Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

From $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

Thinking of Others: On the Talent for Metaphor
Thinking of Others: On the Talent for Metaphor
Thinking of Others: On the Talent for Metaphor
Ebook119 pages1 hour

Thinking of Others: On the Talent for Metaphor

Rating: 3.5 out of 5 stars

3.5/5

()

Read preview

About this ebook

In Thinking of Others, Ted Cohen argues that the ability to imagine oneself as another person is an indispensable human capacity--as essential to moral awareness as it is to literary appreciation--and that this talent for identification is the same as the talent for metaphor. To be able to see oneself as someone else, whether the someone else is a real person or a fictional character, is to exercise the ability to deal with metaphor and other figurative language. The underlying faculty, Cohen argues, is the same--simply the ability to think of one thing as another when it plainly is not.


In an engaging style, Cohen explores this idea by examining various occasions for identifying with others, including reading fiction, enjoying sports, making moral arguments, estimating one's future self, and imagining how one appears to others. Using many literary examples, Cohen argues that we can engage with fictional characters just as intensely as we do with real people, and he looks at some of the ways literature itself takes up the question of interpersonal identification and understanding.


An original meditation on the necessity of imagination to moral and aesthetic life, Thinking of Others is an important contribution to philosophy and literary theory.

LanguageEnglish
Release dateJan 14, 2009
ISBN9781400828951
Thinking of Others: On the Talent for Metaphor

Read more from Ted Cohen

Related to Thinking of Others

Titles in the series (22)

View More

Related ebooks

Philosophy For You

View More

Related articles

Related categories

Reviews for Thinking of Others

Rating: 3.5 out of 5 stars
3.5/5

1 rating0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    Thinking of Others - Ted Cohen

    THINKING OF OTHERS

    PRINCETON MONOGRAPHS IN PHILOSOPHY

    Harry G. Frankfurt, Editor

    The Princeton Monographs in Philosophy series offers short

    historical and systematic studies on a wide variety

    of philosophical topics.

    Justice Is Conflict by STUART HAMPSHIRE

    Liberty Worth the Name: Locke on Free Agency by GIDEON YAFFE

    Self-Deception Unmasked by ALFRED R. MELE

    Public Goods, Private Good by RAYMOND GEUSS

    Welfare and Rational Care by STEPHEN DARWALL

    A Defense of Hume on Miracles by ROBERT J. FOGELIN

    Kierkegaard’s Concept of Despair by MICHAEL THEUNISSEN (TRANSLATED BY BARBARA HARSHAV AND HELMUT ILLBRUCK)

    Physicalism, or Something Near Enough by JAEGWON KIM

    Philosophical Myths of the Fall by STEPHEN MULHALL

    Fixing Frege by JOHN P. BURGESS

    Kant and Skepticism by MICHAEL N. FORSTER

    Thinking of Others: On the Talent for Metaphor by TED COHEN

    THINKING OF OTHERS

    ON THE TALENT FOR METAPHOR


    Ted Cohen


    PRINCETON UNIVERSITY PRESS

    PRINCETON AND OXFORD

    Copyright © 2008 by Princeton University Press

    Published by Princeton University Press, 41 William Street,

    Princeton, New Jersey 08540

    In the United Kingdom: Princeton University Press, 6 Oxford Street,

    Woodstock, Oxfordshire OX20 1TW

    All Rights Reserved

    Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

    Cohen, Ted.

    Thinking of others : on the talent for metaphor / Ted Cohen.

    p. cm. — (Princeton monographs in philosophy)

    Includes index.

    ISBN 978-0-691-13746-9 (cloth : alk. paper)

    1. Metaphor. 2. Empathy. I. Title.

    PN228.M4C58 2008

    808—dc22 2008014920

    British Library Cataloging-in-Publication Data is available

    This book has been composed in Janson Typeface

    Printed on acid-free paper. ∞

    press.princeton.edu

    Printed in the United States of America

    1    3    5    7    9    10    8    6    4    2

    This book is for Andy Austin Cohen


    SHE DOES A BETTER JOB OF THINKING OF OTHER

    PEOPLE THAN ANYONE ELSE I KNOW, DOING IT WITH

    UNDERSTANDING AND GENEROSITY BUT WITHOUT

    EVER BEING FOOLISH. LIKE ALL PEOPLE, ANDY IS

    UNIQUE; AND SHE IS MORE SO.


