in forming fixed doc-
trines, then another fragment that has rarely been interpreted calls for
consideration. B 70 has something to say about human doxai: pa_dym
!h}qlata t !mhq~pima don\slata, childrens toys are the human
opinions. Again as in B 56, we hear of playing children.17 Playing is
16 The grammatical forms of the first and the last word as given above are the most
common accepted emendations; cf. Marcovich fr. 20 (p. 78 ff).
17 As B 52 (aQm pa?r 1sti pa_fym jtk) shows, Heraclitus ought to be taken seri-
ously in what he says about the role of playing children in human life. For in-
terpretation, I may again refer to Dilcher, H. 153 ff.
9. How Not to Conceive Heraclitean Harmony 279
what the boys do with Homer, and what they play with is precisely
Homers opinions. Likewise Heraclitus plays with his readers. So B 70
might suitably be understood as expressing what human beliefs are
there for: to be played with. This might be an indication of a possible
way to deal with that epistemic predicament.
To sum up: the initial question was how to conceive Heraclitean
harmony, and after realizing the problems inherent in formulating a co-
herent concept or doctrine of harmony (or unity) we now reach the re-
sult that attempting to gain and fix any such doctrine is precisely the
mistake humans tend to make. The problem with the Heraclitean con-
cept of harmony turns out to be that harmony is not to be conceived.
Even more, any concept or doctrine in its normal sense, so at least it
seems, will fail to make sense of Heraclitus logos. This epistemic idea
that can be gained from B 56 may still appear puzzling, but it is no
more and in no other way puzzling than the character of Heraclitus
logos itself. In fact, it proves to be a very precise description of the use
of concepts or themes that can recurrently and on different levels
be observed in Heraclitus. What is once taken up as the subject of dis-
course or as an explanatory notion will then be abandoned again, or it
will reappear with different and new connections.18 So B 56 in fact
points at an essential feature of the logos by issuing a warning. If we pro-
ceed on conventional epistemological assumptions, we shall wreak
havoc on the logos and fail to conform with its specific structure, and
that is, with its harmony.
How a more positive way of coming to terms with Heraclitus logos
might look is still out of reach. Yet in B 56 there is an indication. Her-
aclitus does not put us in the situation of Homer not knowing how to
solve the riddle. Instead, he tells us the solution right from the begin-
ning: the boys, he says, were killing lice, vhe?qar jatajte_momter. By
knowing this solution, the reader is able to understand Homers delu-
sion. The words that illuminate for us the situation at the beach may
also illuminate for us, in a way, the meaning of this whole business.
After all, the boys killing of lice is the reason, in the framework of
the legend, for the thoroughgoing negativity that shatters all attempts
to get straightforward answers from Heraclitusafter reading B 56 no
less than before. In the pictorial language of the legend, this is the result
of presenting a trifling activity like killing lice instead of bringing us the
expected catch of fish that would give us a mouth-filling meal. Likewise
our hunger for anything definite is frustrated; no doctrine to fill our in-
tellectual appetite is forthcoming. Even so, killing lice is useful, in that
one thereby gets rid of something annoying. What one gets rid of is in
Greek called vhe?qer, and this word may well be understood from the
root vhe_qeim, to destroy, ruin, eliminate. So somewhat secretly we
here have two words for the same negative activity. The boys are bring-
ing death to the lice which in fact are themselves called destroyers. The
peculiar activity could thus be rendered as killing the killers. What this
may mean for the nature of true understanding must remain open,
but it seems to have something to do with keeping oneself alive.
So, B 56 in the end sheds some important light on Heraclitus
thought as a whole. In view of the fact that it is the only fragment
that actually explains what is wrong in the belief and practice of the nor-
mal pre-philosophical way of thinking, it is a guideline as to how to deal
with Heraclitus main insight. Considering the epistemic predicament
that mankind is in according to Heraclitus, one may well say that with-
out heeding the claims of B 56, the logos will forever remain incompre-
hensible ( just as he says in B 1). In this way, this fragment holds the same
fundamental function as does in Platos philosophy the simile of the
cave: showing the way out of human shortcomings by engaging in phi-
losophy. Surely, Heraclitus is more reticent about what the wise will ex-
perience. Instead of a colorful imagery (as in Plato), we are confronted
with a deceptive but inconspicuous riddle. Yet, by paying close atten-
tion to what it says, we can not only rid ourselves of some delusions,
but what we are in fact also doing is, to some extent, listening and con-
forming to the logos. Only for those who expect big fish will, whatever
they see and take, be and remain a lousy tale.
Bibliography
Buchheim, Thomas. Die Vorsokratiker, Munich 1994.
Frnkel, Hermann. Early Greek Poetry and Philosophy. Oxford 1975.
Hlscher, Uvo. Anfngliches Fragen. Gttingen 1968.
Ohlert, Konrad. Rtsel und Gesellschaftsspiele der alten Griechen. Berlin 1886.
Reinhardt, Karl. Parmenides und die Geschichte der griechischen Philosophie. Bonn 1916.
Robb, Kevin. The Witness in Heraclitus and in early Greek law, The Monist
74 (1991) 638 676.
Snell, Bruno. Die Ausdrcke fr den Begriff des Wissens in der vorplatonischen Phi-
losophie. Berlin 1924.
Gesammelte Schriften. Gttingen 1966.
10. Heraclitus on Logos
Language, Rationality and the Real
Enrique Hlsz
4 For the Greek text, see below, note 12. That B 1 is the !qw^ of the book relies
on the authority of Aristotle and Sextus Empiricus, and is nowadays widely ac-
cepted. Not implausibly, many have proposed that it could have been preceded
by a few words like Heraclitus of Ephesos says as follows. It remains possible
that other preserved fragment or fragments preceded B 1 (B 50 is a recurring
candidate); cf. L. Tarn, The first fragment of Heraclitus, Illinois Classical
Studies, XI, 2; S. Mouravievs recent reconstruction (Heraclitea, IV.A, 2011)
conjectures a series of nine fragments before it. Some think that B 1 and at
least B 114 and 2 (in that order) belong together here and form a neat proem.
5 The Greek noun di^cgsir, meaning something like narrative exposition and/
or explanation, corresponds to the verb actually used, digceOlai (set out in
detail, describe; LSJ s.v.).
6 Heraclitus use of v}sir is arguably the oldest preserved within the philosophical
tradition (since he probably wrote earlier than Parmenides, and the term is not
documented in the scarce authentic fragments of Anaximander and Anaxi-
menes). V}sir is one of Heraclitus main philosophical watchwords endowed
with considerable linguistic density, to use Kahns words. Note in the passage
quoted from B 1 the apo koinou construction of the adverbial phrase jat v}sim,
affecting all three surrounding verbs. For the three other instances of the word
in the fragments, see B 112, 123, and 106the last probably not a full verbatim
quotation. Put in direct style, v}sir Bl]qgr "p\sgr l_a 1sti would be a mini-
malistic and reasonable version of the saying. See Mouraviev, H. III. 3. i-iii for
his reconstruction of B 106.
7 This seems to be the best sense for vq\fym in context, and one that is consistent
with usage at Heraclitus time. Cf. LSJ s. v. vq\fy, 2, show forth, tell, de-
clare.
284 Enrique Hlsz
8 Pace H.-G. Gadamers opinion that v}sir carries no philosophical import yet in
Heraclitus; cf. H.-G. Gadamer, Der Anfang der Philosophie (Stuttgart 1996) 41
42 = 34 35 of the Enlish translation. The opposite view of the idea of v}sir as
an early basic metaphysical concept was, of course, defended by M. Heidegger
in his Einfhrung in die Metaphysik and essays Aletheia (Heraklit, Fragment 16)
and Logos (Heraklit, fr. 50 DK) (all in the Gesamtausgabe, Frankfurt, various
dates). Although Gadamer says he agrees with Kirk (in KRS), his claim misrep-
resents the latters own statements, which do not really back that v}sir has no
philosophical weight whatsoever in Heraclitus. In the better and wider treat-
ment of B 123, Kirk actually states that the broad general sense of v}sir,
from which all specialized senses are derived, is essence or nature, the way
a thing is made, [] the way it normally behaves, and that the most common
early sense of v}sir is being, though the idea of growth is not excluded and
may be emphasized on particular occasions. See Kirk, H. 227 231,
esp. 229. This is a far cry from v}sir not being philosophically significant in
Heraclitus, even if it does not mean Nature, as it allegedly does in Aristotle.
9 Phaedo 96a7. It is crucial for getting the right sense in context not to translate as
nature tout court, but as the nature of things.
10 For Platos reception of Heraclitus, see T. Irwin, Platos Heracliteanism, PQ
27/106 (1977) 1 13; M. Adomenas (2002), The fluctuating fortunes of Her-
aclitus in Plato in A. Laks-C. Louguet (eds.), Quest-ce que la philosophie prsoc-
ratique (Villeneuve-dAscq 2002) 419 447; See also E. Hlsz Piccone, Scra-
tes y el orculo de Delfos (una nota sobre Platn, Apologa de Scrates 20c4
23c1), Theora 14 15 ( June 2003) 71 89, and Anmnesis en el Menn plat-
nico, Apuntes filosficos 22 (2003) 61 79. See id., n. 2 above, as well as id., La
imagen de Herclito en el Cratilo y el Teeteto de Platn, in E. Hlsz (ed.), Nue-
vos ensayos sobre Herclito (Mexico City 2010) 361 389; and id. Platos Ionian
Muses: Sophist 242 d-e, in B. Bossi and T. M. Robinson (eds.), Platos Sophist
Revisited (Berlin 2012).
10. Heraclitus on Logos 285
11 I do not claim exhaustivity here, as there could be a few other fragments com-
ing between B1 and B 114 (B 19 and 34 come to mind). As to the relationship
between B 114 and 2, I follow Marcovich and others in treating it as a single,
continuous whole. This would require more argument that I can give here, but
it is prima facie likely, on grounds of style (i. e. narrative, diegematic form) and
of content affinity (i. e., the num|m), that the texts go together. It is worth no-
ticing that Kahns insightful ordering does not follow this line, nor does Mour-
avievs reconstruction.
12 B 1: toO d k|cou toOd 1|mtor aQe_ !n}metoi c_momtai %mhqypoi ja pq|shem C
!joOsai ja !jo}samter t pq_tom7 cimol]mym cq p\mtym jat tm k|com
t|mde !pe_qoisim 1o_jasi, peiq~lemoi ja 1p]ym ja 5qcym toio}tym, bjo_ym
1c digceOlai jat v}sim diaiq]ym 6jastom ja vq\fym fjyr 5wei. tor d
%kkour !mhq~pour kamh\mei bj|sa 1ceqh]mter poioOsim, fjyspeq bj|sa evdom-
ter 1pikamh\momtai.
B 114: nm m|\ k]comtar Qswuq_feshai wq t` num` p\mtym, fjyspeq m|l\
p|kir, ja pok Qswuqot]qyr. tq]vomtai cq p\mter oR !mhq~peioi m|loi rp
2mr toO he_ou7 jqate? cq tosoOtom bj|som 1h]kei ja 1naqje? psi ja peqic_-
metai.
B 2: di de? 6peshai t` <num`>, toO k|cou d 1|mtor numoO f~ousim oR pok-
ko r Qd_am 5womter vq|mgsim.
286 Enrique Hlsz
13 Starting with Diels, adherents to this general view include W. Jaeger, R. Mon-
dolfo, M. Heidegger, O. Gigon, H. Frnkel, M. Marcovich, C. Eggers, and C.
H. Kahn, all in the bibliography below.
14 Cf., besides Burnet, M. L. West, C. Diano, T. M. Robinson, J. Barnes, and M.
Conche, all in the bibliography below.
15 Such as Wests (see above, n. 2, pp. 124 ff.) insistence that logos refers to Her-
aclitus discourse and nothing else (my italics).
16 As one can see, for example, in Kahns translation: Although this account
holds forever, men ever fail to comprehend (97). That the syntax of the first sen-
tence can work both ways (i. e. k|cou toOd 1|mtor aQe_ or aQe_ !n}metoi c_momtai
%mhqypoi ) is made clear by Aristotles famous complaint in the Art of rhetoric
(iii, 5, 1407b 11 ff.). See D. Sider, Word order and sense in Heraclitus: Frag-
ment One and the river fragment, in K. Boudouris (ed.), Ionian Philosophy
(Athens 1989) 363-368.
10. Heraclitus on Logos 287
(or real) logos,17 even if we take this to mean merely that the discourse is
always true (taking the expression in the weaker veritative sense, rath-
er than in the fuller and more natural predicative sense, or in the stronger
existential one), this does not by itself exclude an intended deeper
meaning18. In fact, the language that Heraclitus uses rather suggests the
eternal existence of its objective contents: if he is saying, at the very
least, that his own account holds true throughout, this could very well
be due to his implicitly attributing irrestricted ontological permanence
to its proper object19 (there could even be an intentional, yet subtle,
play between the logos being (this) forever (fde b k|cor 1m aQe_) and
all things becoming according to it). Burnet may have been right that
logos should not be translated as reason (as a cognitive faculty), but
his interpretation of it as Word misses the objective sense, which
could be better conveyed by the French expression, raison dtre. Logos
as objective rationality pertains to the formal aspect of the real, the way
things are and happen, the structure in all change. Seen in this light,
and without being named, logos is mirrored in the eternal kosmos,
which is an ever-living fire (B 30), kindled and quenched in measures
(l]tqa). More obliquely perhaps, logos is implied in the river statement (B
12), the quintessence of which is identification and opposition of the
same rivers (potalo?si to?sim aqto?sim) and ever different waters
(6teqa ja 6teqa vdata). The common thought here is permanence in
change, sameness in difference, unity in plurality. All these formulae are
but variations that approach the same unitary and dynamic objective ra-
tionality.
If by logos Heraclitus meant only his own discourse, how is it, then,
that men are expected to understand it before having listened to it? 20
How could he say, not only that it is always the same or that it exists
17 Rather than with !n}metoi c_momtai %mhqypoi , although this needs not to be
excluded.
18 Especially since Heraclitus careful expression mimics one Homeric formula
that refers to the blissful existence of the gods, heo aQm 1|mter , Il. 1.290,
494; 21.518; 24.99; Od. 1.263, 378; 2.143; 3.147; 4.583; 5.7; 8.306, etc.
19 As he does in B30, where logos is likely to be implied in the measures, which
surely are as eternal as the world-order, the kosmos itself. As with v}sir, Hera-
clitus usage of j|slor is the first one attested in the history of philosophical lan-
guage.
20 So rightly argued by Kahn, H. 98.
288 Enrique Hlsz
forever21 and that all things happen according to it, if he did not
mean to point to some kind of objective cosmic principle, a single uni-
versal law, as suggested in B 114? And would not it be a bit unlikely
that, by calling the logos common (num|m, B 2), Heraclitus intended to
express only the universality and the formal unity of his own account,
but not the actual complex unity of its subject-matter? Questions like
these are perhaps among the reasons why Diels corrected himself trans-
lating Weltgesetz, Law of the world (appending this latter meaning
to the much simpler original Wort).22 In a different line, but likely
moved by similar reasons, Marcovich translated it as Truth, while
Kirk proposed the formula of things. Kahn, H. 22, interprets it as
being at once the discourse of Heraclitus, the nature of language itself,
the structure of the psukhe and the universal principle in accordance
with which all things come to pass.
Logos must include the generic notion of language, and specifically
Heraclitus own discoursive account as part of its surface meaning, but it
also must refer, as its proper object and the solid ground for true knowl-
edge, to the nature of things themselves, to being or reality (as the
text also suggest: cf. the parallel jat tm k|com, jat v}sim in B 1). It is
no mere coincidence that he insists that v}sir tends to be hidden,23
just as logos is said here to be, from the wits of most men. Ignorance
of the rationale of things themselves, omission of the ontologically
basic facts of logos and phusis lie behind his famous criticisms of venerable
poets as Homer (B 42, 56), Hesiod (B 40, 57, 106) and Archilochus (B
42), and representatives of Ionic Rstoq_g as Xenophanes (B 40), Pytha-
goras (B 40, 129) and Hecataeus (B 40). Hiddenness dialectically refers
precisely to what is manifest (vameq|m), and is best interpreted in an
epistemological context (rather than a purely ontological one).
21 As it is plain that I take aQe_ with the participle 1|mtor, my reading tends to be a
metaphysical one. If the minimalist view is prefered, the phrase would mean
simply that the logos as discourse is true [Burnet], or that it holds through-
out [West], with no ontological overtones.
22 Cf. Diels, Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker 1,2 (Berlin 1903, 1906) 1, ch. 12: Fr
dies Wort. Alles geschieht nach diesem Wort. Weltgesetz was added in
Diels second edition of Herakleitos von Ephesos (Berlin 1909).
23 DK 22 B 123: v}sir jq}pteshai vike?. I owe to Daniel Graham the point that
vike? does not mean here loves, but (in view of the infinitive) something like
it is usual for. See his Does nature love to hide? Heraclitus B 123 DK, CP
98 (2003) 175 179. Compare with B 87, n. 29 below.
10. Heraclitus on Logos 289
the closest affinity with Heraclitus (above, n. 24) 51. See also Long in this vol-
ume.
28 B 39: 1m Pqim, Bar 1cmeto b Teutley, ox pkym kcor C t_m %kkym. It is not
at all clear who these others specifically are: the citizens of Priene, Greeks
generally, perhaps the other six sages? Approval of at least one of Bias moral
gnomai is explicit in B 104, so it seems that, in spite of the usual meaning of
the Ionic expression pkym kcor (= higher esteem), logos must include
what Bias himself said, and he must have suceeded in showing things as they
truly are.
29 B 87: bkn %mhqypor 1p pamt kc\ 1pto/shai vike?. This deals with the re-
ceptive aspect of the process of acquiring knowledge, implicitly contrasting
hearing with the more creative abilities of speaking and acting.
30 B 108: bjsym kcour Ejousa, oqder !vijme?tai 1r toOto ste cimsjeim fti
sovm 1sti pmtym jewyqislmom. I take pmtym as masculine and referring
back to bjsym. The targets would seem to naturally include some great figures
named in other fragments, such as Homer, Hesiod, Archilochus, Hecateus,
Xenophanes, and Pythagoras.
31 B 93: b %man ox lamte?m 1sti t 1m Dekvo?r oute kcei oute jqptei !kk sgla-
mei.
10. Heraclitus on Logos 291
ought to keep both, and interpret Heraclitus logos as the language of the
real35: the language of objective rationality and the rationality of lan-
guage. Logos appears as a voice36 coming from the real itself, the voice
of meaningful and intelligent language, which coincides with the struc-
tural objective single form in things themselves and is mirrored in Her-
aclitus own carefully articulated statements.