    Contents


    Acknowledgments

    CHAPTER ONE

    The Talent for Metaphor

    CHAPTER TWO

    Being a Good Sport

    CHAPTER THREE

    From the Bible: Nathan and David

    CHAPTER FOUR

    Real Feelings, Unreal People

    CHAPTER FIVE

    More from the Bible: Abraham and God

    CHAPTER SIX

    More Lessons from Sports

    CHAPTER SEVEN

    Oneself Seen by Others

    CHAPTER EIGHT

    Oneself as Oneself

    CHAPTER NINE

    Lessons from Art

    CHAPTER TEN

    The Possibility of Conversation, Moral and Otherwise

    CHAPTER ELEVEN

    Conclusion: In Praise of Metaphor

    Index


    Acknowledgments


    Some of the material in this book was published in earlier, different versions, under different titles. Metaphor, Feeling, and Narrative was published in Philosophy and Literature, vol. 21, no. 2 (October, 1997), pp. 223–44. Identifying with Metaphor: Metaphors of Personal Identification was delivered as the presidential address to the American Society for Aesthetics in 1998, and subsequently published in the Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, vol. 57, no. 4 (Fall, 1999), pp. 399–409. Stories was delivered as the presidential address to the Central Division of the American Philosophical Association in 2007, and subsequently published in Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, vol. 81, no. 2 (November, 2007), pp. 33–48.

    This small text is much better for having been reviewed by three of the best readers I know, Stanley Bates, Stanley Cavell, and David Hills.

    Stanley Bates was once my colleague and has been my friend for decades. Except for Howard Stein, I believe Bates reads and knows more than anyone else I know. He showed me that my central idea is connected to more topics, themes, and problems than I had realized.

    Stanley Cavell was once my teacher and has been my friend ever since. Years ago I had the privilege of writing and reading out the citation for him when Cavell received an honorary degree, and I hit on what I thought and think a fitting ascription when I said that he has the courage of his affections. It is this model that has made it possible for eccentrics like me to pursue what appeals to us while supposing that we are still philosophers. In the case of this book, it is Cavell who made me understand that I am taken with and speaking of metaphor not in the narrow sense of that word, but in a much more expanded and ambitious sense, a point that has made my project more difficult and more interesting.

    David Hills is a rarity, an absolutely first-class analytical philosopher who reads what you write as if he were a master literary reader. I once published a pair of essays together, one autobiographical and the other straightforwardly analytical, leaving completely unexplained how those two pieces might go together. Whatever success those essays enjoyed, I think almost all readers took them to be independent and separable. When I later met Hills he made clear that he had found exactly why they go together. In reading this manuscript, Hills found more than a few lapses, places in which I settled for a nice idea and a pleasant phrase without supplying a foundation that would support them.

    It was a pleasure, of course, and also a relief to know that those three thought the material worth sending out. If you do not think so, you might blame them a little, but you should mainly hold me responsible.

    THINKING OF OTHERS

    CHAPTER ONE


    The Talent for Metaphor


    Nonetheless, I agree that there is a pictorial dimension to metaphor and that the perspective it generates cannot be expressed propositionally.

    —JOSEF STERN¹

    We may, therefore, regard the metaphorical sentence as a Duck-Rabbit; it is a sentence that may simultaneously be regarded as presenting two different situations; looked at one way, it describes the actual situation, and looked at the other way, an hypothetical situation with which that situation is being compared.

    —ROGER WHITE²

    There is mystery at the heart of metaphor. During the past several years a number of capable authors have done much to clarify the topic, and they have shown that some earlier central theses about the nature of metaphor are untenable.³ What they have shown, in particular, is that the import of a significant metaphor cannot be delivered literally, that is, in general, that a metaphorical statement has no literal statement that is its equivalent.

    It may or may not be prudent to regard the import of a metaphor as a meaning. If it is, then a metaphorical sentence has two meanings, one literal and one metaphorical. If not, then there is only one meaning, the literal meaning, and the metaphorical import has to be understood in another way. But in either case there will be a metaphorical import that a competent audience will grasp. How the audience does this is, in the end, a mystery.

    In the case of a metaphor of the form ‘A is B’, some comparison is indicated of the properties of A with the properties of B. An early idea, persistent at least since Aristotle, is that this comparison can be made explicit in a formulation of the form ‘A is like B’ and this leads to the further idea that the import of the metaphor can be expressed as an explicit, literal comparison of A with B.

    Both ideas are mistaken, the second more seriously misleading than the first. The first idea, on its face, is simply and wildly implausible. In general, and certainly in the case of literal statements, ‘A is B’ and ‘A is like B’ are not equivalent. For instance, ‘Aristotle is like Plato’ is true: they are both Greek, both Athenians, both philosophers, both long dead, &c, while ‘Aristotle is Plato’ is false. There is no compelling reason to think that this obvious nonequivalence disappears when ‘A is B’ happens to be a metaphor, unless, of course, it were the case that a metaphor ‘A is B’ is somehow, perhaps by convention, to be understood as an alternative formulation of the literal simile ‘A is like B’, and there seems no good reason to suppose this to be the case.

    The second idea is that the ‘A is like B’ associated with the metaphor ‘A is B’ is not itself metaphorical but is literal, and as seductive as this idea has been, it is mistaken. The mistake can be exposed using the useful if timeworn example ‘Juliet is the sun’. If the import of Romeo’s declaration were a literal comparison expressed in ‘Juliet is like the sun’, then the relevant comparison would be of properties literally possessed by both Juliet and the

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1