Unity of all things (4m pmta), as B 50 puts it, is a proper character-
ization of the content of the same logos which is called in the Proem for-
ever real and common or shared by all things, and which is itself a unity
of opposites. Heraclitean logos is, first and foremost, the universal ration-
ale of reality: it is a permanent, formal principle, a sort of law that pertains
to reality itself, conceived of and presented as a rational language. The
explicit notion of a community of all things through logos (and thus
of all men, and of all they say and do) refers to the togetherness or in-
tegrity of being, in itself and as presented in true language. Communion
of intelligent language with the intelligible nature of things is indeed the
suggested basis for true knowledge on the level of human action, and
the reason why logos is a prescriptive, and not merely a descriptive prin-
ciple: being and action are connected through logos as the rational lan-
guage of the real.
Heraclitus criticism of mens epistemic negligence is based on his
attributing them a universal and natural capacity to understand37,
which is nevertheless seldom achieved: even the senses can be deceptive,
but only because the data they provide can be incorrectly interpreted by
their soulswhich in turn must be seen as seat of the faculty of under-
standing: Eyes and ears are bad witnesses, he writes elsewhere, for
men who have barbarian souls.38 A barbarian soul is, of course, one
that does not speak the language of the real, and whose defective dis-
course or account is, because of its being irrational, thus separated
from the wise (B 108). One important point Heraclitus is making
here is that, for good or ill, the human soul is the natural seat for the
An essential link between the human39 soul and logos is focused in B 45:
He who travels every path would not find the boundaries of soul, [as he
goes]: so deep a logos does it have.40
Immediate connection between the soul and logos is apparent, a point
that strenghthens that rationality (and not just language) comes into
play here. Many interpreters have been baffled by the curious paradox
about the souls limits and its suggested virtual unlimitedness or immen-
sity: if Heraclitus is saying that the soul is limited, then why is it that its
boundaries could not be reached? And if he is saying that soul is, in
some sense, infinite, how are we to understand the positive reference
to its peqata? Puzzlement is probably induced, not just by Heraclitus
unmistakable paradoxical style, but also by the readers (understandable)
eagerness to find a sort of definition of the souls nature. But Heraclitus
is perhaps not concerned here (is he ever?) with solving the definitional
aporiai that might trouble his readers or hearers, but with making a point
about the presence of logos (again best interpreted as a rational principle),
precisely within the soul of man. He is succeeding to set down, in a short
string of words, the limits of the souls cognitive power. The souls na-
ture is not exhausted here, but is displayed in a set of other fragments. In
particular, B 3641 implies the souls mortality, and a primarily (though
water it is death to become earth. But water is born from earth, and from water,
soul.)
42 B 101: 1difgslgm 1leyutm. This was sometimes interpreted in antiquity (e. g.,
Diogenes Laertius 10.5) as meaning that Heraclitus was self-taught. But more
could be going on here: the traditional idea of self-knowledge is essentially
linked to sophrosune, which is precisely the virtue praised in B 112. The sentence
also mimics the delphic cm_hi saut|m. To know oneself is, of course, not just
psychological self-awareness, but requires being able to understand what one is
and is not, and so to know ones proper place. See Julia Annas exploration of
Heraclitean self-knowledge in Alcibiades I, Lovers, and Charmides: Self-knowl-
edge in Early Plato, in D. OMeara (ed.), Platonic Investigations (Washington
1985) 111 138.
43 A point denied by Marcovich, H. 57.: [] neither d_fgshai means the same as
cim~sjeim, nor 1leyutm as xuw^.
44 The restrictive character of the interpretation was suggested to me by Conches
text. Contrast with B 116, which I take to refer to self-knowledge as a universal
faculty, not a universal accomplishment.
45 B 18: 1m l 5kpgtai !mkpistom oqj 1neuqsei, !meneqemgtom 1m ja %poqom.
46 B 22: wqusm cq oR difllemoi c/m pokkm aqssousi ja erqsjousim akcom.
10. Heraclitus on Logos 295
53 B 115: xuw/r 1sti kcor 2autm aunym. I cannot make the case for the authen-
ticity of B 115 fully here. It may be summarily laid down, however, that the
onus probandi falls rather on the side of those who deny it is genuine (the source
here is Stobaeus, who also provides the whole series B 108-B 119). Explicit at-
tribution to Socrates (by some unattentive scribe) is not an unsurmountable ob-
jection.
54 I set this apart from his other two objections, which are of a different nature. Cf.
Marcovich, H. 569 ff.
55 B 84a: letabkkom !mapaetai, the first part of the only DK fragment transmit-
ted by Plotinus.
56 I must say that I assume a different reading of B 6, one of the solar fragments.
I propose that what Heraclitus wrote includes the expression always new (b
Fkior oq l|mom jah\peq Jq\jkeit|r vgsim, m]or 1v Bl]q, 1st_m, !kk !e m]or). If
one could follow A. Garca Calvos suggestion (above, n. 1), perhaps the addi-
tion of [ja utr] would be a fitting end. The result would be something like
this: the Sun (so Heraclitus says) is not only new every day, but new always
[and the same]. On my view, Heraclitus could be criticizing a theory (if theory
it could be called) attributed independently to Xenophanes, a known target in
10. Heraclitus on Logos 297
Human conduct, on the other hand, is nothing like this: by his very na-
ture, man is constantly overstepping his measures: ~bqir is a recurring
fact everywhere in human life, either in a political context, as wanton
violence,58 or in the individuals everyday existence (as in the drunkard
with a wet soul in B 11759). Human unreasonableness has a place in the
cosmic order of Heraclitus.
But again, so does the possibility of true excellence, even if this will
be restricted to a few, the true %qistoi.60 In my view, Heraclitus is an eth-
ical optimist at heart, his harsh criticism of his fellow citizens61 and his
well-known unflattering views on men in general notwithstanding.
For, all things considered, those who speak with intelligence, the owners
of non-barbarian souls with ever-changing limits are there too, side by
side the unintelligent hearers. And perhaps even they can change, and
learn to think well, see, hear, speak and act. B 112 wraps it up neatly:
Being of a sound mind is the greatest merit and wisdom: to say what is true
and to act according to nature, as those who pay heed.62
Supreme virtue and wisdom are equated with sound thinking, which
consists of the unity of speech and action. As in B 1, the adverbial phrase
jat vsim is in apo koinou construction, and can be taken as modifying
the three surrounding verbs (kceim, poie?m and the participle 1paomtar),
strongly evoking the language of the proem. Heraclitus moral ideal is
thus quite philosophical, and it could be fairly characterized as an ethical
intellectualistic theory: moral virtue is deeply rooted in knowledge and
the nature of things themselves, including men. One important feature
of this ideal is that it seems feasible, reasonable and earthly, as is befitting
63 B 119: Ghor !mhqp\ dalym. I read into this Heraclitus recognition of moral
autonomy and resposibility of the individual.
64 B 78: Ghor cq !mhqpeiom lm oqj 5wei cmlar, he?om d 5wei. This I take as a
good example of diairesis kata phusin, which focuses on internal opposition with-
in (human) ethos.
65 B 118: aqc ngq xuw sovyttg ja !qstg The basic meaning of aqc^ is
light of the sun (LSJ s. v.). It could perhaps mean here just a bright
light. I follow Kahn in keeping Stobaeus text. In all fairness, it should be
said that there are alternative readings to that proposed here. Another possibility
would be A dry gleam of light is the wisest and best soul, but then what
might a dry gleam of light mean?
66 B 16: t l dOmm pote p_r %m tir khoi. The sentence goes well with B 17: oq
cq vqom]ousi toiaOta pokko_, bj|soi 1cjuqeOsim, oqd lah|mter cim~sjousim,
2yuto?si d doj]ousi. (For many men does not think straight about such
things as they come across, nor do they know after having learned them, but
fancy themselves they do).
67 This implicit imperative Ive modelled after Hesiods formula %joue d_jgr,
heed justice (Erga 213, cf. 275 1p\joue d_jgr ).
10. Heraclitus on Logos 299
ship between things, it operates also as a sort of poetic principle. All this
has to do with the internal physiology of being, thought, language and
action in Heraclitus complex metaphysics. Not only is logos a funda-
mental metaphysical concept, but it is at the centre of Heraclitus
view of man as an ethicaland a politicalbeing.
Bibliography
Adomenas, Mantas.The fluctuating fortunes of Heraclitus in Plato, in A. Laks
and C. Louguet (eds.), Quest-ce que la philosophie prsocratique? / What is Pre-
socratic philosophy (Villeneuve-dAscq 2002) 419 447.
Annas, Julia. Self-knowledge in early Plato, in D. OMeara (ed.), Platonic In-
vestigations (Washington 1985) 111 138.
Barnes, Jonathan. The Presocratic Philosophers. London 1979.
Betegh, Gbor. The limits of the soul: Heraclitus B 45 DK. Its text and inter-
pretation, in E. Hlsz (ed.), Nuevos ensayos sobre Herclito (Mexico City
2009), 391 414.
Burnet, John. Early Greek Philosophy. 4 London 1930.
Capasso, Mario, F. de Martino, F., and P. Rosati (eds.). Studi di filosofia prepla-
tonica. Naples 1985.
Colli, Giorgio. La sapienza greca, III. Eraclito. Milan 1980.
Conche, Marcel. Hraclite. Fragments. Paris 1986.
Diano, Carlo, and G. Serra. Eraclito. I frammenti e le testimonianze. Venice 1980.
Diels, Hermann. Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker. 1 4 Berlin 1903 22.
Herakleitos von Ephesos. 2 Berlin 1909.
Eggers Lan, Conrado. Los filsofos presocrticos. Madrid 1978.
La doctrina heracltea del logos, Nova Tellus 5 (1987) 9 18.
Frnkel, Hermann. A thought pattern in Heraclitus, in A. P. D. Mourelatos
(ed.), The Pre-Socratics. A Collection of Critical Essays (New York 1974)
214 228.
Dichtung und Philosophie des frhen Griechentums. Munich 1962.
Gadamer, Hans-Georg. Der Anfang der Philosophie. Stuttgart 1996 [The Beginning
of Philosophy, English tr. by R. Coltman. New York 1998].
Garca Calvo, Agustn. Razn comn. Edicin crtica, ordenacin, traduccin y comen-
tario de los restos del libro de Heraclito [sic]. Madrid 1985.
Ghidini Tortorelli, Marisa. Limite e circolarit in Eraclito: frr. 45 e 103 D.-
K., in Capasso, de Martino, and Rosati 27 46.
Gigon, Olof. Des Ursprung der griechischen Philosophie. Basel, 1947 [Los orgenes de
la filosofa griega. De Hesodo a Parmnides (Spanish tr. by M. Carrin). Ma-
drid 1980].
Graham, Daniel W. Does nature love to hide? Heraclitus B 123 DK, CP 98
(2003) 175 179.
Hadot, Pierre. Quest-ce que la philosophie antique? Paris 1995.
Heidegger, Martin. Einfhrung in die Metaphysik, in Gesamtausgabe, Band 40.
Frankfurt 1935.
300 Enrique Hlsz
There is a debate that has been going on for the better part of a century
now, as to what Heraclitus utterances about the river are, and what they
mean. The traditional view accepts Diels fragments 12, 49a, and 91 as
different statements about the river, that in general support the view of
Plato, Aristotle, and the ancient tradition that for Heraclitus all things
are in flux like a river, and nothing remains constant. But in 1916 in
a book on Parmenides, Karl Reinhardt argued that a close look at B
12 showed that Heraclitus point was quite different: instead of stressing
the transience of things, he was arguing the constancy of change.1 With
variations, his view has been followed by a number of leading scholars,
including Geoffrey Kirk and Miroslav Marcovich, both of whom accept
only B 12 as a genuine statement of Heraclitus.2 Other scholars, how-
ever, have continued to accept one or both of the other alleged frag-
ments and to defend a radical flux reading.3
As ever, the debate comes down to this: can one, on Heraclitus
view, step twice into the same river? The traditional interpretation
Here are some of the more important statements and reports about the
river:6
T1 [B 12] potalo?si to?sim aqto?sim 1lba_mousim 6teqa ja 6teqa vdata
1piqqe?.
On those stepping into rivers staying the same other and other waters flow.
(Eusebius, Praeparatio Evangelica 15.20; Arius Didymus fr. 39.2)
T2 [A 6] Heraclitus, I believe, says that all things pass and nothing stays, and
comparing existing things to the flow of a river, he says you could not step
twice into the same river [dr 1r tm aqtm potalm oqj #m 1lba_gr] (Plato
Cratylus 402a)
T3 According to Homer, Heraclitus, and all their tribe, all things are in
motion like streams. (Plato Theaetetus 160d)
T4 [Cratylus] finally decided that he could not express any thought in
speech but only wiggled his finger; and he criticized Heraclitus for saying
that it is not possible to step twice into the same river. For he thought it was
not possible to step in even once! (Aristotle Metaphysics 1010a12 15)
T5 [B 49a] potalo?r to?r aqto?r 1lba_mol]m te ja oqj 1lba_molem, eWl]m te
ja oqj eWlem.
Into the same rivers we step and do not step, we are and are not. (Heraclitus
Homericus Homeric Questions 24)
T6 [B 91] (a) It is not possible to step twice into the same river [potal`
cq oqj 5stim 1lb/mai dr t` aqt`] according to Heraclitus, or to come
into contact twice with a mortal being in the same state. But by its swiftness
and speed of change (b) it scatters things and in turn gathers themor rather,
not in turn or later, but at the same time it comes together and separates
approaches and departs. (Plutarch On the E at Delphi 392b)
T7 potalo?r cq dr to?r aqto?r oqj #m 1lba_gr, r vgsim Jq\jkeitor,
6teqa cq 1piqqe? vdata.
Into the same rivers you could not step twice, as Heraclitus says, for other
waters flow on. (Plutarch Natural Questions 912a)
According to Tarn, B 49a (T5) is not a real fragment of Heraclitus, but
only a doublet of B 12 (T1), which restates in more everyday language
what B 12 is saying more profoundly but obscurely (42 3). Tarn also
rejects B 91(b) as alien to Heraclitus message, but accepts B91(a) (T6)
as a genuine fragment, which lies behind statements such as T2, 4, and
7, and has a very different message from B 12 by virtue of adding the
word twice.7
Tarn points out that if we take B 91(a) seriously, Heraclitus is not
saying without restriction that all things pass (A 6) or all things
flow,8 because we can step into the river once at least; hence Heraclitus
defends a kind of measured flux rather than a complete flux (14).9 Fur-
thermore, Plato is stretching his view for his own dialectical purposes
(14 16). Something like B 91(a) has the authority of Plato, Aristotle,
and Cratylus behind it. But with its use of twice and its reference
to the river in the singular rather than the plural, it is highly unlikely
that B 91(a) could be derived from B 12 (16 19).
7 Others, such as Kahn, H. 168 169 also accept B 91(a), and see n. 3 above.
Some of my arguments will apply to all who defend the alleged fragment.
8 A. Lebedev, The Cosmos as a stadium: Agonistic metaphors in Heraclitus,
Phronesis 30 (1985) 143 145, warns against conflating imagery of running
and flowing; but there seems to be some conflation here already.
9 As Plato Tht. 152d-e seems to suggest; in its most extreme interpretation, 182d-
183a.
306 Daniel W. Graham
II
11 Cf. B 34.
308 Daniel W. Graham
would agree that Heraclitus ignorantly falls into the trap of defending a
theory that entails contradictions.15 But however popular, and ancient,
this interpretation may be, it cannot provide a charitable reading of
Heraclitus, inasmuch as self-contradiction is the ultimate philosophical
failure.
Tarn makes one qualification to the traditional interpretation of B
91(a). What kinds of things, he asks, are always changing according to
Heraclitus? Heraclitus must only be thinking of individual things, he an-
swers, not abstract qualities such as Plato sometimes has in mind (49
50). But given that restriction, change for Heraclitus was as universal
as he could imagine, and the river provided a kind of paradigm example
of constant change (50 1). Yet even on this more restricted interpreta-
tion, a contradiction arises within Heraclitus philosophy. For whereas B
91 says that a person cannot step twice into the same river, B 12 says that
a person who steps into the same rivers encounters ever different waters;
but the latter statement surely presupposes or entails that the rivers are
the same. Thus, on Tarns view, B 91 and 12 turn out to be incompat-
ible statements. Curiously, Tarn recognizes this problem early in his
presentation:
[Heraclitus] probably did not realize that, if both the object and the subject
are constantly changing, it would not make sense to say upon those who
step into the same rivers different and different waters flow; one could do
so only if one assumes a stable element not only in the rivers but also in
those who step into them. (11)
Here one awaits some sort of explication that will show how Heraclitus
is not abysmally stupid; but in vain, as Tarn simply moves on to another
topic. Since, by Tarns own account, Heraclitus theory of change has a
universal application, it must apply even to the benighted waders slog-
ging through the river. But according to B 12 the rivers are the same,
and the waders encounter them as such. Not only does B 91 by itself
entail contradiction, but B 91 is incompatible with B 12.
Finally, Tarns defense of B 91(a) (= T6) as an independent text
seems problematic. In considering Plutarchs rendering in T7, he says
Plutarch has conflated B 91 and 12 (45), and tries to explain the con-
flation from the context. But his only real evidence that there is a con-
flation is the difference in language between B 91(a) and T7. Now here
I would like to suggest that we look at T7 without assuming that B 91(a)
T1 = B 12 T7 T6 = B 91(a)
potalo?si to?r potalo?r cq dr to?r aqto?r oqj potal` cq oqj
aqto?sim #m 1lba_gr, 5stim
1lba_mousim (r vgsim Jq\jkeitor), 6teqa cq 1lb/mai dr
6teqa ja 6teqa 1piqqe? vdata. t` aqt`.
vdata 1piqqe?.
In every case the word for river(s) comes first (not the natural word
order in Greek any more than English). In T7, if we leave out the in-
ferential particle gar and the dis of the interpretation (cf. Plato in T2) 16
we have the same three first words as in B 12 (with Attic rather than
Ionic endings),17 then the same fourth word, though in a finite form
rather than a participle; then the same fifth word and (skipping Heracli-
tus duplication and Plutarchs inferential particle) the same last two
words. The most natural supposition here is that in T7 Plutarch is sub-
stituting what he regards as an equivalent expression for the original T1.
If that is so, then he regards B 91(a) as just a stand-in for the first half of
B 12, not an independent and different statement.18 Since Plutarch
knows Heraclitus writings well, and is in a position, as we are not, to
judge whether there are two river fragments or only one, this substitu-
tion offers powerful confirmation for the view that B 91(a) is just a para-
phrase of B 12.19 We could, of course, wonder whether Plutarch had
misread B 91(a) or overlooked its context (whatever that might have
been). T6 shows parallels also, though here river is rendered in the sin-
gular. But now Plutarchs testimony works against Tarns reading and
undermines his claim that there are two independent statements with
different contexts. For lacking direct access to Heraclitus original
manuscript, Plutarch is the best witness we have for the relation of
the two alleged fragments. He gives a close paraphrase in T7 and a
loose paraphrase in T6; but T7 just is T1 with some inferential particles
III
The simplest hypothesis concerning the river fragments is, I believe, that
there is only one, B 12, of which B 91(a), no less than B 49a, is a para-
phrase. But there is one thing wanting for a convincing case, namely
that we be able to show for B 91(a), as Tarn has for B49a, how an in-
telligent reader could misconstrue it so badly as to turn it into a state-
ment that you cannot step twice into the same river. Against the as-
sumption that there are plural river fragments, I hope I have shown
that the alleged fragments other than B 12 are too much like B 12, as
well as too contradictory of it.
Can we, then, reconstruct a plausible account of how B 12 might
have come to be read as B 91(a) and A 6? Marcovich rightly argues
that Cratylus and those who read B 12 as he does must take embainousin
as iterative in force: every time someone steps into the river, different
waters flow.20 Cratylus must also have focused on hetera kai hetera to
the exclusion of toisin autoisin. Then he can claim that each initial
step into the river is a step into different waters. This would be an in-
teresting interpretation, but a hasty one. For since Heraclitus expressly
states that the rivers are the same, it really does not matter for the iden-
tity of the rivers that the waters are different. Nor, in fact, does it matter
whether we think of the entry into the rivers as repeated (iterative) or
ongoing (progressive); in either case the rivers are the same. Tarn ob-
20 Marcovich, H. 206.
312 Daniel W. Graham
jects to Marcovichs reading: why single out merely the action of en-
tering the river and disregard the role of the observer once he is inside
the river? This would unnecessarily restrict the universal validity of the
river-statement in B 12 (33). But this reply will not do. First, it does
not really matter what stage of the river-crossing Heraclitus is talking
about: the truth that the waters are always changing and the rivers stay-
ing the same still applies. Second, this interpretation does not really re-
strict the universality of the statement. Finally, to complain that the role
of the observer is being ignored begs the question, since it is only on
Tarns interpretation that the waders observations make any difference.
Tarn thinks that since Plato and Aristotle most likely had access to
Heraclitus text, they could not be so mistaken in their reading of Hera-
clitus as to miss his point. Yet recent studies have shown how conven-
tional ancient interpretations could be. Not only did the doxographical
tradition perpetuate demonstrably incorrect readings of the Presocratics,
but there was a kind of proto-doxographical tradition that began with
the sophists, and which tended to get recycled and repeated by Plato,
Aristotle, and other early readers of the Presocratics.21 It is quite possible
that Cratylus reading, which likely influenced Platos, came from an
earlier interpreter, namely Hippias of Elis in his Sunagog. 22 And Aristo-
tles reading continues that of Cratylus and Plato without so much as a
notice that they could be wrong (T4). If the interpretation given above
of Plutarch is correct, we see in Plutarch how a scholar with access to
Heraclitus text could read it without noticing the discrepancy between
something like A6 and the actual words of Heraclitus.
It appears from the verbal similarities among the three alleged frag-
ments, from the messages they convey and the settings in which they are
reproduced, that we can account for all other statements about the river
on the basis of B 12 alone. As for Tarns reading of B 12, that seems
unpromising at best. Tarn makes a good deal of the context of the
two alleged fragments he recognizes, and he does a good job of rejecting
the context in which B 12 was quoted. But when all is said and done,
that simply means that in fact we have no context for B 12. We must, as
21 B. Snell, Die Nachrichten ber die Lehren des Thales und die Anfnge der
griechischen Philosophie- und Literaturgeschichte, Philologus 96 (1944)
170 82; J. Mansfeld, Studies in the Historiography of Greek Philosophy (Assen
1990) 126 146 et passim.
22 Mansfeld (above, n. 21) 84 96; A. Patzer, Der Sophist Hippias als Philosophiehis-
toriker (Freiburg 1986) 33 42, 49 55.
11. Once More unto the Stream 313
it were, infer the context from the meaning of the fragment and not vice
versa. It is, indeed, possible, as one prominent view of Heraclitus text
would have it, that there is no extended argument in the book in any
case, but rather a collection of epigrams and riddles.23 If that is so,
even having the original book would not necessarily provide an illumi-
nating context for the meaning of the fragment. In any case, we do not
have the original sequence in which B 12 appeared, and hence the
whole issue of the context is an exercise in futility.
Fortunately, the fragment is complex in structure and rich in impli-
cations, and this very fact speaks both for its being a genuine quotation,
and for its being in a certain sense an autonomous text that can be ap-
preciated in the absence of a discursive context. In this interpretation I
follow especially Kahn, but also Kirk and Marcovich, and leave for an-
other occasion questions of the connection between this fragment and
Heraclitus larger message.
The major contrast in the fragment is between what is the same and
what is other. It is given by the words of the text that the rivers are the
same, the waters are other. The changing waters of the river flow onto
the people fording them. Accordingly, ever different waters from the
same rivers flow onto people who ford them. This is the obvious reading,
if anything in Heraclitus can be said to be obvious. But there is another
reading. The term toisin autoisin the same is sandwiched between pota-
moisi and embainousin, and it agrees not only with the former (masculine
dative plural), but also with the latter. In fact, as Kahn points out, Hera-
clitus has gone to a good deal of trouble to create this (syntactical) ambi-
guity, since any one of a number of changes could avoid it (changing the
word order, making one term singular, different word choice, etc.).24 And
indeed Heraclitus seems to favor putting an ambiguous term between two
possible referents.25 Let us, then, construe toisin autoisin with embainousin:
other waters flow onto the same people stepping into rivers. Again there
23 This was Diels view, embodied in his scheme of numbering the fragments al-
phabetically by source. Kahn, H., looks for a more coherent exposition, also
defended by Barnes (above, n. 3), but the view is opposed by H. Granger, Ar-
gumentation and Heraclitus book, OSAP 26 (2004) 1 17.
24 Rivier (above, n. 2) first called attention to the ambiguity, and argued that it
should be eliminated by deleting 1lba_mousim, which he argued was inserted
by a later editor.
25 E.g., B 1, 119, 51; see Graham, Heraclitus and Parmenides, in V. Caston and
D. W. Graham (eds.), Presocratic Philosophy: Essays in Honour of Alexander Mour-
elatos (Aldershot 2002) 35 37.
314 Daniel W. Graham
is a contrast between the same and other. But this time what is said to
remain the same are the persons fording the river. Curiously, we get pre-
cisely the opposite sense from that envisaged by Cratylus (and Plato and
Aristotle and Plutarch ), stressing the fact that the same action cannot be
repeated twice because of radical flux. To the contrary, the people who
encounter the river stay the same (on one reading); and the rivers they
encounter (on another reading) also stay the same. There is a flux here
(other and other waters), but the consequences of the flux are not chaotic
non-identity, but, surprisingly, some sort of continuity and hence identity
through time.
At least one more feature needs to be noted in the interpretation,
again following Kahn: by putting the first four words of the statement
in the dative plural, Heraclitus paints with sound. He creates the sounds
of a bubbling river, which, in the second clause seems to speed up and
hurry off in a series of alliterations. Heraclitus is a poet as well as a phi-
losopher, even if he does not confine himself to the conventional
rhythms of Greek poetry.
IV
26 Some have wished to find the context in Arius Didymus. On this, see above, n.
10.
11. Once More unto the Stream 315
31 Kahn, H. 89. See also a recent study using Kahns assumptions, Gianvittorio
(above, n. 10).
32 Kahn, H. ibid.
33 Which Gianvittorio (above, n. 10), ch. 2, explores as reti di significazione.
318 Daniel W. Graham
the expression of systematic order in nature. No less real than the con-
stant exchange of hot and cold, wet and dry, earth, water, and fire is the
constant replacement of what is lost by a new supply, drawn from what
is lost of the contrary stuff. The world needs constant flux and inter-
change at the level of material, on which a hidden law operates to main-
tain balance. The cosmos is an ever-living fire precisely because it lives
in its own transformation of opposites; it stays the same as it changes.35
There is one way that Heraclitus theory is profoundly different
from that of all other early philosophers of nature. Whereas they attempt
to explain change in terms of constant realities and their modifications,
Heraclitus attempts to explain constancy in terms of ongoing change.
Whereas in some metaphysical sense they are all philosophers of stasis,
for whom (especially from Parmenides on) stability is fundamental
and change problematic, Heraclitus is a philosopher of process, for
whom change is fundamental and stability problematic. But if he is a
process philosopher, he is not a nihilist or an epistemological or onto-
logical anarchist. His world is orderly through and through, the forces
balanced, the elements proportionate, the cosmos stable. Like a river.36
Bibliography
Barnes, Jonathan. The Presocratic Philosophers. Revised ed. London 1982 [1979].
Bollack, Jean, and Heinz Wismann. Hraclite: ou la sparation. Paris 1972.
Buck, Carl Darling. The Greek Dialects. Chicago 1955.
Colvin, Matthew. Heraclitus and material flux in Stoic psychology, OSAP
28 (2005) 257 72.
Conche, Marcel. Hraclite: fragments. Paris 1986.
Emlyn-Jones, C. J. Heraclitus and the unity of opposites, Phronesis 21 (1976)
89 114.
Furth, Montgomery. Substance, Form and Psyche: An Aristotelian Metaphysics.
Cambridge 1988.
Gemelli Marciano, Laura. Die Vorsokratiker. 3 vols. Dsseldorf 2007 09.
Gianvittorio, Laura. Il discorso di Eraclito: un modello semantico e cosmologico nel pas-
saggio dall oralit alla scrittura. Spudasmata 134. Hildesheim 2010.
Graham, Daniel W. Heraclitus criticism of Ionian philosophy, OSAP 15
(1997) 1 50.
he assumes without argument that Heraclitus ethics were very much those of
the ruling class of his native Ephesos, which entails that Heraclitus never devel-
oped an ethical system of his own. Cf. too M. Adomenas, Heraclitus on reli-
gion, Phronesis 44 (1999) 109, who refers to Heraclitus antipopulist ethics.
This will be disputed below.
3 R. Bolton, Nature and human good in Heraclitus, in K. I. Boudouris (ed.),
Ionian Philosophy (Athens 1989) 49 57; J.W. Evans, Heraclitus and Parmenides as
Moral Philosophers, diss. Yale 1970. Bolton approaches Heraclitus ethics via the
notion of natural law as it would have incorporated Heraclitus idea of physis.
Placing Heraclitus broadly in an early form of the nomos/physis controversy,
Bolton relies most heavily on B 114 nm m|\ k]comtar Qswuq_feshai wq t`
num` p\mtym . tq]vomtai cq p\mter oR !mhq~peioi m|loi rp 2mr, toO
he_ou. From this, along with some other supporting texts, Bolton reasonably
concludes not only that is there a natural (because divine) law, but also that
men can access it and trust in it. Note also B 116 !mhq~poisi psi l]testi
cim~sjeim 2yutor ja syvqome?m, where self-knowledge is coupled with so-
phronein (54). Bolton then offers some criticisms that could be brought to
bear, but his article remains a good place to start. Evans more comprehensive
treatment argues that Heraclitus ethical views are inseparably entwined with
his cosmology and metaphysics (39).
M. Fattal, Paroles et actes chez Hraclite: Sur les fondements thoriques de laction
morale (Paris 2012), appeared as this article was on the point of submission to
the publishers.
12. Heraclitus Ethics 323
4 The Greek is a iambic trimeter, with its caesura preceding the fourth rather than
the third princeps. Since grammatikoi were teachers, Diodotus may have com-
posed verses to serve as mnemonic aids for his students. For a recent discovery
of a teachers verses directed to his students, see R. Cribiore, D. Ratzen, & P.
Davoli, A teachers dipinto from Trimithis (Dakhleh Oasis), Journal of Roman
Archaeology 21 (2008): 170 91.
5 Note how Aristotle in his Ethics, although coming to grips with Plato in EN
1.6, does not provide in this work the same sort of overview of presocratic
or sophistic thought on the subject that he does in his Physics and Metaphysics.
6 The reading of the codd., printed here, is not easy to construe, and has been
frequently altered:
ja cm~lom( Ah_m, <ja jakm> j|slom tq|pym 2m|r te sulp\mtym Diels;
ja cm~lom( Ah_m, <toO h( fkou> j|slou tq|pim 2m|r te sulp\mtym te
Hicks.
324 David Sider
7 The main problem lies in the phrase !p toO sum]womtor. The related adjective
sumew]r is regularly applied to continous words, phrases, etc. (LSJ s.v. I 2).
The verb, however, does not seem to be used in this sense, but perhaps its
basic sense of embrace, comprise, hold together can suggest a translation of
the phrase as from that which holds the work together as a whole, i. e.,
that physis is a constant topic throughout the work.
8 K. Deichgrber, Bemerkungen zu Diogenes Bericht ber Heraklit, Philologus
93 (1938 39) 19. The remaining parts are dialectic, rhetoric, and ethics (D.L.
7.41), the last of which, as I have suggested, may have been too hard to distin-
guish from politics in Heraclitus writings. On the other hand, R. Hirzel, Un-
tersuchungen zu Ciceros philosophischer Schriften (Leipzig 1882) 2.70 178, argued
that Cleanthes six-part division was an expansion of that which he found in
Heraclitus. See further, Dilcher, H. 188 189.
12. Heraclitus Ethics 325
been segregated later into the theological and the physical parts, respec-
tively.
II
Orchomenus and Etna, respectively) would have had a more limited fame soon
after composition.
11 See Graham in this volume.
12 See D. Sider, Word order and sense in Heraclitus: Fragment One and the river
fragment, in K. Boudouris (ed.), Ionian Philosophy (Athens 1989) 363-368.
13 As Marcovich ad loc. notes, Heraclitus original words are open to doubt, since
this reasonable reconstruction from the several citators forms, less one initial syl-
lable (e. g., 5sh( Marc.), an iambic tetrameter. Scythinus versification may have
supplanted the original, which itself may well have had a metrical clausula. In
this case, taking note of the fact that several witnesses insert the phrase !mt pok-
k_m, we may entertain the notion not only that this phrase was original, but also
that B 29, with 6m, !mt_, and %qistoi, originally appeared very close to, and in
obvious contrast to, B 49.
14 Serge Mouraviev, Heraclitea III.1: Recensio: Memoria (Sankt Augustin 2003)
124 126, has argued for placing Heraclitus death as late as 460, but this has
been criticized by Aryeh Finkelberg in his review of this volume, SCI 25
(2006) 151. For the inconsistent testimony, see further Jaap Mansfeld, The
12. Heraclitus Ethics 327
lieve to be the caseit seems to more likely that Heraclitus was re-
sponding to Simonides (and the favorable reaction his poem no doubt
received in Ephesus) than the reverse.15 Read this way, Ephesus
best are in fact not the best, and Heraclitus would be playing on
words in a way that becomes more familiar later in the fifth century.16
On the surface, where The Best are to see nothing but a compliment,
hmgt_m has been taken as masculine with an understood pq|r, by
men; or neuter with a somewhat more easily understood !mt_, instead
of mortal things. I am happy with either of these (or both) as the sur-
face meaning, but, keeping the underlying pejorative meaning in mind,
we can also understand it as a simple causative genitive: The [soi-disant]
Best choose an ever-changing reputation (kleos) for mortal things.
The entire fragment has always been read as if the two clauses were
in complete contrast, although there is in fact no evidence for a l]m in
the first clause. Thus, instead of a contrast between the upper and lower
classes, as is usually understood, the second clause, following the first as
explained above, can now be rendered and the majority [sc. of them,
the aristoi] glut themselves like cattle. In other words, Heraclitean eth-
ics loves to hide. oR %qistoi are not in fact %qistoi, and some of them are
no better than oR pokko_, the people they generally despise. Thus, al-
though Heraclitus may not be a friend of oR pokko_, neither is he to
be taken as a staunch defender of the upper classes. More on this later.
Along the same lines, but somewhat more obvious is B 28 doj]omta
b dojil~tator cim~sjei vuk\sseim,17 the person whose doxa is greatest
knows how to hold on to his beliefs, which also admits of both com-
plimentary and pejorative interpretations, depending on whether doxa
means ones own judgement (cf. Parm. B 1.30, which also combines
d|nar and dojoOmta, along with doj_lyr; 8.51) or the judgement in
which one is held by others, i. e., fame (cf. Sol. 13.4, 34 and CEG
396 [vi c. BC] dr d ( Qm %mhqpoir d|nam 5weim !cahm, Grant that
chronology of Anaxagoras Athenian period and the date of his trial, Mnemo-
syne 32 (1979) 68 69.
15 Another close echo between the two is the phrase vbqim sbemm}mai (Her. B 43 &
Simonides 3 PMG), which could go in either direction, if in fact each is not
independently elaborating on the Homeric phrases s. w|kom and s. l]mor.
16 Cf., e. g., Euripides Ba. 395 t sovm oq sov_a, which in thought returns us to
Heraclitus B 40 poukulah_a m|om oq did\sjei, as was noticed by Sandys ad Eur.
Ba. 395. Note also Thuc. 3.82.4 7 on how words changed meaning.
17 My text remains as close to the mss. as possible; for cicm~sjy + inf., cf. Soph.
Ant. 1089 cm` tq]veim, learn how to.
328 David Sider
III
what even may be regarded as opposites. Since this logos (see in partic-
ular B 1) seems to be all inclusive, it should, if Heraclitus is to be con-
sistent, serve to frame an ethical theory as well. It comes as no surprise,
therefore, that here too Heraclitus is fond of associating, or rather equat-
ing, what ordinary people think of as opposites.
Should the good man be just, as might seeem obvious in a pre-
Sophistic age? Heraclitus, at least at first glance, seems to be saying
something otherwise: Origen C.Cels. 6.42 (B 80) eQd]<mai> d wq
tm p|kelom 1|mta num|m, ja d_jgm 5qim, ja cim|lema p\mta jat( 5qim
ja wqe~m, it is necessary to know that war is universal and justice is
strife; and that everything comes about in accord with strife and neces-
sity.23 Men may want to throw up their hands at trying to deal with
such an universe, but, as Pangloss might put it, t` lm he` jak
p\mta ja !cah ja d_jaia, %mhqypoi d $ lm %dija rpeik^vasim $
d d_jaia (Porphyry Qu.Hom. ad Il. 4.4 = B 102). Gods, that is, recog-
nize that what men may choose to call strife and justice are in fact sub-
sumed under the latter, which comprises the former as well, much as (in
Greek and other languages) day (the 24-hour cycle) comprises day (the
hours of sunlight) and night.24
If so, mankind too may divide into two camps, comparable to day/
night and justice/strife. The best man and the fool (bk\n, B 87)25 have,
though, more than humanity in common; they are also united by their
city wall as well as by the more abstract civil nomos. D.L. 9.1 (B 44)
l\weshai wq tm d/lom rpq toO m|lou fjyspeq te_weor should prob-
ably not to be taken as an aristocratic statement (as Marcovich does
without argument), but as a more comprehensive one that does not dis-
tinguish social classes, all of whom are protected the one law and the
one wall. The wall, though, solidly visible and fixed in place, has a
23 The necessity of knowing what comes about through necessity makes for
an interesting rhetorical and epistemological kyklos. On this fragment, see fur-
ther Evans (above, n. 3) 41.
24 And in biological terminology, man (the species) comprises man (the gender)
and woman, which allows for an article such as T. McKeown and R. G. Re-
cord, Observations on foetal growth in multiple pregnancy in man, Journal of
Endocrinology 8 (1952) 386 401; cf. the occasional B %mhqypor. It is interesting,
but ultimately not very helpful, to compare Heraclitus statements about
wholes, parts, and opposites with those of Aristotle about universals, partic-
ulars, and negations; cf., e. g., Int. 20a16 31.
25 What Heraclitus thinks about foolish men is nicely surveyed by Dilcher, H. 18
26.
12. Heraclitus Ethics 331
26 Thus it is the m|lor which constitutes a city so that it is more than just an as-
sembly of people. It shapes the behaviour of the individuals and so makes a true
unity (Dilcher, H. 49 f.). P. Wheelwright, Heraclitus (Princeton 1959) 88, of-
fers a semireligious idea of Heraclitus city wall which nicely complements the
one offered here: It is a kind of magical encirclement, representing and guar-
anteeing some kind of supernatural protection. See also Evans (above, n. 3)
16 f., who puts B 44 into the larger context of Heraclitus statements about
nomos.
27 Heraclitus somewhat maliciously has the Ephesians indulge in rhetorical over-
kill, as if more than one person could be the the most (of anything).
332 David Sider
other person or group rather than ones own, although I would not want
absolutely to exclude the latter.28
The thrust of B 114, therefore, is for intelligent men to direct their
speech towards the best, in large part because divinely guided, political
activity. As is shown by B 2, that which is common is the logos, aware-
ness of which directs men to live better lives: Sext. Emp. adv.math. 7.133
di de? 6peshai t` num`, toO k|cou d( 1|mtor numoO f~ousim oR pokko
r Qd_am 5womter vq|mgsim. Taken together, then, B 44, 114, and 2 make
a strong case for living an ethical life.29 That is, the fragments we have
looked at are designed to direct mens actions, the 5qca mentioned in B
1, of which some men are ignorant.30
Once again, it seems that, although Heraclitus was born into the
aristocracy, he clearly was not prepared to defend each and every mem-
ber of that class, certainly not those who banished Hermodorus (B 121),
who had been a moloh]tgr for the Ephesians.31 It is even more notewor-
thy that Heraclitus did not despise the lower classes. He seems, in fact, to
have argued that everybody has the same potential for intellectual en-
lightenment: Stob. 3.5.6 (B 116) !mhq~poisi psi l]testi cim~sjeim
2yutor ja syvqome?m and Stob. 3.1.179 (B 113) num|m 1sti psi t
vqom]eim. These are, for Heraclitus time, remarkable statements. What
Heraclitus demanded of himself (cf. Plut. adv. Col. 1118c = B 101 1di-
fgs\lgm 1leyut|m, I examined myself),32 and what he regarded as the
greatest virtue, sophrosyne (see above, on B 112), are open to everybody.
28 An internal hybris would fit well with B 85 hul` l\weshai wakep|m. Arguing
for external hybris is, e. g., C. Diano and G. Serra, Eraclito: I frammenti e le tes-
timonianze (Milan 1980) 186 f., and Marcovich, H. 532 (against Kirk and Ver-
denius), who, however, following his usual line, adducing Theognis, argues that
the hybris is that of the demos alone.
29 Marcovich, in fact, combines B 114 and 2 to produce his fragment 23. It should
also be noted that in these and other fragments Heraclitus does not hesitate to
tell men what they ought to do, which is the hallmark of the ethicist as opposed
to a dispassionate observer of human behavior: wq^ in B 35 (of doubtful authen-
ticity, however), 43, 44, 80, 114; de? in B 2; and %niom in B 121.
30 B 1 (in part) !pe_qoisem 1o_jasi peiq~lemoi ja 1p]ym ja 5qcym toio}tym
bjo_ym digceOlai.
31 For what little testimony there is on Hermodorus, see Mouraviev (above, n. 13)
16 f. An untrustworthy account (Pomponius ap. Digest. 1.2.2.4, Plin. NH
34.21) has Hermodorus advising the first decemvirate in the mid-fifth century,
which would suggest that he was a contemporary of Heraclitus.
32 Which in fact Plutarch and others immediately link to the Delphic cm_hi sau-
t|m. Marcovichs I asked myself and his rejection of the usual meaning are
12. Heraclitus Ethics 333
This helps to explain his anger at fools: they had the chance but re-
jected it. Hence too his attitude towards children, which also is relevant
to his ethical theory. Note Hippol. 9.9.3 4 (B 52) aQm pa?r 1sti pa_fym,
pesse}ym paidr B basikg_g, human life is a child playing childish
games; to the child belongs the power of a king.33 It is not that an
adult should act like a child; quite the reversecf. Celsius ap. Orig.
C.Cels. 6.12 (B 79) !mq m^pior Ejouse pqr da_lomor fjyspeq pa?r
pqr !mdq|r, but in each child is the hope and the potential to be
the one, the best, whose bouk^ will be followed by the city. Children,
however, should not learn from or be influenced by their childish parents:
Marc. Aur. 4.46 (B 74) oq de? pa?dar toje~mym, children should not be
of their parents; that is, they should think and act for themselves, since
parents corrupt their children.34 Note the assumption of childhood inno-
cence in Strabo 14.25 (B 121) %niom 9ves_oir Bbgdm !p\cnashai psi
ja to?r !m^boir tm p|kim jatakipe?m, Hang the Ephesians and leave
the city to the boysboys, by the way, who are capable of leading
their tipsy elders when they have lost their way: Stob. 3.5.7 (B 117)
!mq bj|tam lehush0, %cetai rp paidr !m^bou svakk|lemor, oqj
1pa@ym fjg ba_mei, surely not a sentence meant to be limited to its literal
meaning.
Heraclitus ethics, then, is inextricably linked to his epistemology and
politics. His urging everyone to exercize ones own logos in order to recog-
nize the external logos of the cosmos entails a ethical and political scheme in
which one is persuaded by the one best person, who can only be the one
who exercises this capacity best. An intellectualist theory of ethics, to be
sure, and, further, one that should remind us of that found later in Plato,
especially in the Republic, where also is expressed the extreme view that
it might be advisable to rid the city of adults and start from scratch with
the young, who are to be guided by the best, i. e., most philosophical, citi-
zen. It would be a gross methodological mistake to argue that because the
Bibliography
35 The rather large literature on Platos use and reminiscence of Heraclitus, none
of which will be cited here, concentrates almost entirely on epistemological and
cosmological matters.
Contributors
Gbor Betegh is Professor of Philosophy at the Central European Uni-
versity, Budapest. He has published primarily on ancient natural philo-
sophy, metaphysics, and theology. He is the author of The Derveni Papy-
rus: Cosmology, Theology and Interpretation (2004).
David Sider teaches at New York University and writes on Greek po-
etry and philosophy, especially when they overlap, such as in Empedo-
cles, Parmenides, Plato, Philodemus, and in didactic poetry in general.
He has edited The Fragments of Anaxagoras (second edition, 2005), The
Epigrams of Philodemos (1997), and Theophrastus On Weather Signs (2007).
253, 263 265, 273, 282, 292, Races of men 157, 159, 190 191
315 316, 319, 330 see also Unity Ratio 9 10, 12 16, 21, 62, 80 81,
of opposites 116 117, 124, 126 127, 137
Orpheus, Orphics 40, 159 160, 168 140, 202 203, 208 209, 213
n.10, 166, 168 169, 189, 196, 214, 296
258 259 Riddles 252 n.60, 266 267, 269
72
Rivers 287, ch. 11 passim, 326, 329
Pak_mtqopor, pak_mtomor 125
Parmenides 3 n.1, 15, 22, 26, 30, 45,
67, 180, 216 217, 222, 275, 278, Separation 21, 26, 136, 245
319 Simmias 44, 76
Paron 39 40 Simonides 325 327
Petron 39 40 Sleep 123, 151, 153, 155, 190 191,
238, 245 246, 276, 284 285,
Phaethon 58, 193
289 n.26, 291, 306 307
Phanton 43
Solon 218 220
Pherecydes of Syrus 165 167, 169,
Sophocles 188 189, 251
174 n.16, 183 Soul 58, 61, 79 81, 85, 90 92, 95,
Philo of Alexandria 237 97, 114 116, 123, ch. 5 passim,
Philolaos 3 4, 6 7, 13, 15 n.31, 20 168 169, 80, 189 190, 206,
n.44, 22 25, 35 39, 43 44, 47, 208 211, 215 216, ch. 8 passim,
53 54, 56 57, 59, 66 67, 69 274 275, 292 298, 306, 329
77, 98 99, 101 112, 118 119, Speusippus 18 n.39, 34, 94 n.98
ch.4 passim Spintharus 44
Philoponus 255 Symbola 34, 49 50
Philosophy, nature of 281 282 Stoics, Stoicism 149, 152 n.12, 203
Phintias 36 n.3, 204, 229 n.9, 236, 245 247,
Pindar 151 n.8, 216, 218, 252, 325 258 260, 276, 289 nn.24, 27, 306
n.10, 326, 328 n.10, 324
V}sir see Nature Style, prose 115, 161, 167 n.7, 176
Plato 19 20, 23, 24 n.52, 25 26, 182, 185, 190 191, 195, 222,
39, 46 47, 55, 63, 94, 102, 107, 227, 230, 266 267, 285 n.11,
118, 136 138, 155, 157, 165, 168 293, 313 314, 317
n.9, 196 n.58, 201, 205 214, 218, S_la-s/la 155 156, 160, 207
222, 232, 248, 280, 282, 284, 303, n.12, 247 see also Body
305, 308 309, 312, 318, 322, 328 Syvqos}mg 294, n.42, 329, 332 see
n.19, 333 334 also Measure
Platonism 20 n.43, 21, 25
Plotinus 155 n.16 Tetraktys 3 n.1, 29
Plutarch 22, 24 25, 150 151, 157 Taboos 48 50
158, 309 312, 332 n.32 Tarn, L. 304 312
Polyclitus 40 Theagenes of Rhegium 196
Polymnastes 43 Theodoret 157, 328
Polytheism 169, 176, 191 Theodorus of Cyrene 36, 39, 42, 47
Pythagoreans chs. 1 3 passim, 123 Theogony, rhapsodic 168 n.10
124, 136, 167, 168 nn.9 10, 195 Timaeus of Locri 40
196 Tqopa_ 125
General Index 343
Parmenides Plutarch
B 1.30 327 E ap. Delph. 392b 305
7.5 217 Is. 362a-b 153 n.14
8.34 6 22 Qu.Nat. 912a 305
Qu.Conv. 718e 24
Pherecydes v.Rom. 28.8 157
B1 165
2 166 Porphyry
In Ptol.Harm. 1.3 23
Philo
Aet.Mund. 21 237 n.30 Proclus
In Resp. 2.20.23 155
Philolaus
A 29 14 15 Sextus Empiricus
B1 67 AM 7.126 15 n.29
2 67, 127, 132 7.127 30 151, 245
3 67 Pyrrh. 3.230 159
4 22, 68
5 68, 126 Simonides
6 68, 128, 130, 133 531 PMG 325
137, 139
6a 127, 129, 139 Solon
7 68, 73, 129 1 West 218
17 68 69 16 218, 219
17 218
Pindar
P. 3.61 2 251 Sophocles
N. 3.40 328 Ant. 559 60 251
I. 6.71 2 218 1089 327 n.17
Fr. 131b S-M 157
Stobaeus
Plato 1.49.32.104 259
Gorg. 507e-508a 206
525a 208 Theodoret
Lg. 715e-16b 211 Gr.Aff.Cur. 5.18 237 n.29
716c-d2 212 11.7 328 n.18
Phdo. 86c 210 n.15
108c 210 n.15 Theognis
Phdr. 249c 24 1171 2 219
270c 226 227
Resp. 339b 210 n.15 Thucydides
412a 210 1.114.1 92
431b-c 210
466b 210 n.15 Vettius Valens
528a-d 25 317.19 Pingree 259
Index Locorum Potiorum 349
David Sider teaches at New York University and writes on Greek po-
etry and philosophy, especially when they overlap, such as in Empedo-
cles, Parmenides, Plato, Philodemus, and in didactic poetry in general.
He has edited The Fragments of Anaxagoras (second edition, 2005), The
Epigrams of Philodemos (1997), and Theophrastus On Weather Signs (2007).
253, 263 265, 273, 282, 292, Races of men 157, 159, 190 191
315 316, 319, 330 see also Unity Ratio 9 10, 12 16, 21, 62, 80 81,
of opposites 116 117, 124, 126 127, 137
Orpheus, Orphics 40, 159 160, 168 140, 202 203, 208 209, 213
n.10, 166, 168 169, 189, 196, 214, 296
258 259 Riddles 252 n.60, 266 267, 269
72
Rivers 287, ch. 11 passim, 326, 329
Pak_mtqopor, pak_mtomor 125
Parmenides 3 n.1, 15, 22, 26, 30, 45,
67, 180, 216 217, 222, 275, 278, Separation 21, 26, 136, 245
319 Simmias 44, 76
Paron 39 40 Simonides 325 327
Petron 39 40 Sleep 123, 151, 153, 155, 190 191,
238, 245 246, 276, 284 285,
Phaethon 58, 193
289 n.26, 291, 306 307
Phanton 43
Solon 218 220
Pherecydes of Syrus 165 167, 169,
Sophocles 188 189, 251
174 n.16, 183 Soul 58, 61, 79 81, 85, 90 92, 95,
Philo of Alexandria 237 97, 114 116, 123, ch. 5 passim,
Philolaos 3 4, 6 7, 13, 15 n.31, 20 168 169, 80, 189 190, 206,
n.44, 22 25, 35 39, 43 44, 47, 208 211, 215 216, ch. 8 passim,
53 54, 56 57, 59, 66 67, 69 274 275, 292 298, 306, 329
77, 98 99, 101 112, 118 119, Speusippus 18 n.39, 34, 94 n.98
ch.4 passim Spintharus 44
Philoponus 255 Symbola 34, 49 50
Philosophy, nature of 281 282 Stoics, Stoicism 149, 152 n.12, 203
Phintias 36 n.3, 204, 229 n.9, 236, 245 247,
Pindar 151 n.8, 216, 218, 252, 325 258 260, 276, 289 nn.24, 27, 306
n.10, 326, 328 n.10, 324
V}sir see Nature Style, prose 115, 161, 167 n.7, 176
Plato 19 20, 23, 24 n.52, 25 26, 182, 185, 190 191, 195, 222,
39, 46 47, 55, 63, 94, 102, 107, 227, 230, 266 267, 285 n.11,
118, 136 138, 155, 157, 165, 168 293, 313 314, 317
n.9, 196 n.58, 201, 205 214, 218, S_la-s/la 155 156, 160, 207
222, 232, 248, 280, 282, 284, 303, n.12, 247 see also Body
305, 308 309, 312, 318, 322, 328 Syvqos}mg 294, n.42, 329, 332 see
n.19, 333 334 also Measure
Platonism 20 n.43, 21, 25
Plotinus 155 n.16 Tetraktys 3 n.1, 29
Plutarch 22, 24 25, 150 151, 157 Taboos 48 50
158, 309 312, 332 n.32 Tarn, L. 304 312
Polyclitus 40 Theagenes of Rhegium 196
Polymnastes 43 Theodoret 157, 328
Polytheism 169, 176, 191 Theodorus of Cyrene 36, 39, 42, 47
Pythagoreans chs. 1 3 passim, 123 Theogony, rhapsodic 168 n.10
124, 136, 167, 168 nn.9 10, 195 Timaeus of Locri 40
196 Tqopa_ 125
General Index 343
Parmenides Plutarch
B 1.30 327 E ap. Delph. 392b 305
7.5 217 Is. 362a-b 153 n.14
8.34 6 22 Qu.Nat. 912a 305
Qu.Conv. 718e 24
Pherecydes v.Rom. 28.8 157
B1 165
2 166 Porphyry
In Ptol.Harm. 1.3 23
Philo
Aet.Mund. 21 237 n.30 Proclus
In Resp. 2.20.23 155
Philolaus
A 29 14 15 Sextus Empiricus
B1 67 AM 7.126 15 n.29
2 67, 127, 132 7.127 30 151, 245
3 67 Pyrrh. 3.230 159
4 22, 68
5 68, 126 Simonides
6 68, 128, 130, 133 531 PMG 325
137, 139
6a 127, 129, 139 Solon
7 68, 73, 129 1 West 218
17 68 69 16 218, 219
17 218
Pindar
P. 3.61 2 251 Sophocles
N. 3.40 328 Ant. 559 60 251
I. 6.71 2 218 1089 327 n.17
Fr. 131b S-M 157
Stobaeus
Plato 1.49.32.104 259
Gorg. 507e-508a 206
525a 208 Theodoret
Lg. 715e-16b 211 Gr.Aff.Cur. 5.18 237 n.29
716c-d2 212 11.7 328 n.18
Phdo. 86c 210 n.15
108c 210 n.15 Theognis
Phdr. 249c 24 1171 2 219
270c 226 227
Resp. 339b 210 n.15 Thucydides
412a 210 1.114.1 92
431b-c 210
466b 210 n.15 Vettius Valens
528a-d 25 317.19 Pingree 259
Index Locorum Potiorum 349